Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-gxg78 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-28T07:57:58.408Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Let Us Assume That Gene Editing is Safe—The Role of Safety Arguments in the Gene Editing Debate

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  20 December 2018

Abstract:

This paper provides an analysis of the statement, made in many papers and reports on the use of gene editing in humans, that we should only use the technology when it is safe. It provides an analysis of what the statement means in the context of nonreproductive and reproductive gene editing and argues that the statement is inconsistent with the philosophical commitments of some of the authors, who put it forward in relation to reproductive uses of gene editing, specifically their commitment to Parfitian nonidentity considerations and to a legal principle of reproductive liberty.

But, if that is true it raises a question about why the statement is made. What is its discursive and rhetorical function? Five functions are suggested, some of which are more contentious and problematic than others. It is argued that it is possible, perhaps even likely, that the “only when it is safe” rider is part of a deliberate obfuscation aimed at hiding the full implications of the arguments made about the ethics of gene editing and their underlying philosophical justifications.

Type
Special Section: Genome Editing: Biomedical and Ethical Perspectives
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2018 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Notes

1. Chan, S, Donovan, PJ, Douglas, T, Gyngell, C, Harris, J, Lovell-Badge, R, et al. [on behalf of the Hinxton Group]. Genome editing technologies and human germline genetic modification: The Hinxton Group Consensus Statement. The American Journal of Bioethics 2015;15(12):42–7.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

2. Mathews, DJ, Chan, S, Donovan, PJ, Douglas, T, Gyngell, C, Harris, J, et al. CRISPR: A path through the thicket. Nature News 2015;527(7577):159–61.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

3. Savulescu, J, Pugh, J, Douglas, T, Gyngell, C. The moral imperative to continue gene editing research on human embryos. Protein & cell 2015;6(7):476–9.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

4. Bosley, KS, Botchan, M, Bredenoord, AL, Carroll, D, Charo, RA, Charpentier, E, et al. CRISPR germline engineering—the community speaks. Nature Biotechnology 2015;33(5):478.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

5. Brokowski, C. Do CRISPR germline ethics statements cut it? The CRISPR Journal 2018;1(2):115–25.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

6. See note 1, Chan et al. 2015.

7. See note 3, Savulescu, Pugh, Douglas, Gyngell 2015.

8. Haapaniemi, E, Botla, S, Persson, J, Schmierer, B, Taipale, J. CRISPR–Cas9 genome editing induces a p53-mediated DNA damage response. Nature Medicine 2018;24:927–30.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

9. Ihry, RJ, Worringer, KA, Salick, MR, Frias, E, Ho, D, Theriault, K, et al. p53 inhibits CRISPR–Cas9 engineering in human pluripotent stem cells. Nature Medicine 2018;24:939–46.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

10. Bunnik, EM, Aarts, N, van de Vathorst, S. Little to lose and no other options: Ethical issues in efforts to facilitate expanded access to investigational drugs. Health Policy 2018;122:977–83.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

11. DeTora, L. The dangers of magical thinking: Situating right to try laws, patient rights, and the language of advocacy. Rhetoric of Health & Medicine 2018;24;1(1-2):3757.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

12. Folkers, KM, Bateman-House, A. Improving expanded access in the United States: The role of the institutional review board. Therapeutic Innovation & Regulatory Science 2018;52(3):285–93.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

13. Benatar, D, Wasserman, D. Debating Procreation – Is it wrong to Reproduce? New York: Oxford University Press; 2015.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

14. Parfit, D. Reasons and Persons. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 1985.Google Scholar

15. Harris, J. One principle and three fallacies of disability studies. Journal of Medical Ethics 2001;27(6):383–7.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

16. Savulescu, J. Bioethics: Why philosophy is essential for progress. Journal of Medical Ethics 2015;41(1):2833.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

17. Bredenoord, AL, Dondorp, W, Pennings, G, De Wert, G. Nuclear transfer to prevent mitochondrial DNA disorders: Revisiting the debate on reproductive cloning. Reproductive Biomedicine Online 2011;22(2):200–7.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

18. Holm, S. Mitochondrial replacement therapy and identity: A comment on an exchange between Inmaculada de Melo-Martin and John Harris. Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 2018;27(3):487–91.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

19. Robertson, JA. Procreative liberty and the control of conception, pregnancy, and childbirth. Virginia Law Review 1983;69(3):405–64, at 408.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

20. Harris, J. Is there a coherent social conception of disability? Journal of Medical Ethics 2000;26(2):95100.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

21. Savulescu, J, Kahane, G. The moral obligation to create children with the best chance of the best life. Bioethics 2009;23(5):274–90.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

22. Bennett, R. The fallacy of the principle of procreative ceneficence. Bioethics 2009;23(5):265–73.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

23. Bennett, R. When intuition is not enough: Why the principle of procreative beneficence must work much harder to justify its eugenic vision. Bioethics 2014;28(9):447–55.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

24. Holm, S, Bennett, R. The proper scope of the principle of procreative beneficence revisited. Monash Bioethics Review 2014;32(1-2):2232.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

25. See note 21, Savulescu, Kahane 2009, at 278.

26. See note 21, Savulescu, Kahane 2009, at 279.

27. See note 21, Savulescu, Kahane 2009.

28. Mill, JS. Introductory. In: Rapaport, E, ed. On Liberty. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishers; 1978, at 9.Google Scholar

29. Beck, U. Risk society: Towards a new modernity. London: Sage; 1992.Google Scholar

30. Oswald, M. Should policy ethics come in two colours: Green or white? Journal of Medical Ethics 2013;39(5):312–5.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

31. Holm, S. The grand leap of the whale up the Niagara Falls: Converting philosophical conclusions into policy prescriptions. Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 2015;24(2):195203.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed