Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-7cvxr Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-29T01:50:06.547Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Evidence for core social goal understanding (and, perhaps, core morality) in preverbal infants

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  27 June 2024

J. Kiley Hamlin*
Affiliation:
Department of Psychology, University of British Columbia, Vancouver, BC, Canada cic.psych.ubc.ca
*
Corresponding author: J. Kiley Hamlin; Email: [email protected]

Abstract

Spelke's What Babies Know masterfully describes infants’ impressive repertoire of core cognitive concepts, from which the suite of human knowledge is eventually built. The current commentary argues for the existence of a core concept that Spelke claims preverbal infants lack: social goal. Core social goal concepts, operative extremely early in human development, underlie infants’ basic abilities to interpret and evaluate entities within the moral world; such abilities support claims for a core moral domain.

Type
Open Peer Commentary
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2024. Published by Cambridge University Press

1. What babies know

In What Babies Know (Reference Spelke2022), legendary cognitive scientist Elizabeth Spelke reviews decades of evidence supporting the claim that humans possess “core knowledge”: Innate systems of abstract knowledge that are evolutionarily ancient, early-emerging, and invariant over development; within these systems knowledge operates automatically, unconsciously, and independently of belief. Spelke provides a detailed account of the evidence for and against six systems, or domains, of core knowledge: Objects, number, places, forms, agents, and social beings. Each system contains skeletal versions of particular concepts (e.g., how objects behave), allowing inexperienced human and nonhuman animals to reason productively about the entities within it.

Crucial to Spelke's analysis of which concepts are and are not part of core knowledge is the claim that each domain competes with the others for attention, resulting in an initial failure of domains to communicate with each other. This failure precludes thinking about any concept that involves entities from more than one domain, thereby limiting the range of concepts that can be core to the human mind. Spelke argues that these limitations are overcome with the emergence of language around 10 months; language facilitates communication between domains and allows children to begin constructing myriad novel, non-core concepts.

2. What babies don't know: Social goals

After reviewing concepts she believes young infants possess, Spelke devotes significant discussion to one she believes they lack: social goal. Specifically, although two of Spelke's six core domains are for reasoning about the social world (the agent and social being systems), Spelke holds that neither is capable of social goal understanding by itself. On the one hand, the core agent system solely considers agents’ physical and instrumental goals; it does not consider goals underlying agent-directed actions (e.g., social looking, communication), nor instrumental actions undertaken for social reasons (e.g., cooperating, helping, hindering, other prosocial and antisocial acts). On the other hand, the core social being system solely considers engagements between social entities and between those entities and infants themselves; it does not consider the mental states driving those engagements. Given that understanding social goals requires thinking about social beings as agents whose mental states refer to other agents, it requires communication between the agent and social being systems. Because this communication is impossible prior to language, the concept social goal cannot be part of core knowledge.

Although the observation that core knowledge is limited and the provision of an explanation for how its limitations are eventually overcome are crucial to a proper account of the origins of human cognition, it is curious why Spelke spends so much time arguing that core knowledge lacks social goal understanding. Presumably, this is because she wishes to argue against a potential additional domain of core knowledge that has recently attracted attention: core morality. Indeed, a growing number of cognitive scientists have recently argued that human moral systems are supported by evolved, domain-specific mechanisms for thinking about the moral world (e.g., Baumard, André, & Sperber, Reference Baumard, André and Sperber2013; Buyukozer Dawkins, Sloane, & Baillargeon, Reference Buyukozer Dawkins, Sloane and Baillargeon2019; Hamlin, Reference Hamlin2013a; Krebs, Reference Krebs2008; Macnamara, Reference Macnamara1991; Mikhail, Reference Mikhail2011; Premack, Reference Premack, Vilarroya and Forn i Argimon2007; Woo, Tan, & Hamlin, Reference Woo, Tan and Hamlin2022; Wynn & Bloom, Reference Wynn, Bloom, Killen and Smetana2014). Among other things, these mechanisms might allow inexperienced humans to identify morally relevant (inter)actions, evaluate those actions and agents who engage in them as positive or negative, and generate expectations for further actions the agents might perform. All such capacities would, at minimum, require an understanding of social goals.

Although not exclusively, much recent argumentation for core morality cites evidence that preverbal infants appear to positively and negatively evaluate agents based on their prosocial and antisocial acts (for review, see, Margoni & Surian, Reference Margoni and Surian2018; Woo et al., Reference Woo, Tan and Hamlin2022), and/or possess expectations for the prosocial versus antisocial acts that individuals are likely to perform in distinct contexts (see Buyukozer Dawkins et al., Reference Buyukozer Dawkins, Sloane and Baillargeon2019). Spelke acknowledges that this evidence could suggest that young infants understand social goals, but argues that it actually does not, for two reasons. First, much of the evidence involves infants older than 10 months. At 10 months, the core agent and social being systems can communicate, meaning a concept of social goals can be constructed rather than “core.” Second, evidence with infants <10 months has a viable alternative explanation that does not implicate social goal understanding. Specifically, young infants’ preferences for helpers over hinderers (e.g., Hamlin & Wynn, Reference Hamlin and Wynn2011; Hamlin, Wynn, & Bloom, Reference Hamlin, Wynn and Bloom2007) need not reflect their understanding of (pro- and/or anti-) social goals, as those preferences may stem from mere sensitivity to social beings in states of engagement (or not) with other social beings: Social engagement is handled by the social being system alone.

Specifically, Spelke points out that prototypical helpful/unhelpful acts shown to infants can also be described as imitative/not imitative: In order to help, the helper generally reproduces the actions of a needy protagonist, whereas the hinderer produces opposing actions (see, e.g., Powell & Spelke, Reference Powell and Spelke2018). Under Spelke's core social being system, imitation is a powerful cue that one social being is engaged with another, but certainly lacks moral content (see also Powell, Reference Powell2022). Thus, Spelke holds that much of the evidence used to argue for core moral capacities has no moral content after all.

In what follows, I review evidence that although infants appear sensitive to cues to social engagement like imitation, they can and do reason about social goals prior to 10 months. Indeed, consistent with claims for core morality, preverbal infants may be particularly sensitive to social goals with moral content, including helping/hindering, protection/harm, and fairness/unfairness. Because of space constraints I can only touch on the relevant evidence below; interested readers can find more detailed discussion elsewhere (Hamlin, Reference Hamlin2023; Woo, Tan, Yuen, & Hamlin, Reference Woo, Tan, Yuen and Hamlin2023).

3. Evidence infants’ preference for helpers cannot be explained by imitation

Spelke argues that young infants’ preference for helpers reflects sensitivity to imitation rather than to prosocial/antisocial goals. Indeed, Spelke and her former student Lindsay Powell have demonstrated that infants prefer imitators over non-imitators within scenarios purported to demonstrate infants’ preferences for helpers over hinderers (Powell & Spelke, Reference Powell and Spelke2018). Although Powell (Reference Powell2022) argues that infants’ imitator preference itself reflects social goal understanding (e.g., that one agent has adopted another's “utility,” or goal, as its own), Spelke argues that infants could instead prefer imitators without representing utility adoption/goals at all, by inferring that imitators are engaged with their targets.

Inconsistent with Spelke's analysis, several studies now suggest that infants’ preferences focus on helping rather than imitating. For instance, infants’ preferences rely on their understanding of a needy protagonist's goals. Hamlin (Reference Hamlin2015) manipulated whether or not 6–10-month-olds could recognize the goal of trying but failing to climb a hill, by showing some infants the protagonist's eyes pointing toward the hilltop (suggesting a goal to reach the top) and others the protagonist's eyes pointing away from the hilltop (rendering its goal ambiguous). Critically, in both conditions one character imitated the protagonist (pushed it up), and another character did not imitate the protagonist (pushed it down). Critically, only those infants who saw the protagonist looking toward the hilltop, demonstrating a clear unfulfilled goal, preferred the pusher-upper (here, a helper) to the pusher-downer (a hinderer). Similarly, Tan and Hamlin (Reference Tan and Hamlin2022) showed that infants’ own looking toward the hilltop during the protagonist's failed attempts, arguably indicating goal inference (see Elsner & Adam, Reference Elsner and Adam2020), predicted their individual preference for the agent who pushed it to the top: Only those infants who ever looked to the top of the hill preferred the “helper.”

Other studies more directly compare helpers and imitators. For instance, in Hamlin et al. (Reference Hamlin, Wynn and Bloom2007) and Chae and Song (Reference Chae and Song2018), 6- and 10-month-olds were asked to choose between an agent who pushed a needy protagonist uphill, moving like the protagonist and causing it to achieve its goal, and an agent who moved up the hill in exactly the same way, but independently from the protagonist. Here, infants chose between an imitative helper and a mere imitator, and consistently selected the helper. In a study from Spelke's own laboratory led by her former student Brandon Woo (Woo & Spelke, Reference Woo and Spelke2023), 8-month-olds were led to infer that an agent's goal was one of the two possible options, either to open a specific box or to obtain a specific toy. Subsequently, one agent facilitated the goal they inferred the agent to have, whereas the other agent facilitated the other goal; critically for the present purposes, in one condition the helpful agent was less imitative. Here again, infants’ choices suggested they consistently preferred helpers, but not imitators.

In each of the above studies, one character's actions always matched the protagonist's more closely than the other's. However, infants only chose those imitators whose actions were also helpful: They preferred helpful imitators over mere imitators, and failed to distinguish differentially imitative characters who were not differentially helpful. Thus, Spelke's claim that young infants’ helper preferences can be reduced to preferences for imitators seems unlikely.

4. Evidence young infants can represent (pro- and anti-) social goals

Although the above work suggests that infants are more sensitive to helping than to imitating, it need not indicate that infants represent that helpers possess the prosocial goal to facilitate another's goal or that hinderers possess the antisocial goal to prevent a goal. Indeed, perhaps young infants merely represent whether or not one agent causes another to achieve its goal (which imitators do not do). Of course, adults’ moral concepts privilege others’ prosocial and antisocial intentions (e.g., Cushman, Reference Cushman2008; Malle, Reference Malle1999): Do young infants also consider social intentions?

Multiple studies now suggest that infants represent and evaluate prosocial and antisocial intentions before 10 months (see also Hamlin, Ullman, Tenenbaum, Goodman, & Baker, Reference Hamlin, Ullman, Tenenbaum, Goodman and Baker2013; Kanakogi et al., Reference Kanakogi, Inoue, Matsuda, Butler, Hiraki and Myowa-Yamakoshi2017; Strid & Meristo, Reference Strid and Meristo2020; Woo, Steckler, Le, & Hamlin, Reference Woo, Steckler, Le and Hamlin2017). First, Hamlin (Reference Hamlin2013b) demonstrated that 8-month-olds privileged intentions over outcomes in their preferences for pro- and antisocial others; for instance, preferring an agent who tried but failed to help a protagonist achieve its unfulfilled goal over an agent who tried but failed to hinder the protagonist. Second, Woo and Spelke (Reference Woo and Spelke2022) showed that, remarkably, 8-month-olds preferred an agent who believed it was helping, even though it was not, over an agent who believed it was not helping, even though it was. Finally, Geraci and Surian (Reference Geraci and Surian2023) and Geraci, Simion, and Surian (Reference Geraci, Simion and Surian2022) demonstrated that 4- and 9-month-olds preferred an agent who tried but failed to distribute resources equally between two recipients over one who tried but failed to distribute resources unequally. Because no resources were ever actually given out, infants’ choices must have been based on intent; further control conditions suggest that it was not that infants simply like agents appearing to have more social partners (for related controls with acts of protection, see Kanakogi et al., Reference Kanakogi, Inoue, Matsuda, Butler, Hiraki and Myowa-Yamakoshi2017). These papers suggest that even young infants understand prosocial and/or antisocial intentions within two morally relevant domains, at times at or before they appear to be able to recognize intention in nonmoral contexts (for discussion, see Woo et al., Reference Woo, Tan, Yuen and Hamlin2023).

5. Conclusion

In sum, in contrast to Spelke's claims, young infants appear to possess the concept social goal. Although this may seem like a rather insignificant topic of debate, an inability to understand social goals early in development would, in turn, render recent arguments that humans possess core moral capacities (e.g., Baumard et al., Reference Baumard, André and Sperber2013; Buyukozer Dawkins et al., Reference Buyukozer Dawkins, Sloane and Baillargeon2019; Hamlin, Reference Hamlin2013a; Krebs, Reference Krebs2008; Macnamara, Reference Macnamara1991; Mikhail, Reference Mikhail2011; Premack, Reference Premack, Vilarroya and Forn i Argimon2007; Woo et al., Reference Woo, Tan and Hamlin2022; Wynn & Bloom, Reference Wynn, Bloom, Killen and Smetana2014) moot, given that many if not most moral concepts are fundamentally rooted in notions of social goals. Of course, there is more to moral concepts than social goals, and any effective claim to core morality will include much more data than reviewed here, including from animals and diverse adult humans (see, e.g., Anderson et al., Reference Anderson, Bucher, Chijiiwa, Kuroshima, Takimoto and Fujita2017; Anderson, Kuroshima, Takimoto, & Fujita, Reference Anderson, Kuroshima, Takimoto and Fujita2013a; Anderson, Takimoto, Kuroshima, & Fujita, Reference Anderson, Takimoto, Kuroshima and Fujita2013b; Brosnan, Reference Brosnan2023; Cosmides, Guzmán, & Tooby, Reference Cosmides, Guzmán, Tooby, Zimmerman, Jones and Timmons2018; Cosmides & Tooby, Reference Cosmides and Tooby1992; Curry, Mullins, & Whitehouse, Reference Curry, Mullins and Whitehouse2019; Darden, James, Cave, Brask, & Croft, Reference Darden, James, Cave, Brask and Croft2020; Isik, Koldewyn, Beeler, & Kanwisher, Reference Isik, Koldewyn, Beeler and Kanwisher2017; Mikhail, Reference Mikhail2011). Spelke's What Babies Know (Reference Spelke2022) provides an enviable model of what effective arguments for core moral knowledge – and indeed any account of the origins of knowledge more generally – must look like.

Financial support

This work was supported by the National Sciences and Engineering Research Council of Canada, RGPIN-2022-05037.

Competing interests

None.

References

Anderson, J. R., Bucher, B., Chijiiwa, H., Kuroshima, H., Takimoto, A., & Fujita, K. (2017). Third-party social evaluations of humans by monkeys and dogs. Neuroscience & Biobehavioral Reviews, 82, 95109. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.neubiorev.2017.01.003CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Anderson, J. R., Kuroshima, H., Takimoto, A., & Fujita, K. (2013a). Third-party social evaluation of humans by monkeys. Nature Communications, 4(1), 1561. https://doi.org/10.1038/ncomms2495CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Anderson, J. R., Takimoto, A., Kuroshima, H., & Fujita, K. (2013b). Capuchin monkeys judge third-party reciprocity. Cognition, 127(1), 140146. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cognition.2012.12.007CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Baumard, N., André, J.-B., & Sperber, D. (2013). A mutualistic approach to morality: The evolution of fairness by partner choice. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 36(1), 5978. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0140525X11002202CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Brosnan, S. F. (2023). A comparative perspective on the human sense of justice. Evolution and Human Behavior, 44(3), 242249. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.evolhumbehav.2022.12.002CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Buyukozer Dawkins, M., Sloane, S., & Baillargeon, R. (2019). Do infants in the first year of life expect equal resource allocations? Frontiers in Psychology, 10, 116. https://doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2019.00116CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Chae, J. J. K., & Song, H. (2018). Negativity bias in infants’ expectations about agents’ dispositions. British Journal of Developmental Psychology, 36(4), 620633. https://doi.org/10.1111/bjdp.12246CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Cosmides, L., Guzmán, R. A., & Tooby, J. (2018). The evolution of moral cognition. In Zimmerman, A., Jones, K., & Timmons, M. (Eds.), Routledge handbook on moral epistemology (pp. 174228). Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cosmides, L., & Tooby, J. (1992). Cognitive adaptations for social exchange. In The adapted mind: Evolutionary psychology and the generation of culture (pp. 163228). Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Curry, O. S., Mullins, D. A., & Whitehouse, H. (2019). Is it good to cooperate? Testing the theory of morality-as-cooperation in 60 societies. Current Anthropology, 60(1), 4769. https://doi.org/10.1086/701478CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cushman, F. (2008). Crime and punishment: Distinguishing the roles of causal and intentional analyses in moral judgment. Cognition, 108(2), 353380. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cognition.2008.03.006CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Darden, S. K., James, R., Cave, J. M., Brask, J. B., & Croft, D. P. (2020). Trinidadian guppies use a social heuristic that can support cooperation among non-kin. Proceedings of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 287(1934), 20200487. https://doi.org/10.1098/rspb.2020.0487CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Elsner, B., & Adam, M. (2020). Infants’ goal prediction for simple action events: The role of experience and agency cues. Topics in Cognitive Science, 13(1), 4562. https://doi.org/10.1111/tops.12494CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Geraci, A., Simion, F., & Surian, L. (2022). Infants’ intention-based evaluations of distributive actions. Journal of Experimental Child Psychology, 220, 105429. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.jecp.2022.105429CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Geraci, A., & Surian, L. (2023). Intention-based evaluations of distributive actions by 4-month-olds. Infant Behavior and Development, 70, 101797. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.infbeh.2022.101797CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hamlin, J. K. (2013a). Moral judgment and action in preverbal infants and toddlers: Evidence for an innate moral core. Current Directions in Psychological Science, 22(3), 186193. https://doi.org/10.1177/0963721412470687CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hamlin, J. K. (2013b). Failed attempts to help and harm: Intention versus outcome in preverbal infants’ social evaluations. Cognition, 128(3), 451474. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cognition.2013.04.004CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hamlin, J. K. (2015). The case for social evaluation in preverbal infants: Gazing toward one's goal drives infants’ preferences for helpers over hinderers in the hill paradigm. Frontiers in Psychology, 5, 1563. https://doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2014.01563CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hamlin, J. K. (2023). Core morality? Or merely core agents and social beings? A response to Spelke's What babies know. Mind and Language, 38, 13231335.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hamlin, J. K., Ullman, T., Tenenbaum, J., Goodman, N., & Baker, C. (2013). The mentalistic basis of core social cognition: Experiments in preverbal infants and a computational model. Developmental Science, 16(2), 209226. https://doi.org/10.1111/desc.12017CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hamlin, J. K., & Wynn, K. (2011). Young infants prefer prosocial to antisocial others. Cognitive Development, 26(1), 3039. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cogdev.2010.09.001CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hamlin, J. K., Wynn, K., & Bloom, P. (2007). Social evaluation by preverbal infants. Nature, 450(7169), 557559. http://dx.doi.org/10.1038/nature06288CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Isik, L., Koldewyn, K., Beeler, D., & Kanwisher, N. (2017). Perceiving social interactions in the posterior superior temporal sulcus. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 114(43), E9145E9152. https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.1714471114Google ScholarPubMed
Kanakogi, Y., Inoue, Y., Matsuda, G., Butler, D., Hiraki, K., & Myowa-Yamakoshi, M. (2017). Preverbal infants affirm third-party interventions that protect victims from aggressors. Nature Human Behaviour, 1(2), 17. https://doi.org/10.1038/s41562-016-0037CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Krebs, D. L. (2008). Morality: An evolutionary account. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 3(3), 149172. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1745-6924.2008.00072.xCrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Macnamara, J. (1991). The development of moral reasoning and the foundations of geometry. Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour, 21(2), 125150.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Malle, B. F. (1999). How people explain behavior: A new theoretical framework. Personality and Social Psychology Review, 3(1), 2348. https://doi.org/10.1207/s15327957pspr0301_2CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Margoni, F., & Surian, L. (2018). Infants’ evaluation of prosocial and antisocial agents: A meta-analysis. Developmental Psychology, 54(8), 14451455. https://doi.org/10.1037/dev0000538CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Mikhail, J. (2011). Elements of moral cognition: Rawls’ linguistic analogy and the cognitive science of moral and legal judgment. Cambridge University Press. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511780578CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Powell, L. J. (2022). Adopted utility calculus: Origins of a concept of social affiliation. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 17(5), 12151233. https://doi.org/10.1177/17456916211048487CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Powell, L. J., & Spelke, E. S. (2018). Third-party preferences for imitators in preverbal infants. Open Mind, 2(2), 6171. https://doi.org/10.1162/opmi_a_00018CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Premack, D. (2007). Foundations of morality in the infant. In Vilarroya, O. , & Forn i Argimon, F. (Eds.), Social brain matters (pp. 161167). Brill. https://doi.org/10.1163/9789401204491_015CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Spelke, E. S. (2022). What babies know: Core knowledge and composition (Vol. 1). Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Strid, K., & Meristo, M. (2020). Infants consider the distributor's intentions in resource allocation. Frontiers in Psychology, 11, 596213. https://doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2020.596213CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Tan, E., & Hamlin, J. K. (2022). Mechanisms of social evaluation in infancy: A preregistered exploration of infants’ eye-movement and pupillary responses to prosocial and antisocial events. Infancy, 27(2), 255276. https://doi.org/10.1111/infa.12447CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Woo, B. M., & Spelke, E. (2022). Eight-month-old infants’ social evaluations of agents who act on false beliefs. Proceedings of the Annual Meeting of the Cognitive Science Society, 44, 11841189. https://escholarship.org/uc/item/8k02x1mxGoogle Scholar
Woo, B. M., & Spelke, E. S. (2023). Infants and toddlers leverage their understanding of action goals to evaluate agents who help others. Child Development, 94(3), 734751. doi:10.1111/cdev.13895CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Woo, B. M., Steckler, C. M., Le, D. T., & Hamlin, J. K. (2017). Social evaluation of intentional, truly accidental, and negligently accidental helpers and harmers by 10-month-old infants. Cognition, 168, 154163. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cognition.2017.06.029CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Woo, B. M., Tan, E., & Hamlin, J. K. (2022). Human morality is based on an early-emerging moral core. Annual Review of Developmental Psychology, 4(1), 4161. https://doi.org/10.1146/annurev-devpsych-121020-023312CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Woo, B. M., Tan, E., Yuen, F. L., & Hamlin, J. K. (2023). Socially evaluative contexts facilitate mentalizing. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 27(1), 1729. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.tics.2022.10.003CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Wynn, K., & Bloom, P. (2014). The moral baby. In Killen, M. & Smetana, J. G. (Eds.), Handbook of moral development (pp. 435453). Psychology Press.Google Scholar