No CrossRef data available.
Article contents
The science of consciousness must include its more advanced forms
Published online by Cambridge University Press: 24 November 2016
Abstract
Morsella et al. argue that science should not focus on high forms of consciousness. We disagree. An understanding of high forms of consciousness is invaluable to the scientific study of consciousness. Moreover, it poses challenges to the passive frame theory. Specifically, it challenges the notions that conscious thoughts are not connected and that consciousness serves skeletomotor conflict only.
- Type
- Open Peer Commentary
- Information
- Copyright
- Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2016
References
Baumeister, R. F. & Masicampo, E. J. (2010) Conscious thought is for facilitating social and cultural interactions: How mental simulations serve the animal–culture interface. Psychological Review
117(3):945–71.Google Scholar
Block, N. (1995a) How many concepts of consciousness? (Response article)
Behavioral and Brain Sciences
18(2):272–87.Google Scholar
Damasio, A. R. (1999) The feeling of what happens: Body and emotion in the making of consciousness. Harvest Books.Google Scholar
Edelman, G. M. (2004) Wider than the sky: The phenomenal gift of consciousness. Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Mendl, M. & Paul, E. S. (2004) Consciousness, emotion and animal welfare: Insights from cognitive science. Animal Welfare
13(Suppl.):S17–25.Google Scholar
Panksepp, J. (2005) Affective consciousness: Core emotional feelings in animals and humans. Consciousness and Cognition
14:30–80.Google Scholar
Target article
Homing in on consciousness in the nervous system: An action-based synthesis
Related commentaries (30)
Action-based synthesis of parental brain consciousness
An “ecological” action-based synthesis
At what timescale does consciousness operate?
Calling for a developmental perspective on action-based consciousness
Can skeletomotor action integration occur without consciousness? Evidence from unconscious action inhibition
Conflicts everywhere! Perceptions, actions, and cognition all entail memory and reflect conflict
Conscious content generated by unconscious action-related adjustments
Conscious olfaction: Content, function, and localization
Consciousness around the time of saccadic eye movements
Consciousness for perception and for action: A perspective from unconscious binding
Consciousness of emotions and action selection
Consciousness weaves our internal view of the outside world
Content encapsulation in consciousness is likely to be incomplete
Explaining consciousness: From correlations to foundations
Four questions for passive frame theory
Getting back from the basics: What is the role for attention and fronto-parietal circuits in consciousness?
Heavy objects and small children: Developmental data extend the passive frame theory
Homing in on consciousness: Why is a dream conscious?
How does consciousness for action relate to attention for action?
Human consciousness is fundamental for perception and highest emotions
Infer yourself: Interoception and internal “action” in conscious selfhood
Insights on consciousness from taste memory research
Is conscious content available only to the skeletal muscle system?
Locating consciousness: We are conflicted by the role of conflict
Metacognition and conscious experience
Origins of emotional consciousness
The chemosensory brain requires a distributed cellular mechanism to harness information and resolve conflicts – is consciousness the forum?
The primary (dis)function of consciousness: (Non)Integration
The science of consciousness must include its more advanced forms
What if consciousness has no function?
Author response
Passive frame theory: A new synthesis