1 Introduction
1.1 Motivation
In this paper, we initiate a study of various aspects and forms of club guessing. Our definitions are quite general, and in order to motivate them we start with a brief survey of the various forms of club guessing that have appeared in the literature as well as their applications. All undefined notation can be found in Section 1.4, but we remind the reader right away that for a pair $\lambda < \kappa $ of infinite regular cardinals, $E^\kappa _\lambda := \{\delta < \kappa \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \operatorname {\mathrm {cf}}(\delta ) = \lambda \}$ , and $E^\kappa _{\neq \lambda }:= \{\delta < \kappa \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \operatorname {\mathrm {cf}}(\delta ) \neq \lambda \}$ .
Shortly after Jensen constructed Souslin trees in L [Reference Jensen34], he isolated a combinatorial principle named diamond, which is sufficient for the construction.
Fact 1.1 [Reference Jensen35].
In Gödel’s constructible universe L, for every regular uncountable cardinal $\kappa $ and every stationary $S\subseteq \kappa $ , there is a sequence $\vec A=\langle A_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle $ which is a $\diamondsuit (S)$ -sequence, that is $:$
-
(i) for every $\delta \in S$ , $A_\delta $ is a subset of $\delta ;$
-
(ii) for every subset $A \subseteq \kappa $ , the set $\{\delta \in S \ {\mathrel {|}}\ A_\delta =A\cap \delta \}$ is stationary in $\kappa $ .
It is easy to see that for $S\subseteq \kappa $ as above, $\diamondsuit (S)$ implies that $2^{<\kappa } = \kappa $ , and hence diamond is not a consequence of $\textsf{{ZFC}}$ . In contrast, the following result of Shelah [Reference Shelah, Gabbay, Macintyre and Scott62], which is the most well-known club guessing result, is a theorem of $\textsf{{ZFC}}$ .
Fact 1.2 [Reference Shelah, Gabbay, Macintyre and Scott62].
Suppose that $\lambda < \lambda ^+ < \kappa $ are infinite regular cardinals. Then there is a sequence $\vec C=\langle C_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in E^\kappa _\lambda \rangle $ such that $:$
-
(i) for every $\delta \in E^\kappa _\lambda $ , $C_\delta $ is a club in $\delta ;$
-
(ii) for every club $D \subseteq \kappa $ , the set $\{\delta \in S \ {\mathrel {|}}\ C_\delta \subseteq D\}$ is stationary in $\kappa $ .
In particular, unlike the $\diamondsuit $ principle or its descendants the $\clubsuit $ and principles (see [Reference Broverman, Ginsburg, Kunen and Tall12, Reference Ostaszewski46]), the focus is not on predicting arbitrary or even just cofinal subsets of $\kappa $ , but rather only the closed and unbounded subsets of $\kappa $ . This makes the task of guessing easier, since the collection of club subsets of $\kappa $ generate a normal $\kappa $ -complete filter.
The most famous application of Fact 1.2 is Shelah’s PCF bound (see [Reference Shelah, Gabbay, Macintyre and Scott61] or [Reference Abraham, Magidor, Foreman and Kanamori1, Theorem 7.3]):
Apart from upper bounds on cardinal exponentiation, Fact 1.2 has many other uses in PCF theory. As an example from the basic theory, in obtaining exact upper bounds for sequences of ordinal functions (see [Reference Abraham, Magidor, Foreman and Kanamori1, Lemma 2.19]), in fact showing that there are stationary sets consisting of points of large cofinality in the approachability ideal $I[\lambda ]$ (see [Reference Eisworth, Foreman and Kanamori15, Section 3]). Outside of PCF theory, there are applications of Fact 1.2 to the universality spectrum of models [Reference Dzamonja13, Reference Kojman and Shelah37, Reference Shelah73], cardinal invariants of the continuum [Reference Zapletal84, Reference Zapletal85], cardinal invariants at uncountable cardinals [Reference Blass, Hyttinen and Zhang6, Reference Guzmán, Hrušák and Zapletal22], to the study of the Boolean algebra $\operatorname {\mathrm {P}}(\lambda )/[\lambda ]^{<\lambda }$ for $\lambda $ singular of countable cofinality [Reference Kojman and Shelah39], to showing the incompactness of chromatic number [Reference Shelah72], to obtain a refinement of the downwards Löwenheim–Skolem Theorem [Reference Foreman and Todorčević20], to study the saturation of the non-stationary ideal on $\operatorname {\mathrm {P}}_\lambda (\kappa )$ [Reference Shioya76], to obtain two-cardinal diamond principles in $\textsf{{ZFC}}$ [Reference Matet43, Reference Shelah74, Reference Shioya, Chong, Feng, Slaman, Woodin and Yang77, Reference Todorčević and Thomas79], to obtaining consequence of forcing axioms [Reference Shelah70], to obtain limitative results on forcing [Reference Rosłanowski and Shelah60, Reference Todorčević81], to constructing graphs with a prescribed rate of growth of the chromatic number of its finite subgraphs [Reference Lambie-Hanson40]. That Fact 1.2 is a theorem of $\textsf{{ZFC}}$ also imposes important limitations on the theory of forcing axioms at successors of uncountable cardinals (see, for example, [Reference Neeman45, Reference Shelah67, Reference Shelah68]).
While club guessing was motivated by finding a weak substitute for the diamond principle, in [Reference Shelah71], Shelah, using arguments that materialized through the development of the theory of club guessing, proved the next theorem on diamond, concluding a 40-year-old search for such a result (see the review in [Reference Rinot48]).
Fact 1.3 [Reference Shelah71].
Let $\lambda $ be an uncountable cardinal, and let $S \subseteq E^{\lambda ^+}_{\neq \operatorname {\mathrm {cf}}(\lambda )}$ be stationary. The following are equivalent $:$
-
(1) $2^\lambda = \lambda ^+;$
-
(2) $\diamondsuit (S)$ .
Apart from Fact 1.2, there are other, finer, forms of club guessing which are less well-known and yet altogether have a variety of applications. For instance, Fact 1.2 says nothing about the case $\kappa =\lambda ^+$ . For this, we have the following result of Shelah.
Fact 1.4 [Reference Shelah, Gabbay, Macintyre and Scott62, Claim 2.4].
There is a sequence $\vec C\hspace{-1pt}=\hspace{-1pt}\langle C_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta\hspace{-1pt} \in\hspace{-1pt} E^{\aleph _2}_{\aleph _1}\rangle $ such that:
-
(i) for every $\delta \in E^{\aleph _2}_{\aleph _1}$ , $C_\delta $ is a club in $\delta $ of ordertype $\omega _1;$
-
(ii) for every club $D \subseteq \aleph _2$ , there is a $\delta \in E^{\aleph _2}_{\aleph _1}$ such that the following set is cofinal in $\delta$ :
$$ \begin{align*}\{\beta <\delta \ {\mathrel{|}}\ \min(C_\delta \setminus (\beta+1)) \in D \cap E^{\aleph_2}_{\aleph_1}\}.\end{align*} $$
To compare the preceding with Fact 1.2, we see two differences in the corresponding Clause (ii). The first, here we require a single $\delta $ instead of stationarily many, however, this is easily seen to be equivalent.Footnote 1 Second, which is more important, instead of requiring $C_\delta $ to be a subset of D, we now merely require that the intersection of D with ( $E^{\aleph _2}_{\aleph _1}$ and) the set $\operatorname {\mathrm {nacc}}(C_\delta )$ of all non-accumulation points of $C_\delta $ to be cofinal in $\delta $ . This choice is not arbitrary. For club many $\delta \in E^{\aleph _2}_{\aleph _1}$ , both the set $\operatorname {\mathrm {acc}}(C_\delta )$ of all accumulation points of $C_\delta $ and the set $D\cap \delta $ are clubs in $\delta $ , and hence $\operatorname {\mathrm {acc}}(C_\delta )\cap D$ is trivially cofinal in $\delta $ .
Consider now another example due to Shelah concerning the case $\kappa =\lambda ^+$ (see [Reference Soukup and Soukup78], for a short proof):
Fact 1.5 [Reference Shelah66, Claim 3.5].
There is a sequence $\vec C=\langle C_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in E^{\aleph _2}_{\aleph _1}\rangle $ such that $:$
-
(i) for every $\delta \in E^{\aleph _2}_{\aleph _1}$ , $C_\delta $ is a club in $\delta $ of ordertype $\omega _1;$
-
(ii) for every club $D \subseteq \aleph _2$ , there is a $\delta \in E^{\aleph _2}_{\aleph _1}$ such that the following set is stationary in $\delta :$
$$ \begin{align*}\{\beta <\delta \ {\mathrel{|}}\ \min(C_\delta \setminus (\beta+1)) \in D\}.\end{align*} $$
Comparing the two, we see that Fact 1.4 features a sequence where the guessing is measured against the ideal $J^{\mathrm {bd}}[\delta ]$ of bounded subsets of $\delta $ , whereas here we measure against the nonstationary ideal $\mathrm{NS}_\delta $ . However, Fact 1.4 features a sequence which guesses clubs relative to the set $E^{\aleph _2}_{\aleph _1}$ , and for this reason the two results are incomparable. In this paper, a join of the two results is obtained.
Note that so far we have always required that the clubs $C_\delta $ have the minimal possible ordertype of $\operatorname {\mathrm {cf}}(\delta )$ . The small ordertype requirement is trivially gotten for a sequence that guesses as in Clause (ii) of Fact 1.2. In other cases, however, obtaining that the local clubs have a small ordertype requires extra care (see, for example, [Reference Kojman36, Theorem 9], where the weaker form of Fact 1.4 is proved where one requires each of the $C_\delta $ to merely have size $\aleph _1$ ). As a sample application, we mention that in [Reference Hernández-Hernández and Szeptycki23], a strong form of club guessing at $\aleph _1$ with minimal ordertype is used to construct a small Dowker space.
However, attention should not be restricted only to guessing with minimal ordertypes. At the level of $\aleph _1$ , the ordertypes of guessing sequences play a crucial role in separating forcing axioms at $\aleph _1$ in [Reference Shelah64, Chapter XVII], and later in [Reference Asperó, Friedman, Mota and Sabok3] as well. At higher cardinals, guessing sequences $\vec C$ with very large ordertypes are useful for getting a pathological graph $G(\vec C)$ with maximal chromatic number [Reference Rinot53]. An open question concerning guessing sequences of maximal ordertype is stated in [Reference Rinot52, Question 2]. For an extended discussion, see the introduction to [Reference Rinot54].
At a cardinal $\kappa $ that is a limit or a successor of a limit, another type of relative club guessing has shown to be useful, where the guessing feature stipulates additional conditions on the sequence $\langle \operatorname {\mathrm {cf}}(\gamma ) \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \gamma \in \operatorname {\mathrm {nacc}}(C_\delta ) \rangle $ . In [Reference Hoffman25, Reference Shelah, Gabbay, Macintyre and Scott62], the additional condition is that this sequence is strictly increasing and converging to $|\delta |$ . This is used to construct colourings satisfying strong negative square bracket partition relations [Reference Eisworth and Shelah17, Reference Eisworth and Shelah18]. An earlier construction (see [Reference Shelah, Gabbay, Macintyre and Scott62] or [Reference Eisworth, Foreman and Kanamori15, Theorem 5.19]) requires that the sequence $\langle \operatorname {\mathrm {cf}}(\gamma ) \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \gamma \in \operatorname {\mathrm {nacc}}(C_\delta ) \rangle $ have cofinally many cardinals carrying a Jónsson algebra. This is used to construct Jónsson algebras at $\kappa $ . Note that the existence of a club guessing sequence of large ordertypes in $\textsf{{ZFC}}$ would give rise to such sequences, in particular, solving [Reference Eisworth and Shelah18, Question 2.4] in the affirmative.
We move on to the next example, this time a question of Shelah.
Question 1.6 [Reference Shelah65, Question 5.4].
Let $\lambda < \lambda ^+ = \kappa $ be regular uncountable cardinals. Is there a sequence $\vec C=\langle C_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in E^\kappa _\lambda \rangle $ such that:
-
(i) for every $\delta \in E^\kappa _\lambda $ , $C_\delta $ is a club in $\delta $ of ordertype $\lambda $ ;
-
(ii) for every club $D \subseteq \kappa $ , there is a $\delta \in E^\kappa _\lambda $ such that the following set is stationary in $\delta $ :
$$ \begin{align*}\{\beta <\delta \ {\mathrel{|}}\ \beta_1, \beta_2 \in D,\text{ where }\beta_1&:=\min(C_\delta \setminus(\beta+1))\ \&\\ \beta_2&:=\min(C_\delta \setminus (\beta_1+1))\}.\end{align*} $$
Compared to Fact 1.5, here we require that for stationarily many $\beta < \delta $ , two consecutive non-accumulation points following $\beta $ are in the club D. Shelah mentions (without proof) that this slight strengthening of Fact 1.5 combined with $\textsf{{GCH}}$ allows for the construction of a $\kappa $ -Souslin tree. This is related to the open problem of whether $\textsf{{GCH}}$ implies the existence of an $\aleph _2$ -Souslin tree (see [Reference Rinot56]), and the earlier work of Kojman and Shelah on that matter [Reference Kojman and Shelah38].
Here we shall prove that at the level of $\aleph _2$ , an affirmative answer to Shelah’s question follows from the existence of a sequence as in Fact 1.4 in which $D \cap E^{\aleph _2}_{\aleph _1}$ in Clause (ii) is replaced by $D \cap E^{\aleph _2}_{\aleph _0}$ . However, Asperó has answered Shelah’s question negatively [Reference Asperó, Geschke, Lowe and Schlicht2]. Getting this failure together with the $\textsf{{GCH}}$ remains open.
The feature of guessing consecutive points has other applications in the construction of Souslin trees: in [Reference Brodsky and Rinot11, Section 5], the feature of guessing with two consecutive points allowed to reduce a $\diamondsuit (\kappa )$ hypothesis from [Reference Brodsky and Rinot7] to just $\kappa ^{<\kappa }=\kappa $ . In [Reference Brodsky and Rinot8], a feature of guessing with $\omega $ -many consecutive points is used to construct Souslin trees with precise control over their reduced powers.
Returning to the discussion after Fact 1.5, there is another way to impose that the set of good guesses be ‘large’. Here is an example, again due to Shelah.
Fact 1.7 [Reference Shelah63, Claim 3.10].
Suppose that $\kappa =\lambda ^+$ for a regular uncountable cardinal $\lambda $ that is not strongly inaccessible. Then, there is a sequence $\langle h_\delta :C_\delta \rightarrow \omega \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in E^\kappa _\lambda \rangle $ such that $:$
-
(1) for every $\delta \in E^\kappa _\lambda $ , $C_\delta $ is a club in $\delta $ of ordertype $\lambda ;$
-
(2) for every club $D \subseteq \kappa $ , there is a $\delta \in E^\kappa _\lambda $ such that
$$ \begin{align*}\bigwedge_{n<\omega}\sup\{\beta< \delta \ {\mathrel{|}}\ \min(C_\delta \setminus(\beta+1))\in D \cap h_\delta^{-1}\{n\}\} = \delta.\end{align*} $$
This result is used in [Reference Rinot51, Section 2] in producing a strong oscillation with $\omega $ many colours, sufficient to derive strong colourings [Reference Rinot51, Section 3] and transformations of the transfinite plane [Reference Rinot and Zhang58]. Any improvement of the above result that partitions the club guessing into $\theta $ many pieces immediately translates to getting a strong oscillation with $\theta $ colours. This also connects to our previous discussion on guessing sequences $\langle C_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle $ with very large ordertypes, since the number of pieces into which $C_\delta $ may be partitioned is bounded by $|C_\delta |$ .
We shall later show that for the purpose of obtaining such partitioned club guessings, the move from the unbounded ideal to the non-stationary ideal as in Fact 1.4 to Fact 1.5 is beneficial. Sufficient conditions and applications to an even stronger form of partitioned club guessing in which there is global function $h:\kappa \rightarrow \theta $ such that $h_\delta =h{\mathbin \upharpoonright } C_\delta $ for all $\delta $ may be found in [Reference Shelah, Gabbay, Macintyre and Scott62, Section 3] and [Reference Lambie-Hanson and Rinot41, Theorem 4.20].
A very useful feature of club guessing sequences we have so far ignored is coherence. Coherent club guessing sequences have been applied to set theory of the real line [Reference Bartoszyński, Larson and Shelah5], and to cardinal invariants of the continuum [Reference Shelah and Zapletal75]. Coherent club guessing sequences were also used to show the non-existence of a natural forcing axiom [Reference Shelah69] and to construct strong colourings [Reference Rinot50, Reference Rinot and Zhang59]. Weakly coherent club guessing at the level of $\aleph _1$ has been used to define a pathological topology on the real line [Reference Zapletal83], and weakly coherent club guessing at the level of a successor $\lambda ^+$ of a singular cardinal $\lambda $ was used in [Reference Brodsky and Rinot9, Section 2.1] to prevent $\lambda $ -distributive $\lambda ^+$ -trees from having a cofinal branch, thus, yielding nonspecial $\lambda ^+$ -Aronszajn trees.
The above is hardly an exhaustive list of applications of club guessing but merely a selection biased by the themes of this paper. Additional key results, including those from [Reference Eisworth14, Reference Foreman and Komjath19, Reference Gitik and Shelah21, Reference Ishiu29] will be discussed in Part II of this series. Another caveat is that in this paper we shall only be concerned with getting club guessing results at $\kappa \ge \aleph _2$ . The behavior of club guessing at the level of $\aleph _1$ is entirely independent of $\textsf{{ZFC}}$ , and we refer the reader to [Reference Asperó and Krueger4, Reference Eisworth and Nyikos16, Reference Hirschorn24, Reference Ishiu30–Reference Ishiu and Larson32, Reference Moore44] for more on that matter.
1.2 The results
Throughout the paper, $\kappa $ stands for an arbitrary regular uncountable cardinal; $\theta ,\mu ,\chi $ are (possibly finite) cardinals $\le \kappa $ , $\lambda $ and $\nu $ are infinite cardinals $<\kappa $ , $\xi ,\sigma $ are nonzero ordinals $\le \kappa $ , and S and T are stationary subsets of $\kappa $ . We shall sometimes implicitly assume that S consists of nonzero limit ordinals.
Definition 1.8. A C-sequence over S is a sequence $\vec C=\langle C_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle $ such that, for every $\delta \in S$ , $C_\delta $ is a closed subset of $\delta $ with $\sup (C_\delta )=\sup (\delta )$ . It is said to be $\xi $ -bounded if $\operatorname {\mathrm {otp}}(C_\delta )\le \xi $ for all $\delta \in S$ .
Our first main result fulfills the promise of finding a join of Facts 1.4 and 1.5.
Theorem A. For every successor cardinal $\lambda $ , there exists a $\lambda $ -bounded C-sequence $\vec C=\langle C_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in E^{\lambda ^+}_\lambda \rangle $ satisfying the following. For every club $D \subseteq \lambda ^+$ , there is a $\delta \in E^{\lambda ^+}_\lambda $ such that the following set is stationary in $\delta :$
Our next result deals with coherent guessing sequences.
Theorem B. For every cardinal $\lambda \ge \beth _\omega $ such that $\square (\lambda ^+)$ holds, for all stationary subsets $S,T$ of $\lambda ^+$ , there exists an $\sqsubseteq ^*$ -coherent C-sequence $\vec C=\langle C_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta <\lambda ^+\rangle $ such that, for every club $D\subseteq \lambda ^+$ , there is a $\delta \in S$ such that $\sup (\operatorname {\mathrm {nacc}}(C_\delta )\cap D\cap T)=\delta $ .
The next two results address the problem of partitioning a given club guessing sequence into $\theta $ many pieces as in Fact 1.7.Footnote 2
Theorem C. Suppose that for each $\delta \in E^\kappa _\lambda $ , $J_\delta $ is some $\lambda $ -complete ideal over $\delta $ , where $\lambda $ is regular uncountable, and suppose that $\vec C=\langle C_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in E^\kappa _\lambda \rangle $ is a given $\lambda $ -bounded C-sequence satisfying that for every club $D\subseteq \lambda $ , there exists $\delta \in E^\kappa _\lambda $ such that
Any of the following hypotheses imply that there exists a map $h:\lambda \rightarrow \theta $ such that for every club $D\subseteq \lambda $ , there is a $\delta \in E^\kappa _\lambda $ such that, for every $\tau <\theta $ ,
-
(i) $\theta =\lambda =\lambda ^{<\lambda }$ and $\lambda $ is a successor cardinal $;$
-
(ii) $\theta =\lambda $ , $\diamondsuit (\lambda )$ holds, and $\lambda $ is not Mahlo $;$
-
(iii) $\theta =\lambda $ , $\diamondsuit ^*(\lambda )$ holds, and each $J_\delta $ is normal $;$
-
(iv) $\theta <\lambda $ is regular and $\lambda $ is not greatly Mahlo $;$
-
(v) $\theta <\lambda $ is regular and there is a $\lambda $ -Aronszajn tree.
Theorem D. Under the same setup of the previous theorem, any of the following hypotheses imply that there exists a sequence of maps $\langle h_\delta :\lambda \rightarrow \theta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in E^\kappa _\lambda \rangle $ such that for every club $D\subseteq \lambda $ , there is a $\delta \in E^\kappa _\lambda $ such that, for every $\tau <\theta $ ,
-
(i) $\diamondsuit ^*(\lambda )$ holds and $\theta =\lambda ;$
-
(ii) $\lambda $ is not strongly inaccessible, and $\theta $ is the least to satisfy $2^\theta \ge \lambda ;$
-
(iii) $\lambda $ is strongly inaccessible, not ineffable, and $\theta <\lambda ;$
-
(iv) $\lambda $ is not greatly Mahlo, and $\theta <\lambda $ .
Our last result fulfills the promise to show that at the level of $\aleph _2$ an affirmative answer to Question 1.6 follows from the existence of a sequence as in Fact 1.4 in which $D \cap E^{\aleph _2}_{\aleph _1}$ in Clause (ii) is replaced by $D \cap E^{\aleph _2}_{\aleph _0}$ .
Theorem E. For every successor cardinal $\lambda $ , if there exists a $\lambda $ -bounded C-sequence $\vec C=\langle C_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in E^{\lambda ^+}_{\lambda }\rangle $ such that for every club $D\subseteq \lambda ^+$ , there is a $\delta \in E^{\lambda ^+}_\lambda $ such that $\sup (\operatorname {\mathrm {nacc}}(C_\delta )\cap D\cap E^{\lambda ^+}_{<\lambda })=\delta $ , then there exists a $\lambda $ -bounded C-sequence $\vec C=\langle C_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in E^{\lambda ^+}_{\lambda }\rangle $ such that for every club $D\subseteq \lambda ^+$ , there is a $\delta \in E^{\lambda ^+}_\lambda $ such that the following set is stationary in $\delta :$
1.3 Organization of this paper
The aim of Section 2 is to give the reader a tour of the basic methods for proving club guessing theorems. The purpose is introductory, and with one exception, all the results we prove are not new, though some of them are not widely known. In particular, we give a proof of Fact 1.2. In Section 2.1 our main definition, Definition 2.2, can be found.
In Section 3, our theme is to obtain club guessing sequences with additional coherence properties. This is done by starting with an arbitrary C-sequence with some degree of coherence, and then improving it to make it guess clubs as well, all the while preserving the coherence. This allows us to obtain ‘coherent forms’ of known results such as Fact 1.4. At the end of the section, we record the results which can be obtained by the same proofs, but without any assumptions of coherence on the initial C-sequence. A proof of Theorem B can be found in this section.
In Section 4, we consider partitioned club guessing. We show how the colouring principles of [Reference Inamdar and Rinot26, Reference Inamdar and Rinot27] allow us to not just obtain partitioned club guessing, but in fact partition club guessing (recall footnote 2). Furthermore, using these colouring principles allows us to separate the combinatorial content from the club guessing content in previous results about partitioned club guessing (see [Reference Shelah63, Lemma 3.10]). A proof of Theorem C can be found here.
In Section 5, we turn to the problem of guessing many consecutive non-accumulation points as in the discussion surrounding Question 1.6. We show how a sequence guessing clubs relative to points of small cofinality can be modified for this purpose.
In the last section, Section 6, our focus is on improving the quality of the guessing calibrated against the ideal. Mainly, our focus is moving from the unbounded ideal to the non-stationary as in the move from Fact 1.4 to Fact 1.5. Similar ideas also allow us to improve some results from Section 4. The proofs of Theorems A, D, and E can be found here.
1.4 Notation and conventions
We have already listed some conventions in the beginning of Section 1.2. Here, we list some more. Let $\log _\chi (\lambda )$ denote the least cardinal $\theta \le \lambda $ such that $\chi ^\theta \ge \lambda $ . For sets of ordinals $A,B$ , we denote $A\circledast B:=\{(\alpha ,\beta )\in A\times B\ {\mathrel {|}}\ \alpha <\beta \}$ and we identify $[B]^2$ with $B\circledast B$ . For $\theta>2$ , $[\kappa ]^\theta $ simply stands for the collection of all subsets of $\kappa $ of size $\theta $ . For sets of ordinals $A,B$ , we write $A\sqsubseteq B$ iff there exists an ordinal $\delta $ such that $A=B\cap \delta $ ; we write $A \sqsubseteq ^* B$ iff there exists a pair of ordinals $\epsilon <\delta $ such that $A\setminus \epsilon =B\cap [\epsilon ,\delta )$ .
Let $E^\kappa _\theta :=\{\alpha < \kappa \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \operatorname {\mathrm {cf}}(\alpha ) = \theta \}$ , and define $E^\kappa _{\le \theta }$ , $E^\kappa _{<\theta }$ , $E^\kappa _{\ge \theta }$ , $E^\kappa _{>\theta }$ , $E^\kappa _{\neq \theta }$ analogously. For a stationary $S\subseteq \kappa $ , we write $\operatorname {\mathrm {Tr}}(S):= \{\alpha \in E^\kappa _{>\omega }\ {\mathrel {|}}\ S\cap \alpha \text { is stationary in }\alpha \}$ .
For a set of ordinals A, we write $\operatorname {\mathrm {ssup}}(A) := \sup \{\alpha + 1 \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \alpha \in A\}$ , $\operatorname {\mathrm {acc}}^+(A) := \{\alpha < \operatorname {\mathrm {ssup}}(A) \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \sup (A \cap \alpha ) = \alpha> 0\}$ , $\operatorname {\mathrm {acc}}(A) := A \cap \operatorname {\mathrm {acc}}^+(A)$ , $\operatorname {\mathrm {nacc}}(A) := A \setminus \operatorname {\mathrm {acc}}(A)$ , and $\operatorname {\mathrm {cl}}(A):= A \cup \operatorname {\mathrm {acc}}^+(A)$ . A function $f:A\rightarrow \operatorname {\mathrm {Ord}}$ is regressive iff $f(\alpha )<\alpha $ for every nonzero $\alpha \in A$ . A function $f:[A]^2\rightarrow \operatorname {\mathrm {Ord}}$ is upper-regressive iff $f(\alpha ,\beta )<\beta $ for every pair $(\alpha ,\beta )\in [A]^2$ .
2 Warming up
In this introductory section we have two tasks. The first is to introduce our main definition, Definition 2.2, and the second is to familiarise the reader with the basic idea of all club guessing proofs, the method of ‘collecting counterexamples’.Footnote 3 The former is achieved in Section 2.1.
For the latter purpose, we provide in Section 2.2 a proof of some known club guessing results including the most famous, Fact 1.2. In the process we hope to make the reader comfortable with Definition 2.2. However, we stress that the full generality of Definition 2.2 is not needed in Section 2.2.
2.1 Preliminaries
The aim of our main definition, Definition 2.2, is to provide a language that is able to differentiate between all of the club guessing principles we have met in Section 1.1. While there are numerous parameters in the definition, we hope to have convinced the reader with the examples from Section 1.1 that all of them have been found fruitful from the point of view of applications.
Definition 2.1 [Reference Brodsky and Rinot7].
For a set of ordinals C, write
In particular, for all $\gamma \in C$ such that $\sup (\operatorname {\mathrm {otp}}(C\setminus \gamma ))\ge \sigma $ , $\operatorname {\mathrm {succ}}_\sigma (C\setminus \gamma )$ consists of the next $\sigma $ -many successor elements of C above $\gamma $ .
Throughout the paper, we shall be working with some sequence $\vec J=\langle J_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle $ such that, for each $\delta \in S$ , $J_\delta $ is a $\operatorname {\mathrm {cf}}(\delta )$ -additive proper ideal over $\delta $ extending $J^{\mathrm {bd}}[\delta ]:=\{ B\subseteq \delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \sup (B)<\delta \}$ .
Definition 2.2 (Main definition).
$\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\xi (S, T, \sigma ,\vec J)$ asserts the existence of a $\xi $ -bounded C-sequence $\vec C=\langle C_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle $ such that, for every club $D\subseteq \kappa $ there is a $\delta \in S$ such that
Convention 2.3. We will often simplify the notation by omitting some parameters, in which case, these parameters take their weakest possible values. Specifically, if we omit $\xi $ , then we mean that $\xi =\kappa $ ; if we omit $\vec J$ , then we mean that $\vec J=\langle J^{\mathrm {bd}}[\delta ]\ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle $ , if we omit $\vec J$ and $\sigma $ , then we mean that $\sigma =1$ and $\vec J=\langle J^{\mathrm {bd}}[\delta ]\ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle $ .
The following propositions collect some evident properties of $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}$ .
Proposition 2.4 (Monotonicity).
Suppose that $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\xi (S, T, \sigma , \langle J_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle )$ holds, as witnessed by a sequence $\vec C$ . Then, assuming all of the following conditions are satisfied, $\vec C$ also witnesses that $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_{\xi '}(S', T', \sigma ', \langle J^{\prime }_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S'\rangle )$ holds.
-
(i) $\xi \leq \xi ';$
-
(ii) $S \subseteq S';$
-
(iii) $T \subseteq T';$
-
(iv) $\sigma \geq \sigma ';$
-
(v) for each $\delta \in S'$ , $J^{\prime }_\delta \supseteq J_\delta $ .
Proposition 2.5 (Indecomposability).
Suppose that $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\xi (S, T, \sigma ,\vec J)$ holds, as witnessed by a sequence $\vec C$ .
-
(1) For every regressive map $f:S\rightarrow \kappa $ , there exists some $i<\kappa $ such that $\vec C$ restricted to $S_i:=f^{-1}\{i\}$ witnesses $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\xi (S_i, T, \sigma ,\vec J)$ .
-
(2) For every decomposition $T=\biguplus _{i<\theta }T_i$ , if $S\subseteq E^\kappa _{>\theta }$ , then there exists some $i<\theta $ such that $\vec C$ witnesses $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\xi (S, T_i, \sigma ,\vec J)$ .
2.2 A tour of club guessing
Most of the results in this article will have the following format: we shall assume the existence of a C-sequence $\vec C$ witnessing a certain form of club guessing, and then we shall improve or modify this $\vec C$ so that it satisfies another form of club guessing, or such that it has some other properties. For example, Proposition 2.4 suggests to us that starting from $\vec C$ witnessing $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\xi (S, T, \sigma ,\langle J_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle )$ , we may look into the possibility of reducing $\xi $ , or shrinking S or T, or increasing $\sigma $ , or enlarging the ideals in $\langle J_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle $ , all the while preserving the guessing properties of $\vec C$ . We shall be considering these problems and other similar ones in this article.
What is important in all this is our ability to modify a given C-sequence to satisfy other, or additional, properties. In this section we shall present some of the standard techniques that one uses to make such modifications, and we do this by giving a proof of Fact 1.2 (Corollary 2.14). As our purpose is introductory, we avoid giving the most direct proofs and focus instead upon the gradual process of improving the guessing.
We then move on to proving a less-known theorem of Shelah that $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}(S,\kappa )$ holds for every stationary subset S of every regular cardinal $\kappa \ge \aleph _2$ (Theorem 2.15). An advantage of this theorem is that it will be the first result we will see which also applies to the case when $\kappa $ is a Mahlo cardinal and S is a stationary set of regular cardinals.
We finish by giving in Proposition 2.22 an example of how a prediction principle weaker than $\diamondsuit $ consisting of a matrix of sets can be modified to obtain a club guessing principle. This will also give us an example of a result involving the second parameter, the set T in the notation of Definition 2.2.
We begin by considering a very weak variation of $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\xi (S, T)$ .
Definition 2.6. $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\xi (S,T,-)$ asserts the existence of a $\xi $ -bounded C-sequence, $\langle C_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle $ such that, for every club $D\subseteq \kappa $ there is a $\delta \in S$ with $\sup (C_\delta \cap D\cap T)=\delta $ .
The following might be obvious, but since we have just begun, we give a detailed proof.
Proposition 2.7. For every triple of regular cardinals $\mu <\lambda <\kappa $ , for every stationary $S\subseteq E^\kappa _\lambda $ , any $\lambda $ -bounded C-sequence over S witnesses $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\lambda (S,E^\kappa _\mu ,-)$ .
Proof Let $S \subseteq E^\kappa _\lambda $ be stationary, and let $\langle C_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S \rangle $ be a $\lambda $ -bounded C-sequence. Given a club D in $\kappa $ , pick $\delta \in S \cap \operatorname {\mathrm {acc}}(D)$ . Since $\operatorname {\mathrm {cf}}(\delta ) = \lambda $ which is a regular uncountable cardinal, $D\cap \delta $ is club in $\delta $ . Pick a closed and unbounded subset $B_\delta $ of $\delta $ of ordertype $\lambda $ such that $B_\delta \subseteq D$ . Since $C_\delta $ is also club in $\delta $ , and $\delta $ has uncountable cofinality, $B_\delta \cap C_\delta $ is as well club in $\delta $ . Let $\langle a_\delta (i) \ {\mathrel {|}}\ i < \lambda \rangle $ be the increasing enumeration of $C_\delta \cap D_\delta $ . As this is an increasing and continuous sequence, it is clear then that for every $j \in \operatorname {\mathrm {acc}}(\lambda )$ , $\operatorname {\mathrm {cf}}(a_\delta (j)) = \operatorname {\mathrm {cf}}(j)$ . Since $\mu < \lambda $ , the set $E^\lambda _\mu $ is cofinal in $\lambda $ , and so for every $j \in E^\lambda _\mu $ , $a_\delta (j) \in E^\kappa _\mu $ . It follows that $\{a_\delta (j) \ {\mathrel {|}}\ j\in E^\lambda _\mu \}$ is a subset of $C_\delta \cap D \cap E^\lambda _\mu $ which is unbounded in $\delta $ .
Our goal now is to show that if $\lambda ^+<\kappa $ , then $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\lambda (S,T,-)$ implies that there is a C-sequence $\langle C_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle $ with the property that for every club $D\subseteq \kappa $ , the set $\{\delta \in S\ {\mathrel {|}}\ C_\delta \subseteq D\}$ is stationary. In doing so, the challenge lies in improving instances of “ $\sup (C_\delta \cap D)=\delta $ ” into instances of “ $C_\delta \subseteq D$ ”. A natural approach is to shrink each club $C_\delta $ into a smaller club in $\delta $ , say $\Phi (C_\delta )$ . In an ideal scenario, a single such act of shrinking will be enough and we will have our result. If the scenario is not so ideal, we would hope that $\Phi (C_\delta )$ is at least ‘better’ than $C_\delta $ , or ‘takes care of the requirements imposed by more clubs’ than $C_\delta $ (we will be more precise momentarily). A common strategy in club guessing is to assume that there are no such ideal scenarios, and then in this case perform this shrinking process (equivalently, improvement process) iteratively for long enough that a contradiction results.
We return to precision. We shall need the following operator in what follows for purposes we have already hinted at.
Definition 2.8. For a subset $B\subseteq \kappa $ , we define the operator $\Phi ^B:\mathcal P(\kappa )\rightarrow \mathcal P(\kappa )$ by letting for all $x \subseteq \kappa $ ,
We list a few useful properties of $\Phi ^B$ :
-
(i) $\sup (\Phi ^B(x))=\sup (x)$ .
-
(ii) If $\sup (x\cap B)=\sup (x)$ , then $\operatorname {\mathrm {nacc}}(\Phi ^B(x))$ is a cofinal subset of $x \cap B$ .
-
(iii) If x is a closed subset of $\sup (x)$ , then $\Phi ^B(x) \subseteq x$ and $\operatorname {\mathrm {otp}}(\Phi ^B(x)) \leq \operatorname {\mathrm {otp}}(x)$ .
Lemma 2.9. Suppose that $\vec C=\langle C_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle $ witnesses $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\lambda (S,T,-)$ , where S and T are stationary subsets of $\kappa $ . If $ \lambda ^+<\kappa $ , then there exists a club $D\subseteq \kappa $ such that $\langle \Phi ^{D\cap T}(C_\delta )\ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle $ witnesses $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\lambda (S,T,\kappa )$ .
Proof Without loss of generality, $S\subseteq \operatorname {\mathrm {acc}}(\kappa )$ . Suppose that the conclusion does not hold. In this case, for every club $D\subseteq \kappa $ , there is a club $F^D \subseteq \kappa $ such that, for every $\delta \in S$ ,
Here, we use that
We construct now a $\subseteq $ -decreasing sequence $\langle D_i \ {\mathrel {|}}\ i\leq \lambda ^+ \rangle $ of clubs in $\kappa $ as follows:
-
(i) $D_0 := \kappa $ ;
-
(ii) $D_{i+1} := D_i \cap F^{D_i}$ ;
-
(iii) for $i\in \operatorname {\mathrm {acc}}(\lambda ^++1)$ , $D_i := \bigcap _{i'< i} D_{i'}$ .
Since $\lambda ^+ < \kappa $ , all these are club subsets of $\kappa $ . As $\vec C$ witnesses $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\lambda (S,T,-)$ , let us now pick $\delta \in S$ with $\sup (C_\delta \cap D_{\lambda ^+}\cap T)=\delta $ . In particular, for all $i<\lambda ^+$ , $\sup (C_\delta \cap D_i\cap T)=\sup (C_\delta )$ , so that $\Phi ^{D_i\cap T}(C_\delta )=\operatorname {\mathrm {cl}}(C_\delta \cap D_i\cap T)$ . Now, as $\langle D_i \ {\mathrel {|}}\ i<\lambda ^+ \rangle $ is $\subseteq $ -decreasing, so is $\langle C_\delta \cap D_i\cap T \ {\mathrel {|}}\ i<\lambda ^+ \rangle $ . But $\operatorname {\mathrm {otp}}(C_\delta )\le \lambda $ , so we may find some $i<\lambda ^+$ such that $C_\delta \cap D_i\cap T=C_\delta \cap D_{i+1}\cap T$ .
By the choice of $F^{D_i}$ , and since $D_{i+1} \subseteq F^{D_i}$ , we have that
However, $\operatorname {\mathrm {nacc}}(\Phi ^{D_i\cap T}(C_\delta ))\subseteq C_\delta \cap D_i\cap T= C_\delta \cap D_{i+1}\cap T$ , which is a contradiction.
So $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\lambda (S,T,-)$ implies $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\lambda (S, T,\kappa )$ , provided that $ \lambda ^+<\kappa $ . Likewise, $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}(S, T,\kappa )$ holds whenever there is a witness $\vec C=\langle C_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle $ to $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}(S,T)$ such that $|C_\delta |<\delta $ for club many $\delta \in S$ .
The instance $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}(S,T,\sigma )$ with $\sigma =\kappa $ is sometimes dubbed tail club guessing. The next lemma derives a stronger form of guessing from tail club guessing.
Lemma 2.10. $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}(S,T,\kappa )$ holds iff there is a C-sequence $\langle C_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle $ such that $:$
-
(i) for every $\delta \in S$ , $\operatorname {\mathrm {otp}}(C_\delta )=\operatorname {\mathrm {cf}}(\delta );$
-
(ii) for every club $D\subseteq \kappa $ , the set $\{ \delta \in S\ {\mathrel {|}}\ \operatorname {\mathrm {nacc}}(C_\delta )\subseteq D\cap T\}$ is stationary.
Proof Only the forward implication requires an argument. Let $\vec C=\langle C_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle $ be a $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}(S,T,\kappa )$ -sequence. For every $i<\kappa $ , we define the operator $\Phi _i:\mathcal P(\kappa )\rightarrow \mathcal P(\kappa )$ by letting for all $x \subseteq \kappa $ ,
It is clear that $\Phi _i(x)$ is a cofinal subset of x, and $\operatorname {\mathrm {nacc}}(\Phi _i(x))\subseteq \operatorname {\mathrm {nacc}}(x)$ . Furthermore, if x is club in its supremum, then so is $\Phi _i(x)$ .
Claim 2.10.1. There exists $i<\kappa $ such that, for every club $D\subseteq \kappa $ , the set $\{ \delta \in S \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \operatorname {\mathrm {nacc}}(\Phi _i(C_\delta ))\subseteq D\cap T\}$ is stationary.
Proof Suppose not. For each $i<\kappa $ , fix a sparse enough club $D_i\subseteq \kappa $ for which $\{ \delta \in S \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \operatorname {\mathrm {nacc}}(\Phi _i(C_\delta ))\subseteq D_i\cap T\}$ is disjoint from $D_i$ . Let $D:=\bigtriangleup _{i<\kappa }D_i$ . By the choice of $\vec C$ , there are $\delta \in S\cap D$ and $\beta <\delta $ such that $\operatorname {\mathrm {succ}}_\kappa (C_\delta \setminus \beta )\subseteq D\cap T$ . As $\operatorname {\mathrm {otp}}(C_\delta ) < \kappa $ , we can find an $i<\delta $ such that $\operatorname {\mathrm {nacc}}(C_\delta )\setminus i\subseteq D\cap T$ . Then $\operatorname {\mathrm {nacc}}(\Phi _i(C_\delta ))\subseteq D\cap T$ . But $i<\delta $ and $\delta \in D$ , so that $\delta \in D_i$ . This is a contradiction.
Let i be given by the preceding claim. The sequence $\langle \Phi _i(C_\delta )\ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle $ satisfies Clause (ii) of the lemma. In order to incorporate Clause (i), for each $\delta \in S$ , we simply pick a club $C_\delta ^\bullet $ in $\delta $ of ordertype $\operatorname {\mathrm {cf}}(\delta )$ such that $\operatorname {\mathrm {nacc}}(C_\delta ^\bullet )\subseteq \operatorname {\mathrm {nacc}}(\Phi _i(C_\delta ))$ . Evidently, $\langle C_\delta ^\bullet \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle $ is as sought.
Putting everything together, we arrive at the following striking conclusion.
Corollary 2.11 [Reference Shelah, Gabbay, Macintyre and Scott62].
For every regular uncountable cardinal $\lambda $ such that $\lambda ^+<\kappa $ , for every stationary $S\subseteq E^\kappa _\lambda $ , there is a C-sequence $\vec C=\langle C_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle $ such that the following two hold $:$
-
(i) for every $\delta \in S$ , $\operatorname {\mathrm {otp}}(C_\delta )=\lambda ;$
-
(ii) for every club $D\subseteq \kappa $ , the set $\{ \delta \in S\ {\mathrel {|}}\ C_\delta \subseteq D\}$ is stationary.
Proof By Proposition 2.7, in particular, $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\lambda (S,E^\kappa _{\aleph _0},-)$ holds. Then, Lemma 2.9 implies that so does $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\lambda (S,E^\kappa _{\aleph _0},\kappa )$ . Now, appeal to Lemma 2.10.
At this point, it is natural to ask whether it is possible to waive the uncountability hypothesis on $\lambda $ in the preceding theorem. We shall show that this is indeed the case, by invoking an operation different than that of $\Phi ^B$ .
Definition 2.12. For a subset $D\subseteq \kappa $ , we define the operator $\Phi _D:\mathcal P(\kappa )\rightarrow \mathcal P(\kappa )$ by letting for all $x \subseteq \kappa $ ,
We list a few useful properties of $\Phi _D$ :
-
(ii) $\sup (\Phi _D(x))=\sup (x)$ .
-
(ii) $\operatorname {\mathrm {otp}}(\Phi _D(x)) \leq \operatorname {\mathrm {otp}}(x)$ .
-
(iii) If $\sup (D\cap \sup (x))=\sup (x)$ , then $\operatorname {\mathrm {acc}}^+(\Phi _D(x))\subseteq \operatorname {\mathrm {acc}}^+(D)\cap \operatorname {\mathrm {acc}}^+(x)$ . If in addition, D is closed below $\sup (x)$ , then $\Phi _D(x)\subseteq D$ .
Lemma 2.13. Suppose that $\kappa \ge \aleph _2$ , and that $\langle C_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle $ is an $\omega $ -bounded C-sequence over a stationary $S\subseteq E^{\kappa }_{\aleph _0}$ .
Then there is a club $D\subseteq \kappa $ such that $\langle \Phi _D(C_\delta )\ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle $ witnesses $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\omega (S,\kappa ,\kappa )$ .
Proof Suppose not. In this case, for every club $D \subseteq \kappa $ , there is a club $F^D \subseteq \kappa $ such that, for every $\delta \in S$ ,
Here we have used that since $C_\delta $ has ordertype $\omega $ , $\Phi _D(C_\delta )$ has ordertype $\omega $ as well, and hence all of its points are nonaccumulation points.
As $\kappa>\aleph _1$ , we may construct a $\subseteq $ -decreasing sequence $\langle D_i \ {\mathrel {|}}\ i\leq \omega _1 \rangle $ of clubs in $\kappa $ as follows:
-
(i) $D_0 := \kappa $ ;
-
(ii) $D_{i+1} := D_i \cap F^{D_i}$ ;
-
(iii) for $i\in \operatorname {\mathrm {acc}}(\omega _1+1)$ , $D_i := \bigcap _{i'< i} D_{i'}$ .
Pick $\delta \in S \cap \operatorname {\mathrm {acc}}(D_{\omega _1})$ . For each $i< \omega _1$ , since $D_i\cap \delta $ is a closed unbounded subset of $\delta $ , it is the case that $\Phi _{D_i}(C_\delta ) = \{\sup (D_i \cap \eta )\ {\mathrel {|}}\ \eta \in C_\delta , \eta> \min (D_i)\}$ , and $\Phi _{D_i}(C_\delta )\subseteq D_i$ .
As $\langle D_i \ {\mathrel {|}}\ i\leq \omega _1 \rangle $ is $\subseteq $ -decreasing, for each $\eta \in C_\delta $ , $\langle \sup (D_i \cap \eta ) \ {\mathrel {|}}\ i< \omega _1\rangle $ is a weakly decreasing sequence of ordinals. By well-foundedness of the ordinals, for each $\eta \in C_\delta $ , there must be some $i_{\eta } < \omega _1$ such that $\sup (D_i\cap \eta ) = \sup (D_j \cap \eta )$ whenever $i_\eta \le i<j<\omega _1$ . Let $i^* := \sup _{\eta \in C_\delta }i_\eta $ , which is a countable ordinal as $C_\delta $ is a countable set. It follows that for any $i\in [i^*,\omega _1)$ , $\Phi _{D_i}(C_\delta ) = \Phi _{D_{i+1}}(C_\delta )$ . However, $\Phi _{D_{i+1}}(C_\delta )\subseteq D_{i+1} \subseteq F^{D_i}$ , contradicting the choice of $F^{D_i}$ .
Putting everything together:
Corollary 2.14 [Reference Shelah, Gabbay, Macintyre and Scott62].
For every pair of infinite regular cardinals $\lambda <\kappa $ and every stationary $S\subseteq E^\kappa _\lambda $ , if $\lambda ^+<\kappa $ , then there is a C-sequence $\vec C=\langle C_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle $ with the property that for every club $D\subseteq \kappa $ , the set $\{\delta \in S\ {\mathrel {|}}\ C_\delta \subseteq D\}$ is stationary.
We now move on to prove a lesser-known theorem of Shelah concerning club guessing. Unlike the previous result, in the following, S is not assumed to be a subset of $E^\kappa _\lambda $ for some fixed cardinal $\lambda <\kappa $ . So, for instance, S could be the set of regular cardinals below a Mahlo cardinal $\kappa $ .
Theorem 2.15 (Shelah).
Suppose $\kappa \ge \aleph _2$ .
For every stationary $S\subseteq \kappa $ , $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}(S,\kappa ,1)$ holds.
Our proof of Theorem 2.15 goes through the notion of an amenable C-sequence, which is a strengthening of $\otimes _{\vec C}$ from [Reference Shelah, Gabbay, Macintyre and Scott62, page 134]. As well, amenable C-sequences are implicit in the elementary proof of Solovay’s theorem on partitioning stationary sets, see, for example, [Reference Jech33, Theorem 8.10].
Definition 2.16 [Reference Brodsky and Rinot9, Definition 1.3].
For a stationary $S\subseteq \kappa $ , a C-sequence $\langle C_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle $ is amenable iff for every club $D\subseteq \kappa $ , the set $\{ \delta \in S\ {\mathrel {|}}\ \sup ({D\cap \delta }\setminus C_\delta )<\delta \}$ is nonstationary in $\kappa $ .
Fact 2.17 [Reference Inamdar and Rinot26, Corollary 3.11].
For every stationary $S\subseteq \kappa $ , there exists a stationary $S^-\subseteq S$ such that $S^-$ carries an amenable C-sequence.
Lemma 2.18. Suppose that $S\subseteq \kappa $ is stationary and $\vec C=\langle C_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle $ is an amenable C-sequence. If $\kappa \ge \aleph _2$ , then there exists a club $D\subseteq \kappa $ for which $\langle \Phi _D(C_\delta )\ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle $ witnesses $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}(S,\kappa ,1)$ .
Proof Suppose not. In this case, for every club $D \subseteq \kappa $ , there is a club $F^D \subseteq \kappa $ such that, for every $\delta \in S$ ,
As $\kappa \ge \aleph _2$ , we may construct a $\subseteq $ -decreasing sequence $\langle D_i \ {\mathrel {|}}\ i\leq \omega _1 \rangle $ of clubs in $\kappa $ as follows:
-
(i) $D_0 := \kappa $ ;
-
(ii) $D_{i+1} := D_i \cap F^{D_i}$ ;
-
(iii) for $i\in \operatorname {\mathrm {acc}}(\omega _1+1)$ , $D_i := \bigcap _{i'< i} D_{i'}$ .
As $\vec C$ is amenable and $D_{\omega _1}$ is club in $\kappa $ , we may pick some $\delta \in S$ such that $\sup (D_{\omega _1}\cap \delta \setminus C_\delta )=\delta $ . For each $i< \omega _1$ , since $D_i\cap \delta $ is a closed unbounded subset of $\delta $ , it is the case that
So $\Phi _{D_i}(C_\delta )\subseteq D_i$ and $\operatorname {\mathrm {acc}}(\Phi _{D_i}(C_\delta ))\subseteq \operatorname {\mathrm {acc}}(D_i)\cap \operatorname {\mathrm {acc}}(C_\delta )$ .
In addition, for each $i<\omega _1$ , since $D_{i+1}\subseteq F^{D_i}$ , the following ordinal is smaller than $\delta $ :
Claim 2.18.1. There exists $I\subseteq \omega _1$ of ordertype $\omega $ such that $\sup \{\epsilon _i\ {\mathrel {|}}\ i\in I\}<\delta $ .
Proof If $\operatorname {\mathrm {cf}}(\delta )>\omega _1$ , then just let $I:=\omega $ . If $\operatorname {\mathrm {cf}}(\delta )=\omega $ , then pick a countable cofinal subset E of $\delta $ and for each $i\in \omega _1$ , find the least $\epsilon \in E$ such $\epsilon _i\le \epsilon $ . By the pigeonhole principle, there is an $\epsilon \in E$ for which $\{ i\in I\ {\mathrel {|}}\ \epsilon _i\le \epsilon \}$ is uncountable. In particular, this set contains a subset of ordertype $\omega $ .
Fix I as in the claim, and then pick $\gamma \in D_{\omega _1}\cap \delta \setminus C_\delta $ above $\sup \{ \epsilon _i\ {\mathrel {|}}\ i\in I\}$ . As $\gamma \notin C_\delta $ , $\eta :=\min (C_\delta \setminus \gamma )$ is in $\operatorname {\mathrm {nacc}}(C_\delta )$ . As $\langle \sup (D_i \cap \eta ) \ {\mathrel {|}}\ i\in I\rangle $ is a weakly decreasing sequence of ordinals, by well-foundedness there must be a pair of ordinals $i<j$ in I such that $\beta _i:=\sup (D_i\cap \eta )$ is equal to $\beta _j:=\sup (D_j \cap \eta )$ .
As $\gamma \in D_{\omega _1}\subseteq D_i$ , $\epsilon _i<\gamma \le \beta _i\le \eta $ , so $\beta _i\in \Phi _{D_i}(C_\delta )\cap (\epsilon _i,\eta ]$ . Likewise, $\beta _j\in \Phi _{D_j}(C_\delta )\cap (\epsilon _j,\eta ]$ . Recalling that $\beta _i=\beta _j\in D_j\subseteq D_{i+1}$ , it follows that $\beta _i$ is an element of $\Phi _{D_i}(C_\delta )\cap D_{i+1}$ above $\epsilon _i$ and hence $\beta _i\in \operatorname {\mathrm {acc}}(\Phi _{D_i}(C_\delta ))$ . However, $\operatorname {\mathrm {acc}}(\Phi _{D_i}(C_\delta ))\subseteq \operatorname {\mathrm {acc}}(D_i)\cap \operatorname {\mathrm {acc}}(C_\delta )$ , and hence $\beta _i\in \operatorname {\mathrm {acc}}(C_\delta )$ . But $\gamma \le \beta _i\le \eta $ and $C_\delta \cap [\gamma ,\eta ]=\{\eta \}$ , and hence $\beta _i=\eta $ , contradicting the fact that $\eta \in \operatorname {\mathrm {nacc}}(C_\delta )$ .
Proof of Theorem 2.15
Given a stationary $S\subseteq \kappa $ , appeal to Fact 2.17 to find an amenable C-sequence $\langle C_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S^-\rangle $ for some stationary $S^-\subseteq S$ . Then, by Lemma 2.18, $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}(S^-,\kappa ,1)$ holds. So $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}(S,\kappa ,1)$ holds as well.
As pointed out in the introduction, if $\diamondsuit (S)$ holds for a given stationary subset S of $\kappa $ , then, for every stationary $T\subseteq \kappa $ , $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}(S,T,\kappa )$ holds. The next result shows how to get $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}(S,T,\kappa )$ from a principle weaker than $\diamondsuit (S)$ and even weaker than $\clubsuit (S)$ and of which many instances hold true in $\textsf{{ZFC}}$ .
Definition 2.19 [Reference Rinot47].
For a stationary subset S of a regular uncountable cardinal $\kappa $ , $\clubsuit ^-(S)$ asserts the existence of a sequence $\langle \mathcal A_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle $ such that:
-
(i) for all $\delta \in S$ , $\mathcal A_\delta \subseteq [\delta ]^{<|\delta |}$ and $|\mathcal A_\delta |\le |\delta |$ ;
-
(ii) for every cofinal $Z\subseteq \kappa $ , there are $\delta \in S$ and $A\in \mathcal A_\delta $ with $\sup (A\cap Z)=\delta $ .
Remark 2.20. Note that if $\clubsuit ^-(S)$ holds, then $\{\delta \in S\ {\mathrel {|}}\ \operatorname {\mathrm {cf}}(\delta )<|\delta |\}$ must be stationary.
Fact 2.21 [Reference Rinot47].
For an infinite cardinal $\lambda $ and a stationary $S\subseteq \lambda ^+:$
-
• If $S\cap E^{\lambda ^+}_{\neq \operatorname {\mathrm {cf}}(\lambda )}$ is stationary, then $\clubsuit ^-(S)$ holds.
-
• If $\square _\lambda ^*$ holds and S reflects stationarily often, then $\clubsuit ^-(S)$ holds.
In reading the statement of the next two propositions, keep in mind Lemma 2.10.
Proposition 2.22. Suppose that $\clubsuit ^-(S)$ holds for a given stationary $S\subseteq \kappa $ .
Then, for every stationary $T\subseteq \kappa $ , $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}(S,T,\kappa )$ holds.
Proof Let $\langle \mathcal A_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle $ be a $\clubsuit ^-(S)$ -sequence. For each $\delta \in S$ , fix an enumeration $\{ A_{\delta ,i}\ {\mathrel {|}}\ i<\delta \}$ of $\mathcal A_\delta $ .
Claim 2.22.1. There exists $i<\kappa $ such that, for every club $E\subseteq \kappa $ , there is a $\delta \in S$ with $\sup (A_{\delta ,i}\cap E\cap T)=\delta $ .
Proof Otherwise, for each $i<\kappa $ , we may pick a counterexample $E_i$ . Let $Z:=T\cap \bigtriangleup _{i<\kappa }E_i$ . Pick $\delta \in S$ and $i<\delta $ such that $\sup (A_{\delta , i}\cap Z)=\delta $ . Since $Z\cap (i,\delta )\subseteq T\cap E_i$ , we have that $\sup (A_{\delta ,i}\cap E_i\cap T)=\delta $ . This contradicts the choice of $E_i$ .
Fix i as given by the preceding claim, and denote $A_\delta :=A_{\delta ,i}$ . We shall now make use of the operator $\Phi ^B$ from Definition 2.8.
Claim 2.22.2. There exists a club $D\subseteq \kappa $ such that, for every club $E\subseteq \kappa $ , there exists $\delta \in S$ with $\sup (A_{\delta })=\delta $ and $\operatorname {\mathrm {nacc}}(\Phi ^{D\cap T}(A_{\delta }))\subseteq E$ .
Proof Suppose not. In this case, for every club $D\subseteq \kappa $ , there is a club $F^D \subseteq \kappa $ such that for every $\delta \in S$ , either $\sup (A_\delta )<\delta $ or $\operatorname {\mathrm {nacc}}(\Phi ^{D\cap T}(A_{\delta }))\nsubseteq F^D$ . We construct a $\subseteq $ -decreasing sequence $\langle D_i \ {\mathrel {|}}\ i<\kappa \rangle $ of clubs in $\kappa $ as follows:
-
(i) $D_0 := \kappa $ ;
-
(ii) $D_{i+1} := D_i \cap F^{D_i}$ ;
-
(iii) for $i\in \operatorname {\mathrm {acc}}(\kappa )$ , $D_i := \bigcap _{i'< i} D_{i'}$ .
Let $E:=\bigtriangleup _{i<\kappa }D_i$ . Pick $\delta \in S$ with $\sup (A_\delta \cap E\cap T)=\delta $ . For every $i<\delta $ , $\delta \in \operatorname {\mathrm {acc}}^+(D_i\cap T)$ and $\operatorname {\mathrm {nacc}}(\Phi ^{D_i\cap T}(A_\delta ))\nsubseteq D_{i+1}$ , so that we may pick $\beta _i\in (A_\delta \cap D_i\cap T)\setminus D_{i+1}$ . As $|A_\delta |<\delta $ , let us fix $i<j<\delta $ such that $\beta _i=\beta _j$ . So $\beta _i\notin D_{i+1}$ while $\beta _j\in D_j\subseteq D_{i+1}$ . This is a contradiction.
Let D be given by the preceding claim. For $\delta \in S$ , let $C_\delta :=\Phi ^{D\cap T}(A_\delta )$ . Then $\langle C_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle $ witness $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}(S,T,\kappa )$ .
Corollary 2.23. For every uncountable cardinal $\lambda $ , every stationary $S\subseteq E^{\lambda ^+}_{\neq \operatorname {\mathrm {cf}}(\lambda )}$ , and every stationary $T\subseteq \lambda ^+$ , $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}(S,T,\kappa )$ holds.
Remark 2.24. In Corollary 3.34 we provide a sufficient condition enabling to handle the critical cofinality (that is, $S\subseteq E^{\lambda ^+}_{\operatorname {\mathrm {cf}}(\lambda )}$ ) as well.
We end this section by saying a few words about the following natural generalisation of Definition 2.2.
Definition 2.25. For an ideal $J_\kappa $ over $\kappa $ , $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\xi (J_\kappa , T, \sigma ,\vec J)$ asserts the existence of a C-sequence $\vec C=\langle C_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta <\kappa \rangle $ such that $\{\delta <\kappa \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \operatorname {\mathrm {otp}}(C_\delta )>\xi \}\in J_\kappa $ , and such that for every club $D\subseteq \kappa $ ,
First, the proof of Lemma 2.10 makes it clear that obtaining a single witness $\delta \in S$ to an instance of guessing a club is equivalent to obtaining stationarily-many such witnesses. More precisely, the usual principle $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\xi (S, T, \sigma , \vec J)$ coincides with $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\xi (J_\kappa , T, \sigma ,\vec J)$ for $J_\kappa :=\mathrm{NS}_\kappa {\mathbin \upharpoonright } S$ . Furthermore, if $\vec C$ witnesses $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\xi (S, T, \sigma , \vec J)$ , then the collection of all $S'\subseteq S$ for which $\vec C{\mathbin \upharpoonright } S'$ fails to witness $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\xi (S', T, \sigma , \vec J)$ forms a $\kappa $ -complete normal (and proper) ideal extending $\mathrm{NS}_\kappa {\mathbin \upharpoonright } S$ .
Second, in any of the upcoming results that involve pumping an instance $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\xi (S,\ldots )$ into a better instance $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_{\bar \xi }(S,\ldots )$ , no new ideas would be needed in order to get the analogous result where S is replaced by an abstract $\kappa $ -complete ideal $J_\kappa $ over $\kappa $ . In fact, for many of the results, letting $J_\kappa $ be an $\aleph _1$ -indecomposable ideal (see, for instance, [Reference Eisworth14, Section 2]) over $\kappa $ would be sufficient. For this reason we eschew the added generality of Definition 2.25 and focus on Definition 2.2.
3 Coherent sequences
We begin by reflecting on the previous section and pointing out some commonalities in the proofs of Lemmas 2.9, 2.10, 2.13, and 2.18. In all of these, we started with a C-sequence, and then we improved it using some operation $\Phi :\mathcal P(\kappa )\rightarrow \mathcal P(\kappa )$ . These similarities leads one to describe abstractly the class of such operations to which the examples we’ve met belong, in the hope that known members or properties of this class might be of assistance in future endeavours. This class has in fact already been delineated in work of Brodsky and Rinot in [Reference Brodsky and Rinot9], where they occurred in the work on constructing trees with prescribed properties by studying how the properties of a C-sequence affect the properties of the trees derived from walks on ordinals.
Definition 3.1 [Reference Brodsky and Rinot9].
Let $\mathcal K(\kappa ):=\{ x\in \mathcal P(\kappa )\ {\mathrel {|}}\ x\neq \emptyset \ \&\ \operatorname {\mathrm {acc}}^+(x)\subseteq x\ \& \ \sup (x) \notin x\}$ be the set of all closed unbounded subsets of nonzero limit ordinals $\le \kappa $ . An operator $\Phi :\mathcal K(\kappa )\rightarrow \mathcal K(\kappa )$ is a postprocessing function if for every $x\in \mathcal K(\kappa )$ :
-
(i) $\Phi (x)$ is a club in $\sup (x)$ ;
-
(ii) $\operatorname {\mathrm {acc}}(\Phi (x)) \subseteq \operatorname {\mathrm {acc}}(x)$ ;
-
(iii) $\Phi (x)\cap \bar \alpha =\Phi (x\cap \bar \alpha )$ for every $\bar \alpha \in \operatorname {\mathrm {acc}}(\Phi (x))$ .
Remark 3.2. By the first clause, $\operatorname {\mathrm {otp}}(\Phi (x))\ge \operatorname {\mathrm {cf}}(\sup (x))$ , and by the second clause, $\operatorname {\mathrm {otp}}(\Phi (x))\le \operatorname {\mathrm {otp}}(x)$ .
It is easy to verify that the three operations we met in Section 2—when their domains are restricted to $\mathcal K(\kappa )$ —are postprocessing functions. What’s nice about postprocessing functions is that requirement (iii) implies that they maintain coherence features of C-sequences. Indeed, the theme of this section is to obtain club guessing sequences which have additional coherence features. The particular coherence features we consider can be found in the following definition and in Definition 3.16.
Definition 3.3. Let $\vec C=\langle C_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle $ be a C-sequence.
-
(i) For an infinite cardinal $\chi \le \kappa $ , we say that $\vec C$ is $\mathrel {{}_{\chi }{\sqsubseteq }}$ -coherent iff for all $\delta \in S$ and $\bar \delta \in \operatorname {\mathrm {acc}}(C_\delta )\cap E^\kappa _{\ge \chi }$ , it is the case that $\bar \delta \in S$ and $C_{\bar \delta }=C_\delta \cap \bar \delta $ .
-
(ii) We say that $\vec C$ is coherent iff it is $\mathrel {{}_{\omega }{\sqsubseteq }}$ -coherent.
-
(iii) We say that $\vec C$ is weakly coherent iff for every $\alpha <\kappa $ , $|\{ C_\delta \cap \alpha \ {\mathrel {|}} \delta \in S\}|<\kappa $ .Footnote 4
It is routine to verify that if $\Phi : \mathcal K(\kappa ) \rightarrow \mathcal K(\kappa )$ is a postprocessing function, and $\langle C_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S \rangle $ satisfies any of the above coherence properties, then $\langle \Phi (C_\delta ) \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle $ satisfies the same coherence property as well, Clause (iii) being key in the verification.
In particular, as a consequence of the use of postprocessing functions, in each of Lemmas 2.9, 2.10, 2.13, and 2.18, if we start with a C-sequence with one of the coherence properties above, the exact same proof ensures that the guessing C-sequence obtained satisfies the same coherence property. In Facts 3.8 and 3.9 and Theorem 3.11 we give three examples of this. To this end, we first remind the reader of a couple of definitions.
Definition 3.4. $\square _\xi (\kappa ,{<}\mu )$ asserts the existence of a sequence $\langle \mathcal C_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta <\kappa \rangle $ satisfying all of the following:
-
• for every limit ordinal $\delta <\kappa $ , $1<|\mathcal C_\delta |<\mu $ , and each $C\in \mathcal C_\delta $ is club in $\delta $ with $\operatorname {\mathrm {otp}}(C)\le \xi $ ;
-
• for every $\delta <\kappa $ , $C\in \mathcal C_\delta $ , and $\bar \delta \in \operatorname {\mathrm {acc}}(C)$ , $C\cap \bar \delta \in \mathcal C_{\bar \delta }$ ;
-
• for every club D in $\kappa $ , there exists some $\delta \in \operatorname {\mathrm {acc}}(D)$ such that $D\cap \delta \notin \mathcal C_\delta $ .
Remark 3.5. The instance $\square _\kappa (\kappa ,{<}2)$ is better known as $\square (\kappa )$ , the instance $\square _\lambda (\lambda ^+,{<}2)$ is better known as $\square _\lambda $ , and the instance $\square _\lambda (\lambda ^+,{<}\lambda ^+)$ is better known as $\square _\lambda ^*$ .
Note that $\square _\lambda $ holds iff there exists a coherent $\lambda $ -bounded C-sequence over $\lambda ^+$ , and that $\square ^*_\lambda $ holds iff there exists a weakly coherent $\lambda $ -bounded C-sequence over $\lambda ^+$ . The following terminology is also quite useful.
Definition 3.6. A C-sequence $\vec C=\langle C_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta <\kappa \rangle $ is a transversal for $\square _\xi (\kappa ,{<}\mu )$ iff there exists a witness $\langle \mathcal C_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta <\kappa \rangle $ for $\square _\xi (\kappa ,{<}\mu )$ such that $C_\delta \in \mathcal C_\delta $ for all $\delta <\kappa $ .
Remark 3.7. A transversal for $\square ^*_\lambda $ is nothing but a $\lambda $ -bounded and weakly coherent C-sequence over $\lambda ^+$ .
By [Reference Brodsky and Rinot9, Lemma 1.23], every transversal for a $\square _\xi (\kappa ,{<}\mu )$ -sequence with $\xi <\kappa $ or $\mu <\kappa $ gives an amenable C-sequence $\langle C_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta <\kappa \rangle $ which can then be supplied to the machinery in Lemma 2.18. Indeed, in [Reference Brodsky and Rinot9], solving Question 16 from [Reference Rinot, Babinkostova, Caicedo, Geschke and Scheepers49] in the affirmative, a wide club guessing theorem was proven using Lemma 2.18:Footnote 5
Fact 3.8 [Reference Brodsky and Rinot9, Lemma 2.5].
If $\square _\xi (\kappa ,{<}\mu )$ holds for a regular cardinal $\kappa \ge \aleph _2$ and a cardinal $\mu <\kappa $ , then for every stationary $S\subseteq \kappa $ , $\square _\xi (\kappa ,{<}\mu )$ may be witnessed by a sequence $\langle \mathcal C_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta <\kappa \rangle $ with the added feature that for every club $D\subseteq \kappa $ , there exists $\delta \in S$ such that, for every $C\in \mathcal C_\delta $ , $\sup (\operatorname {\mathrm {nacc}}(C)\cap D)=\delta $ .
A special case of Fact 3.8 states that if $\square (\kappa )$ holds and $\kappa \ge \aleph _2$ , then for every stationary $S\subseteq \kappa $ , there exists a $\square (\kappa )$ -sequence $\vec C$ such that $\vec C{\mathbin \upharpoonright } S$ witnesses $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}(S,\kappa )$ .Footnote 6 Replacing $\square (\kappa )$ by $\square _\lambda $ , better forms of guessing are available:
Fact 3.9 [Reference Rinot52, Corollary 2.4].
Suppose that $\lambda $ is an uncountable cardinal.
Then $\square _\lambda $ holds iff there exists a coherent $\lambda $ -bounded C-sequence $\langle C_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta <\lambda ^+\rangle $ with the feature that for every club $D\subseteq \lambda ^+$ and every $\sigma \in \operatorname {\mathrm {acc}}(\lambda )$ , there exists some $\delta <\lambda ^+$ with $\operatorname {\mathrm {otp}}(C_\delta )=\sigma $ such that $C_\delta \subseteq D$ .
Remark 3.10. Note that for a $\vec C$ as above, the map $\delta \mapsto \operatorname {\mathrm {otp}}(C_\delta )$ yields a canonical partition of $\operatorname {\mathrm {acc}}(\lambda ^+)$ into $\lambda $ -many pairwise disjoint stationary sets.
An inspection of the proofs of [Reference Rinot52, Lemma 2.8] and Proposition 2.22 makes it clear that the following holds true.
Theorem 3.11. Suppose that $\lambda $ is an uncountable cardinal, and $S,T$ are stationary subsets of $\lambda ^+$ . Suppose also that either $S\cap E^{\lambda ^+}_{\neq \operatorname {\mathrm {cf}}(\lambda )}$ is stationary or that $\operatorname {\mathrm {Tr}}(S)$ is stationary. Then $:$
-
(1) $\square _\lambda $ holds iff there exists a coherent $\lambda $ -bounded C-sequence $\langle C_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta <\lambda ^+\rangle $ with the feature that for every club $D\subseteq \lambda ^+$ , there exists a $\delta \in S$ such that $\operatorname {\mathrm {nacc}}(C_\delta )\subseteq D\cap T$ .
-
(2) $\square ^*_\lambda $ holds iff there exists a weakly coherent $\lambda $ -bounded C-sequence $\langle C_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta <\lambda ^+\rangle $ with the feature that for every club $D\subseteq \lambda ^+$ , there exists a $\delta \in S$ such that $\operatorname {\mathrm {nacc}}(C_\delta )\subseteq D\cap T$ .
We now turn to present another postprocessing function.
Lemma 3.12 (See [Reference Brodsky and Rinot11, Lemma 4.9]).
For every function $f:\kappa \rightarrow [\kappa ]^{<\omega }$ , the operator $\Phi _f:\mathcal K(\kappa )\rightarrow \mathcal K(\kappa )$ defined via:
is a postprocessing function.
The definition of $\Phi _f$ is motivated by the regressive functions ideal $J[\kappa ]$ from [Reference Rinot55], and the following extension of it from [Reference Rinot57].
Definition 3.13 [Reference Rinot57].
$J_\omega [\kappa ]$ stands for the collection of all subsets $S\subseteq \kappa $ for which there exist a club $C\subseteq \kappa $ and a sequence of functions $\langle f_i:\kappa \rightarrow [\kappa ]^{<\omega }\ {\mathrel {|}}\ i<\kappa \rangle $ with the property that for every $\delta \in S\cap C$ , every regressive function $f:\delta \rightarrow \delta $ , and every cofinal subset $\Gamma \subseteq \delta $ , there exists an $i<\delta $ such that
The next lemma gives a sufficient condition for moving from $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\xi (S,\kappa )$ to $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\xi (S,T)$ .
Lemma 3.14. Suppose that $\vec C=\langle C_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle $ is a C-sequence witnessing $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\xi (S,\kappa )$ . If $S\in J_\omega [\kappa ]$ , then for every stationary $T\subseteq \kappa $ , there exists a function $f:\kappa \rightarrow [\kappa ]^{<\omega }$ such that $\langle \Phi _f(C_\delta )\ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle $ witnesses $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\xi (S,T)$
Proof Without loss of generality, $S\subseteq \operatorname {\mathrm {acc}}(\kappa )$ . Suppose that $S\in J_\omega [\kappa ]$ , and fix a club $C\subseteq \kappa $ and a sequence of functions $\langle f_i:\kappa \rightarrow [\kappa ]^{<\omega }\ {\mathrel {|}}\ i<\kappa \rangle $ as in Definition 3.13. For all $i<\kappa $ and $\delta \in S$ , denote $C_\delta ^i:=\Phi _{f_i}(C_\delta )$ , so that $\operatorname {\mathrm {otp}}(C_\delta ^i)\le \operatorname {\mathrm {otp}}(C_\delta )$ .
Let T be an arbitrary stationary subset of $\kappa $ .
Claim 3.14.1. There is an $i< \kappa $ such that $\langle C^i_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle $ witnesses $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}(S,T)$ .
Proof Suppose not. For each $i< \kappa $ , pick a club $D_i \subseteq \kappa $ such that for every $\delta \in S$ ,
Consider the two clubs $D:= C\cap \bigtriangleup _{i< \kappa } D_i$ and $D':=\operatorname {\mathrm {acc}}^+(D\cap T)$ . By the choice of $\vec C$ , pick $\delta \in S$ such that $\Gamma :=\operatorname {\mathrm {nacc}}(C_\delta )\cap D'$ is cofinal in $\delta $ . As $\Gamma $ is a subset of $\operatorname {\mathrm {nacc}}(C_\delta )\cap D'$ , we may define a regressive function $f:\Gamma \rightarrow \delta $ via:
As $\gamma \in S\cap C$ , find $i<\delta $ such that $\Gamma ':=\{ \gamma \in \Gamma \ {\mathrel {|}}\ f(\gamma )\in f_i(\gamma )\}$ is cofinal in $\delta $ . By possibly omitting an initial segment of $\Gamma '$ , we may assume that $\sup (C_\delta \cap \min (\Gamma '))>i$ . Recalling the definition of D, it follows that for every $\gamma \in \Gamma '$ , $f(\gamma )\in D_i\cap T$ . So, for every $\gamma \in \Gamma '$ , if we let $\beta :=\sup (C_\delta \cap \gamma )$ , then $C_\delta ^i\cap (\beta ,\gamma )$ is equal to the finite set $f_i(\gamma )\cap (\beta ,\gamma )$ that contains $f(\gamma )$ which is an element of $D_i\cap T$ . So $\sup (\operatorname {\mathrm {nacc}}(C^i_\delta ) \cap D_{i} \cap T)= \delta $ , contradicting the choice of $D_i$ .
Let i be given by the preceding claim. Then $f:=f_i$ is as sought.
By [Reference Rinot57, Proposition 3.3], $J_\omega [\lambda ^+]$ contains no stationary subsets of $E^{\lambda ^+}_{\operatorname {\mathrm {cf}}(\lambda )}$ . In particular, $J_\omega [\omega _1]$ is empty. So, unlike Fact 3.8, in the following we don’t need to explicitly require $\kappa $ to be $\ge \aleph _2$ .
Corollary 3.15. If $\square (\kappa )$ holds, then for every stationary $S\in J_\omega [\kappa ]$ and every stationary $T\subseteq \kappa $ , there exists a $\square (\kappa )$ -sequence $\vec C$ such that $\vec C{\mathbin \upharpoonright } S$ witnesses $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}(S,T)$ .
We have described a way of moving from $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}(S,\kappa )$ to $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}(S,T)$ . Our next goal is to describe a way for moving from $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}(\kappa ,T)$ to $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}(S,T)$ . First, a definition.
Definition 3.16. We say that a C-sequence $\vec C=\langle C_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle $ is $\sqsubseteq ^*$ -coherent iff for all $\delta \in S$ and $\bar \delta \in \operatorname {\mathrm {acc}}(C_\delta )$ , it is the case that $\bar \delta \in S$ and $\sup (C_{\bar \delta }\mathbin \triangle (C_\delta \cap \bar \delta )) < \bar \delta $ .
Remark 3.17. Every $\sqsubseteq ^*$ -coherent C-sequence is weakly coherent.
To preserve $\sqsubseteq ^*$ -coherence, one needs to consider a strengthening of Definition 3.1.
Definition 3.18. An operator $\Phi :\mathcal K(\kappa )\rightarrow \mathcal K(\kappa )$ is a postprocessing $^*$ function if for every $x\in \mathcal K(\kappa )$ , Clause (i)–(iii) of Definition 3.1 hold true, and, in addition:
-
(iv) for every $\bar x\in \mathcal K(\kappa )$ such that $\bar x\sqsubseteq ^* x$ and $\sup (\bar x)\in \operatorname {\mathrm {acc}}(\Phi (x))$ , $\Phi (\bar x)\sqsubseteq ^*\Phi (x)$ .
It is readily checked that all the postprocessing functions we have met so far are moreover postprocessing $^*$ functions. An example of a postprocessing function that is not postprocessing $^*$ function may be found in [Reference Lambie-Hanson and Rinot42, Lemma 3.8]. In fact, it is unknown at present how to obtain the same effect of that map using a postprocessing $^*$ function.
Theorem 3.19. Suppose that $\kappa \ge \aleph _2$ , and that there exists an $\sqsubseteq ^*$ -coherent C-sequence witnessing $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}(\kappa ,T)$ .
For every stationary $S\subseteq \kappa $ , there exists an $\sqsubseteq ^*$ -coherent C-sequence over $\kappa $ whose restriction to S witnesses $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}(S,T)$ .
Proof The proof will be an adaptation of the proof of [Reference Rinot55, Theorem 4.13]. Suppose towards a contradiction that S is a counterexample. Fix an $\sqsubseteq ^*$ -coherent C-sequence $\vec e=\langle e_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta <\kappa \rangle $ witnessing $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}(\kappa ,T)$ . By recursion on $i< \omega _1$ , we construct a club $D_i\subseteq \kappa $ and an $\sqsubseteq ^*$ -coherent C-sequence $\vec {C^i}=\langle C^i_\alpha \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \alpha < \kappa \rangle $ . Our construction will have the property that for all $\alpha < \kappa $ and $j< i<\omega _1$ , $C^j_\alpha \subseteq C^i_\alpha $ .
$\blacktriangleright $ For $i=0$ , let $D_0 := \kappa $ and $\vec {C^0}:=\vec e$ .
$\blacktriangleright $ For every $i<\omega _1$ such that a club $D_i\subseteq \kappa $ and an $\sqsubseteq ^*$ -coherent C-sequence $\vec {C^i}$ have been constructed, by the assumption we can find a club $F^{D_i}$ such that, for every $\delta \in S$ ,
So let $D_{i+1}:= D_i \cap F^{D_i}$ . As for constructing $\vec {C^{i+1}}$ , we do this by recursion on $\alpha < \kappa $ . To start, let $C^{i+1}_0:= \emptyset $ , and for every $\alpha < \kappa $ let $C^{i+1}_{\alpha +1}:=\{\alpha \}$ . Next, for $\alpha \in \operatorname {\mathrm {acc}}(\kappa )$ ,
It is clear that $\vec {C^{i+1}}=\langle C^{i+1}_\alpha \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \alpha < \kappa \rangle $ is $\sqsubseteq ^*$ -coherent as well.
$\blacktriangleright $ For every $i\in \operatorname {\mathrm {acc}}(\omega _1)$ such that $\langle (D_j,\vec {C^j})\ {\mathrel {|}}\ j<i\rangle $ has been constructed as required, let $D_i:= \bigcap _{j< i} D_j$ and for every $\alpha < \kappa $ , let $C^i_\alpha := \bigcup _{j< i}C^j_\alpha $ .
Claim 3.19.1. Let $\alpha <\kappa $ . Then $\operatorname {\mathrm {acc}}^+(C^i_\alpha )= \bigcup _{j< i}\operatorname {\mathrm {acc}}(C^j_\alpha )$ .
Proof Let $\beta \in \operatorname {\mathrm {acc}}^+(C^i_\alpha )$ . The sequence $\langle \min (C^j_\alpha \setminus \beta )\ {\mathrel {|}}\ j< i\rangle $ is weakly decreasing, and as i is a nonzero limit ordinal, it stabilizes at some $j^*< i$ . Let $\beta ^+$ be this stable value (which may be equal to $\beta $ ). If there exists $j \in [j^*, i)$ such that $\beta ^+\in \operatorname {\mathrm {acc}}(C^{j}_\alpha )$ , then in fact $\beta ^+ = \beta $ and we can finish. So, suppose that this is not so. If there exists $j \in [j^*, i)$ such that $\beta ^+\notin F^{D_j}\cap T$ , then $\beta ^+ \in \operatorname {\mathrm {acc}}(C^{j+1}_\alpha )$ and again we can finish. So suppose this is not so. Let $\beta ^- : =\sup (C^{j^*}_\alpha \cap \beta ^+)$ so that $\beta ^-<\beta \leq \beta ^+$ . Now examining the construction of $C^j_\alpha $ for $j \in (j^*, i)$ , it is clear that for every $j\in [j^*, i)$ ,
However, this implies that $\beta \notin \operatorname {\mathrm {acc}}(C^i_\alpha )$ , which is a contradiction.
So $\vec {C^i}=\langle C^i_\alpha \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \alpha < \kappa \rangle $ is a C-sequence. Furthermore, since, $\vec {C^j}$ is $\sqsubseteq ^*$ -coherent for every $j<i$ , the preceding claim altogether implies that $\vec {C^i}$ is $\sqsubseteq ^*$ -coherent.
Consider the club $D:=\bigcap _{i< \omega _1}D_i$ . As $\vec C$ witnesses $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}(\kappa , T)$ , the following set is stationary:
Notice that by the nature of our recursive construction, for all $i< \omega _1$ ,
and hence, for all $\beta \in B$ and $i<\omega _1$ ,
Pick $\delta \in S\cap \operatorname {\mathrm {acc}}^+(B)$ . For each $i< \omega _1$ the following ordinal is smaller than $\delta $
We now perform a case analysis to reach a contradiction.
CASE 1. $\operatorname {\mathrm {cf}}(\delta )> \aleph _0$ . Let $\epsilon ^*:= \sup _{i< \omega } \epsilon _i$ , so that $\epsilon ^*< \delta $ . Pick $\beta \in (\epsilon ^*, \delta )\cap B$ . For every $i< \omega $ , let $\gamma _i:= \min (C^i_\delta \setminus \beta )$ so that $\langle \gamma _i \ {\mathrel {|}}\ i< \omega \rangle $ is weakly decreasing. Then pick $i< \omega $ such that $\gamma _i= \gamma _{i+1}$ .
SUBCASE 1.1. $\gamma _i> \beta $ . It follows that $\gamma _i \in \operatorname {\mathrm {nacc}}(C^i_\delta )$ . As $\epsilon ^*< \beta < \gamma _i$ , we have that $\gamma _i \notin F^{D_i}\cap T$ . It follows from our recursive construction that $C^{i+1}_\delta \cap [\beta , \gamma _i) = C^{i+1}_{\gamma _i} \cap [\beta , \gamma _i)$ and the latter set is nonempty so that $\gamma _{i+1} < \gamma _i$ which is a contradiction.
SUBCASE 1.2. $\gamma _i = \beta $ and $\beta \in \operatorname {\mathrm {nacc}}(C^i_\delta )$ . So $\gamma _i$ is an element of $\operatorname {\mathrm {nacc}}(C^i_\delta )$ above $\epsilon ^*$ , and we are back to Subcase 1.1.
SUBCASE 1.3. $\gamma _i = \beta $ and $\beta \in \operatorname {\mathrm {acc}}(C^i_\delta )$ . In this case, by $\sqsubseteq ^*$ -coherence, we have that $\sup ((C^i_{\beta }\mathbin \triangle C^i_\delta )\cap \beta ) < \beta $ . This implies that
But $D\subseteq F^{D_i}$ , contradicting the fact that $\epsilon _i< \beta $ .
CASE 2. $\operatorname {\mathrm {cf}}(\delta )= \aleph _0$ . Find an uncountable $I \subseteq \omega _1$ such that
is smaller than $\delta $ . Pick $\beta \in (\epsilon ^*, \delta )\cap B$ . For every $i< \omega _1$ , let $\gamma _i:= \min (C^i_\delta \setminus \beta )$ so that $\langle \gamma _i \ {\mathrel {|}}\ i< \omega _1\rangle $ is weakly decreasing. Pick a large enough $i\in I$ such that $\gamma _i= \gamma _{i+1}$ .
SUBCASE 2.1. $\gamma _i> \beta $ . Same as in Subcase 1.1.
SUBCASE 2.2. $\gamma _i = \beta $ and $\beta \in \operatorname {\mathrm {nacc}}(C^i_\delta )$ . Same as in Subcase 1.2.
SUBCASE 2.3. $\gamma _i = \beta $ and $\beta \in \operatorname {\mathrm {acc}}(C^i_\delta )$ . Same as in Subcase 1.3.
Corollary 3.20. If $\square (\kappa )$ holds and $J_\omega [\kappa ]$ contains a stationary set, then for all stationary subsets $S,T$ of $\kappa $ , there exists an $\sqsubseteq ^*$ -coherent C-sequence $\vec C=\langle C_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta <\kappa \rangle $ such that $\vec C{\mathbin \upharpoonright } S$ witnesses $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}(S,T)$ .
Remark 3.21. By [Reference Rinot57, Corollary 5.7], for every cardinal $\lambda \ge \beth _\omega $ , $J[\lambda ^+]$ contains a stationary set, in particular, so does $J_\omega [\lambda ^+]$ . When put together with the preceding, this yields Theorem B.
Question 3.22. Suppose that $\square (\kappa )$ holds with $\kappa \ge \aleph _2$ . Does there exist an $\sqsubseteq ^*$ -coherent C-sequence that witnesses $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}(\kappa ,E^\kappa _{\ge \aleph _1})$ ?
Recalling Theorem 3.11, we now turn to deal with stationary subsets of $E^{\lambda ^+}_{\operatorname {\mathrm {cf}}(\lambda )}$ , dividing the results into two, depending on whether $\lambda $ is regular or singular.
Theorem 3.23. Suppose that $\lambda $ is a regular uncountable cardinal, and $\square ^*_\lambda $ holds.
For every stationary $S\subseteq E^{\lambda ^+}_\lambda $ , there exists a transversal $\vec C=\langle C_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta <\lambda ^+ \rangle $ for $\square ^*_\lambda $ such that $\vec C{\mathbin \upharpoonright } S$ witnesses $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\lambda (S,E^{\lambda ^+}_\lambda )$ .
Proof Suppose not, and fix a stationary $S\subseteq E^{\lambda ^+}_\lambda $ that constitutes a counterexample. As $\square ^*_\lambda $ holds, we may fix a transversal $\vec e=\langle e_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta <\lambda ^+ \rangle $ for $\square ^*_\lambda $ . We shall recursively construct a sequence $\langle (D_n,\vec {e^n},\vec {C^n})\ {\mathrel {|}}\ n<\omega \rangle $ such that $D_n$ is a club in $\lambda ^+$ , and $\vec {e^n}$ and $\vec {C^n}$ are transversals for $\square ^*_\lambda $ .
Set $D_0:=\operatorname {\mathrm {acc}}(\lambda ^+)$ , $\vec {e^0}:=\vec e$ and $\vec {C^0}:=\vec e$ . Next, suppose that $n<\omega $ and that $\langle (D_j,\vec {e^j},\vec {C^j})\ {\mathrel {|}}\ j\le n\rangle $ has already been successfully defined. As $\vec {C^n}=\langle C_\delta ^n\ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta <\lambda ^+\rangle $ is a transversal for $\square ^*_\lambda $ , by the choice of the stationary set S, it follows that we may pick a subclub $D_{n+1}\subseteq D_n$ such that, for every $\delta \in S$ ,
Consider the postprocessing function $\Phi _{D_{n+1}}$ from Definition 2.12. For every $\delta \in \lambda ^+\setminus S$ , let $e_\delta ^{n+1}:=e_\delta $ and $C_\delta ^{n+1}:=e_\delta $ . For every $\delta \in S$ , let $e_\delta ^{n+1}:=\Phi _{D_{n+1}}(C^n_\delta )$ , and then let
By [Reference Brodsky and Rinot10, Lemma 2.8], $\vec {e^{n+1}}:=\langle e_\delta ^{n+1}\ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta <\lambda ^+\rangle $ is again a transversal for $\square ^*_\lambda $ .
Claim 3.23.1. $\vec {C^{n+1}}:=\langle C_\delta ^{n+1}\ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta <\kappa \rangle $ is a transversal for $\square ^*_\lambda $ .
Proof Since $\vec {e^{n+1}}$ is a $\lambda $ -bounded C-sequence, the definition of $\vec {C^{n+1}}$ makes it clear that it is as well. Suppose that $\vec {C^{n+1}}$ is not weakly coherent, and pick the least $\alpha <\lambda ^+$ such that
As $\vec {C^{n+1}}{\mathbin \upharpoonright }(\lambda ^+\setminus S)=\vec {e^{n+1}}{\mathbin \upharpoonright }(\lambda ^+\setminus S)$ , and $\vec {e^{n+1}}$ is a transversal for $\square ^*_\lambda $ , it follows that
so we may fix $\Delta \in [S]^{\lambda ^+}$ such that:
-
• $\delta \mapsto C^{n+1}_\delta \cap \alpha $ is injective over $\Delta $ , but
-
• $\delta \mapsto e^{n+1}_\delta \cap \alpha $ is constant over $\Delta $ .
Fix $\epsilon <\alpha $ such that $\sup (e^{n+1}_\delta \cap \alpha )=\epsilon $ for all $\delta \in \Delta $ . By minimality of $\alpha $ , and by possibly shrinking $\Delta $ further, we may also assume that
-
• $\delta \mapsto C^{n+1}_\delta \cap \epsilon $ is constant over $\Delta $ .
It thus follows from the definition of $\vec {C^{n+1}}$ that the map $\delta \mapsto C^{n+1}_\delta \cap [\epsilon ,\alpha )$ is injective over $\Delta $ , and that, for every $\delta \in \Delta $ , $C^{n+1}_\delta \cap [\epsilon ,\alpha )=e_\gamma \cap [\epsilon ,\alpha )$ for $\gamma :=\min (e_\delta ^{n+1}\setminus (\epsilon +1))$ . In particular,
contradicting the fact that $\vec e$ is a transversal for a $\square ^*_\lambda $ -sequence.
This completes the construction of the sequence $\langle (D_n,\vec {e^n},\vec {C^n})\ {\mathrel {|}}\ n<\omega \rangle $ . Now, let $D:=\bigcap _{n<\omega }D_n$ . Pick $\delta \in S$ such that $\operatorname {\mathrm {otp}}(D\cap \delta )=\omega ^\delta>\lambda $ . Recall that, for every $n<\omega $ , the following ordinal is smaller than $\delta $ :
Since $\operatorname {\mathrm {cf}}(\lambda )>\omega $ , for every $\alpha <\delta $ , $\operatorname {\mathrm {otp}}(\bigcup _{n<\omega }C_\delta ^n\cap \alpha )<\lambda $ . So, $\operatorname {\mathrm {otp}}(\bigcup _{n<\omega }C_\delta ^n)=\lambda <\omega ^\delta =\operatorname {\mathrm {otp}}(D\cap \delta )$ , and we may fix $\beta \in D\setminus \bigcup _{n<\omega }C_\delta ^n$ above $\sup _{n<\omega }\epsilon _n$ . Clearly, for each $n<\omega $ , $\gamma _n:=\min (C_\delta ^n\setminus \beta )$ is an element of $\operatorname {\mathrm {nacc}}(C_\delta ^n)$ above $\beta $ .
Let $n<\omega $ . Since $e^{n+1}_\delta =\Phi _{D_{n+1}}(C^n_\delta )$ and $\sup (D_{n+1}\cap \delta )=\delta $ ,
In particular, $\sup (D_{n+1}\cap \gamma _n)\in e_\delta ^{n+1}$ . As $\gamma _n>\beta $ and $\beta \in D\subseteq D_{n+1}$ , it is the case that $\beta \le \sup (D_{n+1}\cap \gamma _n)$ . As $e^{n+1}_\delta \subseteq C^{n+1}_\delta $ , altogether,
Now, pick $n<\omega $ such that $\gamma _{n+1}=\gamma _n$ . There are two options, each leads to a contradiction.
$\blacktriangleright $ If $\gamma _{n+1}\in e^{n+1}_\delta $ , then since $e^{n+1}_\delta \subseteq C^{n+1}_\delta $ , and $\gamma _{n+1}\in \operatorname {\mathrm {nacc}}(C^{n+1}_\delta )$ , $\gamma _{n+1}\in \operatorname {\mathrm {nacc}}(e^{n+1}_\delta )$ . As $\gamma _{n+1}\in e^{n+1}_\delta \subseteq D_{n+1}\subseteq D_0$ , $\gamma _{n+1}$ is a limit ordinal. Since $C_\delta ^{n+1}\cap [\beta ,\gamma _{n+1})$ is empty, the definition of $C^{n+1}_\delta $ implies that $\operatorname {\mathrm {cf}}(\gamma _{n+1})=\lambda $ . Altogether, $\gamma _{n+1}\in \operatorname {\mathrm {nacc}}(C^{n+1}_\delta )\cap D_{n+1}\cap E^{\lambda ^+}_\lambda $ , contradicting the fact that $\gamma _{n+1}>\beta >\epsilon _{n+1}$ .
$\blacktriangleright $ If $\gamma _{n+1}\notin e^{n+1}_\delta $ , then since $\gamma _{n+1}=\gamma _n\in C^n_\delta $ , the definition of $e^{n+1}_\delta $ implies that $\gamma _{n+1}<\sup (D_{n+1}\cap \gamma _n)$ . So, this time,
contradicting the choice of n.
In order to obtain a correct analogue of the preceding result, we introduce the following natural strengthening of Definition 2.2, in which we replace the stationary set $T\subseteq \kappa $ by a sequence $\vec T = \langle T_i \ {\mathrel {|}}\ i< \theta \rangle $ of stationary subsets of $\kappa $ .
Definition 3.24. $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\xi (S, \vec T, \sigma ,\vec J)$ asserts the existence of a $\xi $ -bounded C-sequence $\vec C=\langle C_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle $ such that, for every club $D\subseteq \kappa $ there is a $\delta \in S$ such that for every $i< \min \{\delta , \theta \}$ ,
Convention 3.25. Convention 2.3 applies to the above definition, as well.
Theorem 3.26. Suppose that $\lambda $ is a singular cardinal of uncountable cofinality, and $\square ^*_\lambda $ holds. Let $\langle \lambda _i\ {\mathrel {|}}\ i<\operatorname {\mathrm {cf}}(\lambda )\rangle $ be the increasing enumeration of a club in $\lambda $ .
For every stationary $S \subseteq E^{\lambda ^+}_{>\omega }$ , there exists a transversal $\vec C=\langle C_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta <\lambda ^+ \rangle $ for $\square ^*_\lambda $ such that $\vec C{\mathbin \upharpoonright } S$ witnesses $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\lambda (S, \langle E^{\lambda ^+}_{\geq \lambda _i}\ {\mathrel {|}}\ i<\operatorname {\mathrm {cf}}(\lambda )\rangle )$ .
Proof Suppose not, and fix a stationary $S\subseteq E^{\lambda ^+}_{>\omega }$ that constitutes a counterexample. Without loss of generality, $\min (S)\ge \lambda $ . As $\square ^*_\lambda $ holds, we may fix a transversal $\vec e=\langle e_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta <\lambda ^+ \rangle $ for $\square ^*_\lambda $ . As $\lambda $ is singular, we may assume that $\operatorname {\mathrm {otp}}(e_\delta )<\lambda $ for every $\delta <\lambda ^+$ (e.g., by appealing to [Reference Brodsky and Rinot9, Lemma 3.1] with $\Sigma :=\{\lambda _i\ {\mathrel {|}}\ i<\operatorname {\mathrm {cf}}(\lambda )\}$ ).
Following the proof approach of Theorem 3.23, we shall recursively construct a sequence $\langle (D_n,\vec {e^n},\vec {C^n})\ {\mathrel {|}}\ n<\omega \rangle $ such that $D_n$ is a club in $\lambda ^+$ , and $\vec {e^n}$ and $\vec {C^n}$ are transversals for $\square ^*_\lambda $ .
Set $D_0:=\operatorname {\mathrm {acc}}(\lambda ^+)$ , $\vec {e^0}:=\vec e$ and $\vec {C^0}:=\vec e$ . Next, suppose that $n<\omega $ and that $\langle (D_j,\vec {e^j},\vec {C^j})\ {\mathrel {|}}\ j\le n\rangle $ has already been successfully defined. As $\vec {C^n}=\langle C_\delta ^n\ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta <\lambda ^+\rangle $ is a transversal for $\square ^*_\lambda $ , by the choice of the stationary set S, it follows that we may pick a subclub $D_{n+1}\subseteq D_n$ such that, for every $\delta \in S$ , for some $i_\delta ^{n+1}<\operatorname {\mathrm {cf}}(\lambda )$ ,
Consider the postprocessing function $\Phi _{D_{n+1}}$ from Definition 2.12. For every $\delta \in \lambda ^+\setminus S$ , let $e_\delta ^{n+1}:=e_\delta $ and $C_\delta ^{n+1}:=e_\delta $ . For every $\delta \in S$ , let $e_\delta ^{n+1}:=\Phi _{D_{n+1}}(C^n_\delta )$ , and then let
By [Reference Brodsky and Rinot10, Lemma 2.8], $\vec {e^{n+1}}:=\langle e_\delta ^{n+1}\ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta <\lambda ^+\rangle $ is again a transversal for $\square ^*_\lambda $ . By the exactly same proof of Claim 3.23.1, also $\vec {C^{n+1}}:=\langle C_\delta ^{n+1}\ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta <\lambda ^+\rangle $ is a transversal for $\square ^*_\lambda $ . Furthermore, $\operatorname {\mathrm {otp}}(e_\delta ^{n+1})\le \operatorname {\mathrm {otp}}(C_\delta ^{n+1})<\lambda $ for all $\delta <\lambda ^+$ .
This completes the construction of the sequence $\langle (D_n,\vec {e^n},\vec {C^n})\ {\mathrel {|}}\ n<\omega \rangle $ . Now, let $D:=\bigcap _{n<\omega }D_n$ . Pick $\delta \in S$ such that $\operatorname {\mathrm {otp}}(D\cap \delta )=\omega ^\delta>\lambda $ . Recall that, for every $n<\omega $ , the following ordinal is smaller than $\delta $ :
As $\operatorname {\mathrm {cf}}(\lambda )>\omega $ , $\operatorname {\mathrm {otp}}(\bigcup _{n<\omega }C_\delta ^n)<\lambda $ , so, we may fix $\beta \in D\setminus \bigcup _{n<\omega }C_\delta ^n$ above $\sup _{n<\omega }\epsilon _n$ . Clearly, for each $n<\omega $ , $\gamma _n:=\min (C_\delta ^n\setminus \beta )$ is an element of $\operatorname {\mathrm {nacc}}(C_\delta ^n)$ above $\beta $ .
Let $n<\omega $ . Since $e^{n+1}_\delta =\Phi _{D_{n+1}}(C^n_\delta )$ and $\sup (D_{n+1}\cap \delta )=\delta $ ,
In particular, $\sup (D_{n+1}\cap \gamma _n)\in e_\delta ^{n+1}$ . As $\gamma _n>\beta $ and $\beta \in D\subseteq D_{n+1}$ , it is the case that $\beta \le \sup (D_{n+1}\cap \gamma _n)$ . As $e^{n+1}_\delta \subseteq C^{n+1}_\delta $ , altogether,
Now, pick $n<\omega $ such that $\gamma _{n+1}=\gamma _n$ . There are two options, each leads to a contradiction.
$\blacktriangleright $ If $\gamma _{n+1}\in e^{n+1}_\delta $ , then since $e^{n+1}_\delta \subseteq C^{n+1}_\delta $ , and $\gamma _{n+1}\in \operatorname {\mathrm {nacc}}(C^{n+1}_\delta )$ , $\gamma _{n+1}\in \operatorname {\mathrm {nacc}}(e^{n+1}_\delta )$ . As, $\gamma _{n+1}\in e^{n+1}_\delta \subseteq D_{n+1}\subseteq D_0$ , $\gamma $ is a limit ordinal. So, since $C_\delta ^{n+1}\cap [\beta ,\gamma _{n+1})$ is empty, the definition of $C^{n+1}_\delta $ implies that $\operatorname {\mathrm {cf}}(\gamma _{n+1})\ge \lambda _{i^{n+1}_\delta }$ . Altogether, $\gamma _{n+1}\in \operatorname {\mathrm {nacc}}(C^{n+1}_\delta )\cap D_{n+1}\cap E^{\lambda ^+}_{\lambda _{i^{n+1}_\delta }}$ , contradicting the fact that $\gamma _{n+1}>\beta >\epsilon _{n+1}$ .
$\blacktriangleright $ If $\gamma _{n+1}\notin e^{n+1}_\delta $ , then since $\gamma _{n+1}=\gamma _n\in C^n_\delta $ , the definition of $e^{n+1}_\delta $ implies that $\gamma _{n+1}<\sup (D_{n+1}\cap \gamma _n)$ . So, this time,
contradicting the choice of n.
By applying the proof of Proposition 2.22 on the C-sequence produced by the preceding, we get a somewhat cleaner form of guessing, as follows.
Corollary 3.27. Suppose that $\lambda $ is a singular cardinal of uncountable cofinality, and $\square ^*_\lambda $ holds. For every stationary $S \subseteq E^{\lambda ^+}_{>\omega }$ , there exists a transversal $\vec C=\langle C_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta <\lambda ^+ \rangle $ for $\square ^*_\lambda $ satisfying the following $:$
-
• for every $\delta <\lambda ^+$ , $\operatorname {\mathrm {otp}}(C_\delta )<\lambda ;$
-
• for every club $D\subseteq \lambda ^+$ , there exists $\delta \in S$ such that $C_\delta \subseteq D$ and $\sup (\operatorname {\mathrm {nacc}}(C_\delta )\cap D\cap E^{\lambda ^+}_{>\mu })=\delta $ for every $\mu <\lambda $ .
Question 3.28. Is it possible to waive the assumption of Corollary 3.27 that the singular cardinal $\lambda $ be of uncountable cofinality?
3.1 When coherence is not available
Just as Facts 3.8 and 3.9 and Theorem 3.11 were obtained simply from running the proofs of Section 2 on C-sequences which had additional coherence features, we can conversely run the proofs we have just seen on C-sequences which lack coherence and still obtain useful results.
Specifically, the proofs of Theorems 3.23 and 3.26 (together with Proposition 2.22) yield, respectively, the general case of the introduction’s Fact 1.4 and a result from [Reference Eisworth and Shelah18].
Fact 3.29 [Reference Shelah, Gabbay, Macintyre and Scott62, Claim 2.4].
For every regular uncountable cardinal $\lambda $ , for every stationary $S\subseteq E^{\lambda ^+}_\lambda $ , $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\lambda (S,E^{\lambda ^+}_\lambda )$ holds. Furthermore, for every triple $\lambda \le \nu <\kappa $ of regular uncountable cardinals, for every stationary $S\subseteq E^\kappa _\lambda $ , $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\nu (S, E^\kappa _{\ge \nu })$ holds.
Fact 3.30 [Reference Eisworth and Shelah18, Theorem 2].
For every singular cardinal $\lambda $ of uncountable cofinality and every stationary $S \subseteq E^{\lambda ^+}_{\operatorname {\mathrm {cf}}(\lambda )}$ , there exists a $\operatorname {\mathrm {cf}}(\lambda )$ -bounded C-sequence $\langle C_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle $ satisfying the following.
For every club $D\subseteq \lambda ^+$ , there exists $\delta \in S$ such that $C_\delta \subseteq D$ and $\langle \operatorname {\mathrm {cf}}(\gamma )\ {\mathrel {|}}\ \gamma \in \operatorname {\mathrm {nacc}}(C_\delta )\rangle $ is strictly increasing and converging to $\lambda $ .
Likewise, by changing the choice of the initial C-sequence $\vec e$ in the proof of Theorem 3.19, one obtains a proof of the following.
Theorem 3.31 (Shelah).
Suppose that $R,S,T$ are stationary subsets of a regular cardinal $\kappa \ge \aleph _2$ .
-
(1) If T is a nonreflecting stationary set, then $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}(S,T)$ holds.
-
(2) If R is a nonreflecting stationary subset of $E^\kappa _{\ge \sigma }$ , then $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}(R,T,\sigma )$ implies $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}(S,T,\sigma )$ .
Remark 3.32. Note that even if $S\subseteq E^\kappa _\xi $ , we still get $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}(S,T)$ , but not $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\xi (S,T)$ . Indeed, by the preceding corollary, if there exists a nonreflecting stationary subset of $E^{\aleph _2}_{\aleph _0}$ , then $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}(E^{\aleph _2}_{\aleph _1},E^{\aleph _2}_{\aleph _0})$ holds. In contrast, running the forcing from [Reference Asperó, Geschke, Lowe and Schlicht2, Theorem 1.6] over a model of $\square _{\omega _1}$ , one gets a generic extension with a nonreflecting stationary subset of $E^{\aleph _2}_{\aleph _0}$ in which $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_{\omega _1}(E^{\aleph _2}_{\aleph _1},E^{\aleph _2}_{\aleph _0})$ fails.
Corollary 3.33. Suppose $\sigma <\sigma ^+<\kappa $ are infinite regular cardinals, and $E^\kappa _\sigma $ admits a nonreflecting stationary set. For every stationary $S\subseteq \kappa :$
-
(1) $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}(S,\kappa ,\sigma )$ holds.
-
(2) If $\kappa =\lambda ^+$ and $\sigma \neq \operatorname {\mathrm {cf}}(\lambda )$ , then $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}(S,T,\sigma )$ holds for every stationary $T\subseteq \kappa $ .
Proof Let R be a nonreflecting stationary subset of $E^\kappa _\sigma $ , By Theorem 2.14, $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}(R,\kappa ,\sigma )$ holds. By Corollary 2.23, if $\kappa =\lambda ^+$ and $\sigma \neq \operatorname {\mathrm {cf}}(\lambda )$ , then furthermore $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}(R,T,\sigma )$ holds for every stationary $T\subseteq \kappa $ . Now appeal to Corollary 3.31(2).
Forgetting about coherence, Corollary 3.20 has the following strong consequence.
Corollary 3.34. Suppose that $\square (\lambda ^+)$ holds, and one of the following $:$
-
• $\lambda \ge \beth _\omega $ .
-
• $\lambda ^{\aleph _0}=\lambda $ .
-
• $\lambda =\mathfrak b=\aleph _1$ .
-
• $\lambda \ge 2^{\aleph _1}$ and Shelah’s Strong Hypothesis ( $\textsf{{SSH}}$ ) holds.
-
• There exists an infinite regular cardinal $\theta $ such that $2^\theta \le \lambda <\theta ^{+\theta }$ .
Then $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}(S,T)$ holds for all stationary subsets $S,T$ of $\lambda ^+$ .
Proof By Corollaries 5.1, 5.3, and 5.7 of [Reference Rinot57], any of the above hypotheses imply that $J_\omega [\lambda ^+]$ contains a stationary set.
4 Partitioned club guessing
The theme of this section is partitioned club guessing as in Fact 1.7. The main definition is Definition 4.1, where two types of partitions are considered. The bulk of our results, with the exception of Section 4.2, however are about the stronger notion of partitioning club guessing. The difference being that in the former we obtain a C-sequence and a partition, whereas in the latter we are supplied with a C-sequence which, for example, may possess additional features, and then are given the task of partitioning it,
In Section 4.1, we partition club guessing sequences using colouring principles from [Reference Inamdar and Rinot26, Reference Inamdar and Rinot27] which in fact arose while working on partitioning club guessing. We show how these colouring principles allow for an abstract approach to partitioning club guessing, separating the club guessing technology from the combinatorial technology given to us by the relevant hypothesis.Footnote 7
In Section 4.2, we construct partitioned club guessing using these colouring principles. Furthermore, we can obtain partitioned club guessing sequences satisfying coherence features as well.
In Section 4.3, we list results from [Reference Inamdar and Rinot26–Reference Inamdar and Rinot28] under which the colouring principles can be obtained, and draw conclusions. In particular, we find a setup sufficient for an higher analogue of a combinatorial construction on $\aleph _1$ due to Moore from [Reference Moore44].
In Section 4.4, we address the problem of partitioning a club guessing C-sequence $\vec C$ over $S\subseteq \kappa $ into $\kappa $ many guessing sequences $\langle \vec C{\mathbin \upharpoonright } S_i\ {\mathrel {|}}\ i<\kappa \rangle $ .
Definition 4.1. For a C-sequence $\vec C=\langle C_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle $ , we define two sets of cardinals:
-
• $\Theta _1(\vec C,T,\sigma ,\vec J)$ denotes the set of all nonzero cardinals $\theta $ for which there exists a function $h:\kappa \rightarrow \theta $ satisfying the following.For every club $D\subseteq \kappa $ , there exists $\delta \in S$ such that, for every $\tau <\theta $ ,
$$ \begin{align*}\{\beta<\delta\ {\mathrel{|}}\ h(\operatorname{\mathrm{otp}}(C_\delta\cap\beta))=\tau \ \&\ \operatorname{\mathrm{succ}}_\sigma(C_\delta\setminus\beta)\subseteq D\cap T\}\in J_\delta^+.\end{align*} $$ -
• $\Theta _2(\vec C,T,\sigma ,\vec J)$ denotes the set of all nonzero cardinals $\theta $ for which there exists a sequence of functions $\langle h_\delta :C_\delta \rightarrow \theta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle $ satisfying the following.
For every club $D\subseteq \kappa $ , there exists $\delta \in S$ such that, for every $\tau <\theta $ ,
$$ \begin{align*}\{\beta<\delta\ {\mathrel{|}}\ h_\delta(\min(C_\delta\setminus\beta))=\tau \ \&\ \operatorname{\mathrm{succ}}_\sigma(C_\delta\setminus\beta)\subseteq D\cap T\}\in J_\delta^+.\end{align*} $$
Convention 4.2. Convention 2.3 applies to the above definition, as well.
Remark 4.3. $\Theta _1(\vec C,T,\sigma ,\vec J)\subseteq \Theta _2(\vec C,T,\sigma ,\vec J)$ .
Proposition 4.4. For a stationary $S\subseteq E^\kappa _\theta $ and a sequence $\vec C$ witnessing $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}(S,T,\kappa )$ , $\theta \in \Theta _2(\vec C,T,\sigma )$ for any choice of $\sigma <\theta $ .
Lemma 4.5. Suppose that $\vec C=\langle C_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle $ is a C-sequence witnessing $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\xi (S,T)$ . For every $\theta \in \Theta _2(\vec C,T)$ such that $\alpha +\beta <\xi $ for all $(\alpha ,\beta )\in \theta \times \xi $ , there exists a C-sequence $\vec C^\bullet =\langle C^{\bullet }_{\delta }\ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle $ witnessing $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\xi (S,T)$ for which $\theta \in \Theta _1(\vec {C^\bullet },T)$ .
Proof Without loss of generality, $S\subseteq \operatorname {\mathrm {acc}}(\kappa )$ . Suppose that $\theta \in \Theta _2(\vec C,T)$ is such that $\alpha +\beta <\xi $ for all $(\alpha ,\beta )\in \theta \times \xi $ . Let $h:\kappa \rightarrow \theta $ be a surjection such that, for every $\epsilon <\kappa $ , $\{ h(\iota +1)\ {\mathrel {|}}\ \epsilon <\iota <\epsilon +\theta \}=\theta $ . If $\theta $ is uncountable, we also require that $\{ h(\omega \cdot \iota )\ {\mathrel {|}}\ \epsilon <\iota <\epsilon +\theta \}=\theta $ for every $\epsilon <\kappa $ . It follows that for each $(\gamma ,\epsilon ,\tau )\in \kappa \times \kappa \times \theta $ , we may fix $y_{\gamma ,\epsilon ,\tau }$ such that:
-
• $y_{\gamma ,\epsilon ,\tau }$ is a closed nonempty subset of $E^\kappa _{<\theta }$ ;
-
• $\min (y_{\gamma ,\epsilon ,\tau })=\gamma $ ;
-
• $\max (y_{\gamma ,\epsilon ,\tau })<\gamma +\theta $ ;
-
• $h(\epsilon +\operatorname {\mathrm {otp}}(y_{\gamma ,\epsilon ,\tau })-1)=\tau $ .
Fix a sequence $\langle h_\delta :C_\delta \rightarrow \theta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle $ witnessing that $\theta \in \Theta _2(\vec C,T)$ . We now construct $\vec {C^\bullet }=\langle C_\delta ^\bullet \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle $ as follows. Given $\delta \in S$ , let $\langle \delta _i\ {\mathrel {|}}\ i<\operatorname {\mathrm {otp}}(C_\delta )\rangle $ denote the increasing enumeration of $\{0\}\cup C_\delta $ . Construct a sequence $\langle x^\delta _i\ {\mathrel {|}}\ i<\operatorname {\mathrm {otp}}(C_\delta )\rangle $ by recursion on $i<\operatorname {\mathrm {otp}}(C_\delta )$ , as follows:
$\blacktriangleright $ If $\delta _{i+1}<\delta _i+\theta $ , then set $x_i^\delta :=\{\delta _i\}$ .
$\blacktriangleright $ If $\delta _{i+1}\ge \delta _i+\theta $ , then set $x_i^\delta :=y_{\gamma ,\epsilon ,\tau }$ , for $\gamma :=\delta _i$ , $\epsilon :=\operatorname {\mathrm {otp}}(\bigcup _{i'<i}x^\delta _{i'})$ , and $\tau :=h_\delta (\delta _{i})$ . In particular, $h(\operatorname {\mathrm {otp}}(\bigcup _{i'\le i}x^\delta _{i'})-1)=h_\delta (\delta _{i})$ .
Finally, let $C^{\bullet }_{\delta }:=\bigcup _{i<\operatorname {\mathrm {otp}}(C_\delta )}x^\delta _i$ , so that $C^{\bullet }_{\delta }$ is a club in $\delta $ . Note that $\operatorname {\mathrm {otp}}(C^{\bullet }_{\delta })\le \xi $ , since $\operatorname {\mathrm {otp}}(C_\delta )\le \xi $ and $\alpha +\beta <\xi $ for all $(\alpha ,\beta )\in \theta \times \xi $ . Thus, to see that $\vec C^\bullet :=\langle C^{\bullet }_{\delta }\ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle $ and h are as sought, let D be a club in $\kappa $ . By possibly shrinking D, we may assume that every element of D is an indecomposable ordinal greater than $\theta $ .
Pick $\delta \in S$ such that, for every $\tau <\theta $ ,
Equivalently, for every $\tau <\theta $ , the following set is cofinal in $\delta $ :
Let $\tau <\theta $ and let $\beta \in B_\tau $ . Pick $i<\operatorname {\mathrm {otp}}(C_\delta )$ such that $\beta =\delta _i$ . Put $\beta ':=\max (x^\delta _i)$ so that $\beta \le \beta '<\delta _{i+1}=\min (C^{\bullet }_{\delta }\setminus (\beta '+1))$ . Since $\delta _{i+1}\in D$ , we know that $\delta _i+\theta <\delta _{i+1}$ . Consequently,
as sought.
Remark 4.6. The preceding lemma should not be interpreted as saying that $\Theta _1(\ldots )$ and $\Theta _2(\ldots )$ are essentially the same, since the move from $\vec C$ to $\vec {C^\bullet }$ may lead to the loss of coherence features of $\vec C$ . In addition, the above lemma is limited to $\sigma =1$ , though a simple tweak yields that if $\vec C$ is a witness for $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\xi (S,T,\sigma ,\langle J_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle )$ with $\sigma <\min \{\omega +1,\theta \}$ , and $\operatorname {\mathrm {nacc}}(\delta )\in J_\delta $ for all $\delta \in S$ , then a $\vec C^\bullet $ may be cooked-up to satisfy $\theta \in \Theta _1(\vec {C^\bullet },T,\sigma )$ .
4.1 Using colourings
We now introduce two colouring principles from [Reference Inamdar and Rinot26] which we shall use in this subsection. As explained in [Reference Inamdar and Rinot26, Remark 8.2], these principles are a spin-off of Sierpiński’s onto mapping principle.
Definition 4.7 [Reference Inamdar and Rinot26].
Let J be an ideal over $\lambda $ , and $\theta \le \lambda $ be some cardinal.
-
• $\operatorname {{{\sf onto}}}(J,\theta )$ asserts the existence of a colouring $c:[\lambda ]^2\rightarrow \theta $ such that for every $B\in J^+$ , there is an $\eta <\lambda $ such that
$$ \begin{align*}c[\{\eta\}\circledast B]=\theta;\end{align*} $$ -
• $\operatorname {{{\sf unbounded}}}(J,\theta )$ asserts the existence of an upper-regressive colouring $c:[\lambda ]^2\rightarrow \theta $ such that for every $B\in J^+$ , there is an $\eta <\lambda $ such that
$$ \begin{align*}\operatorname{\mathrm{otp}}(c[\{\eta\}\circledast B])=\theta.\end{align*} $$
Our first application of which will make use of the following pumping up result.
Fact 4.8 [Reference Inamdar and Rinot27, Theorem 4.1].
Let $\theta \le \lambda $ be a pair of infinite cardinals, with $\lambda $ regular.
-
(1) If $\operatorname {{{\sf onto}}}(J^{\mathrm {bd}}[\lambda ],\theta )$ holds, then there exists a colouring $c:[\lambda ]^2\rightarrow \theta $ such that for every $\lambda $ -complete ideal J on some ordinal $\delta $ of cofinality $\lambda $ and every map $\psi :\delta \rightarrow \lambda $ satisfying $\sup (\psi [B])=\lambda $ for all $B\in J^+$ , the following holds. For every $B\in J^+$ , there exists an $\eta <\lambda $ such that
$$ \begin{align*}\{ \tau<\theta\ {\mathrel{|}}\ \{ \beta\in B\ {\mathrel{|}}\ \eta<\psi(\beta)\ \&\ c(\eta,\psi(\beta))=\tau\}\in J^+\}=\theta.\end{align*} $$ -
(2) If $\operatorname {{{\sf unbounded}}}(J^{\mathrm {bd}}[\lambda ],\theta )$ holds, then there exists a colouring $c:[\lambda ]^2\rightarrow \theta $ such that for every $\lambda $ -complete ideal J on some ordinal $\delta $ of cofinality $\lambda $ and every map $\psi :\delta \rightarrow \lambda $ satisfying $\sup (\psi [B])=\lambda $ for all $B\in J^+$ , the following holds. For every $B\in J^+$ , there exists an $\eta <\lambda $ such that
$$ \begin{align*}\operatorname{\mathrm{otp}}(\{ \tau<\theta\ {\mathrel{|}}\ \{ \beta\in B\ {\mathrel{|}}\ \eta<\psi(\beta)\ \&\ c(\eta,\psi(\beta))=\tau\}\in J^+\})=\theta.\end{align*} $$
Theorem 4.9. Suppose that $\vec C$ witnesses $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\xi (S,T,\sigma ,\vec J)$ with $S\subseteq E^\kappa _\lambda $ , and that $\theta \le \lambda $ is infinite.
-
(1) If $\operatorname {{{\sf onto}}}(J^{\mathrm {bd}}[\lambda ],\theta )$ holds and $\xi =\lambda $ , then $\theta \in \Theta _1(\vec C,T,\sigma ,\vec J)$ .
-
(2) If $\operatorname {{{\sf onto}}}(J^{\mathrm {bd}}[\lambda ],\theta )$ holds, then $\theta \in \Theta _2(\vec C,T,\sigma ,\vec J)$ .
-
(3) If $\operatorname {{{\sf unbounded}}}(J^{\mathrm {bd}}[\lambda ],\theta )$ holds and $\theta ^+<\kappa $ , then $\theta \in \Theta _2(\vec C,T,\sigma ,\vec J)$ .
Proof For every $\delta \in S$ , fix a subclub $e_\delta $ of $C_\delta $ of ordertype $\lambda $ . In case that $\xi =\lambda $ , moreover set $e_\delta :=C_\delta $ . Define $\psi _\delta :\delta \rightarrow \lambda $ via $\psi _\delta (\beta ):= \operatorname {\mathrm {otp}}(e_\delta \cap \beta )$ and note that for every $\beta <\delta $ , $\psi _\delta (\beta )=\psi _\delta (\min (C_\delta \setminus \beta ))$ . As $J_\delta $ is a $\lambda $ -complete ideal on $\delta $ extending $J^{\mathrm {bd}}[\delta ]$ , it is also the case that $\sup (\psi _\delta [B])=\lambda $ for every $B \in J_\delta ^+$ .
(1) and (2): Suppose that $\operatorname {{{\sf onto}}}(J^{\mathrm {bd}}[\lambda ],\theta )$ holds, and fix a colouring $c:[\lambda ]^2\rightarrow \theta $ as in Fact 4.8(1).
Claim 4.9.1. There exists an $\eta <\lambda $ such that, for every club $D\subseteq \kappa $ , there exists a $\delta \in S$ , such that, for every $ \tau <\theta $ ,
Proof Suppose not. For every $\eta <\lambda $ , fix a counterexample club $D_\eta \subseteq \kappa $ . Let $D:=\bigcap _{\eta <\lambda }D_\eta $ . By the choice of $\vec C$ , let us now pick $\delta \in S$ such that the following set is in $J_\delta ^+$ :
Recalling that c was given by Fact 4.8(1), there is an $\eta < \lambda $ such that
However, as $D \subseteq D_\eta $ , this contradicts the choice of $D_\eta $ .
Let $\eta <\lambda $ be given by the preceding claim. Choose $\vec h=\langle h_\delta :C_\delta \rightarrow \theta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle $ satisfying $h_\delta (\beta )=c(\eta ,\psi _\delta (\beta ))$ for all $\delta \in S$ and $\beta \in C_\delta $ such that $\eta <\psi _\delta (\beta )$ . Then $\vec h$ witnesses that $\theta \in \Theta _2(\vec C,T,\sigma ,\vec J)$ . Furthermore, in the special case that $\vec C$ is $\lambda $ -bounded, any map $h:\kappa \rightarrow \theta $ satisfying $h(\bar \beta )=c(\eta ,\bar \beta )$ for every $\bar \beta \in (\eta ,\lambda )$ witnesses that $\theta \in \Theta _1(\vec C,T,\sigma ,\vec J)$ .
(3) Suppose that $\operatorname {{{\sf unbounded}}}(J^{\mathrm {bd}}[\lambda ],\theta )$ holds with $\theta < \lambda $ , and fix a colouring $c:[\lambda ]^2\rightarrow \theta $ as in Fact 4.8(2). For every club $D\subseteq \kappa $ , for all $\delta \in S$ and $\eta < \lambda $ , denote
Claim 4.9.2. There exists an $\eta <\lambda $ such that, for every club $D\subseteq \kappa $ , there exists a $\delta \in S$ such that $|D(\eta ,\delta )| = \theta $ .
Proof Suppose not. For every $\eta <\lambda $ , fix a counterexample club $D_\eta \subseteq \kappa $ . Let $D:=\bigcap _{\eta <\lambda }D_\eta $ . By the choice of $\vec C$ , let us now pick $\delta \in S$ such that the following set is in $J_\delta ^+$ :
Recalling that c was given by Fact 4.8(2), there is an $\eta < \lambda $ such that
So $|D(\eta , \delta )| = \theta $ . However, as $D \subseteq D_\eta $ , and $D_\eta $ was chosen so that $|D_\eta (\eta , \delta )|<\theta $ , we reach a contradiction.
We fix from here on an $\eta < \lambda $ as given by the previous claim, and for simplicity of notation, for $D\subseteq \kappa $ a club and $\delta \in S$ , we denote $D(\delta ):= D(\eta , \delta )$ .
Claim 4.9.3. There exists a club $D^* \subseteq \kappa $ such that for every club $D \subseteq D^*$ , there exists $\delta \in S$ such that $D(\delta )= D^*(\delta )$ and this set has size $\theta $ .
Proof Suppose this is not so. In that case, we can construct a $\subseteq $ -decreasing sequence $\langle D_i \ {\mathrel {|}}\ i \le \theta ^+\rangle $ of clubs in $\kappa $ as follows:
-
(i) $D_0 := \kappa $ ;
-
(ii) $D_{i+1} \subseteq D_i$ is some club such that for every $\delta \in S$ , either $|D(\delta )|<\theta $ or $D_{i+1}(\delta ) \subsetneq D_i(\delta )$ ;
-
(iii) for $i \in \operatorname {\mathrm {acc}}(\theta ^++1)$ , $D_i:=\bigcap _{i' < i}D_{i'}$ .
Since $D_{\theta ^+}$ is again a club in $\kappa $ , we may fix a $\delta \in S$ such that $|D_{\theta ^+}(\delta )|=\theta $ . In particular, for every $i \leq \theta ^+$ , $|D_{i}(\delta )|=\theta $ , and hence, by the construction, $\langle D_i(\delta ) \ {\mathrel {|}}\ i \leq \theta ^+\rangle $ must be a strictly $\subseteq $ -decreasing sequence of subsets of $D_0(\delta )$ , contradicting the fact that $|D_0(\delta )|=\theta $ .
Let $D^* \subseteq \kappa $ be given by the preceding claim. Then any sequence $\vec h=\langle h_\delta :C_\delta \rightarrow \theta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle $ satisfying that for all $\delta \in S$ and $\beta \in C_\delta $ with $\psi _\delta (\beta )>\eta $ ,
witnesses that $\theta \in \Theta _2(\vec C,T,\sigma ,\vec J)$ .
We now move on to the case of normal ideals. We first need an analogue of Fact 4.8. In what follows, for a set of ordinals A, its collapsing map is the unique function $\psi :A\rightarrow \operatorname {\mathrm {otp}}(A)$ satisfying $\psi (\alpha )=\operatorname {\mathrm {otp}}(A\cap \alpha )$ for all $\alpha \in A$ .
Theorem 4.10. Suppose that $\lambda $ is a regular uncountable cardinal, and $\theta \le \lambda $ is a cardinal.
-
(1) If $\operatorname {{{\sf unbounded}}}(\mathrm{NS}_\lambda ,\theta )$ holds, then there exists a colouring $c:[\lambda ]^2\rightarrow \theta $ such that for every $\lambda $ -complete normal ideal J on some ordinal $\delta $ of cofinality $\lambda $ , for every club A in $\delta $ of ordertype $\lambda $ , for its collapsing map $\psi :A\rightarrow \lambda $ the following holds. For all $B\in J^+$ , there exists an $\eta <\lambda $ such that
$$ \begin{align*}\operatorname{\mathrm{otp}}(\{ \tau<\theta\ {\mathrel{|}}\ \{ \beta\in B\cap A\ {\mathrel{|}}\ \eta<\psi(\beta)\ \&\ c(\eta,\psi(\beta))=\tau\}\in J^+\})=\theta.\end{align*} $$ -
(2) If $\operatorname {{{\sf onto}}}(\mathrm{NS}_\lambda ,\theta )$ holds, then there exists a colouring $c:[\lambda ]^2\rightarrow \theta $ such that for every normal $\lambda $ -complete ideal J on some ordinal $\delta $ of cofinality $\lambda $ , for every club A in $\delta $ of ordertype $\lambda $ , for its collapsing map $\psi :A\rightarrow \lambda $ the following holds. For all $B\in J^+$ , there exists an $\eta <\lambda $ such that
$$ \begin{align*}\{ \tau<\theta\ {\mathrel{|}}\ \{ \beta\in B\cap A\ {\mathrel{|}}\ \eta<\psi(\beta)\ \&\ c(\eta,\psi(\beta))=\tau\}\in J^+\}=\theta.\end{align*} $$
Proof Clauses (1) and (2) follow from [Reference Inamdar and Rinot26, Proposition 2.25]. Since the proof of Clause (2) was omitted in [Reference Inamdar and Rinot26], we give it here.
(2) Given a normal $\lambda $ -complete ideal J on some ordinal $\delta $ of cofinality $\lambda $ , and a club A in $\delta $ of ordertype $\lambda $ , it is the case that $A\in J^*$ , since J is normal. Let $\psi $ denote the collapsing map of A. For all $B \subseteq \delta $ , $\eta < \lambda $ and $\tau < \theta $ , denote
Suppose $\operatorname {{{\sf onto}}}(\mathrm{NS}_\lambda , \theta )$ holds, and fix a witnessing colouring $c:[\lambda ]^2\rightarrow \theta $ . Towards a contradiction, suppose that there exists $B\in J^+$ such that, for every $\eta < \lambda $ , there is a $\tau _\eta < \theta $ such that $B^{\eta , \tau _\eta } \in J$ . As J is normal, $E:= \psi ^{-1}[\bigtriangleup _{\eta <\lambda }(\lambda \setminus \psi [B^{\eta ,\tau _\eta }]]$ is in $J^*$ . Note that
As $E\in J^*$ and $B\in J^+$ , $B\cap E\in J^+$ , so since J is normal, $\psi [B\cap E]$ is stationary. It thus follows from the choice of c that we may pick $\eta < \lambda $ such that $c[\{\eta \}\circledast \psi [B\cap E]]=\theta $ . Find $\beta \in B\cap E$ such that $\psi (\beta )>\eta $ and $c(\eta , \psi (\beta )) = \tau _\eta $ . Then $\beta \in B^{\eta ,\tau _\eta }$ , contradicting the fact that $\beta \in E$ .
Theorem 4.11. Suppose that $\lambda $ is a regular uncountable cardinal, $\vec C$ witnesses $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\xi (S,T,\sigma ,\vec J)$ with $S\subseteq E^\kappa _\lambda $ and for every $\delta \in S$ , $J_\delta $ is a normal $\lambda $ -complete ideal on $\delta $ extending $J^{\mathrm {bd}}[\delta ]$ . Then $:$
-
(1) If $\operatorname {{{\sf onto}}}(\mathrm{NS}_\lambda ,\theta )$ holds and $\xi =\lambda $ , then $\theta \in \Theta _1(\vec C,T,\sigma ,\vec J)$ .
-
(2) If $\operatorname {{{\sf onto}}}(\mathrm{NS}_\lambda ,\theta )$ holds, then $\theta \in \Theta _2(\vec C,T,\sigma ,\vec J)$ .
-
(3) If $\operatorname {{{\sf unbounded}}}(\mathrm{NS}_\lambda ,\theta )$ holds and $\theta < \lambda $ , then $\theta _2\in \Theta _2(\vec C,T,\sigma ,\vec J)$ .
Proof Write $\vec C$ as $\langle C_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle $ . For each $\delta \in S$ , if $\operatorname {\mathrm {otp}}(C_\delta )=\lambda $ , then set $A_\delta :=C_\delta $ . Otherwise, just let $A_\delta $ be some club in $\delta $ of ordertype $\lambda $ . Then, let $\psi _\delta :A_\delta \rightarrow \lambda $ be the corresponding collapsing map. We can now repeat the proof of Theorem 4.9 except that we use Theorem 4.10 instead of Fact 4.8.
4.2 Maintaining coherence
By Theorem 4.9, $\operatorname {{{\sf onto}}}(J^{\mathrm {bd}}[\lambda ],\theta )$ implies that $\theta \in \Theta _1(\vec C,T)$ . In contrast, $\operatorname {{{\sf unbounded}}}(J^{\mathrm {bd}}[\lambda ],\theta )$ gives $\theta \in \Theta _2(\vec C,T)$ , and then Lemma 4.5 only yields another C-sequence $\vec {C^\bullet }$ such that $\theta \in \Theta _1(\vec {C^\bullet },T)$ .
In the next theorem, we combine the two results carefully in order to obtain a C-sequence $\vec {C^\bullet }$ with $\theta \in \Theta _1(\vec {C^\bullet },T)$ while maintaining some coherence features of the original sequence $\vec C$ .
Theorem 4.12. Suppose that $\theta <\lambda <\kappa $ are infinite cardinals, $\operatorname {{{\sf unbounded}}}(J^{\mathrm {bd}}[\lambda ],\theta )$ holds, and S is a stationary subset of $E^\kappa _\lambda $ .
For every C-sequence $\vec C=\langle C_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta <\kappa \rangle $ such that $\vec C{\mathbin \upharpoonright } S$ witnesses $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\lambda (S,T)$ , there exists a corresponding C-sequence $\vec {C^\bullet }=\langle C^{\bullet }_{\delta }\ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta <\kappa \rangle $ such that $:$
-
• $\vec {C^\bullet }{\mathbin \upharpoonright } S$ is $\lambda $ -bounded.
-
• If $\vec C$ is weakly coherent, then so is $\vec {C^\bullet }$ .
-
• For every infinite cardinal $\chi \in [\theta ,\kappa )$ , if $\vec C$ is $\mathrel {{}_{\chi }{\sqsubseteq }}$ -coherent, then so is $\vec {C^\bullet }$ .
-
• $\theta \in \Theta _1(\vec {C^\bullet }{\mathbin \upharpoonright } S,T)$ .
Proof Without loss of generality, $0\in C_\delta $ for all nonzero $\delta <\kappa $ . For every $\delta <\kappa $ , denote $\xi _\delta :=\operatorname {\mathrm {otp}}(C_\delta )$ , let $\psi _\delta :C_\delta \rightarrow \xi _\delta $ be the collapsing map of $C_\delta $ , and let $\langle \delta _i\ {\mathrel {|}}\ i<\xi _\delta \rangle $ denote the increasing enumeration of $C_\delta $ so that $\psi _\delta (\delta _i) = i$ for every $i< \xi _\delta $ .
Fix a colouring $c:[\lambda ]^2\rightarrow \theta $ as in Fact 4.8(2). For every club $D\subseteq \kappa $ , for all $\delta \in S$ and $\eta < \lambda $ , denote
By Claims 4.9.2 and 4.9.3, we may pick $\eta ^*<\lambda $ and a club $D^*\subseteq \kappa $ such that for every club $D \subseteq D^*$ , there exists $\delta \in S$ such that $D(\eta ^*,\delta )= D^*(\eta ^*,\delta )$ and this set has size $\theta $ . By possibly shrinking $D^*$ , we may assume that $D^*$ consists of indecomposable ordinals, and that $\min (D^*)>\theta $ .
For every $\delta \in S$ , since $\operatorname {\mathrm {cf}}(\delta )=\lambda>\theta $ , the set
is bounded in $\delta $ . So, by one more stabilization argument, we may fix an $\varepsilon <\lambda $ such that every club $D \subseteq D^*$ , there exists $\delta \in S$ such that $D(\eta ^*,\delta )= D^*(\eta ^*,\delta )$ , $|D^*(\eta ^*,\delta )|=\theta $ , and also
For all $\delta \in \operatorname {\mathrm {acc}}(\kappa )$ and $i\le \xi _\delta $ , denote
Fix a surjection $h:\kappa \rightarrow \theta $ and a sequence of sets $\langle y_{\gamma ,\epsilon ,\tau }\ {\mathrel {|}}\ (\gamma ,\epsilon ,\tau )\in \kappa \times \kappa \times \theta \rangle $ as in the proof of Lemma 4.5. We now construct the new C-sequence $\vec {C^\bullet }=\langle C_\delta ^\bullet \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta <\kappa \rangle $ , as follows. Set $C^\bullet _0:=\emptyset $ and $C^\bullet _{\gamma +1}:=\{\gamma \}$ for every $\gamma <\kappa $ . Next, given $\delta \in \operatorname {\mathrm {acc}}(\kappa )$ , construct a sequence $\langle x_\delta ^i\ {\mathrel {|}}\ i<\xi _\delta \rangle $ by recursion on $i<\xi _\delta $ , as follows:
$\blacktriangleright $ If $\delta _{i+1}\notin D^*$ , then set $x^i_\delta :=\{\delta _i\}$ .
$\blacktriangleright $ If $\delta _{i+1}\in D^*$ , then in particular, $\delta _{i+1}\ge \delta _i+\theta $ , so we set $x_\delta ^i:=y_{\gamma ,\epsilon ,\tau }$ , for $\gamma :=\delta _i$ , $\epsilon :=\operatorname {\mathrm {otp}}(\bigcup _{i'<i}x_\delta ^{i'})$ , and
Note that, for every $\delta \in \operatorname {\mathrm {acc}}(\kappa )$ , $C_\delta \subseteq C^{\bullet }_{\delta }$ , and also $\operatorname {\mathrm {acc}}(C^{\bullet }_{\delta })\cap E^\kappa _{\ge \theta }\subseteq \operatorname {\mathrm {acc}}(C_\delta )$ , since $y_{\gamma ,\epsilon ,\tau }\subseteq E^\kappa _{<\theta }$ for every $(\gamma ,\epsilon ,\tau )\in \kappa \times \kappa \times \theta $ . In addition, for every $\delta \in \operatorname {\mathrm {acc}}(\kappa )$ , if $\alpha +\beta <\xi _\delta $ for all $(\alpha ,\beta )\in \theta \times \xi _\delta $ , then $\operatorname {\mathrm {otp}}(C_\delta ^\bullet )=\xi _\delta $ . In particular, $\operatorname {\mathrm {otp}}(C^{\bullet }_{\delta })=\lambda $ for all $\delta \in S$ .
Claim 4.12.1. Let $\chi \in [\theta ,\kappa )$ be an infinite cardinal.
If $\vec C$ is $\mathrel {{}_{\chi }{\sqsubseteq }}$ -coherent, then so is $\vec {C^\bullet }$ .
Proof Suppose that $\vec C$ is $\mathrel {{}_{\chi }{\sqsubseteq }}$ -coherent. Let $\delta <\kappa $ and $\bar \delta \in \operatorname {\mathrm {acc}}(C^{\bullet }_\delta )\cap E^\kappa _{\ge \chi }$ ; we need to verify that $C^{\bullet }_{\delta }\cap \bar \delta \sqsubseteq C^{\bullet }_{\delta }$ . As $\operatorname {\mathrm {acc}}(C^{\bullet }_{\delta })\cap E^\kappa _{\ge \theta }\subseteq \operatorname {\mathrm {acc}}(C_\delta )$ and $\chi \ge \theta $ , we infer that $\bar \delta \in \operatorname {\mathrm {acc}}(C_\delta )$ , so by $\mathrel {{}_{\chi }{\sqsubseteq }}$ -coherence of $\vec C$ , $C_\delta \cap \bar \delta \sqsubseteq C_\delta $ . It follows that:
-
• $\langle \bar \delta _i\ {\mathrel {|}}\ i<\xi _{\bar \delta }\rangle =\langle \delta _i\ {\mathrel {|}}\ i<\xi _{\bar \delta }\rangle $ ,
-
• $\langle T^i_{\bar \delta }\ {\mathrel {|}}\ i<\xi _{\bar \delta }\rangle =\langle T^i_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ i<\xi _{\bar \delta }\rangle $ , and hence
-
• $\langle x^i_{\bar \delta }\ {\mathrel {|}}\ i<\xi _{\bar \delta }\rangle =\langle x^i_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ i<\xi _{\bar \delta }\rangle $ ,
so $C^\bullet _{\delta }\cap \bar \delta =\bigcup _{i<\xi _{\bar \delta }}x^i_{\delta }=\bigcup _{i<\xi _{\bar \delta }}x^i_{\bar \delta }=C^\bullet _{\bar \delta }$ , as sought.
Claim 4.12.2. If $\vec C$ is weakly coherent, then so is $\vec {C^\bullet }$ .
Proof Towards a contradiction, suppose that $\vec C$ is weakly coherent, but $\vec {C^\bullet }$ is not. Fix the least $\alpha <\kappa $ such that $|\{ C_\delta ^\bullet \cap \alpha \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta <\kappa \}|=\kappa $ . So we may fix a cofinal subset $\Delta $ of $\operatorname {\mathrm {acc}}(\kappa )$ such that:
-
(1) $\delta \mapsto C^{\bullet }_{\delta }\cap \alpha $ is injective over $\Delta $ , but
-
(2) $\delta \mapsto C_\delta \cap \alpha $ is constant over $\Delta $ .
Fix $\gamma <\alpha $ such that $\sup (C_\delta \cap \alpha )=\gamma $ for all $\delta \in \Delta $ . By minimality of $\alpha $ , and by possibly shrinking $\Delta $ further, we may also assume that
-
(3) $\delta \mapsto C^{\bullet }_{\delta }\cap \gamma $ is constant over $\Delta $ .
It thus follows that the map $\delta \mapsto C^{\bullet }_{\delta }\cap [\gamma ,\alpha )$ is injective over $\Delta $ . However, for every $\delta \in \Delta $ , $C^{\bullet }_{\delta }\cap [\gamma ,\alpha )$ is equal to $y_{\gamma ,\epsilon ,\tau }\cap \alpha $ , for $\epsilon :=\operatorname {\mathrm {otp}}(C^{\bullet }_{\delta }\cap \gamma )$ and some $\tau <\theta $ . Recalling Clause (3), there exists an $\epsilon <\kappa $ such that:
contradicting the fact that the set on the right hand size has size $\le \theta <\kappa $ .
Finally, to see that $\theta \in \Theta _1(\vec {C^\bullet }{\mathbin \upharpoonright } S,T)$ , let D be a club in $\kappa $ . By possibly shrinking D, we may assume that $D\subseteq D^*$ . Pick $\delta \in S$ such that $D(\eta ^*,\delta )= D^*(\eta ^*,\delta )$ , $|D^*(\eta ^*,\delta )|=\theta $ , and also
For any $D'\in \{D,D^*\}$ ,
So, since $D(\eta ^*,\delta )= D^*(\eta ^*,\delta )$ , the definition of $\varepsilon $ implies that
In particular, $|T_\delta ^{\lambda }|=\theta $ . Now, given a prescribed colour $\tau ^*$ and some $\alpha <\delta $ , we shall find a $\beta ^*\in C^{\bullet }_{\delta }$ above $\alpha $ such that $\min (C^{\bullet }_{\delta }\setminus (\beta ^*+1))\in D\cap T$ and $h(C^{\bullet }_{\delta }\cap \beta ^*)=\tau ^*$ . Fix the unique $\tau \in T^\lambda _\delta $ such that $\operatorname {\mathrm {otp}}(T^\lambda _\delta \cap \tau )=\tau ^*$ . Note that for a tail of $i<\lambda $ , $T_\delta ^\lambda \cap \tau =T_\delta ^i\cap \tau $ .
As $\tau \in D(\eta ^*,\delta )$ , there are cofinally many $\beta \in C_\delta $ such that $\min (C_\delta \setminus (\beta +1))\in D\cap T$ , $\eta ^*<\psi _\delta (\beta )$ and $c(\eta ^*,\psi _\delta (\beta ))=\tau $ . So, we may find a large enough $i<\lambda $ such that:
-
• $\delta _{i+1}\in D\cap T$ ,
-
• $\eta ^*<i$ ,
-
• $c(\eta ^*,i)=\tau $ ,
-
• $\alpha <\delta _i$ , and
-
• $T_\delta ^\lambda \cap \tau =T_\delta ^i\cap \tau $ .
So $\operatorname {\mathrm {otp}}(c(\eta ^*,i)\cap T^i_\delta )=\operatorname {\mathrm {otp}}(\tau \cap T^i_\delta )=\operatorname {\mathrm {otp}}(T^\lambda _\delta \cap \tau )=\tau ^*$ . Put $\beta ^*:=\max (x_\delta ^i)$ so that $\delta _i\le \beta ^*<\delta _{i+1}=\min (C^{\bullet }_{\delta }\setminus (\beta ^*+1))$ . Since $\delta _{i+1}\in D\subseteq D^*$ , we know that $x_\delta ^i=y_{\gamma ,\epsilon ,\tau ^*}$ , for $\gamma :=\delta _i$ and $\epsilon :=\operatorname {\mathrm {otp}}(\bigcup _{i'<i}x_\delta ^{i'})$ . Consequently,
as sought.
By [Reference Inamdar and Rinot26, Proposition 2.18 and Lemma 8.4], in Gödel’s constructible universe L, for every weakly compact cardinal $\lambda $ that is not ineffable, $\operatorname {{{\sf unbounded}}}(J^{\mathrm {bd}}[\lambda ],\theta )$ fails for every cardinal $\theta \in [3,\lambda ]$ , but $\operatorname {{{\sf onto}}}(\mathrm{NS}_\lambda ,\lambda )$ holds. Thus, it is easier to get $\operatorname {{{\sf unbounded}}}(J,\theta )$ with $J:=\mathrm{NS}_\lambda $ than with $J:=J^{\mathrm {bd}}[\lambda ]$ . In the upcoming theorem, the hypothesis of $\operatorname {{{\sf unbounded}}}(J^{\mathrm {bd}}[\lambda ],\theta )$ from Theorem 4.12 is reduced to $\operatorname {{{\sf unbounded}}}(\mathrm{NS}_\lambda ,\theta )$ at the cost of requiring $\vec C{\mathbin \upharpoonright } S$ to witness $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\lambda (S,T,1, \langle \mathrm{NS}_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle )$ .
Theorem 4.13. Suppose that $\theta <\lambda <\kappa $ are infinite cardinals, $\operatorname {{{\sf unbounded}}}(\mathrm{NS}_\lambda ,\theta )$ holds, and S is a stationary subset of $E^\kappa _\lambda $ .
For every C-sequence $\vec C=\langle C_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta <\kappa \rangle $ such that $\vec C{\mathbin \upharpoonright } S$ witnesses $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\lambda (S,T,1, \langle \mathrm{NS}_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle )$ , there exists a corresponding C-sequence $\vec {C^\bullet }=\langle C^{\bullet }_{\delta }\ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta <\kappa \rangle $ such that $:$
-
• $\vec {C^\bullet }{\mathbin \upharpoonright } S$ is $\lambda $ -bounded.
-
• If $\vec C$ is weakly coherent, then so is $\vec {C^\bullet }$ .
-
• For every infinite cardinal $\chi \in [\theta ,\kappa )$ , if $\vec C$ is $\mathrel {{}_{\chi }{\sqsubseteq }}$ -coherent, then so is $\vec {C^\bullet }$ .
-
• $\theta \in \Theta _1(\vec {C^\bullet }{\mathbin \upharpoonright } S,T)$ .
Proof For every $\delta <\kappa $ , let $\psi _\delta :C_\delta \rightarrow \operatorname {\mathrm {otp}}(C_\delta )$ denote the collapsing map of $C_\delta $ . Let $c:[\kappa ]^2\rightarrow \theta $ be a colouring given by Theorem 4.10(1).
Claim 4.13.1. There exists an $\eta <\lambda $ such that, for every club $D\subseteq \kappa $ , there exists a $\delta \in S$ , such that the following set has size $\theta :$
Proof Suppose not. For every $\eta <\lambda $ , fix a counterexample club $D_\eta \subseteq \kappa $ . Let $D:=\bigcap _{\eta <\lambda }D_\eta $ . By the hypothesis on $\vec C{\mathbin \upharpoonright } S$ , let us now pick $\delta \in S$ such that the following set is stationary in $\delta $ :
By the choice of c, there is an $\eta < \lambda $ such that
In particular, $|D(\eta , \delta )| = \theta $ , contradicting the fact that $D \subseteq D_\eta $ .
The rest of the proof is now identical to that of Theorem 4.12.
Remark 4.14. Since $\operatorname {\mathrm {nacc}}(\delta )\in \mathrm{NS}_\delta $ for all $\delta \in S$ , for every $\sigma \le \omega $ such that $\sigma <\theta $ , if $\vec C{\mathbin \upharpoonright } S$ moreover witnesses $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\lambda (S,T,\sigma , \langle \mathrm{NS}_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle )$ , then the preceding proof may be slightly tweaked to secure that $\theta \in \Theta _1(\vec {C^\bullet }{\mathbin \upharpoonright } S,T,\sigma )$ . The first change is to require that the surjection $h:\kappa \rightarrow \theta $ satisfies that for every $\epsilon <\kappa $ , for every $\tau <\theta $ , there exists $\iota \in (\epsilon ,\epsilon +\theta )$ such that $\{ h(\iota +\varsigma )\ {\mathrel {|}}\ \varsigma \le \sigma \}=\{\tau \}$ . The second change is to impose $x^i_\delta =\{\delta _i\}$ for all $i\in \operatorname {\mathrm {nacc}}(\xi _\delta )$ . The details are left to the reader.
4.3 Applications
We now utilize the results from [Reference Inamdar and Rinot26–Reference Inamdar and Rinot28] in order to partition club guessing sequences. This proves Theorem C.
Fact 4.15 [Reference Inamdar and Rinot26].
Suppose that $\lambda $ is regular and uncountable.
Any of the following implies that $\operatorname {{{\sf onto}}}(J^{\mathrm {bd}}[\lambda ], \theta )$ holds $:$
-
(1) $\theta =\lambda =\aleph _1=\operatorname {\mathrm {non}}(\mathcal M)$ .
-
(2) $\theta =\lambda $ is a successor cardinal, and holds.
-
(3) $\theta =\lambda $ and $\diamondsuit (T)$ holds for a stationary $T\subseteq \lambda $ that does not reflect at regulars.
-
(4) $\theta <\lambda $ and $\lambda \nrightarrow [\lambda ]^2_\theta $ holds.
-
(5) $\theta <\lambda $ is regular and $\operatorname {{{\sf unbounded}}}(J^{\mathrm {bd}}[\lambda ], \lambda )$ holds.Footnote 8
Fact 4.16 [Reference Inamdar and Rinot27].
Suppose that $\lambda $ is regular and uncountable, and $\theta \le \lambda $ .
Any of the following implies that $\operatorname {{{\sf unbounded}}}(J^{\mathrm {bd}}[\lambda ], \theta )$ holds $:$
-
(1) $\lambda $ admits a nontrivial C-sequence in the sense of [Reference Todorčević80, Definition 6.3.1].
-
(2) $\square (\lambda ,{<}\mu )$ holds for some $\mu <\lambda $ .
-
(3) $\lambda $ is not greatly Mahlo.
-
(4) $\lambda $ is not weakly compact in L.
-
(5) $\lambda $ is not weakly compact, and $\theta =\omega $ .
-
(6) $\lambda $ is not strongly inaccessible, and $\theta =\log _2(\lambda )$ .Footnote 9
Fact 4.17 [Reference Inamdar and Rinot28].
If $\lambda $ is a regular uncountable cardinal and there exists a $\lambda $ -Aronszajn tree, then $\operatorname {{{\sf unbounded}}}(J^{\mathrm {bd}}[\lambda ], \theta )$ holds for every cardinal $\theta <\lambda $ . In particular, if $\lambda $ is a strongly inaccessible cardinal that is not weakly compact, then $\operatorname {{{\sf onto}}}(J^{\mathrm {bd}}[\lambda ], \theta )$ holds for every $\theta <\lambda $ .
Corollary 4.18. Suppose that $\lambda $ is a regular uncountable cardinal, and $\vec C$ witnesses $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\lambda (S,T,\sigma ,\vec J)$ with $S\subseteq E^\kappa _\lambda $ .
-
(1) If $\lambda =\lambda ^{<\lambda }$ is a successor cardinal, then $\lambda \in \Theta _1(\vec C,T,\sigma ,\vec J)$ .
-
(2) If $\lambda =\theta ^+$ and $\theta $ is regular, then $\theta \in \Theta _1(\vec C,T,\sigma ,\vec J)$ .
-
(3) If $\lambda $ is not Mahlo and $\diamondsuit (\lambda )$ holds, then $\lambda \in \Theta _1(\vec C,T,\sigma ,\vec J)$ .
-
(4) If $\lambda $ is not greatly Mahlo or if there is a $\lambda $ -Aronszajn tree, then $\theta \in \Theta _2(\vec C, T,\sigma ,\vec J)$ for every cardinal $\theta <\lambda $ .
-
(5) If $\lambda $ is not strongly inaccessible, then $\log _2(\lambda )\in \Theta _2(\vec C,T,\sigma ,\vec J)$ .
Fact 4.19 [Reference Inamdar and Rinot26].
Let $\lambda $ be a regular uncountable cardinal.
-
(1) If $\diamondsuit ^*(\lambda )$ holds, then so does $\operatorname {{{\sf onto}}}(\mathrm{NS}_\lambda , \lambda )$ .
-
(2) If $\lambda $ admits an amenable C-sequence, then $\operatorname {{{\sf onto}}}(\mathrm{NS}_\lambda , \theta )$ holds for all regular $\theta <\lambda $ .
-
(3) $\operatorname {{{\sf unbounded}}}(\mathrm{NS}_\lambda , \omega )$ holds iff $\lambda $ is not ineffable.
Fact 4.20 [Reference Inamdar and Rinot28].
If $\lambda $ is a regular uncountable cardinal such that $\lambda $ - $\operatorname {\mathrm {ITP}}$ fails,Footnote 10 then $\operatorname {{{\sf unbounded}}}(\mathrm{NS}_\lambda , \theta )$ holds for every $\theta <\lambda $ . In particular, if $\lambda $ is a strongly inaccessible cardinal that is not ineffable, then $\operatorname {{{\sf onto}}}(\mathrm{NS}_\lambda , \theta )$ holds for every $\theta <\lambda $ .
Corollary 4.21. Suppose that $\lambda $ is a regular uncountable cardinal, and $\vec C$ witnesses $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\lambda (S,T,\sigma ,\vec J)$ with $S\subseteq E^\kappa _\lambda $ and $\vec J$ is a sequence of normal ideals.
-
(1) If $\diamondsuit ^*(\lambda )$ holds, then $\lambda \in \Theta _1(\vec C,T,\sigma ,\vec J)$ .
-
(2) If $\lambda $ admits an amenable C-sequence, then $\theta \in \Theta _1(\vec C,T,\sigma ,\vec J)$ for all regular $\theta <\lambda $ .
-
(3) If $\lambda $ is a non-ineffable strongly inaccessible, then $\theta \in \Theta _1(\vec C,T,\sigma ,\vec J)$ for every cardinal $\theta <\lambda $ .
-
(4) If $\lambda $ is a non-ineffable, then $\omega \in \Theta _2(\vec C,T,\sigma ,\vec J)$ .
In [Reference Moore44], the (weak) club guessing principle $\mho $ was shown to give rise to a C-sequence $\vec C$ over $\omega _1$ for which the corresponding object $\mathcal T(\rho _0^{\vec C})$ is a special Aronszajn tree of pathological nature. In the terminology developed in this paper, the key features of $\vec C$ sufficient for the construction are that $\vec C$ be a transversal for $\square ^*_\omega $ and that $\omega \in \Theta _1(\vec C,\omega _1)$ . Arguably, the higher analog of this would assert the existence of a transversal $\vec C=\langle C_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta <\lambda ^+\rangle $ for $\square ^*_{\lambda }$ such that $\log _2(\lambda )\in \Theta _1(\vec C,\lambda ^+)$ . By the next corollary, if $\lambda $ is not strongly inaccessible (in particular, if $\lambda =\aleph _1$ ), then the existence of such a C-sequence is in fact no stronger than $\square ^*_{\lambda }$ .
Corollary 4.22. Suppose that $\lambda $ is a regular uncountable cardinal, and $\theta =\log _2(\lambda )$ .
-
(1) If $\square _{\lambda }^*$ holds and $\theta <\lambda $ , then there exists a transversal $\vec C$ for $\square _\lambda ^*$ such that $\theta \in \Theta _1(\vec C{\mathbin \upharpoonright } E^{\lambda ^+}_{\lambda },E^{\lambda ^+}_{\lambda })$ .
-
(2) If $\diamondsuit (\lambda )$ holds and $\lambda $ is not Mahlo, then there exists a transversal $\vec C$ for $\square _\lambda ^*$ such that $\theta \in \Theta _1(\vec C{\mathbin \upharpoonright } E^{\lambda ^+}_{\lambda },E^{\lambda ^+}_\lambda )$ .
-
(3) If $\diamondsuit ^*(\lambda )$ holds, then there exists a transversal $\vec C$ for $\square _\lambda ^*$ such that $\theta \in \Theta _1(\vec C{\mathbin \upharpoonright } E^{\lambda ^+}_{\lambda },\lambda ^+)$ .
Proof (1) Suppose that $\theta <\lambda $ and $\square ^*_\lambda $ holds. Appeal to Theorem 3.23 to find a transversal $\vec C$ for $\square _\lambda ^*$ such that $\vec C{\mathbin \upharpoonright } E^{\lambda ^+}_{\lambda }$ witnesses $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\lambda (E^{\lambda ^+}_{\lambda },E^{\lambda ^+}_{\lambda })$ . By Corollary 4.18(5), $\theta \in \Theta _1(\vec C{\mathbin \upharpoonright } E^{\lambda ^+}_{\lambda },E^{\lambda ^+}_{\lambda })$ .
(2) Appeal to Fact 3.29 to pick a $\lambda $ -bounded C-sequence $\vec C=\langle C_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta <\lambda ^+\rangle $ such that $C{\mathbin \upharpoonright } E^{\lambda ^+}_\lambda $ witnesses $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\lambda (E^{\lambda ^+}_\lambda ,E^{\lambda ^+}_\lambda )$ . Suppose that $\diamondsuit (\lambda )$ holds. In particular, $\lambda ^{<\lambda }=\lambda $ , so $\vec C$ is trivially weakly coherent. In addition, since $\diamondsuit (\lambda )$ holds, Corollary 4.18(3) implies that $\lambda \in \Theta _1(E^{\lambda ^+}_\lambda ,E^{\lambda ^+}_\lambda )$ .
(3) By Fact 3.29 together with Corollary 6.10 below, we may fix a $\lambda $ -bounded C-sequence $\vec C=\langle C_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta <\lambda ^+\rangle $ such that $\vec C{\mathbin \upharpoonright } E^{\lambda ^+}_\lambda $ witnesses $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\lambda (E^{\lambda ^+}_{\lambda },\lambda ^+,1,\langle \mathrm{NS}_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle )$ . Suppose that $\diamondsuit ^*(\lambda )$ holds. In particular, $\vec C$ is trivially weakly coherent. In addition, since $\diamondsuit ^*(\lambda )$ holds, Corollary 4.21(1) implies that $\lambda \in \Theta _1(\vec C{\mathbin \upharpoonright } E^{\lambda ^+}_\lambda ,\lambda ^+)$ .
We also record the following variation.
Corollary 4.23. Suppose that $\lambda $ is a regular uncountable cardinal that is not strongly inaccessible. If $\square _\lambda $ holds, then it may be witnessed by a C-sequence $\vec C$ such that $\log _2(\lambda )\in \Theta _1(\vec C{\mathbin \upharpoonright } E^{\lambda ^+}_{\lambda },\lambda ^+)$ .
4.4 Another form of partitioning
By [Reference Brodsky and Rinot11, Theorem 3.7], if $\clubsuit (S)$ holds, then there exists a decomposition $S=\biguplus _{i<\kappa }S_i$ such that $\clubsuit (S_i)$ holds for every $i<\kappa $ . We close this section by showing that this form of partitioning also holds for $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}$ . When taken together with Theorem 2.15, this yields Solovay’s decomposition theorem for cardinals greater than $\aleph _1$ (at the level of $\aleph _1$ , Solovay’s theorem follows using an Ulam matrix).
Proposition 4.24. Suppose that $\vec C$ witnesses $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\xi (S,T,\sigma ,\vec J)$ . Then there exists a decomposition $S=\biguplus _{i<\kappa }S_i$ such that $\vec C{\mathbin \upharpoonright } S_i$ witnesses $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\xi (S_i,T,\sigma ,\vec J)$ for all $i<\kappa $ .
Proof For all $\beta <i<\kappa $ , let $S^\beta _i:=\{ \delta \in S\cap \operatorname {\mathrm {acc}}(\kappa \setminus \beta )\ {\mathrel {|}}\ \min (C_\delta \setminus (\beta +1))=i\}$ . It suffices to prove that there exists a $\beta <\kappa $ for which the following set has size $\kappa $ :
So, suppose that this is not the case, and fix a sparse enough club $E\subseteq \kappa $ such that, for every $\epsilon \in E$ , for every $\beta <\epsilon $ , $\sup (I_\beta )<\epsilon $ . In addition, fix a triangular matrix $\langle D^\beta _i\ {\mathrel {|}}\ \beta <i<\kappa \rangle $ of clubs in $\kappa $ such that, for all $\beta <i<\kappa $ , if $i\notin I_\beta $ , then for every $\delta \in S^\beta _i$ ,
Consider the club $D:=\{\delta \in E\ {\mathrel {|}}\ \forall i<\delta \forall \beta <i(\delta \in D_i^\beta )\}$ . By the choice of $\vec C$ , pick $\delta \in S$ such that the following set is in $J_\delta ^+$ :
Claim 4.24.1. For every $\beta <\delta $ , $\min (C_\delta \setminus (\beta +1))\in I_\beta $ .
Proof Given $\beta <\delta $ , if we let $i:=\min (C_\delta \setminus (\beta +1))$ , then $\delta \in S_i^\beta $ , and since $D \cap \delta $ is almost included in $D^\beta _i\cap \delta $ , it is the case that
so that $i\in I_\beta $ .
Pick $\beta \in B$ and set $\epsilon :=\min (C_\delta \setminus (\beta +1))$ . As $\epsilon \in D\cap T\subseteq E$ and $\beta <\epsilon $ , $\sup (I_\beta ) < \epsilon $ , contradicting the preceding claim.
5 Increasing $\sigma $
In this section we are interested in improving the quality of guessing by guessing many consecutive nonaccumulation points as in Question 1.6. As we shall see, guessing clubs relative to points of prescribed cofinality turns out be of great help for this purpose. The main result of this section reads as follows.
Corollary 5.1. Suppose $\nu <\xi \le \kappa $ are infinite cardinals, and that $S\subseteq E^\kappa _{>\nu }$ .
For every $($ possibly finite $)$ cardinal $\sigma <\nu $ , if $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\xi (S, E^\kappa _{\ge \sigma }\cap E^\kappa _{\le \nu },1,\vec J)$ holds, then so does $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\xi (S, \kappa , \sigma ,\vec J)$ .
Proof $\blacktriangleright $ If $\sigma $ is finite, then appeal to Theorem 5.2.
$\blacktriangleright $ If $\sigma =\omega $ and $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\xi (S, E^\kappa _{\sigma },1,\vec J)$ holds then appeal to Theorem 5.4.
$\blacktriangleright $ If $\sigma =\omega $ and $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\xi (S, E^\kappa _{\sigma },1,\vec J)$ fails, then since $S\subseteq E^\kappa _{>\nu }$ , it follows from Proposition 2.5 that $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\xi (S, E^\kappa _{\bar \nu },1,\vec J)$ holds for some cardinal $\bar \nu $ with $\sigma <\bar \nu \le \nu $ . Now appeal to Theorem 5.5(2) with $T:=\kappa $ .
$\blacktriangleright $ If $\sigma>\omega $ , then appeal to Theorem 5.5 with $T:=\kappa $ .
Another key result is Theorem 5.5 where a version of this result relative to a set T is proved.
We commence with a result that pumps up $\sigma $ from $1$ to any prescribed positive integer using a postprocessing $^*$ function (thereby, preserving coherence features).
Theorem 5.2. Suppose $\sigma <\omega \le \nu <\kappa $ are cardinals.
Suppose that $\vec C=\langle C_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle $ witnesses $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\xi (S, E^\kappa _{\le \nu },1,\vec J)$ , with $S\subseteq E^\kappa _{>\nu }$ . Then there exists a postprocessing $^*$ function $\Phi :\mathcal K(\kappa )\rightarrow \mathcal K(\kappa )$ such that $\langle \Phi (C_\delta )\ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle $ witnesses $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\xi (S, \kappa , \sigma ,\vec J)$ .
Proof Fix an auxiliary C-sequence $\vec e = \langle e_\gamma \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \gamma <\kappa \rangle $ such that $\operatorname {\mathrm {otp}}(e_\gamma ) = \operatorname {\mathrm {cf}}(\gamma )$ for every $\gamma <\kappa $ . In what follows we shall use the operator $\Phi _D$ from Definition 2.12.
Claim 5.2.1. There is a club $D \subseteq \kappa $ such that for every club $E \subseteq \kappa $ there is a $\delta \in S$ such that
Proof Suppose that the claim does not hold. In this case, for every club $D\subseteq \kappa $ , there is a club $F^D \subseteq \kappa $ such that for every $\delta \in S$ ,
Let $\mu := \aleph _0$ so that $\mu \le \nu <\kappa $ . We construct now a $\subseteq $ -decreasing sequence $\langle D_i \ {\mathrel {|}}\ i\leq \mu \rangle $ of clubs in $\kappa $ as follows:
-
(i) $D_0 := \kappa $ ;
-
(ii) $D_{i+1} := D_i \cap F^{D_i}$ ;
-
(iii) for $i\in \operatorname {\mathrm {acc}}(\mu +1)$ , $D_i := \bigcap _{i'< i} D_{i'}$ .
Since $\mu < \kappa $ , all these are clubs in $\kappa $ . Finally, consider the club
As $\vec C=\langle C_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle $ witnesses $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\xi (S, E^\kappa _{\le \nu },1,\vec J)$ , let us pick $\delta \in S $ such that
is in $J_\delta ^+$ .
For every $i < \mu $ , by the choice of $F^{D_i}$ , the following set
is in $J_\delta $ . As $J_\delta $ is $\operatorname {\mathrm {cf}}(\delta )$ -additive, and $\operatorname {\mathrm {cf}}(\delta )>\nu $ , we may now fix $\alpha \in A\setminus \bigcup _{i<\mu }A_i$ . Set $\gamma :=\min (C_\delta \setminus (\alpha +1))$ , so that $\gamma \in D^*\cap E^\kappa _{\leq \nu }$ . Since $\gamma \in D^* \subseteq \operatorname {\mathrm {acc}}(D_{i})$ for every $i \leq \mu $ , we have that $\Phi _{D_{i}}(e_\gamma ) \subseteq D_i$ .
As $\gamma \in D^*$ , $\operatorname {\mathrm {otp}}(D_\mu \cap \gamma )=\gamma>\nu \ge \operatorname {\mathrm {otp}}(e_\gamma )$ , so that $(D_\mu \cap \gamma )\setminus e_\gamma $ is cofinal in $\gamma $ . Recursively construct $\langle (\delta ^n,\beta ^n) \ {\mathrel {|}}\ n\le \sigma \rangle $ by letting:
-
(i) $\delta ^0:=\min ( D_\mu \setminus (e_\gamma \cup \alpha ))$ ,
-
(ii) $\beta ^0:=\min (e_\gamma \setminus \delta ^0)$ ,
-
(iii) $\delta ^{n+1}:=\min (D_\mu \setminus (e_\gamma \cup \beta ^n))$ , and
-
(iv) $\beta ^{n+1}:=\min (e_\gamma \setminus \delta ^{n+1})$ .
Evidently, $\alpha \le \delta ^n<\beta ^n<\delta ^{n+1}$ .
For every $n\le \sigma $ , denote $\beta ^n_i := \sup (\beta ^n \cap D_i)$ , and fix a large enough $j_n < \omega $ such that $\beta ^n_i=\beta ^n_{j_n}$ for every integer $i\ge j_n$ . Set $i^*:=\max \{j_n\ {\mathrel {|}}\ n\le \sigma \}$ which is finite as $\sigma $ is finite. Altogether, for every $n<\sigma $ ,
It thus follows that $\{\beta ^n_{i^*}\ {\mathrel {|}}\ n\le \sigma \}$ consists of $\sigma +1$ many distinct elements of $\Phi _{D_{i^*}}(e_\gamma )\cap (D_{i^*+1}\setminus \alpha )$ . But $D_{i^*+1}$ is a subset of $F^{D_{i^*}}$ so $|\Phi _{D_{i^*}}(e_\gamma )\cap (F^{D_{i^*}}\setminus \alpha )|> \sigma $ , and since $\gamma =\min (C_\delta \setminus (\alpha +1))$ , we have contradicted the fact that $\alpha \not \in A_{i^*}$ .
Let $D\subseteq \kappa $ be a club as given by the preceding claim. For all $\gamma \in E^\kappa _{\le \nu }$ and $z\in [\nu ]^{<\omega }$ , we define a finite subset of $\gamma $ :
Now, for every $z\in [\nu ]^{<\omega }$ , define a postprocessing $^*$ function $\Phi ^z:\mathcal K(\kappa )\rightarrow \mathcal K(\kappa )$ via
Claim 5.2.2. There exists $z\in [\nu ]^{\sigma +1}$ such that $\vec {C^z}:=\langle \Phi ^z(C_\delta )\ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle $ witnesses $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\xi (S, \kappa , \sigma ,\vec J)$ .
Proof Suppose not. For each $z\in [\nu ]^{\sigma +1}$ fix a counterexample $E_z$ . Set $E:=\bigcap \{ E_z\ {\mathrel {|}}\ z\in [\nu ]^{\sigma +1}\}$ . Recalling the choice of D, let us now fix $\delta \in S$ for which
is in $J_\delta ^+$ . For every $\alpha \in A$ , let $\gamma _\alpha :=\min (C_\delta \setminus (\alpha +1))$ and fix $z_\alpha \in [\nu ]^{\sigma +1}$ such that $(z_\alpha )_{\gamma _\alpha }\subseteq E\setminus \alpha $ . As $J_\delta $ is $\operatorname {\mathrm {cf}}(\delta )$ -additive and $\operatorname {\mathrm {cf}}(\delta )>\nu =|[\nu ]^{\sigma +1}|$ , it follows that there exists some $z\in [\nu ]^{\sigma +1}$ for which $\{\alpha \in A\ {\mathrel {|}}\ z_\alpha =z\}$ is in $J_\delta ^+$ . As $E\subseteq E_z$ , this is a contradiction.
Let z be given by the preceding claim. Then $\Phi ^z$ is as sought.
Corollary 5.3. Suppose $\nu <\lambda <\kappa $ are infinite regular cardinals, and $S\subseteq E^\kappa _\lambda $ .
If $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\lambda (S, E^\kappa _{\nu })$ holds, then there exists a $\lambda $ -bounded C-sequence $\vec C=\langle C_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}} \delta \in S\rangle $ satisfying the following. For every club $D\subseteq \kappa $ , for every $n<\omega $ , there exists a $\delta \in S$ such that $\sup \{ \beta <\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \operatorname {\mathrm {succ}}_n(C_\delta \setminus \beta )\subseteq D\}=\delta $ .
Theorem 5.4. Suppose $\xi \le \kappa $ are uncountable cardinals.
For every stationary $S\subseteq E^\kappa _{>\omega _1}$ , $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\xi (S, E^\kappa _\omega ,1,\vec J)$ implies $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\xi (S, \kappa , \omega ,\vec J)$ .
Proof Suppose that $\vec C=\langle C_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle $ witnesses $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\xi (S, E^\kappa _\omega ,1,\vec J)$ , with $S\subseteq E^\kappa _{>\omega }$ . In particular, $\kappa \ge \aleph _2$ . Fix an auxiliary C-sequence $\vec e = \langle e_\gamma \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \gamma <\kappa \rangle $ such that $\operatorname {\mathrm {otp}}(e_\gamma ) = \operatorname {\mathrm {cf}}(\gamma )$ for every $\gamma <\kappa $ . In what follows we shall use the operator $\Phi _D$ from Definition 2.12.
Claim 5.4.1. There is a club $D \subseteq \kappa $ such that for every club $E \subseteq \kappa $ there is a $\delta \in S$ such that
Proof Suppose that the claim does not hold. In this case, for every club $D\subseteq \kappa $ , there is a club $F^D \subseteq \kappa $ such that for every $\delta \in S$ ,
Let $\mu :=\aleph _1$ so that $\mu <\kappa $ . We construct now a $\subseteq $ -decreasing sequence $\langle D_i \ {\mathrel {|}}\ i\leq \mu \rangle $ of clubs in $\kappa $ as follows:
-
(i) $D_0 := \kappa $ ;
-
(ii) $D_{i+1} := D_i \cap F^{D_i}$ ;
-
(iii) for $i\in \operatorname {\mathrm {acc}}(\mu +1)$ , $D_i := \bigcap _{i'< i} D_{i'}$ .
Since $\mu < \kappa $ , all these are club in $\kappa $ . Finally, consider the club
As $\vec C=\langle C_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle $ witnesses $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\xi (S, E^\kappa _\omega ,1,\vec J)$ , let us pick $\delta \in S$ such that
is in $J_\delta ^+$ .
For every $i < \mu $ , by the choice of $F^{D_i}$ , the following set is in $J_\delta $ :
As $J_\delta $ is $\operatorname {\mathrm {cf}}(\delta )$ -additive, and $\operatorname {\mathrm {cf}}(\delta )>\omega _1$ , we may now fix $\alpha \in A\setminus \bigcup _{i<\mu }A_i$ . Set $\gamma :=\min (C_\delta \setminus (\alpha +1))$ , so that $\gamma \in D^*\cap E^\kappa _\omega $ . Since $\gamma \in D^* \subseteq \operatorname {\mathrm {acc}}(D_{i})$ for every $i \leq \mu $ , we have that $\Phi _{D_{i}}(e_\gamma ) \subseteq D_i$ for every $i< \mu $ .
For $\beta \in e_\gamma $ , let $\beta _i := \sup (\beta \cap D_i)$ . Since $\langle D_i \ {\mathrel {|}}\ i\leq \mu \rangle $ is $\subseteq $ -decreasing, $\langle \beta _i\ {\mathrel {|}}\ i < \mu \rangle $ is a non-increasing sequence, and hence it must stabilize beyond some ordinal $j(\beta ) < \mu $ . That is, for every $i \geq j(\beta )$ we have $\beta _i = \beta _{j(\beta )}$ . Let $i^* := \sup _{\beta \in e_\gamma }j(\beta )$ , and note that $i^*<\mu $ , since $\mu =\aleph _1=|e_\gamma |^+$ . In particular, this implies that
On the other hand, since $\alpha \notin A_{i^*}$ , we have that $\Phi _{D_{i^*}}(e_\gamma ) \nsubseteq F^{D_{i^*}}$ . This is a contradiction.
Let $D\subseteq \kappa $ be a club as given by the preceding claim. Consider a new C-sequence $\vec C^\bullet =\langle C^{\bullet }_{\delta }\ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle $ defined via
Note that for any $\delta \in S$ , since $\operatorname {\mathrm {otp}}(C_\delta ) \leq \xi $ and for each $\gamma \in E^\kappa _\omega $ we have $\operatorname {\mathrm {otp}}(\Phi _D(e_\gamma )) \leq \operatorname {\mathrm {otp}}(e) \leq \omega $ , we have that the ordertype of every initial segment of $C^{\bullet }_{\delta }$ is strictly less than $\xi $ , and hence $\operatorname {\mathrm {otp}}(C^{\bullet }_{\delta }) \leq \xi $ .
Now, if $E \subseteq \kappa $ is a club, then by the choice of D there is some $\delta \in S$ such that
is in $J_\delta ^+$ . For every $\alpha \in A$ , if we let $\gamma _\alpha :=\min (C^{\bullet }_{\delta }\setminus (\alpha +1))$ , then $\gamma _\alpha \in E^\kappa _\omega $ and $C^{\bullet }_{\delta } \cap [\alpha ,\gamma _\alpha )$ is equal to $\Phi _D(e_{\gamma _\alpha }) \setminus \alpha $ , which is an end segment of $\Phi _D(e_{\gamma _\alpha })$ . Since any end segment of $\Phi _D(e_{\gamma _\alpha })$ has ordertype $\omega $ as well, it follows that for any $\alpha \in A$ , there is an end segment of $C^{\bullet }_{\delta } \cap \gamma _\alpha $ of ordertype $\omega $ which is contained in E. Since this interval of ordertype $\omega $ which is contained in E also contains $\omega $ successive non-accumulation points of $C^{\bullet }_{\delta } \cap \gamma _\alpha $ , we infer that
covers A. In particular, $B\in J_\delta ^+$ .
Theorem 5.5. Let $\sigma < \nu < \xi \le \kappa $ be infinite cardinals. Suppose that $S\subseteq E^\kappa _{>\nu }$ and $T\subseteq \kappa $ are stationary sets.
-
(1) If $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\xi (S, E^\kappa _\sigma \cap \operatorname {\mathrm {Tr}}(T),1,\vec J)$ holds, then so does $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\xi (S, T, \sigma ,\vec J)$ .
-
(2) If $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\xi (S, E^\kappa _\nu \cap \operatorname {\mathrm {Tr}}(T),1,\vec J)$ holds, then so does $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\xi (S, T, \sigma ,\vec J)$ .
Proof For the proof of both cases, we fix an auxiliary C-sequence $\vec e = \langle e_\gamma \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \gamma <\kappa \rangle $ such that $\operatorname {\mathrm {otp}}(e_\gamma ) = \operatorname {\mathrm {cf}}(\gamma )$ for every $\gamma <\kappa $ .
(1) Suppose that $\vec C=\langle C_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle $ witnesses $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\xi (S, E^\kappa _{\sigma }\cap \operatorname {\mathrm {Tr}}(T), 1,\vec J)$ . Let $\Phi ^B$ be the operator from Definition 2.8.
Claim 5.5.1. There is a club $D \subseteq \kappa $ such that for every club $E \subseteq \kappa $ there is a $\delta \in S$ such that
Proof Suppose that the claim does not hold. In this case, for every club $D\subseteq \kappa $ , there is a club $F^D \subseteq \kappa $ such that, for every $\delta \in S$ ,
Set $\mu :=\sigma ^+$ , so that $\mu \le \nu <\kappa $ . We construct now a $\subseteq $ -decreasing sequence $\langle D_i \ {\mathrel {|}}\ i\leq \mu \rangle $ of clubs in $\kappa $ as follows:
-
(i) $D_0 := \kappa $ ;
-
(ii) $D_{i+1} := D_i \cap F^{D_i}$ ;
-
(iii) for $i\in \operatorname {\mathrm {acc}}(\mu +1)$ , $D_i := \bigcap _{i'< i} D_{i'}$ .
Next, let $D^* := \operatorname {\mathrm {acc}}(D_{\mu })$ and fix $\delta \in S$ such that
is in $J_\delta ^+$ .
For every $i < \mu $ , as $D_{i+1}\subseteq F^{D_i}$ , the following set
is in $J_\delta $ . As $\operatorname {\mathrm {cf}}(\delta )>\nu \ge \mu $ , we may fix $\alpha \in A\setminus \bigcup _{i<\mu }A_i$ . Set $\gamma :=\min (C_\delta \setminus (\alpha +1))$ , so that $\gamma \in D^*\cap E^\kappa _\sigma \cap \operatorname {\mathrm {Tr}}(T)$ .
For every $i < \mu $ , $\gamma \in \operatorname {\mathrm {acc}}(D_i)\cap \operatorname {\mathrm {Tr}}(T)$ , so that $e_\gamma \cap D_i\cap T$ is stationary in $\gamma $ , and hence $\Phi ^{D_i\cap T}(e_\gamma )=\operatorname {\mathrm {cl}}(e_\gamma \cap D_i\cap T)$ . Thus, for every $i<\mu $ , as $\alpha \notin A_i$ , it must be the case that $\Phi ^{D_i\cap T}(e_\gamma ) \nsubseteq D_{i+i}$ ; but $D_{i+1}$ is closed, so that, in fact, $e_\gamma \cap D_i\cap T\nsubseteq D_{i+i}$ . For each $i<\mu $ , pick $\beta _i\in (e_\gamma \cap D_i\cap T)\setminus D_{i+i}$ . As $|e_\gamma |<\mu $ , we may now fix $(i,j)\in [\mu ]^2$ such that $\beta _i=\beta _j$ . So $\beta _i\notin D_{i+1}$ while $\beta _j\in D_j\subseteq D_{i+1}$ . This is a contradiction.
Let $D\subseteq \kappa $ be given by the preceding claim. Consider the C-sequence $\vec C^\bullet =\langle C^{\bullet }_{\delta }\ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle $ defined via
It is clear that $\vec C^\bullet $ witnesses $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\xi (S, T, \sigma ,\vec J)$ .
(2) Suppose that $\vec C=\langle C_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle $ witnesses $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\xi (S, E^\kappa _{\nu }\cap \operatorname {\mathrm {Tr}}(T), 1,\vec J)$ . For all $\gamma <\kappa $ and $\epsilon <\nu $ , let $e_\gamma ^\epsilon :=\{\beta \in e_\gamma \cap T\ {\mathrel {|}}\ \operatorname {\mathrm {otp}}(e_\gamma \cap \beta )<\epsilon \}$ so that it is an initial segment of $e_\gamma \cap T$ .
Claim 5.5.2. There is $\epsilon <\nu $ such that, for every club $E \subseteq \kappa $ , there is $\delta \in S$ with
Proof Otherwise, pick a counterexample $E_\epsilon $ for each $\epsilon <\nu $ , and set $E:=\bigcap _{\epsilon <\nu }E_\epsilon $ . Pick $\delta \in S$ such that
is in $J_\delta ^+$ . For every $\alpha \in A$ , if we let $\gamma _\alpha :=\min (C_\delta \setminus (\alpha +1))$ , then $e_\gamma \cap E\cap T$ is a stationary subset of $\gamma $ of ordertype $\nu $ , so there exists some $\epsilon _\alpha <\nu $ such that $\operatorname {\mathrm {otp}}(e^{\epsilon _\alpha }_{\gamma _\alpha }\cap E\setminus \alpha )>\sigma $ . As $J_\delta $ is $\operatorname {\mathrm {cf}}(\delta )$ -additive and $\operatorname {\mathrm {cf}}(\delta )>\nu $ , there must exist some $\epsilon <\nu $ for which $A_\epsilon :=\{\alpha \in A\ {\mathrel {|}}\ \epsilon _\alpha =\epsilon \}$ is in $J_\delta ^+$ . But $E\subseteq E_\epsilon $ . This is a contradiction.
Let $\epsilon $ be given by the claim.
Claim 5.5.3. There is a club $D \subseteq \kappa $ such that for every club $E \subseteq \kappa $ there is a $\delta \in S$ such that
Proof Suppose that the claim does not hold. In this case, for every club $D\subseteq \kappa $ , there is a club $F^D \subseteq \kappa $ such that, for every $\delta \in S$ ,
We construct now a $\subseteq $ -decreasing sequence $\langle D_i \ {\mathrel {|}}\ i\leq \nu \rangle $ of clubs in $\kappa $ as follows:
-
(i) $D_0 := \kappa $ ;
-
(ii) $D_{i+1} := D_i \cap F^{D_i}$ ;
-
(iii) for $i\in \operatorname {\mathrm {acc}}(\nu +1)$ , $D_i := \bigcap _{i'< i} D_{i'}$ .
Let $D^*:=D_\nu $ and fix $\delta \in S$ such that
is in $J_\delta ^+$ .
For every $i < \nu $ , the following set
is in $J_\delta $ . Fix $\alpha \in A\setminus \bigcup _{i<\nu }A_i$ . Set $\gamma :=\min (C_\delta \setminus (\alpha +1))$ , so that $\operatorname {\mathrm {otp}}(e^\epsilon _\gamma \cap (D^*\setminus \alpha ))>\sigma $ .
For every $i < \nu $ , since $D^* \subseteq D_i$ and $D_{i+1}\subseteq F^{D_i}$ , we have that $\operatorname {\mathrm {otp}}(e^\epsilon _\gamma \cap (D_{i}\setminus \alpha ))>\sigma $ , and hence it must be the case that $D_i\cap e^\epsilon _\gamma \nsubseteq F^{D_i}$ , and therefore, $D_i\cap e^\epsilon _\gamma \nsubseteq D_{i+1}$ . So $\langle D_i\cap e^\epsilon _\gamma \ {\mathrel {|}}\ i<\nu \rangle $ is a strictly $\subseteq $ -decreasing sequence of subsets of $e^\epsilon _\gamma $ , contradicting the fact that $|e^\epsilon _\gamma |\le |\epsilon |<\nu $ .
Let D be given by the claim. As $\epsilon <\nu $ , for every $\gamma <\kappa $ , $|e^\epsilon _\gamma |<\nu $ . It altogether follows that the C-sequence $\vec C^\bullet =\langle C^{\bullet }_{\delta }\ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle $ defined via
is as sought.
Corollary 5.6. Let $\mu <\sigma < \sigma ^+ < \lambda < \kappa $ be infinite regular cardinals.
Then $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\lambda (E^\kappa _\lambda , E^\kappa _\sigma ,1,\vec J)$ implies $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\lambda (E^\kappa _\lambda , E^\kappa _\mu , \sigma ,\vec J)$ .
Proof Appeal to Theorem 5.5(1) with $\nu :=\sigma ^+$ , $\xi :=\lambda $ , $S:=E^\kappa _\lambda $ and $T:=E^\kappa _\mu $ .
Corollary 5.7. For every successor cardinal $\lambda $ , if $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\xi (E^{\lambda ^+}_\lambda , E^{\lambda ^+}_{<\lambda },1)$ holds, then so does $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\xi (E^{\lambda ^+}_\lambda , \lambda ^+,2)$ .
Proof By Theorem 5.2, using $\sigma :=2$ , $\lambda :=\nu ^+$ , $\kappa :=\lambda ^+$ , $S:=E^\kappa _\lambda $ , and $\vec J:=\langle J^{\mathrm {bd}}[\delta ]\ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle $ .
Remark 5.8. This shows that Clause (4) of [Reference Asperó, Geschke, Lowe and Schlicht2, Theorem 1.6] follows from Clause (5) of the same theorem, provided that the cardinal $\kappa $ there is a successor cardinal.
6 Moving between ideals
As shown in the Section 4, it is easier to partition a witness for $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\xi (S,T,\sigma , \vec J)$ in the case that the ideals in $\vec J$ are normal. So, we address here the problem of deriving $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\xi (S,T,\sigma ,\langle \mathrm{NS}_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle )$ from $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\xi (S,T,\sigma ,\langle J^{\mathrm {bd}}[\delta ]\ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle )$ . The key lemma is Lemma 6.3. In Theorem 6.4 it is used to improve results from Section 4. At successor cardinals, Lemma 6.3 is particularly useful as seen by the main result of this section, which combines Theorems A and E:
Corollary 6.1. Suppose that $\lambda $ is a successor cardinal, and $S\subseteq E^{\lambda ^+}_\lambda $ is stationary.
Then $:$
-
(1) $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\lambda (S,E^{\lambda ^+}_\lambda ,1,\langle \mathrm{NS}_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle )$ holds.
-
(2) $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\lambda (S,E^{\lambda ^+}_{<\lambda })$ implies $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\lambda (S,\lambda ^+,n,\langle \mathrm{NS}_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle )$ for every $n<\omega $ .
-
(3) If $\lambda>\aleph _1$ , then $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\lambda (S,E^{\lambda ^+}_{<\lambda })$ implies $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\lambda (S,\lambda ^+,\omega ,\langle \mathrm{NS}_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle )$ .
Proof Let $\nu $ denote the predecessor of $\lambda $ .
(1) By Fact 3.29 and Theorem 6.11(1).
(2) Suppose that $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\lambda (S,E^{\lambda ^+}_{<\lambda })$ , equivalently $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\lambda (S,E^{\lambda ^+}_{\ge \omega }\cap E^{\lambda ^+}_{\le \nu })$ , holds. Then, by Corollary 5.1, also $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\lambda (S,\lambda ^+,n)$ holds for every $n<\omega $ . Finally, By Theorem 6.11(1), moreover $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\lambda (S,\lambda ^+,n, \langle \mathrm{NS}_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in E^{\lambda ^+}_{\lambda }\rangle )$ holds for every $n<\omega $ .
(3) Assuming that $\nu $ is uncountable, by Corollary 5.1, $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\lambda (S,E^{\lambda ^+}_{\ge \omega }\cap E^{\lambda ^+}_{\le \nu })$ implies $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\lambda (S,\lambda ^+,\omega )$ , which, by Theorem 6.11(1), implies $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\lambda (S,\lambda ^+,\omega ,\langle \mathrm{NS}_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in E^{\lambda ^+}_{\lambda }\rangle )$ .
Lemma 6.2. Let $\aleph _0 < \xi < \kappa $ and $S\subseteq E^\kappa _\xi $ be stationary. Assume $1\le \sigma <\xi $ .
If $\vec J=\langle J_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle $ is such that $\mathrm{NS}_\delta \subseteq J_\delta $ for all $\delta $ , then $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}(S,T,\sigma ,\vec J)$ implies $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\xi (S,T,\sigma ,\vec J)$ .
Proof Let $\vec C=\langle C_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle $ be a witness to $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}(S,T,\sigma ,\vec J)$ . For each $\delta \in S$ , define a function $f_\delta :\delta \rightarrow \delta $ via
then fix a club $e_\delta $ in $\delta $ of ordertype $\operatorname {\mathrm {cf}}(\delta )$ consisting of closure points of $f_\delta $ , and finally let $C_\delta ^\bullet $ be the ordinal closure below $\delta $ of the following set:
To see that $\langle C_\delta ^\bullet \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle $ witnesses $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\xi (S,T,\sigma ,\vec J)$ , let D be a club in $\kappa $ . Pick $\delta \in S$ for which the following set is in $J_\delta ^+$ :
Then $e_\delta \cap B\in J_\delta ^+$ , and for every $\beta \in e_\delta \cap B$ , $\operatorname {\mathrm {succ}}_\sigma (C^{\bullet }_{\delta }\setminus \beta )= \operatorname {\mathrm {succ}}_\sigma (C_\delta \setminus \beta )$ .
Lemma 6.3. Suppose that $\vec C=\langle C_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle $ witnesses $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}(S,T,\sigma )$ , with $S\subseteq E^\kappa _{>\omega }$ and $T\subseteq \kappa $ . Then there exists a C-sequence $\vec e=\langle e_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle $ such that, for every club $D\subseteq \kappa $ , there exists $\delta \in S$ such that the following set is stationary in $\delta :$
Proof Suppose not. For every $\delta \in S$ , let $e_\delta ^0:=C_\delta $ . Next, suppose that $i<\omega $ and that $\langle e_\delta ^i\ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle $ has already been defined. By assumption, we can find a club $D_i\subseteq \kappa $ such that, for every $\delta \in S$ , the following set is nonstationary in $\delta $ :
so let us pick a subclub $e_\delta ^{i+1}$ of $e_\delta ^i$ disjoint from it.
Put $D:=\bigcap _{i<\omega }D_i$ . By the choice of $\vec C$ , let us now pick $\delta \in S$ such that
Pick $\beta <\delta $ above $\min (\bigcap _{i<\omega }e_\delta ^i)$ such that $\operatorname {\mathrm {succ}}_\sigma (C_\delta \setminus \beta )\subseteq D\cap T$ . Consider the ordinal
and then, for every $i<\omega $ , let $\alpha _i:=\sup (e^i_\delta \cap \gamma )$ . As $\operatorname {\mathrm {acc}}(e^i_\delta )\subseteq \operatorname {\mathrm {acc}}(C_\delta )$ , and $\gamma $ is in $\operatorname {\mathrm {nacc}}(C_\delta )$ and above $\min (e^i_\delta )$ , we infer that $\alpha _i\in e^i_\delta \cap \gamma $ . As $\langle e^i_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ i<\omega \rangle $ is a $\subseteq $ -decreasing chain, $\langle \alpha _i\ {\mathrel {|}}\ i<\omega \rangle $ is $\le $ -decreasing, so we may find a large enough $i<\omega $ such that $\alpha _{i+1}=\alpha _i$ . In particular, $\alpha _i\in e^{i+1}_\delta $ , so by the choice of $e^{i+1}_\delta $ ,
On the other hand, since $\alpha _i=\sup (e^i_\delta \cap \gamma )$ , it is the case that $\min (e_\delta ^i\setminus (\alpha _i+1))\ge \gamma $ . Recalling also that $e_\delta ^0\subseteq C_\delta $ , altogether $\alpha _i\le \beta <\min (e_\delta ^i\setminus (\alpha _i+1))$ , and
This is a contradiction.
An immediate consequence of the preceding lemma is an improvement of Clauses (2) and (3) of Theorem 4.9, for the special case of $\vec J=\langle J^{\mathrm {bd}}[\delta ]\ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle $ .
Theorem 6.4. Suppose that $\vec C$ witnesses $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}(S,T,\sigma )$ with $S\subseteq E^\kappa _\lambda $ , and $\lambda $ regular uncountable.
-
(1) If $\operatorname {{{\sf onto}}}(\mathrm{NS}_\lambda ,\lambda )$ holds, then $\lambda \in \Theta _2(\vec C,T,\sigma )$ .
-
(2) If $\operatorname {{{\sf unbounded}}}(\mathrm{NS}_\lambda ,\theta )$ holds and $\theta < \lambda $ , then $\theta \in \Theta _2(\vec C,T,\sigma )$ .
Proof Let $\vec e=\langle e_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle $ be the corresponding C-sequence given by Lemma 6.3. Without loss of generality, $e_\delta \subseteq C_\delta $ and $\operatorname {\mathrm {otp}}(e_\delta )=\lambda $ for all $\delta \in S$ . Define $\psi _\delta :\delta \rightarrow \lambda $ via $\psi _\delta (\beta ):=\operatorname {\mathrm {otp}}(e_\delta \cap \beta )$ , so that, for every $A\subseteq \delta $ , $\psi _\delta [A]$ is stationary in $\lambda $ iff A is stationary in $\delta $ .
(1) Suppose that $\operatorname {{{\sf onto}}}(\mathrm{NS}_\lambda ,\lambda )$ holds, and fix a colouring $c:[\lambda ]^2\rightarrow \lambda $ as in Theorem 4.10(2). As $\operatorname {\mathrm {nacc}}(\kappa )$ is in $\mathrm{NS}_\lambda $ , we may assume that for all $\eta <\alpha <\kappa $ , $c(\eta ,\alpha +1)=c(\eta ,\alpha )$ . Now, a proof nearly identical to that of Claim 4.9.1 yields an $\eta <\lambda $ such that, for every club $D\subseteq \kappa $ , there exists a $\delta \in S$ , such that, for every $ \tau <\lambda $ :
Choose $\vec h=\langle h_\delta :C_\delta \rightarrow \lambda \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle $ satisfying $h_\delta (\beta )=c(\eta ,\psi _\delta (\beta ))$ for all $\delta \in S$ and $\beta \in C_\delta $ such that $\eta <\psi _\delta (\beta )$ . Then $\vec h$ witnesses that $\lambda \in \Theta _2(\vec C,T,\sigma )$ .
(2) Suppose that $\operatorname {{{\sf unbounded}}}(J^{\mathrm {bd}}[\lambda ],\theta )$ holds with $\theta < \lambda $ , and fix a colouring $c:[\lambda ]^2\rightarrow \theta $ as in Theorem 4.10(1). For every club $D\subseteq \kappa $ , for all $\delta \in S$ and $\eta < \lambda $ , let $D(\eta ,\delta )$ denote the set:
A proof nearly identical to that of Claim 4.9.2 yields an $\eta <\lambda $ such that, for every club $D\subseteq \kappa $ , there exists $\delta \in S$ , such that $|D(\eta ,\delta )| = \theta $ . The rest of the proof is now identical to that of Theorem 4.9(3).
We are now in conditions to prove Theorem D:
Corollary 6.5. Suppose that $\vec C$ witnesses $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}(S,T,\sigma )$ with $S\subseteq E^\kappa _\lambda $ , and $\lambda $ regular uncountable.
-
(i) If $\diamondsuit ^*(\lambda )$ holds, then $\lambda \in \Theta _2(\vec C,T,\sigma )$ .
-
(ii) If $\lambda $ is not strongly inaccessible, then $\log _2(\lambda )\in \Theta _2(\vec C,T,\sigma )$ .
-
(iii) If $\lambda $ is strongly inaccessible, not ineffable, then $\theta \in \Theta _2(\vec C,T,\sigma )$ for every $\theta <\lambda $ .
-
(iv) If $\lambda $ is not greatly Mahlo, then $\theta \in \Theta _2(\vec C,T,\sigma )$ for every $\theta <\lambda $ .
Proof
Motivated by Fact 4.16(1), we ask:
Question 6.6. Suppose that $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}(S,T)$ holds for stationary $S\subseteq E^\kappa _{>\omega }$ and $T\subseteq \kappa $ .
Does there exist a cardinal $\mu <\kappa $ such that $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}(S,T,1,\langle \mathrm{NS}_\delta {\mathbin \upharpoonright } E^\delta _\mu \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle )$ holds?
Lemma 6.3 suggests the following variation of Definition 2.2.
Definition 6.7. $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\xi (S, T, \frac {1}{2} ,\vec J)$ asserts the existence of a $\xi $ -bounded C-sequence $\vec C=\langle C_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle $ such that, for every club $D\subseteq \kappa $ there is a $\delta \in S$ such that
Corollary 6.8. For all stationary $S\subseteq E^\kappa _{>\omega }$ and $T\subseteq \kappa $ , if $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}(S,T)$ holds, then so does $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}(S,T,\frac {1}{2},\langle \mathrm{NS}_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle )$ .
Note that by extending Definition 4.1 to incorporate the case $\sigma =\frac {1}{2}$ , Moore’s principle $\mho $ holds iff there is an $\omega $ -bounded C-sequence $\vec C$ over $\omega _1$ such that $\omega \in \Theta _2(\vec C,\omega _1,\frac {1}{2})$ . We now show that over subsets of $E^\kappa _{>\omega }$ it is possible to upgrade $\sigma =\frac {1}{2}$ to $\sigma =1$ , but at the cost of losing control over the set T.
Lemma 6.9. Suppose that $S\subseteq E^\kappa _{>\omega }$ is stationary.
For every C-sequence $\langle C_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle $ witnessing $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}(S,\kappa ,\frac {1}{2},\vec J)$ , there exists a postprocessing $^*$ function $\Phi :\mathcal K(\kappa )\rightarrow \mathcal K(\kappa )$ such that $\langle \Phi (C_\delta )\ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle $ witnesses $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}(S,\kappa ,1,\vec J)$ .
Proof We shall make use of the operator $\Phi _D$ from Definition 2.12.
Claim 6.9.1. There exists a club $D\subseteq \kappa $ such that, $\langle \Phi _D(C_\delta )\ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle $ witnesses $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}(S,\kappa ,1,\vec J)$ .
Proof Suppose not. In this case, for every club $D\subseteq \kappa $ , there is a club $F^D \subseteq \kappa $ such that for every $\delta \in S$
Construct a $\subseteq $ -decreasing sequence $\langle D_n \ {\mathrel {|}}\ n<\omega \rangle $ of clubs in $\kappa $ by letting $D_0 := \kappa $ and $D_{n+1} := \operatorname {\mathrm {acc}}(D_n) \cap F^{D_n}$ for every $n<\omega $ . Set $D:=\bigcap _{n<\omega }D_n$ and then pick $\delta \in S$ for which the following set is in $J_\delta ^+$ :
In particular, $\delta \in \operatorname {\mathrm {acc}}(D)$ , so that, for every $n<\omega $ ,
Now, as $\operatorname {\mathrm {cf}}(\delta )>\omega $ and $J_\delta $ is $\operatorname {\mathrm {cf}}(\delta )$ -complete, the following set is nonempty:
so we may pick in it some ordinal $\beta $ . Set $\gamma :=\min (C_\delta \setminus (\beta +1))$ . As $\beta \in B$ , we know that $D\cap (\beta ,\gamma ]\neq \emptyset $ . In particular, for every $n<\omega $ , $\operatorname {\mathrm {acc}}(D_n)\cap (\beta ,\gamma ]\neq \emptyset $ and $\beta _n:=\sup (D_n\cap \gamma )$ is an element of $D_n$ greater than $\beta $ , so that
As $\langle D_n \ {\mathrel {|}}\ n<\omega \rangle $ is a $\subseteq $ -decreasing chain, we may fix $n<\omega $ such that $\beta _{n+1}=\beta _n $ . Then $\min (\Phi _{D_n}(C_\delta )\setminus (\beta +1))=\beta _n=\beta _{n+1}\in D_{n+1}\subseteq F^{D_n}$ , contradicting the choice of $\beta $ .
Let D be given by the preceding claim. Then $\Phi :=\Phi _D$ is as sought.
Corollary 6.10. Suppose that $S\subseteq E^\kappa _{>\omega }$ is stationary.
If $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}(S,\kappa )$ holds, then so does $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}(S,\kappa ,1,\langle \mathrm{NS}_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle )$ .
Note that the preceding result is restricted to $\sigma :=1$ and $T:=\kappa $ . We now provide a condition sufficient for waiving this restriction.
Theorem 6.11. Suppose that $\xi $ is an infinite successor cardinal, and $S\subseteq E^\kappa _{\xi }$ is stationary.
-
(1) If $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\xi (S,T,\sigma )$ holds, then so does $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\xi (S,T,\sigma ,\langle \mathrm{NS}_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle )$ .
-
(2) If $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\xi (S,T,\frac {1}{2})$ holds, then so does $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\xi (S,T,1,\langle \mathrm{NS}_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle )$ .
Proof We provide a proof of Clause (1) and leave the modification of the argument to obtain Clause (2) to the reader.
As $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\xi (S,T,\xi )$ is equivalent to $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}(S,T,\kappa )$ , by Lemma 2.10, we may assume that $\sigma <\xi $ . Now, suppose that $\vec C=\langle C_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle $ witnesses $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\xi (S,T,\sigma )$ , and let $\vec e=\langle e_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle $ be the corresponding C-sequence given by Lemma 6.3. For each $\delta \in S$ , by possibly shrinking $e_\delta $ as in the proof of Lemma 6.2, we may assume that for every $\gamma \in e_\delta $ and every $\beta <\gamma $ , $\sup (\operatorname {\mathrm {succ}}_\sigma (C_\delta \setminus \beta ))<\gamma $ .
Let $\mu $ be such that $\xi =\mu ^+$ , and then, for all $\delta \in S$ and $\alpha \in e_\delta $ , let $\varphi _{\delta ,\alpha }$ be some surjection from $\mu $ to $C_\delta \cap [\alpha ,\min (e_\delta \setminus (\alpha +1)))$ .
For every $i<\mu $ , let $C_\delta ^i$ be the ordinal closure below $\delta $ of the following set:
Claim 6.11.1. There exists $i<\mu $ , such that, for every club $D\subseteq \kappa $ , there exists $\delta \in S$ for which the following set is stationary in $\delta :$
Proof Suppose not. For each $i<\mu $ , pick a counterexample club $D_i\subseteq \kappa $ . Consider the club $D:=\bigcap _{i<\mu }D_i$ . By the choice of $\vec e$ , pick $\delta \in S$ such that
is stationary. For every $\alpha \in A$ , pick $i_\alpha <\mu $ such that $\beta :=\varphi _{\delta ,\alpha }(i)$ witnesses that $\alpha \in A$ , that is, such that $\operatorname {\mathrm {succ}}_\sigma (C_\delta \setminus \varphi _{\delta ,\alpha }(i))\subseteq D\cap T$ . As $\operatorname {\mathrm {cf}}(\delta )=\xi>\mu $ , there must exist some stationary $A^*\subseteq A$ on which the map $\alpha \mapsto i_\alpha $ is constant, with value, say, $i^*$ . For every pair $\alpha <\alpha '$ of ordinals from $e_\delta $ ,
so, recalling the definition of $C_\delta ^{i*}$ , for every $\alpha \in A^*$ ,
contradicting the fact that $D\subseteq D_{i^*}$ .
Let $i<\mu $ be given by the preceding. Then $\langle C_\delta ^i\ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle $ witnesses $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\xi (S,T,\sigma , \langle \mathrm{NS}_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle )$ .
Remark 6.12. The above ordertype restriction cannot be waived, that is, the hypothesis $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_\xi (S,T,\sigma )$ in Theorem 6.11 cannot be relaxed to $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}(S,T,\sigma )$ .
By Theorem 3.31(1), if there exists a nonreflecting stationary subset of $E^{\aleph _2}_{\aleph _0}$ , then $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}(E^{\aleph _2}_{\aleph _1},E^{\aleph _2}_{\aleph _0})$ holds, and then, by Theorem 5.2, using $\xi =\kappa =\aleph _2$ and $S=E^{\aleph _2}_{\aleph _1}$ , so does $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}(E^{\aleph _2}_{\aleph _1},\omega _2,2)$ . Now, if the ordertype restriction in Theorem 6.11 could have been waived, then this would imply that $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}(E^{\aleph _2}_{\aleph _1},\omega _2,2,\langle \mathrm{NS}_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in E^{\aleph _2}_{\aleph _1}\rangle )$ holds. In particular, by Lemma 6.2, $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_{\omega _1}(E^{\aleph _2}_{\aleph _1},\omega _2,2)$ holds. However, running the forcing from [Reference Asperó, Geschke, Lowe and Schlicht2, Theorem 1.6] over a model of $\square _{\omega _1}$ , one gets a generic extension with a nonreflecting stationary subset of $E^{\aleph _2}_{\aleph _0}$ in which $\operatorname {\mathrm {CG}}_{\omega _1}(E^{\aleph _2}_{\aleph _1},\omega _2,2)$ fails. This is a contradiction.
Remark 6.13. An obvious complication of the proof of Theorem 6.11 shows that if $\xi $ an infinite successor cardinal, $S\subseteq E^\kappa _{\xi }$ is stationary, and $\vec C$ is a $\xi $ -bounded C-sequence over S such that $\theta \in \Theta _2(\vec C,T,\sigma )$ , then there exists a $\xi $ -bounded C-sequence $\vec {C^\bullet }$ over S such that $\theta \in \Theta _2(\vec {C^\bullet },T,\sigma ,\langle \mathrm{NS}_\delta \ {\mathrel {|}}\ \delta \in S\rangle )$ .
Acknowledgments
The results of this paper were presented by the second author in a tutorial at the Winter School in Abstract Analysis meeting in Štěkeň, Czech Republic, January 2023. We thank the organizers for the invitation and the participants for their feedback.
Funding
The first author is supported by the Israel Science Foundation (grant agreements 2066/18 and 665/20). The second author is partially supported by the Israel Science Foundation (grant agreement 203/22) and by the European Research Council (grant agreement ERC-2018-StG 802756).