Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-t7czq Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-23T18:45:07.587Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

More Ramsey theory for highly connected monochromatic subgraphs

Part of: Set theory

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  24 November 2023

Michael Hrušák
Affiliation:
Centro de Ciencas Matemáticas, Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México (UNAM), A.P. 61-3, Xangari, Morelia, Michoacán 58089, México e-mail: [email protected]
Saharon Shelah
Affiliation:
Department of Mathematics, Rutgers University, Hill Center, Piscataway, NJ 08854-8019, United States and Institute of Mathematics, Hebrew University, Givat Ram, Jerusalem 91904, Israel e-mail: [email protected]
Jing Zhang*
Affiliation:
Department of Mathematics, University of Toronto, Bahen Centre, 40 St. George Street, Room 6290, Toronto, ON M5S 2E4, Canada
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

An infinite graph is said to be highly connected if the induced subgraph on the complement of any set of vertices of smaller size is connected. We continue the study of weaker versions of Ramsey’s theorem on uncountable cardinals asserting that if we color edges of the complete graph, we can find a large highly connected monochromatic subgraph. In particular, several questions of Bergfalk, Hrušák, and Shelah (2021, Acta Mathematica Hungarica 163, 309–322) are answered by showing that assuming the consistency of suitable large cardinals, the following are relatively consistent with ZFC:

  • $\kappa \to _{hc} (\kappa )^2_\omega $ for every regular cardinal $\kappa \geq \aleph _2$,

  • $\neg \mathsf {CH}+ \aleph _2 \to _{hc} (\aleph _1)^2_\omega $.

Building on a work of Lambie-Hanson (2023, Fundamenta Mathematicae. 260(2):181–197), we also show that

  • $\aleph _2 \to _{hc} [\aleph _2]^2_{\omega ,2}$ is consistent with $\neg \mathsf {CH}$.

To prove these results, we use the existence of ideals with strong combinatorial properties after collapsing suitable large cardinals.

Type
Article
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of The Canadian Mathematical Society

1 Introduction

The paper studies weak versions of the Ramsey theorem on uncountable cardinals. Following [Reference Bergfalk, Hrušák and Shelah5], we say that a graph $G=(X,E)$ is highly connected if for every $Y\subseteq X$ of cardinality strictly smaller than $|X|$ , the subgraph $(X\setminus Y , E\cap [X\setminus Y]^2)$ is connected. Given cardinal numbers $\theta \leq \lambda \leq \kappa $ ,

$$ \begin{align*}\kappa\to_{hc}(\lambda)^2_\theta\end{align*} $$

denotes the statement that for every $c:[\kappa ]^2\to \theta $ , there is an $\xi \in \theta $ and $A\in [\kappa ]^\lambda $ such that $(A, c^{-1}(\xi )\cap [A]^2)$ is highly connected, in which case we shall say that A is highly connected in color  $\xi $ .

The original motivation for studying this partition relation came from the study of higher derived limits in forcing extensions (see [Reference Bannister, Bergfalk, Moore and Todorcevic2, Reference Bergfalk, Hrušák and Lambie-Hanson4, Reference Bergfalk and Lambie-Hanson6, Reference Veličković and Vignati19] and [Reference Mitchell18]) and is related in spirit to both the partition hypotheses of [Reference Bannister, Bergfalk, Moore and Todorcevic2] and another weak Ramsey property concerning the so-called topological  $K_\kappa $ (first studied by Erdős and Hajnal in [Reference Erdős and Hajnal8]) considered by Komjáth and Shelah in [Reference Komjáth and Shelah15].

This paper continues the study initiated in [Reference Bergfalk, Hrušák and Shelah5] and further investigated in [Reference Bergfalk3, Reference Lambie-Hanson16] of those cardinals $\theta < \lambda \leq \kappa $ for which the $\to _{hc}$ arrow holds. Among the facts proved in [Reference Bergfalk, Hrušák and Shelah5] are:

  • for every infinite cardinal $\kappa $ and natural number n, $\kappa \to _{hc}(\kappa )^2_n$ ,

  • if $\kappa \leq 2^\theta $ , then $\kappa \not \to _{hc}(\kappa )^2_\theta $ , and

  • if $\lambda =\lambda ^\theta $ , then $\lambda ^+\to _{hc}(\lambda )^2_\theta $ ;

in particular, $2^\omega \not \to _{hc} (2^\omega )^2_\omega $ . On the other hand, it was shown there that assuming the existence of a weakly compact cardinal, consistently $2^{\omega _1}\to _{hc}(2^{\omega _1})^2_\omega $ . However, in the model witnessing this relation, $2^{\omega _1}$ is weakly inaccessible, being a former large cardinal in a forcing extension by a poset satisfying a small chain condition.

In light of the results mentioned above, the following natural questions were raised in [Reference Bergfalk3, Reference Bergfalk, Hrušák and Shelah5]:

Question 1.1

  1. (1) Is it consistent that $\kappa \to _{hc}(\kappa )^2_{\omega }$ holds for an accessible $\kappa $ ? For example, when $\kappa $ is $\aleph _2$ or $\aleph _{\omega +1}$ ?

  2. (2) Is $\aleph _2\to _{hc}(\aleph _1)^2_\omega $ equivalent to the Continuum Hypothesis?

Note that by a result of Lambie-Hanson [Reference Lambie-Hanson16], if $\kappa \to _{hc}(\kappa )^2_{\omega }$ holds, then $\square (\kappa )$ necessarily fails. In particular, if $\aleph _2\to _{hc}(\aleph _2)^2_{\omega }$ were to hold, our arguments would require at least a weakly compact cardinal, and if $\aleph _{\omega +1}\to _{hc}(\aleph _{\omega +1})^2_{\omega }$ were to hold, then our arguments would require significantly stronger large cardinals.

Here, we answer the first question in the positive and the second question in the negative by analyzing remnants of large cardinal properties on smaller cardinals after suitable forcing, often the Levy or Mitchell collapse, in the form of the existence of ideals having strong combinatorial properties.

We finish this section with a few more definitions and notations. Let $\kappa $ be a regular uncountable cardinal.

Definition 1.2 Fix $k\in \omega $ . We let

$$ \begin{align*}\kappa\to [\kappa]^2_{\omega,k}\end{align*} $$

to abbreviate the assertion that for any $c: [\kappa ]^2\to \omega $ , there exist $H\in [\kappa ]^{\kappa }$ and $K \in [\omega ]^k$ such that $(H, c^{-1}(K))\cap [H]^2)$ is highly connected.

The following is a more refined variation of the highly connected partition relations, conditioned on the lengths of the paths.

Definition 1.3 Fix $n\in \omega $ . Let $\kappa \to _{hc, <n}(\kappa )^2_\omega $ abbreviate $\kappa \to _{hc}(\kappa )^2_\omega $ via paths of length $<n$ . More precisely, it asserts: for any $c: [\kappa ]^2\to \omega $ , there exists $A\in [\kappa ]^\kappa $ and $i\in \omega $ such that for any $C\in [A]^{<\kappa }$ and $\alpha ,\beta \in A \backslash C$ , there exist $l<n$ and a path $\langle \gamma _k: k<l+1\rangle \subseteq A\backslash C$ with $\gamma _0=\alpha $ and $ \gamma _{l}=\beta $ such that for all $j<l$ , $c(\gamma _{j}, \gamma _{j+1})=i$ .

The organization of the paper is:

  1. (1) in Section 2, we establish the consistency of $\aleph _2\to _{hc} (\aleph _1)^2_{\omega } $ and $\neg \mathsf {CH}$ ,

  2. (2) in Section 3, we isolate and investigate 2-precipitous ideals (see Definition 3.1) whose existence implies $\kappa \to _{hc}[\kappa ]^2_{\omega ,2}$ ,

  3. (3) in Section 4, we demonstrate two methods of constructing 2-precipitous ideals and show that $\aleph _2\to _{hc}[\aleph _2]^2_{\omega ,2} + 2^{\aleph _0} \geq \aleph _2$ is consistent,

  4. (4) in Section 5, we deduce the consistency of $\aleph _2\to _{hc}(\aleph _2)^2_{\omega }$ from an ideal hypothesis,

  5. (5) in Section 6, we sketch how to use large cardinals to establish the consistency of the ideal hypothesis used in Section 5,

  6. (6) in Section 7, we show we cannot improve the result in Section 6 by making the lengths of the paths required to connect vertices shorter,

  7. (7) finally in Section 8, we finish with some open questions.

2 The consistency of $\aleph _2\to _{hc} (\aleph _1)^2_{\omega } + \neg \mathsf {CH}$

We call an ideal I on $\omega _1 \aleph _1$ -proper with respect to  $S\subseteq P_{\aleph _2}(H(\theta ))$ where $\theta $ is a large enough regular cardinal if for any $M\in S$ and $X\in M\cap I^+$ , there exists an extension $Y\subseteq _I X$ such that Y is $(M,I^+)$ -generic, meaning that for any dense $D\subseteq I^+$ with $D\in M$ and any $Y'\subseteq _I Y$ , there exists $Z\in D\cap M$ such that $Y'\cap Z\in I^+$ .

Lemma 2.1 If I is $\aleph _1$ -proper with respect to $\{M\}$ with $M\prec H(\theta )$ of size $\aleph _1$ containing I, then whenever $Y\in I^+$ is an $(M, I^+)$ -generic condition, the following holds:

for any $E\subseteq I^+$ in M, if there is some $Y'\in E$ such that $Y\subseteq _I Y'$ , then there exists $Z\in E\cap M$ such that $Y\cap Z\in I^+$ .

Proof Define a dense subseteq $D_E\subseteq I^+$ in M as follows: $A\in D_E$ iff either there exists $B\in E$ , $A\subseteq _I B$ or for all $B\in E$ , $A\cap B =_I \emptyset $ . By the hypothesis, there exists $Z'\in D_E\cap M$ such that $Y\cap Z'\in I^+$ . Note that there exists $Z\in E$ such that $Z'\subseteq _I Z$ since $Z'\cap Y \neq _I \emptyset $ and $Y\subseteq _I Y'\in E$ . The elementarity of M then guarantees the existence of such $Z\in M$ .

If I is $\aleph _2$ -saturated, then I is $\aleph _1$ -proper with respect to a closed unbounded subset of $P_{\aleph _2}(H(\theta ))$ for sufficiently large $\theta $ . There are many models where $\omega _1$ carries a $\sigma $ -complete $\aleph _2$ -saturated ideal and $\mathsf {CH}$ fails. For example, they are both consequences of Martin’s Maximum [Reference Foreman, Magidor and Shelah10].

Proposition 2.2 If there exists a $\sigma $ -complete $\aleph _1$ -proper ideal on $\omega _1$ with respect to a stationary subset of $\{X\in P_{\aleph _2}(H(\theta )): \sup X\cap \omega _2\in \mathrm {cof}(\omega _1) \}$ for some large enough $\theta $ , then $\aleph _2\to _{hc} (\aleph _1)^2_{\omega }$ .Footnote 1

Proof Given $c: [\omega _2]^2\to \omega $ , we will find $A\in [\omega _1]^{\aleph _1}$ and $B\in [\omega _2 \setminus \omega _1]^{\aleph _1}$ satisfying the following properties: there exists $k\in \omega $ such that:

  1. (1) for any $\alpha _0,\alpha _1\in A$ , there are uncountably many $\beta \in B$ such that $c(\alpha _0,\beta )=k=c(\alpha _1, \beta )$ , and

  2. (2) for any $\beta _0\in B$ , there are uncountably many $\alpha \in A$ satisfies that $c(\alpha ,\beta _0)=k$ .

Claim 2.3 $A\cup B$ is highly connected in the color k.

Proof of the claim

Let C be the countable set of vertices being removed. If $\alpha _0, \alpha _1\in A\backslash C$ , then it follows immediately by the first requirement that there is some $\beta \in B\backslash C$ such that $c(\alpha _0,\beta )=c(\alpha _1,\beta )=k$ .

Let us check the case when $\alpha \in A\backslash C$ and $\beta \in B\backslash C$ . We can find some large enough $\alpha '\in A\backslash C$ such that $c(\alpha ',\beta )=k$ . After that, we find some $\beta '\in B \backslash C$ such that $c(\alpha ',\beta ')=k=c(\alpha ,\beta ')$ . Then $\alpha $ is connected to $\beta $ via the k-path: $\alpha , \beta ', \alpha ',\beta $ .

If $\beta _0,\beta _1\in B\backslash C$ , then we can easily reduce to the previous case by finding some large enough $\alpha _0\in A\backslash C$ such that $c(\alpha _0, \beta _0)=k$ . Apply the previous analysis to $\alpha _0\in A\backslash C, \beta _1\in B\backslash C$ .

We proceed to find $A, B, k$ as above. For each $\alpha \in \omega _2\backslash \omega _1$ and $i\in \omega $ , let

$$ \begin{align*}X_{\alpha,i}=\{\gamma\in \omega_1: c(\gamma,\alpha)=i\}.\end{align*} $$

Let $M\prec H(\theta )$ of size $\aleph _1$ contain $I, c$ with $\sup M\cap \omega _2\in \mathrm {cof}(\omega _1)$ , and let $Y\in I^+$ be $(M,I^+)$ -generic. Let $\rho \in \omega _2 \backslash \sup M\cap \omega _2$ . By the $\sigma $ -completeness of I, find some $k\in \omega $ such that $A=Y\cap X_{\rho , k}\in I^+$ , which is still $(M,I^+)$ -generic, since it extends Y which is $(M, I^+)$ -generic. Finally, let us define B recursively. Let $\langle a^i=(a^i_0, a^i_1): i<\omega _1\rangle $ enumerate $[A]^2$ with unbounded repetitions. Suppose we have defined $\langle \beta _j: j<\alpha \rangle $ for some $\alpha <\omega _1$ satisfying that for all $j<\alpha $ ,

  1. (1) $a^j\subseteq X_{\beta _j, k}$ and

  2. (2) $X_{\beta _j,k}\cap A\in I^+$ .

It is clear if we may extend the construction through all $\alpha <\omega _1$ , then $A, B=\{\beta _j: j<\omega _1\}$ and k are as desired.

Suppose we are at the $\alpha $ th step of the construction, and let us find $\beta _\alpha $ maintaining the same requirements. Let $\bar {\beta }=\min (M \backslash \sup _{j<\alpha }\beta _j)<\sup M\cap \omega _2$ . Consider $E=\{X_{\beta ,k}\in I^+: a^\alpha _0, a^\alpha _1\in X_{\beta ,k}, \beta>\bar {\beta }\}$ . In particular, $E\in M$ and $A\subseteq _I X_{\rho ,k}\in E$ . By Lemma 2.1, there exists a $\beta>\bar {\beta }$ such that $X_{\beta ,k}\in M\cap E$ such that $A\cap X_{\beta ,k}\in I^+$ ; letting $\beta _\alpha =\beta $ completes the $\alpha $ th step.

3 2-precipitous ideals on $\kappa $ and $\kappa \to _{hc} [\kappa ]^2_{\omega ,2}$

Lambie-Hanson [Reference Lambie-Hanson16] showed that adding weakly compact many Cohen reals forces that $2^\omega \to _{hc} [2^\omega ]^2_{\omega ,2}$ , in contrast with the ZFC fact that $2^\omega \not \to _{hc} (2^\omega )^2_{\omega }$ . He also demonstrated that such partition relations already have nontrivial consistency strength, by showing that $\square (\kappa )$ implies $\kappa \not \to _{hc}[\kappa ]^2_{\omega , <\omega }$ .

In this section, we investigate the ideal hypothesis on $\kappa $ that implies $\kappa \to _{hc} [\kappa ]^2_{\omega ,2}$ . In particular, such analysis enables us to have more consistent scenarios, such as a model where $2^{\aleph _0}\geq \aleph _2$ and $\aleph _2\to _{hc} [\aleph _2]^2_{\omega ,2}$ both hold.

Definition 3.1 We say an ideal I on $\kappa $ is 2-precipitous if Player Empty does not have a winning strategy in the following game $G_{I}$ with perfect information: Player Empty and Nonempty take turns playing a $\subseteq $ -decreasing sequence of pairs of I-positive sets $\langle (A_n, B_n): n\in \omega \rangle $ with Player Empty starting the game. Player Nonempty wins iff there exist $\alpha <\beta $ with $\alpha \in \bigcap _{n\in \omega } A_n$ and $\beta \in \bigcap _{n\in \omega } B_n$ .

Lemma 3.2 Fix a dense subset $D\subseteq P(\kappa )/I$ . Player Empty has a winning strategy in $G_I$ iff Player Empty has a winning strategy $\sigma $ in $G_I$ such that $range(\sigma )\subseteq \{A \backslash M: A\in D, M\in I\}$ .

Proof Let us show the nontrivial direction $(\rightarrow )$ . Fix a winning strategy $\sigma $ of Player Empty. The input of $\sigma $ will be $(I^+\times I^+)^{<\omega }$ , corresponding to the sequence of positive sets Player Nonempty has played so far. Let $\pi : I^+ \to I^+$ be a map such that $\pi (B)=A \backslash M$ where $(A,M)\in D\times I$ is least (with respect to some fixed well-ordering) such that $A\backslash M\subseteq B$ . Such $\pi $ exists since D is dense in $P(\kappa )/I$ . Consider $\sigma '=\pi \circ \sigma $ . Clearly, the range of $\sigma '$ is a subset of $\{A\backslash M: A\in D, M\in I\}$ . To see that it is a winning strategy for Player Empty, suppose $\langle (A_n, B_n): n\in \omega \rangle $ is a play such that Player Empty plays according to $\sigma '$ . Notice that $\langle (A^{\prime }_n, B^{\prime }_n): n\in \omega \rangle $ , where $(A^{\prime }_n, B^{\prime }_n)=(A_n, B_n)$ when n is odd and $(A^{\prime }_n,B^{\prime }_n)=\sigma (\langle (A_{2k-1}, B_{2k-1}): 2k-1<n\rangle )$ is a legal play where Player Empty is playing according to $\sigma $ . As a result, there do not exist $\alpha <\beta $ such that $\alpha \in \bigcap _{n\in \omega } A_n' \subseteq \bigcap _{n\in \omega } A_n$ and $\beta \in \bigcap _{n\in \omega } B_n'\subseteq \bigcap _{n\in \omega } B_n$ . Therefore, $\sigma '$ is a winning strategy for Player Empty.

Theorem 3.3 If $\kappa $ carries a uniform normal $2$ -precipitous ideal, then $\kappa \to _{hc}[\kappa ]^2_{\omega , 2}$ .

Proof Fix a uniform normal $2$ -precipitous ideal I on $\kappa $ and a coloring $c: [\kappa ]^2\to \omega $ . Given $A,B$ two sets of ordinals, we let $A\otimes B=\{(\alpha ,\beta )\in A\times B: \alpha <\beta \}$ . We say a pair of I-positive sets $(B_0,B_1)$ is $(i,j)$ -frequent if for any I-positive sets $B_0'\subseteq B_0$ , $B_1'\subset B_1$ , there are:

  • $\alpha <\beta $ with $\alpha \in B_0', \beta \in B_1'$ such that $c(\alpha ,\beta )=i$ and

  • $\beta '<\alpha '$ with $\beta '\in B_1'$ , $\alpha '\in B_0'$ such that $c(\beta ',\alpha ')=j$ .

Claim 3.4 There exists a pair of I-positive sets $(B_0, B_1)$ and $i,j\in \omega $ such that $(B_0, B_1)$ is $(i,j)$ -frequent.

Proof of the claim

Starting with a positive pair $(A_0, A_1)$ , we find some $i\in \omega $ and positive $(C_0,C_1)\subseteq (A_0, A_1)$ such that $(C_0, C_1)$ satisfies the first requirement of the $(i,j)$ -frequency, namely, for all positive sets $C_0'\subseteq C_0, C_1'\subseteq C_1$ , there are $(\alpha ,\beta )\in C_0'\otimes C_1'$ such that $c(\alpha ,\beta )=i$ . Suppose for the sake of contradiction that such $(C_0,C_1)$ and i do not exist. We define a strategy $\sigma $ for Player Empty: they start by playing $(A^0, B^0)=_{def}(A_0,A_1)$ . At stage $2i$ , denoting the game played so far is $\langle (A^k, B^k): k<2i\rangle $ , by the hypothesis, there are positive $(A',B')\subseteq (A^{2i-1}, B^{2i-1})$ such that no $(\alpha ,\beta ) \in A'\otimes B'$ satisfies $c(\alpha ,\beta )=i$ . Player Empty then plays $(A^{2i}, B^{2i})=(A',B')$ . Since by the hypothesis of I, Player Empty does not have a winning strategy, there is a play $\langle (A^n,B^n): n\in \omega \rangle $ where Player Empty plays according to the strategy $\sigma $ , but in the end, there are $(\alpha ,\beta ) \in \bigcap _{n\in \omega } A^n \otimes \bigcap _{n\in \omega } B^n$ . However, if $c(\alpha ,\beta )=k$ , then at stage $2k$ , the strategy of Empty makes sure $c" A^{2k}\otimes B^{2k}$ omits $\{k\}$ , which is a contradiction.

Finally, we repeat the previous argument with input $(C_1, C_0)$ in place of $(A_0, A_1)$ to find positive $(B_1, B_0)\subseteq (C_1, C_0)$ and $j\in \omega $ satisfying the second condition of the $(i,j)$ -frequency, as desired.

Fix an $(i,j)$ -frequent pair $(B_0,B_1)$ . We strengthen this property of $(B_0, B_1)$ by using the normality of I. Recall that for any positive $S\in I^+$ , $I^*\restriction S$ denotes the dual filter of I restricted to S.

Claim 3.5 For any I-positive $B_0'\subseteq B_0, B_1'\subseteq B_1$ ,

  • $\{\alpha \in B_0: \{\beta \in B_1': c(\alpha ,\beta )=i\}\in I^+\}\in I^*\restriction B_0$ ,

  • $\{\beta '\in B_1: \{\alpha '\in B_0': c(\beta ',\alpha ')=j\}\in I^+\}\in I^*\restriction B_1$ .

Proof of the claim

Let us just show the first part; the proof of the second part is identical. Suppose for the sake of contradiction that $B^0=_{def}\{\alpha \in B_0: B^1_{\alpha }=_{def}\{\beta \in B_1': c(\alpha ,\beta )=i\}\in I\}\in I^+$ . Since I is normal, $B^1=\bigtriangledown _{\alpha \in B^0} B^1_\alpha \in I$ . Applying the assumption that $(B_0, B_1)$ is $(i,j)$ -frequent to $B^0$ and $B_1'\backslash B^1$ , we get $(\alpha ,\beta )\in B^0 \otimes (B_1' \backslash B^1)$ such that $c(\alpha ,\beta )=i$ . However, by the definition of $B^1$ , $\beta \in B^1$ , which is a contradiction.

Applying Claim 3.5, we find $B_0^*\in I^*\restriction B_0, B_1^*\in I^*\restriction B_1$ such that:

  1. (1) for any $\alpha \in B^*_0$ , $\{\beta \in B^*_1: c(\alpha ,\beta )=i\}\in I^+$ and

  2. (2) for any $\beta '\in B^*_1$ , $\{\alpha '\in B^*_0: c(\beta ',\alpha ')=j\}\in I^+$ .

Let us check that $(B_0^* \cup B^*_1, c^{-1}(\{i,j\}))$ is a highly connected subgraph of size $\aleph _2$ . Given $C\in [B_0^* \cup B^*_1]^{\leq \aleph _1}$ , $\alpha ,\beta \in B_0^* \cup B^*_1 \backslash C$ , we need to find an $(i,j)$ -valued path connecting them in $B_0^* \cup B^*_1 \backslash C$ . Consider the following cases.

  • $\alpha \in B^*_0, \beta \in B^*_1$ : let $A_\alpha =\{\gamma \in B^*_1: c(\alpha ,\gamma )=i\}\in I^+$ and let $B_\beta =\{\eta \in B^*_0: c(\beta , \eta )=j\}\in I^+$ . Since $(B^*_0, B^*_1) $ is $(i,j)$ -frequent, we can find $(\gamma ,\eta )\in (A_\alpha \backslash C)\otimes (B_\beta \backslash C)$ such that $c(\gamma ,\eta )=j$ . Then the path $\alpha , \gamma , \eta , \beta $ is as desired.

  • $\alpha , \beta \in B^*_0$ or $\alpha , \beta \in B^*_1$ : we can reduce to the previous case by moving either $\alpha $ or $\beta $ to the other side using an edge of c-color either i or j.

4 The consistency of the existence of a 2-precipitous ideal

In this section, we discuss two forcing constructions of a 2-precipitous ideal on $\kappa $ . The first is cardinal preserving and the second involves collapsing cardinals. First, let us record some characterizations of 2-precipitous ideals analogous to those of precipitous ideals in [Reference Jech and Prikry14].

Definition 4.1 A tree T of maximal antichains of $P(\kappa )/I \times P(\kappa )/I$ is a sequence of maximal antichains $\langle \mathcal {A}_n: n\in \omega \rangle $ of $P(\kappa )/I \times P(\kappa )/I$ such that $\mathcal {A}_{n+1}$ refines $\mathcal {A}_n$ for each $n\in \omega $ . A branch through T is a decreasing sequence of conditions $\langle b_n: n\in \omega \rangle $ such that $b_n\in \mathcal {A}_n$ .

The proof by Jech and Prikry [Reference Jech and Prikry14] (see also [Reference Foreman9, Proposition 2.7]) essentially gives the following.

Theorem 4.2 [Reference Jech and Prikry14]

I is 2-precipitous if for any pair of positive sets $(C_0, C_1)$ and a tree T of maximal antichains $\langle \mathcal {A}_n : n\in \omega \rangle $ below $(C_0,C_1)$ , there exists a sequence $\langle (A_n,B_n): n\in \omega \rangle $ such that:

  1. (1) $\langle (A_n, B_n): n\in \omega \rangle $ is a branch through the tree T and

  2. (2) there exist $\alpha <\beta $ such that $\alpha \in \bigcap _{n\in \omega } A_n$ and $\beta \in \bigcap _{n\in \omega } B_n$ .

Remark 4.3 Suppose that we are given a dense subset $D\subseteq P(\kappa )/I$ . By Lemma 3.2, it is no loss of generality to assume that $ \{(C_0,C_1)\} \cup \bigcup _{n\in \omega }\mathcal {A}_n\subseteq \{A\backslash M: A\in D, M\in I\}\times \{A\backslash M: A\in D, M\in I\}$ .

For the rest of this section, we will apply Remark 4.3 liberally. Also, it turns out that suppressing the quotiented ideal I does not affect the reasoning. Therefore, to avoid cumbersome notations, we will further assume that $\mathcal {A}_n\subseteq D\times D$ for all $n\in \omega $ . Given a partial order $\mathbb {P}$ , we denote the complete Boolean algebra generated by $\mathbb {P}$ as $\mathbb {B}(\mathbb {P})$ .

Proposition 4.4 If I is a $\kappa $ -complete normal ideal on $\kappa $ and $P(\kappa )/I\simeq \mathbb {B}(Add(\omega ,\lambda ))$ for some $\lambda $ , then I is 2-precipitous.

Proof Let $\pi : \mathbb {B}(Add(\omega ,\lambda ))\to P(\kappa )/I$ be an isomorphism. For each $r\in Add(\omega ,\lambda )$ , let $X_r = \pi (r)$ . Here, we identify $Add(\omega ,\lambda )$ as a dense subset of $\mathbb {B}(Add(\omega ,\lambda ))$ , $D=\{X_r: r\in Add(\omega ,\lambda )\}$ .

Suppose for the sake of contradiction that I is not 2-precipitous. By Theorem 4.2, there exist a $(C_0,C_1)$ and a tree T of maximal antichains below $(C_0,C_1)$ for which conditions (1) and (2) simultaneously hold. Note that since $P(\kappa )/I\times P(\kappa )/I$ is c.c.c., each $\mathcal {A}_n \subseteq D\times D$ is countable. Find $r_0,r_1\in Add(\omega ,\lambda )$ such that $C_i=X_{r_i}$ for $i<2$ .

Let $G\subseteq P(\kappa )/I$ be a generic filter containing $C_0$ . Then, in $V[G]$ , there is a generic elementary embedding $j: V\to M$ which can be taken to be the ultrapower embedding with respect to the added generic V-ultrafilter extending the dual filter of I.

Consider $T^{\prime }_n=\{B^*: \exists (A^*,B^*)\in j(\mathcal {A}_n), \kappa \in A^*\}$ . Note that $\langle T^{\prime }_n: n\in \omega \rangle \in M$ since $V[G]\models {}^{\omega }M\subseteq M$ by [Reference Foreman9, Proposition 2.14]. Note that $T^{\prime }_n\subseteq j"V$ . This follows from the fact that each $\mathcal {A}_n$ is countable, and hence $j(\mathcal {A}_n)=j" \mathcal {A}_n$ .

Claim 4.5 In M, $T^{\prime }_n$ is a maximal antichain below $j(C_1)$ for the poset $j(P(\kappa )/I)$ .

Proof of the claim

Suppose not. By the product lemma, $\mathcal {B}=\{B: \exists (A,B)\in \mathcal {A}_n, A\in G\}$ is a maximal antichain for

$$ \begin{align*}(P(\kappa)/I)^V\simeq \mathbb{B}(Add(\omega,\lambda))\end{align*} $$

below $X_{r_1}$ in $V[G]$ . We can enumerate

$$ \begin{align*}\mathcal{B}=\langle X_{p_n}: n\in \omega, r_n\in Add(\omega,\lambda)\rangle.\end{align*} $$

In particular, $\langle p_n: n\in \omega \rangle $ is a maximal antichain for $Add(\omega ,\lambda )$ below $r_1$ in $V[G]$ .

If $\langle j(X_{p_n}): n\in \omega \rangle $ is not a maximal antichain in $j(P(\kappa )/I)\simeq j(\mathbb {B}(Add(\omega ,\lambda )))$ , then there exists a condition $r\in Add(\omega , j(\lambda ))$ such that $X_r^*=_{\mathrm {def}}j(\pi )(r)$ is incompatible with any condition in the set $\{j(X_{p_n}): n\in \omega \}$ . This means r is incompatible with any condition in $\{j(p_n): n\in \omega \}$ . Since $j(p_n)=j"p_n$ , we may assume $r\in Add(\omega ,j"\lambda )$ . Let $r^*=j^{-1}(r)$ . Then $r^*\in Add(\omega ,\lambda )/r_1$ is incompatible with any condition in $\{p_n: n\in \omega \}$ . This contradicts with the fact that $\langle p_n: n\in \omega \rangle $ is a maximal antichain subset of $Add(\omega ,\lambda )$ below $r_1$ in $V[G]$ .

Let $H\subseteq j(P(\kappa )/I)$ be a generic filter over $V[G]$ containing $j(D)$ . Since $M\models j(P(\kappa )/I)$ is a $j(\kappa )$ -complete and $\aleph _1$ -saturated ideal, H gives rise to an ultrapower embedding $k: M\to N$ with critical point $j(\kappa )$ . Consider $b=\{(A_n,B_n): (\kappa ,j(\kappa ))\in k(j(A_n))\times k(j(B_n))\}$ . By Claim 4.8, H meets $T^{\prime }_n$ for all $n\in \omega $ . As a result, $k\circ j(b)=k\circ j"b$ is a branch $\langle (A^*_n, B^*_n): n\in \omega \rangle $ through $k(j(T))$ in $V[G*H]$ with $(\kappa ,j(\kappa ))\in \bigcap _{n\in \omega } A^*_n \otimes \bigcup _{n\in \omega } B^*_n$ . Since N is well-founded, there is such a branch in N. By the elementarity of $k\circ j$ , T has a branch $\langle (A_n, B_n): n\in \omega \rangle $ in V for which there are $\alpha <\beta $ with $\alpha \in \bigcap _{n\in \omega } A_n$ and $\beta \in \bigcap _{n\in \omega } B_n$ .

It is easy to see that if $P(\kappa )/I$ has a $\sigma $ -closed dense subset, then I is 2-precipitous. However, in this case, it is necessary that $2^{\aleph _0} < \kappa $ .

The second construction gives a scenario where $\kappa $ is a small uncountable cardinal (like $\aleph _2$ ) and $\mathrm {CH}$ fails. In particular, such an ideal can be constructed using the Mitchell collapse [Reference Mitchell18].Footnote 2

Recall the Mitchell forcing from [Reference Mitchell18] (the representation of the forcing here is due to Abraham; see [Reference Abraham1] and [Reference Cummings7, Section 23]) $\mathbb {M}(\omega ,\lambda )$ consists of conditions of the form $(p,r)$ where $p\in Add(\omega ,\lambda )$ and r is a function on $\lambda $ of countable support such that for any $\alpha <\lambda $ , $\Vdash _{Add(\omega ,\alpha )} r(\alpha )$ is a condition in $Add(\omega _1,1)$ . The order is that $(p_2, r_2)\leq (p_1, r_1)$ iff $p_2\supset p_1$ , $supp(r_2)\supset supp(r_1)$ , and for any $\alpha \in supp(r_1)$ , $p_2\restriction \alpha \Vdash _{Add(\omega ,\alpha )} r_2(\alpha )\leq _{Add(\omega _1,1)} r_1(\alpha )$ .

Define R to be the poset consisting of countably supported functions r with domain $\lambda $ such that for each $\alpha \in supp(r)$ , $r(\alpha )$ is an $Add(\omega , \alpha )$ -name for a condition in $Add(\omega _1, 1)$ . The order of R is the following: $r_2\leq _R r_1$ iff $supp(r_2)\supset supp(r_1)$ and for any $\alpha \in supp(r_1)$ , $\Vdash _{Add(\omega ,\alpha )} r_2(\alpha )\leq _{Add(\omega _1, 1)} r_1(\alpha )$ .

The following are standard facts about this forcing (see [Reference Cummings7]):

  1. (1) $\mathbb {M}(\omega ,\lambda )$ projects onto $Add(\omega ,\lambda )$ by projecting onto the first coordinate.

  2. (2) $Add(\omega ,\lambda )\times R$ projects onto $\mathbb {M}(\omega ,\lambda )$ by the identity map.

Remark 4.6 Whenever $(p_2, r_2)\leq _{\mathbb {M}(\omega ,\lambda )}(p_1, r_1)$ , there exists $r_2'\in R$ with $dom(r_2')=dom(r_2)$ such that $r_2'\leq _{R} r_1$ and $p_2\restriction \alpha \Vdash _{Add(\omega ,\alpha )} r_2(\alpha )=r_2'(\alpha )$ for any $\alpha \in dom(r_2)$ . In other words, $(p_2, r_2)$ and $(p_2, r_2')$ are equivalent conditions. We will use this fact freely in the following proofs.

Note that the poset R has the property that any countable decreasing sequence has a greatest lower bound.

Proposition 4.7 If $P(\kappa )/I\simeq \mathbb {B}(\mathbb {M}(\omega ,\lambda ))$ for some $\lambda $ , then I is 2-precipitous.

Proof Let $\pi : \mathbb {M}(\omega ,\lambda )\to D$ be an isomorphism where $D\subseteq P(\kappa )/I$ is a dense subset. For any $(p,r)\in \mathbb {M}(\omega ,\lambda )$ , let $X_{p,r}$ denote $\pi (p,r)$ . Assume for the sake of contradiction that I is not 2-precipitous. Fix a winning strategy $\sigma $ for Player Empty in the game $G_I$ . We may assume $\sigma $ satisfies the conclusion of Lemma 3.2 applied to D. To avoid cumbersome notations, we will assume for simplicity that $\sigma $ outputs elements from $D\times D$ , as discussed after Remark 4.3. We will use $\sigma $ to construct a tree of antichains $T=\langle \mathcal {A}_n: n\in \omega \rangle $ below $\sigma (\emptyset )=(A,B)=(X_{p^{-1}_a, r^{-1}_a}, X_{p^{-1}_b, r^{-1}_b})=\mathcal {A}_{-1}$ satisfying the following additional properties:

  1. (1) $\mathcal {A}_{n+1}$ refines $\mathcal {A}_n$ .

  2. (2) $\mathcal {A}_n=\langle (a^n_i, b^n_i):i<\gamma _n\rangle \subseteq D$ is countable (note that it is not maximal anymore).

  3. (3) For each $n\in \omega ,i\in \gamma _n$ , there are unique $(p^n_{i,a}, r^n_{i,a}),(p^n_{i,b}, r^n_{i,b}) \in \mathbb {M}(\omega ,\lambda )$ such that $X_{p^n_{i,a}, r^n_{i,a}}=a^n_i$ and $X_{p^n_{i,b}, r^n_{i,b}}=b^n_i$ .

  4. (4) For any n and $i<j\in \gamma _n$ , $(r^n_{j,a}, r^n_{j,b})\leq _{R\times R} (r^n_{i,a}, r^n_{i,b})$ .

  5. (5) For any lower bound $(r_0, r_1)$ for $\langle (r^n_{i,a}, r^n_{i,b}): i\in \gamma _n\rangle $ , we have that $\mathcal {A}_n \downarrow (r_0, r_1)=_{def} \{X_{p^n_{i,a}, r_0}, X_{p^n_{i,b}, r_1}: i\in \gamma _n\}$ is a maximal antichain in $(A\cap X_{\emptyset , r_0}, B\cap X_{\emptyset ,r_1})$ .

  6. (6) For any n and $i,j$ , $(r^{n+1}_{j,a}, r^{n+1}_{j,b})\leq _{R\times R} (r^n_{i,a}, r^n_{i,b})$ .

  7. (7) For any branch $\langle (A_n,B_n): n\in \omega \rangle $ through T, there do not exist $\alpha <\beta $ such that $\alpha \in \bigcap _{n\in \omega } A_n$ and $\beta \in \bigcap _{n\in \omega } B_n$ .

Assuming that the construction of such T is possible, let us derive a contradiction. Let $(r_a, r_b)$ be the greatest lower bound in $R\times R$ for $\langle \langle (r^n_{i,a}, r^n_{i,b}): i\in \gamma _n\rangle : n\in \omega \rangle $ . By property (5), we know that for each n, $\mathcal {A}_n\downarrow (r_a, r_b)$ is a maximal antichain below $(X_{\emptyset , r_a}\cap A, X_{\emptyset , r_b}\cap B)$ as a subset of $(P(\kappa )/I)^V$ in $V[G]$ .

Force over V to get a generic $G\subseteq P(\kappa )/I$ over V containing $X_{\emptyset ,r_a}\cap A$ . Using G, we find an elementary embedding $j: V\to M$ with critical point $\kappa $ . In $V[G]$ , consider the tree $T'$ consisting of $\mathcal {A}_n'=\{j(C): \kappa \in j(D), (D,C)\in \mathcal {A}_n \downarrow (r_a, r_b)\}$ . Notice that by property (5) and the product lemma, $\mathcal {A}^*_n=\{C: j(C)\in \mathcal {A}^{\prime }_n\}$ is a maximal antichain below $X_{\emptyset , r_b}\cap B$ .

Claim 4.8 For each $n\in \omega $ , $\mathcal {A}_n' \subseteq j(P(\kappa )/I)$ is a maximal antichain below $j(B)\cap X_{\emptyset ,j(r_b)}$ in $V[G]$ (and in M, since $V[G]\models {}^\omega M\subseteq M$ ).

Proof of the claim

Otherwise, we can find $(p, r^*)\in j(\mathbb {M}(\omega ,\lambda ))$ below $(\emptyset , j(r_b))$ such that $X_{p,r^*}^*=_{\mathrm {def}}j(\pi )((p,r^*))\subseteq j(B)\cap X_{\emptyset , j(r_b)}$ and $X_{p,r^*}^*$ is incompatible with any element in $\mathcal {A}^{\prime }_n$ . By changing to an equivalent condition if necessary, we may assume that $r^*\leq _{j(R)} j(r_b) $ . As a result, $p\perp _{j(Add(\omega ,\lambda ))}j(p^n_{k,b})$ for all $k\in \omega $ . Consider $p'=j^{-1}(p)\in Add(\omega ,\lambda )$ . Then $p'\perp _{Add(\omega ,\lambda )} p^n_{k,b}$ for all $k\in \omega $ . As a result, $X_{p', r_{b}}$ is incompatible with each element in $\mathcal {A}^*_n$ , but $X_{p', r_b}\cap B\cap X_{\emptyset , r_b}\in I^+$ , which is a contradiction to the fact that $\mathcal {A}^*_n$ is a maximal antichain below $X_{\emptyset , r_b}\cap B$ .

Let $H\subseteq j(P(\kappa )/I)$ be a V-generic filter containing $j(B\cap X_{\emptyset , r_b})$ . Then, in $V[G*H]$ , we can form an elementary embedding $k: M\to N$ with critical point $j(\kappa )$ . Consider $b=\{(A_n,B_n): (\kappa ,j(\kappa ))\in j(A_n)\otimes k(j(B_n)), (A_n, B_n)\in \mathcal {A}_n, n\in \omega \}$ . By Claim 4.8, $k\circ j"b\in V[G*H]$ is a branch through $k(j(T))$ violating property (7) as witnessed by $(\kappa , j(\kappa ))$ . Since N is a well-founded inner model of $V[G*H]$ , there is such a branch in N. By the elementarity of $k\circ j$ , there is such a branch in V through T violating property (7), which is a contradiction.

Let us turn to the construction of T. We will construct T levelwise recursion. Let $\mathcal {A}_{-1}=\sigma (\emptyset )=(A,B)=(X_{p^{-1}_a, r^{-1}_a}, X_{p^{-1}_b, r^{-1}_b})$ . To avoid excessive repetitions, we will assume that all the conditions from $\mathbb {M}(\omega ,\lambda )\times \mathbb {M}(\omega ,\lambda )$ extend $((p^{-1}_a, r^{-1}_a),(p^{-1}_b, r^{-1}_b))$ .

Let us first define $T(0)=\mathcal {A}_0$ . Recursively, suppose we have defined $\mathcal {A}_{0,<\eta }=\langle (X_{p^0_{i,a}, r^0_{i,a}}, X_{p^0_{i,b}, r^0_{i,b}}): i<\eta \rangle $ (partially) satisfying property (4). Let $(t_0,t_1)$ be a lower bound for $\langle (r^0_{i,a}, r^0_{i,b}): i<\eta \rangle $ in $R\times R$ . If there exists $(q_0, t^{\prime }_0)\leq (p_a^{-1}, t_0), (q_1, t^{\prime }_1)\leq (p_b^{-1}, t_1)$ such that $(X_{q_0, t^{\prime }_0}, X_{q_1, t^{\prime }_1})$ is incompatible with any element in $\mathcal {A}_{0,<\eta }$ , let $(Y^0_{\eta ,a}, Y^0_{\eta ,b})$ be one such $(X_{q_0, t^{\prime }_0}, X_{q_1, t^{\prime }_1})$ . Then we define $(X_{p^0_{\eta ,a}, r^0_{\eta ,a}}, X_{p^0_{\eta ,b}, r^0_{\eta ,b}})$ to be $\sigma (\langle \emptyset , (Y^0_{\eta ,a}, Y^0_{\eta ,b})\rangle )$ . Notice that this process must stop at some countable stage $\gamma _0<\omega _1$ since $\{(p^0_{i,a}, p^0_{i,b}): i<\gamma _0\}$ is an antichain in $Add(\omega , \lambda )\times Add(\omega ,\lambda )$ below $(p_a^{-1}, p_b^{-1})$ , which satisfies the countable chain condition. Let us verify all the properties are satisfied. Properties (1)–(4) and (6) are satisfied by the construction. Property (7) is not relevant at this stage. Property (5) is satisfied since we only stop when the process described above cannot be continued, which is exactly saying property (5) is satisfied.

In general, the definition of $\mathcal {A}_{n+1}$ is very similar to the construction above. Basically, for each $(C_0, C_1)\in \mathcal {A}_n$ , we repeat the process above with $(C_0,C_1)$ playing the role of $\mathcal {A}_{-1}$ . One difference, in order to satisfy property (6), is that at the beginning of the construction, we let $(h_0, h_1)$ be the lower bound in $R\times R$ for $\langle (r^n_{i,a}, r^n_{i,b}): i<\gamma _n\rangle $ and work below $((p_a^{-1}, h_0), (p_b^{-1}, h_1))$ in $\mathbb {M}(\omega ,\lambda )\times \mathbb {M}(\omega ,\lambda )$ .

Finally, to see that property (7) is satisfied, notice that any branch b through T corresponds to a play of the game $G_I$ where Player Empty is playing according to their winning strategy $\sigma $ . More precisely, b is the sequence of sets played by Player Empty according to $\sigma $ in a play of the game $G_I$ . As a result, the winning condition of Player Empty ensures (7) is satisfied.

Corollary 4.9 It is consistent that $\aleph _2\to _{hc}[\aleph _2]^2_{\omega ,2}$ and $2^{\aleph _0}\geq \aleph _2$ .

Proof Let $\kappa $ be a measurable cardinal. Then, in $V^{\mathbb {M}(\omega ,\kappa )}$ , $2^{\aleph _0}\geq \aleph _2$ and there is an ideal satisfying the hypothesis of Proposition 4.7 (see, for example, [Reference Cummings7, Theorem 23.2]). Apply Proposition 4.7 and Theorem 3.3.

5 $\sigma $ -closed ideals and monochromatic highly connected subgraphs

In this section, we prove the following theorem.

Theorem 5.1 Suppose that a regular cardinal $\kappa $ carries a countably complete uniform ideal I such that there exists a dense $\sigma $ -closed collection $H\subseteq I^+$ . Then $\kappa \to _{hc}(\kappa )^2_\omega $ . Moreover, $\kappa \to _{hc, <4}(\kappa )^2_\omega $ holds.

Fix an ideal I as in the hypothesis of Theorem 5.1. It is worth comparing such ideals with those of the previous section:

  • We do not insist that I is normal any more.

  • We impose the stronger requirement that the ideal has a $\sigma $ -closed dense subset; note that any such ideal is 2-precipitous.

Fix a coloring $c: [\kappa ]^2\to \omega $ . Given $B_0, B_1\in I^+$ and $i\in \omega $ , we say that $(B_0,B_1)$ is i-frequent if for any positive $B_0'\subseteq B_0$ and positive $B_1'\subseteq B_1$ , it is the case that $\{\alpha \in B_0': \{\beta \in B_1': c(\alpha ,\beta )=i\}\in I^+\}\in I^+$ .

Remark 5.2 Equivalently, $(B_0,B_1)$ is i-frequent if for any positive $B_1'\subseteq B_1$ , it is the case that $\{\alpha \in B_0: \{\beta \in B_1': c(\alpha ,\beta )=i\}\in I^+\}\in I^*\restriction B_0$ . See the argument in Claim 3.5.

Claim 5.3 There exist a positive $B\in I^+$ and $i\in \omega $ such that for any positive $B'\subseteq B$ , there are positive $B_0, B_1\subseteq B'$ such that $(B_0,B_1)$ is i-frequent.

In the following proof, to avoid repetitions, whenever we mention a positive set, we implicitly assume that the positive set is in the $\sigma $ -closed dense collection H.

Proof Suppose otherwise for the sake of contradiction. For $A\in I^+$ and $j\in \omega $ , let $(*)_{A,j}$ abbreviate the assertion: there are positive sets $B_0, B_1\subseteq A$ such that $(B_0, B_1)$ is j-frequent. By the hypothesis, we can recursively define $\langle B^{\prime }_k \in I^+: k\in \omega \rangle $ such that:

  • $B^{\prime }_0 = \kappa $ ,

  • for any $k\in \omega $ , $B^{\prime }_{k+1}\subseteq B^{\prime }_k$ and $\neg (*)_{B^{\prime }_{k+1},k}$ .

Let $B'=\bigcap _{k\in \omega } B^{\prime }_k$ . By the $\sigma $ -closure of I, we have that $B'\in I^+$ . Then it satisfies that for any $i\in \omega $ , such that there are no positive $B_0, B_1\subseteq B'$ such that $(B_0, B_1)$ is i-frequent.

Recursively construct an $\omega $ -sequence of pairs of I-positive sets

$$ \begin{align*}\langle (C_k,D_k): k\in \omega\rangle\end{align*} $$

as follows: start with $(B',B')=(C_{-1}, D_{-1})$ ; since it is not $0$ -frequent, there are positive $(C_0, D_0)$ such that for all $\alpha \in C_0$ , $\{\beta \in D_0: c(\alpha ,\beta )=0\}\in I$ . In general, as $(C_i, D_i)$ is not ( $i+1$ )-frequent, we can find $(C_{i+1}, D_{i+1})$ such that for all $\alpha \in C_i$ , $\{\beta \in D_i: c(\alpha ,\beta )=i+1\}\in I$ . Let $C^*=\bigcap _{i\in \omega } C_i$ and $D^*=\bigcap _{i\in \omega } D_i$ . By the $\sigma $ -closure of I, both $C^*$ and $D^*$ are in $I^+$ . By the $\sigma $ -completeness of the ideal, we can find some i and $\alpha \in C^*$ such that $\{\beta \in D^*: c(\alpha ,\beta )=i\}\in I^+$ . However, this contradicts with the assumption that $\alpha \in C_i$ .

To finish the proof of Theorem 5.1, by repeatedly applying Claim 5.3, we can find $\langle B_n\in I^+: n\in \omega \rangle $ and $i\in \omega $ such that for any $n<k$ , $(B_n, B_k)$ is i-frequent.

Given $n\in \omega $ , let $B_n^*\subseteq B_n$ be the collection of $\alpha \in B_n$ satisfying that for any $k>n$ , $\{\beta \in B_k: c(\alpha ,\beta )=i\}\in I^+$ . Notice that $B^*_n=_I B_n$ by Remark 5.2 and the fact that I is $\sigma $ -complete.

We claim that $B=\bigcup _{n\in \omega } B^*_n$ is highly connected in the color i. Given $\alpha <\beta \in B$ and $C\in [B]^{<\kappa }$ , there must be some $n_0, n_1 \in \omega $ such that $\alpha \in B^*_{n_0}$ and $\beta \in B^*_{n_1}$ . Find $k>\max \{n_0, n_1\}$ . By the hypothesis, $C_0=\{\gamma \in B_k^*: c(\alpha ,\gamma )=i\}\in I^+$ and $C_1=\{\gamma \in B_{k+1}^*: c(\beta ,\gamma )=i\}\in I^+$ . As $(B_k, B_{k+1})$ is i-frequent, we can find $\gamma _0\in C_0\setminus C$ and $\gamma _1\in C_1 \setminus C$ such that $c(\gamma _0, \gamma _1)=i$ . As a result, $\alpha , \gamma _0, \gamma _1, \beta $ is the required path of color i.

6 Remarks on the consistency of the ideal hypothesis

For regular cardinal $\lambda \geq \kappa $ , if $\kappa $ be $\lambda $ -supercompact, we show that in $V^{Coll(\omega _1, <\kappa )}$ , $\lambda $ carries a $\kappa $ -complete uniform ideal which admits a dense and $\sigma $ -closed collection of positive sets. The construction is due to Galvin, Jech, and Magidor [Reference Galvin, Jech and Magidor11] and, independently to Laver [Reference Laver17]. We supply a proof for the sake of completeness.

Let U be a fine normal ultrafilter on $P_{\kappa }\lambda $ . By a theorem of Solovay (see [Reference Hugh Woodin, Davis and Rodríguez13, Theorem 14] for a proof), there exists $B\in U$ such that $a\in B\mapsto \sup a$ is injective. Let $j: V\to M\simeq Ult(V, U)$ . Let $\delta =\sup j"\lambda $ . Let $G\subseteq Coll(\omega _1, <\kappa )$ be generic over V. It is well known that if $H\subseteq Coll(\omega _1,[\kappa , j(\kappa )))$ is generic over $V[G]$ , then we can lift j to $j^+: V[G]\to M[G*H]$ in $V[G*H]$ .

In $V[G]$ , consider the ideal

$$ \begin{align*}I=\{X\subseteq \lambda: \Vdash_{Coll(\omega_1, [\kappa,<j(\kappa)))} \delta \not\in j^+(X)\}.\end{align*} $$

The fact that I is $\kappa $ -complete and uniform is immediate. Let us show that there exists a dense $\sigma $ -closed collection of positive sets.

For each $r\in Coll(\omega _1, <j(\kappa ))^M/G$ , there exists a function $f_r: B\to P$ such that $j(f_r)(j" \lambda )=r$ . Define $X_r=\{\sup a: a\in B, f_r(a)\in G\}$ .

Claim 6.1 $X_r\in I^+$ .

Proof It suffices to check that $r\Vdash \delta \in j^+(X_r)$ . Let $H\subseteq Coll(\omega _1, <j(\kappa ))^M/G$ containing r be generic over $V[G]$ , then we can lift j to $j^+: V[G]\to M[H]$ . In particular, $H=j^+(G)$ . Since $j(f_r)(j"\lambda )=r\in j^+(G)$ , we have that $\delta \in j^+(X_r)$ .

Claim 6.2 $X_r\subseteq _I X_{r'}$ iff $r\leq _{Coll(\omega _1, <j(\kappa ))^M/G} r'$ .

Proof If $r\leq r'$ , then it is clear that $X_r\subseteq _I X_{r'}$ . For the other direction, suppose for the sake of contradiction that $r\not \leq _{Coll(\omega _1, <j(\kappa ))^M/G} r'$ . In particular, there is some extension $r^*$ of r that is incompatible with $r'$ . Then $r^*\Vdash \delta \in j^+(X_r)\setminus j^+(X_{r'})$ . Hence, $X_{r}\not \subseteq _I X_{r'}$ .

As a result,

$$ \begin{align*}\{X_r: r\in Coll(\omega_1, <j(\kappa))^M/G\}\end{align*} $$

is $\sigma $ -closed, since $ Coll(\omega _1, <j(\kappa ))^M/G$ is $\sigma $ -closed in $V[G]$ .

Claim 6.3 For any $X\in I^+$ , there exists some r such that $X_r\subseteq _I X$ .

Proof Let $r\in Coll(\omega _1, <j(\kappa ))^M/G$ force that $\delta \in j^+(X)$ . We show that $X_r\subseteq _{I} X$ . Otherwise, there is some $r'$ forcing that $\delta \in j^+(X_r)\setminus j^+(X)$ . In particular, $r'$ forces that $j(f_r)(j"\lambda )=r\in j^+(G)$ . By the separability of the forcing, $r'\leq _{Coll(\omega _1, <j(\kappa ))^M/G} r$ . This contradicts the fact that r forces $\delta \in j^+(X)$ .

The following is now immediate from the preceding arguments, coupled with Theorem 5.1.

Theorem 6.4

  1. (1) If $\kappa $ is measurable, then in $V^{Coll(\omega _1, <\kappa )}$ , $\aleph _2\to _{hc}(\aleph _2)^2_{\omega }$ .

  2. (2) If $\kappa $ is supercompact, then in $V^{Coll(\omega _1, <\kappa )}$ , for all regular cardinal $\lambda \geq \aleph _2$ , $\lambda \to _{hc}(\lambda )^2_{\omega }$ .

Some large cardinal assumption is necessary to establish the consistency of $\kappa \to _{hc}(\kappa )^2_{\omega }$ , as shown in [Reference Lambie-Hanson16].

7 The lengths of the paths

In Section 5, we have shown that if there exists a $\sigma $ -complete uniform ideal on $\omega _2$ admitting a $\sigma $ -closed collection of dense positive sets, then $\omega _2\to _{hc, <4} (\omega _2)^2_\omega $ . One natural question is whether we can improve the conclusion to $\omega _2\to _{hc, <3} (\omega _2)^2_\omega $ . In this section, we show that the answer is no, at least not from the same hypothesis.

Remark 7.1 If there is a $\sigma $ -closed forcing P such that in $V^P$ , there is a transitive class M and an elementary embedding $j: V\to M$ with critical point $\kappa $ , then $\kappa \to _{hc}(\kappa )^2_\omega $ holds. Essentially the same proof from Section 5 works.

Theorem 7.2 It is consistent relative to the existence of a measurable cardinal that $\aleph _2\to _{hc, <4} (\aleph _2)^2_\omega $ but $\aleph _2\not \to _{hc, <3} (\aleph _2)^2_\omega $ .

Proof Let $\kappa $ be a measurable cardinal. We will make use of a forcing poset $\mathbb {P}_{\kappa }$ due to Komjáth and Shelah [Reference Komjáth and Shelah15, Theorem 7]. The final forcing will be $Coll(\omega _1, <\kappa )* \mathbb {P}_{\kappa }$ . It follows from Komjáth and Shelah’s work that $\aleph _2\not \to _{hc, <3} (\aleph _2)^2_\omega $ in the final model. More specifically, this was proved in Claim 4 inside the proof of Theorem 7 of [Reference Komjáth and Shelah15]. Note that $(*)$ in [Reference Komjáth and Shelah15] is a consequence of $\aleph _2\to _{hc, <3} (\aleph _2)^2_\omega $ .

Let $G\subseteq Coll(\omega _1, <\kappa )* \mathbb {P}_{\kappa }$ be a generic filter over V. By Remark 7.1 applied in $V[G]$ (namely, replacing the occurrences of “V” there with “ $V[G]$ ”), it is enough to check that in a further countably closed forcing extension over $V[G]$ , there exists an elementary embedding $j: V[G]\to M$ with critical point $\omega _2^{V[G]}=\kappa $ .

To that end, let us recall the definition of $\mathbb {P}_\kappa $ : conditions consist of $(S, f, \mathcal {H}, h)$ such that:

  • $S\in [\kappa ]^{\leq \aleph _0}$ ,

  • $f: [S]^2\to [\omega ]^\omega $ ,

  • $\mathcal {H}\subseteq [S]^\omega $ , $|\mathcal {H}|\leq \aleph _0$ , for each $H\in \mathcal {H}$ , $otp(H)=\omega $ and for any $H, H'\in \mathcal {H}$ , $H\cap H'$ is finite,

  • if $\alpha \in S$ , $H\in \mathcal {H}$ with $\min H < \alpha $ , then $|\{\beta \in H: h(H)\in f(\alpha ,\beta )\}|\leq 1$ .

The order is: $(S', f', \mathcal {H}', h')\leq (S, f, \mathcal {H}, h)$ iff $S'\supset S$ , $\mathcal {H}'\supset \mathcal {H}$ , $f'\restriction [S]^2 = f$ , $h'\restriction \mathcal {H} = h$ and for any $H\in \mathcal {H}'-\mathcal {H}$ , $H\not \subseteq S$ . Note that $\mathbb {P}_\kappa $ is a countably closed forcing of size $\kappa $ .

Let $j: V\to M$ witness that $\kappa $ is measurable. Let $G*H\subseteq Coll(\omega _1,<\kappa )*\mathbb {P}_\kappa $ . Let $G^*\subseteq Coll(\omega _1, <j(\kappa ))/G*H$ be generic over $V[G*H]$ . This is possible since $Coll(\omega _1,<\kappa )*\mathbb {P}_\kappa $ regularly embeds into $Coll(\omega _1, <j(\kappa ))$ with a countably closed quotient (see [Reference Cummings7, Theorem 14.3]). As a result, we can lift $j: V[G]\to M[G^*]$ . In order to lift further to $V[G*H]$ , we need to force $j(\mathbb {P}_\kappa )/H$ over $V[G^*]$ . It suffices to show that in $V[G^*]$ , $j(\mathbb {P}_\kappa )/H$ is countably closed.

Suppose $\langle p_n=_{def} (S_n, f_n, \mathcal {H}_n, h_n): n\in \omega \rangle \subseteq j(\mathbb {P}_\kappa )/H$ is a decreasing sequence. We want to show that $q=\bigcup _{n\in \omega } p_n$ is the lower bound desired. For this, we only need to verify that $q\in j(\mathbb {P}_\kappa )/H$ . More explicitly, we need to verify that q is compatible with $h\in H$ for any $h\in H$ . For each $p=(S_p,f_p,\mathcal {H}_p, h_p)\in j(\mathbb {P}_\kappa )$ , let $p\restriction \kappa $ denote the condition: $(S_p\cap \kappa , f_p\restriction [S_p\cap \kappa ]^2, \mathcal {H}_p\cap P(\kappa ), h_p\restriction (\mathcal {H}_p\cap P(\kappa )))$ . It is not hard to check that $p\restriction \kappa \in \mathbb {P}_\kappa $ and $p\leq _{j(\mathbb {P}_\kappa )} p\restriction \kappa $ .

Claim 7.3 $p\in j(\mathbb {P}_\kappa )/H$ iff $p\restriction \kappa \in H$ .

Proof of the claim

If $p\restriction \kappa \in H$ , to see $p\in j(\mathbb {P}_\kappa )/H$ , it suffices to see that for any $r\leq _{\mathbb {P}_\kappa } p\restriction \kappa $ and $r\in H$ , r is compatible with p. To check that $r\cup p$ can be extended to a condition, it suffices to check that for any $B\in \mathcal {H}_r\setminus \mathcal {H}_p$ , $B\not \subseteq S_p$ and for any $B\in \mathcal {H}_p\setminus \mathcal {H}_r$ , $B\not \subseteq S_r$ . To see the former, note that if $B\in \mathcal {H}_r\setminus \mathcal {H}_p$ , then $B\in \mathcal {H}_r \setminus \mathcal {H}_{p\restriction \kappa }$ , since $r\leq p\restriction \kappa $ , $B\not \subseteq S_p\cap \kappa $ . Since $B\subseteq \kappa $ , we have $B\not \subseteq S_p$ . To see the latter, note that $B\in \mathcal {H}_p\setminus \mathcal {H}_r$ implies that $B\in \mathcal {H}_p \setminus \mathcal {H}_{p\restriction \kappa }$ . In particular, $B\cap [\kappa ,j(\kappa ))\neq \emptyset $ . Hence, $B\not \subseteq S_r$ since $S_r\subseteq \kappa $ .

If $p\in j(\mathbb {P}_\kappa )/H$ , then for any $h\in H$ , h and p are compatible. In particular, since $p\leq p\restriction \kappa $ , we know that any $h\in H$ is compatible with $p\restriction \kappa $ . This implies that $p\restriction \kappa \in H$ .

To finish the proof, since for each $n\in \omega $ , by Claim 7.3 and the fact that $p_n\in j(\mathbb {P}_\kappa )/H$ , we have that $p_n\restriction \kappa \in H$ . As a result, we must have $q\restriction \kappa \in H$ . By Claim 7.3, we have $q\in j(\mathbb {P}_\kappa )/H$ .

8 Open questions

Question 8.1 Starting from the existence of a weakly compact cardinal, can one force that $\aleph _2\to _{hc}(\aleph _2)^2_{\omega }$ ?

It is possible to use a weaker assumption than the existence of a measurable cardinal to run the proof of Theorem 5.1. In particular, we can use a strongly Ramsey cardinal instead. Recall that $\kappa $ is strongly Ramsey if for any $A\subset \kappa $ , there is a $\kappa $ -model M containing A (namely, M is a transitive model of $\mathrm {ZFC}^-$ containing $\kappa $ and is closed under $<\kappa $ -sequences), such that there exists a $\kappa $ -complete M-ultrafilter that is weakly amenable to M, meaning that for any $\mathcal {F}\in M$ and $|\mathcal {F}|\leq \kappa $ , $\mathcal {F}\cap U \in M$ . See [Reference Gitman12] for more information on Ramsey-like cardinals. However, being a strongly Ramsey cardinal is a much stronger condition than being a weakly compact cardinal.

Question 8.2 Is $\aleph _2\to _{hc,<3} (\aleph _2)^2_{\omega }$ consistent?

Question 8.3 Can one separate $\aleph _2\to _{hc,<m} (\aleph _2)^2_{\omega }$ from $\aleph _2\to _{hc,<n} (\aleph _2)^2_{\omega }$ where $4\leq m<n\leq \omega $ ?

Question 8.4 Is $\aleph _2\not \to _{hc}(\aleph _1)^2_{\omega }$ consistent?

Our next problem is more open-ended, which concerns the natural generalizations of $2$ -precipitous ideals. Recall that we have shown that the existence of a uniform normal $2$ -precipitous ideal on $\kappa $ implies that $\kappa \geq \omega _2$ .

Problem 8.5 For $n\geq 2$ and an ideal I on $\kappa \geq \aleph _2$ , find a natural definition of n-precipitousness that generalizes Definition 3.1 in the case that $n=2$ , such that if $\kappa $ carries a uniform normal n-precipitous ideal, then $\kappa \geq \aleph _n$ .

The referee suggested the following interesting problem, which is worth further investigation. Fix cardinals $\kappa ,\lambda ,\theta $ and an ideal $\mathcal {J}$ on $\lambda $ containing $[\lambda ]^{<\lambda }$ . For any set X of order type $\lambda $ , let $\mathcal {J}_X$ be the ideal on X moved from $\mathcal {J}$ using the order isomorphism between X and $\lambda $ .

Problem 8.6 Investigate the following partition relations: $\kappa \to _{\mathcal {J}-hc}(\lambda )^2_\theta $ which asserts that for any $c: [\kappa ]^2\to \theta $ , there are $X\subset \kappa $ of order type $\lambda $ and $i\in \theta $ such that for any $J\in \mathcal {J}_X$ , $(X\setminus J, c^{-1}(i)\cap [X\setminus J]^2)$ is connected.

Acknowledgments

We thank Stevo Todorcevic and Spencer Unger for helpful discussions and comments. We are grateful to the anonymous referee, whose helpful suggestions, corrections, and comments greatly improve the exposition of this paper.

Footnotes

Research of the first author was partially supported by a PAPIIT grant IN101323 and CONACyT grant A1-S-16164. Research of the second author was partially supported by the NSF grant DMS 1833363 and by the Israel Science Foundation (ISF) grant 1838/19. Research of the third author was supported by the European Research Council (Grant Agreement No. ERC-2018-StG 802756) and NSERC grants RGPIN-2019-04311, RGPIN-2021-03549, and RGPIN-2016-06541. The paper appears as number 1242 on the second author’s publications list.

1 Originally, we used the hypothesis that $\omega _1$ carries a countably complete $\aleph _2$ -Knaster ideal. Stevo Todorcevic pointed out that our proof should work from a weaker saturation hypothesis, such as $\aleph _2$ -saturation.

2 We thank Spencer Unger for his suggestion on the relevance of the Mitchell collapse.

References

Abraham, U., Aronszajn trees on  ${\aleph}_2$  and  ${\aleph}_3$ . Ann. Pure Appl. Logic 24(1983), no. 3, 213230.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bannister, N., Bergfalk, J., Moore, J. T., and Todorcevic, S., A descriptive approach to higher derived limits. Journal of European Mathematical Society, to appear, 2023. arXiv:2203.00165 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bergfalk, J., Ramsey theory for monochromatically well-connected subsets . Fund. Math. 249(2020), no. 1, 95103.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bergfalk, J., Hrušák, M., and Lambie-Hanson, C., Simultaneously vanishing higher derived limits without large cardinals . J. Math. Log. 23(2023), no. 1, Article no. 2250019, 40 pp.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bergfalk, J., Hrušák, M., and Shelah, S., Ramsey theory for highly connected monochromatic subgraphs . Acta Math. Hungar. 163(2021), no. 1, 309322.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bergfalk, J. and Lambie-Hanson, C., Simultaneously vanishing higher derived limits . Forum Math. Pi 9(2021), Article no. E4, 31 pp.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cummings, J., Iterated forcing and elementary embeddings . In: Handbook of set theory, Vols. 1–3, Springer, Dordrecht, 2010, pp. 775883.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Erdős, P. and Hajnal, A., On complete topological subgraphs of certain graphs . Ann. Univ. Sci. Budapest. Eötvös Sect. Math. 7(1964), 143149.Google Scholar
Foreman, M., Ideals and generic elementary embeddings . In: Handbook of set theory. Vols. 1–3, Springer, Dordrecht, 2010, pp. 8851147.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Foreman, M., Magidor, M., and Shelah, S., Martin’s maximum, saturated ideals, and nonregular ultrafilters I . Ann. Math. 127(1988), no. 1, 147.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Galvin, F., Jech, T., and Magidor, M., An ideal game . J. Symb. Log. 43(1978), no. 2, 284292.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gitman, V., Ramsey-like cardinals . J. Symb. Log. 76(2011), no. 2, 519540.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hugh Woodin, W., Davis, J., and Rodríguez, D., The HOD dichotomy . In: Appalachian set theory: 2006–2012, London Mathematical Society Lecture Note Series, 406, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2013, pp. 397418.Google Scholar
Jech, T. and Prikry, K., On ideals of sets and the power set operation . Bull. Amer. Math. Soc. 82(1976), no. 4, 593595.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Komjáth, P. and Shelah, S., Monocolored topological complete graphs in colorings of uncountable complete graphs . Acta Math. Hungar. 163(2021), no. 1, 7184.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lambie-Hanson, C., A note on highly connected and well-connected Ramsey theory. Fundamenta Mathematicae. 260(2023), no. 2, 181197.Google Scholar
Laver, R., Precipitousness in forcing extensions . Israel J. Math. 48(1984), nos. 2–3, 97108.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mitchell, W., Aronszajn trees and the independence of the transfer property . Ann. Math. Logic 5(1972/73), 2146.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Veličković, B. and Vignati, A., Non-vanishing higher derived limits. Communications in Contemporary Mathematics, to appear 2023. https://doi.org/10.1142/S0219199723500311CrossRefGoogle Scholar