No CrossRef data available.
Published online by Cambridge University Press: 20 December 2018
1. Rakic V. Genome editing for involuntary moral enhancement. In this issue of Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics.
2. Douglas, T. Moral enhancement. Journal of Applied Philosophy 2008;25:228–45.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
3. See note 2, Douglas 2008, at 228.
4. See note 2, Douglas 2008, at 228.
5. Persson, I, Savulescu, J. Unfit for the Future: The Need for Moral Enhancement. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 2012, at 46.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
6. Persson, I, Savulescu, J. Moral enhancement, freedom and the God Machine. The Monist 2012;95(3):399–21.Google Scholar
7. Harris, J. Moral enhancement and freedom. Bioethics 2011;25:102–11.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
8. Agar, N. Moral bioenhancement is dangerous. Journal of Medical Ethics 2015;41:343–5.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
9. See note 5, Persson 2012.
10. Agar, N. Moral bioenhancement and the utilitarian catastrophe. Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 2015;24:37–47.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
11. See Corruption Perceptions Index 2017; available at https://www.transparency.org/news/feature/corruption_perceptions_index_2017 (last accessed 27 Sept 2018).
12. See Agar, N. Liberal Eugenics: In Defence of Human Enhancement. Oxford: Blackwell; 2004CrossRefGoogle Scholar for my interpretation of the scope and significance of procreative freedom in respect of choices about our children’s genetic makeups.