Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-v9fdk Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-03T00:54:22.686Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

1 - Worldviews in World Politics

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  29 June 2022

Peter J. Katzenstein
Affiliation:
Cornell University, New York

Summary

This chapter discusses the concept of worldview; relates it to paradigms and substantialist and relational reasoning; maps Newtonianism and Post-Newtonianism (quantum mechanics) and humanism and hyper-humanism (scientific cosmology) as two different dimensions structuring implicit worldviews; specifies four analytical perspectives on world politics; and concludes briefly with two illustrative applications.

Type
Chapter
Information
Uncertainty and Its Discontents
Worldviews in World Politics
, pp. 1 - 70
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2022
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BYCreative Common License - NC
This content is Open Access and distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence CC-BY-NC 4.0 https://creativecommons.org/cclicenses/

The fact that financial markets went markedly into shock has to be attributed to a lack of confidence in policies and leadership. It’s a failure of worldview.

Adam Posen, March 2020Footnote 1

I found out to my intense surprise and disappointment that my father did not have, what I then thought was a basic necessity for any real person – a “Weltanschauung”! The subsequent history of my life and thought could probably be written in terms of the progressive discovery on my part how right my father had been.

Albert O. Hirschman, March 1993Footnote 2

Sometimes we get overwhelmed by the uncertainties of life and the open-endedness of the future. The pandemic gripping the world in 2020/21 is one such instance. As the virus spread, a sense of personal vulnerability and radical uncertainty spread as well, barely masked by incessant talk about changing risk calculations.Footnote 3 In such moments many of us do not turn to theories, models, or hypotheses. Instead, we turn to worldviews to give us some traction in a world suddenly turned upside down. President Trump’s worldview valued national borders that could be closed to foreigners. Early on, he imposed a ban on travel from China. The World Health Organization and many others were aghast. Their worldview valued open borders and unobstructed travel. In January 2021, during his last day in office, President Trump lifted travel bans his administration had previously imposed, only to have the incoming Biden administration immediately reverse his decision. This is not to deny the obvious. After four years in office, President Trump’s general worldview had affected state and local officials of the Republican party, not to mention tens of millions of his supporters.Footnote 4

The 2020/21 pandemic is merely the latest example of the kinds of uncertainties students of world politics confront on a daily basis.Footnote 5 On March 3–4, 2020, for example, it was unclear how the stock market would react to the biggest emergency rate cut of the Federal Reserve since the Great Recession of 2008. Most market analysts expected a bounce in stock prices; instead, the market tanked. A few weeks later – again to everyone’s total surprise, as the real economy cratered and the number of unemployed topped 30 million – April 2020 turned out to be the best month Wall Street had recorded since 1987. Politics is similarly unpredictable. For example, the outcome of the Super Tuesday Democratic primary of March 2020 was entirely uncertain. Nobody had a clue how it would affect the relative standing of the main contenders. In the event, Joe Biden’s string of victories stunned analysts and practitioners alike. Shomik Dutta, a veteran of Obama campaigns, lamented: “It’s a bizarre feeling to realize that all the things I obsess over in politics … did not seem to matter very much at all.”Footnote 6 Eight months later, most pollsters agreed that Joe Biden would win the 2020 US Presidential election comfortably, and perhaps with a blow-out. Pollsters had tweaked their models, learning from their 2016 mistakes. All the hard work was to no avail. The cliff-hanger election disproved a tsunami of surveys.Footnote 7

With its unexpected turns and twists, time and again world politics has stumped participants and analysts with momentous events. The end of the Cold War, German unification, the peaceful disintegration of the Soviet Union, the 9/11 attacks on the World Trade Center and the Pentagon, the 2008 financial crisis and its aftermath, the Arab Spring, Brexit and the election of Donald Trump, the surge of protest across the United States after the murder of George Floyd, the coronavirus pandemic, and the wildfires engulfing the American West coast in 2020 were all big surprises. Insider knowledge and the political intuition of central protagonists are of little help. Chancellor Kohl’s 1989 predictions about the process of German unification were wrong, as were those of Prime Minister Cameron in 2016 about the outcome of the Brexit referendum. And so too were the well-considered judgments of leading American international relations theorists. In the late 1970s and early 1980s, Kenneth Waltz bet that the Soviet Union would last another century, Robert Keohane that the era of American hegemony had passed.Footnote 8 When the unexpected undermines or overturns our most respected theories, we often fall back on our worldviews for guidance.

For Theodore White, “It is the nature of politics that men must always act on the basis of uncertain facts … Were it otherwise, then … politics would be an exact science in which our purposes and destiny could be left to great impersonal computers.”Footnote 9 Putting aside the concept of uncertainty, most students of world politics have followed economics in focusing their attention on calculable risk.Footnote 10 For example, in her authoritative and sophisticated analysis of risk and uncertainty in international politics, Rose McDermott writes that risk and uncertainty comingle.Footnote 11 She thus combines both as she identifies mechanisms of risk propensity that occur under conditions of “high” uncertainty. In the remainder of her book, however, she puts aside the problem of uncertainty and focuses exclusively on the domain of risk.

While it is not possible to scale the magnitude of uncertainty, it is possible to distinguish between two types: operational uncertainty and radical uncertainty. Known unknowns create operational uncertainty which, given more or better information, may transform into calculable risk. This, however, is not a panacea. Under conditions of operational uncertainty, better and more information and knowledge, as in the squeezing of a balloon, can simply push radical uncertainty into some other, unrecognized part of the political context.Footnote 12 On questions of security and political economy, this is standard practice in the analysis of world politics.Footnote 13 Uncertainty is conflated with the concept of risk and thus remains invisible.Footnote 14 McDermott acknowledges this fact. “It is impossible,” she writes, “to predict the characteristics of many different variables simultaneously in advance, especially when they may have unknown interaction effects. Even the nature of many of the critical variables may be unknown beforehand.”Footnote 15 Analysis proceeds based on the unrealistic assumption that, separated by different information, parties to a conflict in world politics share in the same understanding of how the world works. New information leads to revised risk calculations and thus offers a way forward.

Withdrawn from the precarious domain of uncertainty, the future is domesticated into the more agreeable form of risk, thus retaining a family resemblance with the present and the past. Measurable confidence intervals strip the future of the deep anxiety that attends the unknown. We live life forward while understanding it backward. The malleability of the world is reflected in the multiple ways we have convinced ourselves of knowing the future. Prediction becomes a specific technology of “future making and world crafting,” made possible by severing the link between a man-made future and religion.Footnote 16 This offers us an avenue for managing expectations and thus to exercise some control over time. But such efforts can run up against manifestations of uncertainty such as technological breakthroughs, authority crises, consensus breakdowns, revolutionary upheavals, generational conflicts, and other forces that restructure the political landscape.Footnote 17 Theories and models are thus defeated by the unpredictable as world politics moves beyond control.Footnote 18 And, as Ernst Haas observed long ago, theories and models can unwittingly exacerbate problems of turbulence by pretending to create predictability for parts of political reality while weakening our understanding of the whole.Footnote 19

Worldviews differ in the salience they assign to risk and uncertainty. Approaches such as subjective probability theory explore ways of thinking about rationality and its relation to risk and uncertainty.Footnote 20 Rationality can take the form of different, situationally specific kinds of reasonableness. Since total chaos and existential uncertainty are terrifying, concepts such as ontological security probe different forms of reasonableness under conditions of risk and uncertainty.Footnote 21 And reasonableness differs in worldviews populated by different cosmologies, memories, imaginaries, emotions, and moral sensibilities: “It is not the information but the worldview that drives actors.”Footnote 22

The concept of a risk-inflected control of nature and society is so reassuring that we simply close our eyes to the self-evident: the ineluctability of the uncertainties of life. Why we do so is not self-evident. To be sure, the idea of risk is profound and has been immensely beneficial in human affairs. Indeed, a couple of centuries ago it was revolutionary to think that the future could serve the present, and that the chance of loss is an opportunity for gain.Footnote 23 But these important insights should not make us deny the obvious: uncertainty and an open future are important aspects of world politics. Uncertainty results in part from people holding different theories of how the world works. The financial meltdown of 2008 showed widely accepted risk models to have been utterly useless in predicting the crisis. Very little has changed either in the specific field of finance or in the broader analysis of world politics. We have been so fully seduced by the Hobbesian notion of control that we overlook the surprises Machiavelli writes about. We have placed all of our bets on the all-controlling Leviathan, while forgetting about the jolts fortuna administers regularly.Footnote 24

This is not to argue that uncertainty is the only factor shaping political life. Social science and common sense offer tools that equip us to cope with “knowable unknowns” and the risky aspects of life in a partly orderly world.Footnote 25 However, “unknowable unknowns” also exist, and these radical uncertainties shape a reality not amenable to risk analysis. Compared to the Great Recession of 2008, the 2020 pandemic raised broader uncertainties, thereby linking challenges in public health to escalating individual and social fears, and to collapsing economies. And this global pandemic is mild compared to the dramatic environmental changes that may well be unfolding under conditions of global warming. That crisis, Scott Hamilton writes, may pose “an unprecedented existential and temporal uncertainty concerning the future of human subjectivity, and of the Earth itself.”Footnote 26

The first typical reaction to our encounters with uncertainty is bafflement at the unexpected, and subsequently a labored process of normalizing the abnormal, followed by amnesia. Metaphors help. Echoing George Kennan’s insistence that we are gardeners, not mechanics, former Secretary of State George Shultz once remarked that “diplomacy is like gardening. The layout of the garden is set. It just has to be tended.”Footnote 27 But times have changed. For many students of politics, today’s world looks and feels like a jungle. Robert Kagan, a prominent neoconservative public intellectual, captures this mood in the title of his book, The Jungle Grows Back.Footnote 28 He explains that liberalism “took root, spread and evolved” in an order that “was always artificial and tenuous, challenged from within and without” by the natural forces of an anarchic geopolitics. “Like a garden, it can last only so long as it is tended and protected. Today, the US seems bent on relinquishing its duties in pushing back the jungle.”Footnote 29 Susan Rice, who served as National Security Advisor under President Obama, concurs when she speaks of “Trump’s Hobbesian jungle.”Footnote 30 And an unflappable, rational former physicist, Germany’s Chancellor Merkel, watches as the liberal multilateral world she helped sustain is “shoved aside by the law of the jungle.”Footnote 31 Like Germany, Canada too must learn how to navigate a “jungle-like world.”Footnote 32 Today, the jungle has become a common metaphor for the many disruptions and weirdnesses of the unpredictable.Footnote 33 Jungle and garden metaphors are stand-ins for worldviews that often remain unspoken while helping us navigate the turbulent currents of world affairs.

We should be wary, though, of loading the dice only on the side of looming threats. Jungles and forests are not only places of dread but also sites of hope. Uncertainty can reveal vulnerabilities that lead to creative responses and empowerment of the disempowered. Such bigger issues could be environmental or social. Viewed in a broader context, Jared Diamond argues, a “successful resolution of the pandemic crisis may motivate us to deal with … bigger issues that we have until now balked at confronting.”Footnote 34 Aided by the shocking vulnerabilities of African Americans revealed once again by the pandemic, the explosion of the Black Lives Matter movement in America in the summer of 2020 created a powerful multiracial coalition that vented its fury at police violence as one among many instances of systemic racism. This was the latest installment of a rights revolution that has spread globally during the last half-century, in fits and starts to be sure, and often in unpredictable directions.

Although they provide important anchors at many moments of uncertainty, the lack of attention to worldviews in the analysis of world politics is striking. Measured by Google Books Ngram Viewer, in sharp contrast to the concepts of “theory” and “model,” Figure 1.1 shows that the concept of “worldview” is barely used.Footnote 35 Two decades ago, Peter Haas popularized the concept of epistemic communities, writing in the most cited article of International Organization, the highest-ranked journal of world politics in the United States, that epistemic communities refer to networks of knowledge-based individuals “who share the same worldview.”Footnote 36 While many scholars have followed his lead in developing the concept of epistemic community, none, to my knowledge, has followed up to inquire into the concept of worldview. While we might be vaguely aware of uncertainty’s role in global politics, we seem to prefer not to look this challenge in the face by examining our worldviews.

Figure 1.1 Ngrams: worldview, theory, model

In conceiving and contributing to this book, I have ventured for a third time off the conventional garden path of international relations scholarship. As was true of all other scholars of world politics, the end of the Cold War caught me by surprise. I wanted to understand why and turned to cultural sociology for new insights. The Culture of National Security,Footnote 37 mainstream realists and liberals thought in the mid-1990s, was no more than a futile exercise in postmodern flim-flam that had nothing to do with respectable social science. It turned out, however, that cultural sociology was central to the constructivist theories of international relations that quickly secured for themselves seats at the high table of theory. Seeking to understand the Great Recession of 2008–09 two decades later, I tracked the broader political implications of uncertainty and developed a conceptualization of power that was less materialist and less focused on Hobbesian notions of control. Film and cultural studies provided me with valuable insights into the dynamics of unpredictable possibilities and potentialities of what Lucia Seybert and I called Protean Power.Footnote 38 The evident difficulty that book’s argument created for many of my colleagues, as it forced them to come to terms with uncertainty and potentiality, has led me in this book to turn to the natural sciences, which for more than a century have been no strangers to these two concepts. Uncertainty and Its Discontents seeks to show the deep Newtonian roots of the firm convictions of what a scientific study of world politics entails, and our never-ending amazement when the unexpected derails those scientific endeavors. I will argue that “the relational revolution” in twentieth-century physics, and many of the natural sciences more generally, can enrich sociological relationalism in the social sciences.Footnote 39 It embeds risk-based, Newtonian thinking about a “world of being” in an uncertainty-inflected, Post-Newtonian thinking about a “relational world of becoming.” Thus, it explicitly acknowledges uncertainty and the open-ended potentialities of world politics.

This chapter seeks to better understand the scientific worldviews that make us overlook uncertainty as a central aspect of world politics. It examines the concept of worldview (Section 1.1); considers for the field of world politics the substantive and analytical formulations of worldviews in the form of political and analytical paradigms, as well as substantialist and relational ontologies and epistemologies that are embedded in them (Section 1.2); differentiates between Newtonianism and Post-Newtonianism (quantum mechanics) and humanism and hyper-humanism (scientific cosmology) as two dimensions structuring different worldviews (Sections 1.3 and 1.4); exemplifies the resulting four worldviews as presented in greater detail in Chapters 25 (Section 1.5); and concludes briefly with two illustrations (Section 1.6).

This chapter’s presentation of four strikingly different worldviews is balanced in Chapter 10 by a discussion of some workarounds and commonalities that provide a shared intellectual space for Newtonianism and Post-Newtonianism. Newtonianism prefers sharp distinctions. Philosophically, Post-Newtonianism does not. Chapter 10 thus adheres to Samuel Beckett’s admiration of “greyness.”Footnote 40 Moving from clearly demarcated “either–or” conceptual spaces in Chapter 1 to entangled “both–and” spaces in Chapter 10 suggests a radical reconceptualization of conventional understandings of science operating at both macro- and microlevels. Specific approaches in the field of scientific cosmology and quantum mechanics put the individual human experience rather than objective laws of nature at the center of the universe. This eliminates the traditional insistence on the difference between the natural and social sciences and holds forth the promise for the analysis of uncertainty and risk, rather than the insistence that world politics is marked simply by risk.

1.1 Worldviews

Worldviews offer global overviews evident in relatively constant, repetitive habits of beliefs and emotions that mediate the relations between an individual or group and the world.Footnote 41 They are animated by a sense of being in the world and of viewing how the world works or should work. Worldviews are neither purely descriptive nor purely explanatory. They contain both prescriptive and practical elements. Far from immutable, they are susceptible to fluctuations brought about by personal experience and change in the world. They comprise a flexible conceptual apparatus rooted in values. Relationally mediated by discourses and institutions, worldviews create narratives about what is possible, what is worth doing, and what needs to be done, as well as what is impossible, what is shameful, and what needs to be avoided. They thus have effects on the purposes and interests that shape policies and practices. Many techniques and rules, on their own terms, might be considered inadequate or too weak to justify policy and practice, yet they acquire a deeper legitimacy when embedded in a broader worldview. What Daston writes about natural orders is also apposite for worldviews: they are “long-lived, polyvalent, and evocative of powerful emotions.”Footnote 42 Operating at different levels of abstraction, several authors in this book point to a close relationship between worldviews and other, commonly used concepts. For example, in Chapter 5, Michael Barnett disaggregates holistic worldviews and points to the internal contradictions of their different components; and in Chapter 8 Bentley Allan considers worldviews built from more encompassing cosmologies.

Worldviews are concerned with viewing the world and understanding one’s place in it. They are suffused with epistemologies and ontologies. But in the discipline of international relations, in the words of John Ruggie, “epistemology is often confused with method, and the term ‘ontology’ typically draws either blank stares or bemused smiles.”Footnote 43 Today, almost without fail, social theories “posit an ontological beginning point … that one takes to be the foundations of the (world-) view being explored or posited.”Footnote 44 As epistemologies, worldviews concern the scientific or religious basis for knowing the world. Worldviews can be analytic or substantive. Paradigms, theories, models, and the explanatory constructs they deploy are analytic. Liberalism, Realism, and Marxism are substantive. Worldviews provide elastic interpretive guides to help navigate the world. They differ from both universal, trans-historical cosmologies and more specific, time-bound ideologies. The concept of worldview is contested and, for some, considered inherently contestable.Footnote 45 The chapters in this book provide ample material for both contestation and inherent contestability.

Because they are foundational, worldviews are important for understanding and evaluating human choice. Embodied in both views and practice, they both passively “re-flect” and actively “re-present” the world, offering views both of and for the world.Footnote 46 Because “we believe what we do largely because of the way our beliefs fit into our worldview,”Footnote 47 our diagnoses and solutions are not cheap talk. Worldviews consist of big yet simple ideas that operate at both individual and collective levels. They reflect and shape individual ideas, experiences, memories, and imaginations that always remain open to modifications and reinterpretations.Footnote 48 They are also collective systems of thought that offer some measure of coherence and consistency in an often unfathomable world.Footnote 49 Worldviews can incorporate contradictory and tension-inducing elements. Loosely coupled, they compete, coexist, and coevolve with one another.

The growing schisms dividing “metro” from “retro” have prompted a few observers to apply the concept of worldview to contemporary American politics.Footnote 50 Reflecting on the partisanship of the 1990s and early 2000s, cognitive scientist George Lakoff writes that “contemporary American politics is about worldview.”Footnote 51 Conservatives and Liberals have a very difficult time understanding each other because they rely on different commonsense notions as they interpret what they experience. Conservatives hold to a “Strict Father,” Liberals to a “Nurturing Parent” trope. In a similar vein, and adapting Max Weber to twentieth-century America, Eric Oliver and Thomas Wood try to capture the different intuitions and modes of reasoning that distinguish American’s disenchanted and enchanted worldviews.Footnote 52 Marc Hetherington and Jonathan Weiler, finally, develop a related argument that focuses on two worldviews epitomized by pick-up truck and Prius, John Wayne and Jane Fonda, meatloaf and vegetable biryani, and a preference for a fixed or fluid politics.Footnote 53 During the last half-century, operational political ideologies have increasingly lined up with such underlying worldviews and are now creating a polarized politics that is threatening the very fabric of American democracy. The notion of a unique and singular American worldview captured by the trope of American exceptionalism is mistaken. American worldviews express political inclinations and moral sensibilities that differentiate liberals from conservatives along a number of dimensions. On closer inspection, though, all of these dualities are oversimplified and fail to capture the fractal patterns of political change in America.Footnote 54 Despite such qualifications, it is difficult to deny that worldviews play a substantial role in American politics.

Individually experienced yet irreducibly social, worldviews circulate through society.Footnote 55 They have emotional and rational components that are seamlessly fused.Footnote 56 As modern neuroscience tells us, one does not exist without the other.Footnote 57 “Emotions are not irrational pushes and pulls,” Martha Nussbaum writes. “They are ways of viewing the world. They reside at the core of one’s being, the part of it with which one makes sense of the world.”Footnote 58 For Nussbaum, emotions are “appraisals or value judgements which ascribe to things and persons outside the person’s own control great importance for the person’s own flourishing.”Footnote 59 The Latin root of the word emotion means to “move out” from the individual toward others and the world. Although emotions are individual, they also have an inherently social character.Footnote 60 Their collective reality is closely linked to individual identity.Footnote 61 Emotions are an important aspect of how we view the world. This is not to deny that a worldview is also grounded in rational beliefs with little or no emotional content. Newtonian and Post-Newtonian scientific worldviews, for example, differ in their rejection or acceptance of uncertainty as a constitutive aspect of both the natural world and the political world.

Emotional and rational worldviews, Miriam Steiner has argued, can appear in a modified form that acknowledges the fuzzy boundary between optimization and intuition.Footnote 62 A modified rationalist worldview incorporates the notion of bounded rationality operating under constraints that encourages satisficing rather than optimizing behavior.Footnote 63 A modified nonrationalist worldview highlights the importance of intuition and subjective awareness. Some rationalist elements are always present in predominantly nonrationalist views, and vice versa. A comprehensive worldview integrates elements of both, featuring complex configurations of rationality and non-rationality.Footnote 64 Feelings of being in the world and being anchored in a particular worldview thus can challenge or reinforce our core beliefs. Such complementarities or contradictions can reinforce worldviews, alter them, or make them crumble.

The concept of worldview operates at a higher level than several related concepts that scholars of world politics have deployed in their analyses of world politics.Footnote 65 Foreign policy ideologies, belief systems, strategic cultures, operational codes, causal beliefs, cognitive maps, narratives, and policy and political paradigms are all related to, though distinct from, overarching worldviews. For example, worldviews are less coherent than Mark Haas’s foreign policy ideologies.Footnote 66 They are conceptually less clear than Ole Holsti’s belief systems, Alastair Iain Johnson’s strategic cultures, and Nathan Leites’s operational codes.Footnote 67 They are broader than the causal beliefs that interest Jeffrey Legro and the cognitive maps Robert Axelrod has deployed, and less determinative than the narratives that concern Ron Krebs.Footnote 68 They are less cognitive, less influenced by academic and bureaucratic experts, and socially and culturally more deeply embedded than are policy paradigms.Footnote 69 And they are overtly less political than political paradigms.Footnote 70

Worldviews can act as both stabilizing anchors and emergent processes. They can be both explicit and implicit. The very idea of a choice of worldview is itself the product of a specific worldview. In fact, some strands of neuroscience suggest the possibility that reason and consciousness set in only after – rather than before – the act of choosing has occurred.Footnote 71 Worldviews shape the views of both scholars and of the various actors they study. Worldviews connect the interpretation of the self in the analysis of the other and the world. In this chapter, for example, I am particularly interested in the scientific worldviews of scholars and the effect they have on the neglect or recognition of the constitutive importance of uncertainty in world politics. By contrast, in Chapter 2 Mark Haas and Henry Nau examine the worldviews of political leaders and the effects these worldviews have on political norms and practices. In Chapter 7, Prasenjit Duara covers the worldviews of both scholars and leaders.

These general characteristics of worldviews find more specific expression in the difference between the Newtonian and Post-Newtonian scientific worldviews that concern me here.Footnote 72 In the analysis of world politics and the social sciences, Newtonianism has been hegemonic. In contrast, quantum mechanics, with its insistence on the centrality of uncertainty at the subatomic level, has occupied a marginal position in the social sciences – including the study of world politics.Footnote 73 Furthermore, the relational revolution in scientific cosmology and several other branches of the natural sciences puts the concept of uncertainty into a much broader context. Both quantum mechanics and scientific cosmology are instances of a Post-Newtonian scientific worldview with far-reaching ramifications for our understanding of society and history. Yet, students of world politics have shown little interest in exploring and learning from Post-Newtonianism.

Newtonian uncertainty is cast in agentic terms and is believed to be manageable through the exercise of control power and risk management. In Post-Newtonianism it is considered systemic and can include protean power effects that thrive in the domain of the unexpected.Footnote 74 In the analysis of world politics, scholars with a Newtonian worldview typically downplay or overlook the distributed agency that is highlighted by Post-Newtonianism. Newtonianism offers a commitment to intervening in the world by accountable agents who seek to achieve some purpose or value. Post-Newtonianism is less focused on individual accountability. It points instead to the inherent contradiction within a Newtonian worldview, with its firm belief in laws or causal mechanisms that deny or limit freedom and agency while at the same time insisting on the primacy of agency and accountability. Although Newtonianism reigns supreme in the analysis of world politics and some of the other social sciences, it has been sidelined in physics and the natural sciences. Debates in quantum mechanics, for example, do not seek to attack or defend Newtonianism in general; they focus instead on which elements of a closed Newtonian system can be usefully incorporated in a broader view of a universe that is open.

The determinism and certainty of Newton’s macro world, softened by the laws of probability, has been replaced by the indeterminism and uncertainty of the micro world of quantum physics. According to Feynman, Mermin, and Baeyer, Newtonian and quantum physics are examples of scientific worldviews.Footnote 75 Taken together, these two scientific worldviews illuminate a politics marked by risk and uncertainty. In the Newtonian worldview, “the future after a fashion repeats the past.”Footnote 76 Novelty in Newtonianism is conceived of as recombinatorial, in contrast to the possibility of radical creativity and innovation in Post-Newtonianism. In the conventional understanding of world politics, the world is viewed as closed and inhabited by actors who feel threatened by uncontrollable uncertainty. Envisaging a world that is open and actors who are enabled by new possibilities seems implausible and uncomfortable.

Only a handful of scholars of world politics have explicitly introduced the concept of worldview into their analysis. For Patrick James, building on Rosenau, worldviews provide complex, holistic foundations for scientific research. They are not analytically consistent.Footnote 77 They subsume paradigms, theories, models, and hypotheses that seek to understand and explain patterned or specific events. Worldviews are inescapably normative and shape the understanding and explanation of reality. They are often self-confirming and sometimes self-invalidating. Divergent worldviews do not get resolved by appeals to logic and evidence but through individual experiences and social processes.Footnote 78 In contrast to James, worldviews for Jürg Gabriel are extremely simple and highlight a few concepts that for centuries have remained largely unchanged.Footnote 79 He identifies optimists among scholars who believe in a general accumulation of knowledge, and pessimists who are frustrated by the fact that, beyond a handful of small islands, accumulation is smothered by a proliferation of often incommensurable approaches. In contrast to the cumulative process of knowledge creation in the natural sciences, knowledge creation in international relations is repetitive. Time and again, students of world politics deal with foundational issues and concepts in light of new circumstances and information.

The stabilization of an uncertain world through worldviews is a political act.Footnote 80 Worldviews offer basic ideas that shape the questions we ask or fail to ask, provide us with explanatory and interpretive concepts, and suggest hunches or plausible answers.Footnote 81 They are a handle that organizes many of the world’s unknown or poorly understood facts. For Max Weber, a world image (Weltbild) or worldview consists of concepts and judgments that can provide the groundwork for a thoughtful ordering of the world and a narrative shaping of “salient areas of daily, human practice.”Footnote 82 But, contra Weber, worldviews operate in all societies and in all historical times.Footnote 83 They are imaginaries that are built around basic and often unarticulated assumptions such as “time, space, language and embodiment.”Footnote 84 Worldviews contain arguments about the ontological building blocks of the world, the epistemic requirements of acceptable knowledge claims, and the origin and destiny of humanity. They find expression in institutional and symbolic orders. They are legitimated by being part of the natural order of things, privilege some actors, such as priests or scientists, and embody shared values that are considered “natural.” Within a given worldview there can always exist a variety of different and often competing ways of understanding. Christianity’s religious wars are one example. Scientific schisms between Aristotelian and modern science and within modern science, between classical physics and quantum mechanics, are another. Lacking tight internal integration, worldviews infuse meaning into world politics. Inchoate as they often are, worldviews are central to our readiness to accept uncertainty as a constitutive aspect of world politics.

1.2 Paradigms, Substantialism, and Relationalism

In their discussions of worldviews, students of world politics have tended to collapse this concept’s multifarious analytical and political components into the more mundane “paradigm.” Footnote 85 Specifically, since the 1970s they have debated both Thomas Kuhn’s work on analytical paradigms and substantive political paradigms such as liberalism, realism, and Marxism. Commitments to Newtonian substantialism and Post-Newtonian relationalism, and the attendant (in)ability to conceptualize uncertainty as a constitutive part of world politics, are embedded in discussions about both types of paradigm.

Paradigms. Historian of science Thomas Kuhn used the concept of paradigm to characterize and distinguish the foundational assumptions of different scientific approaches.Footnote 86 Scientific progress was not a story of continuous and cumulative progress. It consisted instead of periods of normal science interrupted by brief periods of revolutionary science. Normal science is marked by the ascendance of a single paradigm that determines the central research questions, theoretical vocabulary, and acceptable methods and criteria for assessing how well a given question has been answered. When fully institutionalized, weak links of dominant paradigms are no longer recognized, foundational assumptions are no longer questioned, and anomalies are consistently overlooked or considered as lying outside of acceptable research programs. Revolutionary science occurs in brief spurts when scientists are frustrated by increasing numbers of anomalies, interested in new research questions, and committed to developing new approaches that might resolve troubling anomalies. Once the insurgents have acquired sufficient clout, conditions are ripe for the emergence of a new paradigm. Controversially, for Kuhn, paradigms are incommensurable with one another, so it is impossible to integrate or compare theories developed within different paradigms.

Kuhn’s argument about “paradigm shift” and “paradigm incommensurability” is analytical.Footnote 87 It tells us nothing about the world itself. His argument is about the perception of reality and not about the real world. In a Gestalt-flip paradigm shift, we do not necessarily lose the ability to see the rabbit or the duck, but we may not be able to see them at the same time. The argument about incommensurability that captured the imagination of the humanities and some of the social sciences resonates with shifts in the “soft” parts of paradigms. It fails, however, to capture their “hard” parts that deal with predictive accuracy, explanatory depth, and power. The incommensurability account mischaracterizes the process of inquiry in the modern natural sciences, specifically in the maturing of paradigms and their theoretical developments over time.Footnote 88 Difficulties of understanding across paradigms are not the same as the impossibility of understanding. The question of “what is,” after all, is not the same as “what is known” or “what can be made meaningful.”Footnote 89 Such difficulties do not imply that all statements about truth are contingent.Footnote 90 As a matter of fact, Kuhn’s later writings reflect a modified view on incommensurability, toward a more circumscribed claim about meaning variance across paradigms and the limits of our ability to translate adequately from one paradigm to another.Footnote 91 In any case, as Gunnell observes, “philosophy is no more the basis of science than social science is the basis of society.”Footnote 92 For those who believe that there is a reality outside of and apart from the observer, it makes little sense to ask a natural or social scientist whether they have nature or society right.

Kuhn sometimes likened revolutionary, paradigm-shifting scientific progress to the process of Darwinian evolution: nondirectional improvement with no specific purpose. By contrast, change during normal times, within a well-understood paradigm, is directional.Footnote 93 There are multiple truths in all scientific endeavors and, on the record of the last several centuries, natural scientists have ruled out many things previously thought to be true. There is thus justified hope of movement in the direction of greater truth.Footnote 94 That hope is weaker in the social sciences – which Kuhn saw as lingering in a preparadigmatic stateFootnote 95 – including the analysis of global politics, especially as long as it is captured by a worldview that fails to recognize the constitutive effects of uncertainty.

Since the middle of the twentieth century, students of world politics have debated their worldviews, first by employing the terminology of images and subsequently of substantive political paradigms. Carried by the unspoken assumption that we live in a world of probabilistic laws and risk, uncertainty has not been a subject in any of those debates. In the 1950s, the debate focused on the “image” of international relations.Footnote 96 For Wright, a synthesis of different mental images defined each scholar’s perspective on international relations.Footnote 97 The world thus generates a uniform picture that lines up with the worldview accepted by individuals or groups. McClosky, Boulding, and Waltz all assumed that a stable, external world is reflected in multiple, shifting, subjective representations that scholars imagine to be images of unified, coherent wholes.Footnote 98 The image of world politics thus was embedded deeply in a Newtonian worldview. As Robert Dahl wrote in a foundational article on power in 1957, power and risk may be complicated, but “they don’t defy the laws of nature as we understand them.”Footnote 99 The role of uncertainty in the world was not a matter of concern within a Newtonian worldview or paradigm.

In the late 1960s, Graham Allison shifted away from anchoring international relations scholarship in images.Footnote 100 He developed three conceptual lenses or paradigms to capture how individuals, organizations, and governments behave. Allison was not interested in developing a comprehensive view of the world as much as picking up different pieces of the world that warrant explanation. As was true of the 1950s, his perspective betrayed a Newtonian worldview. His conceptual lenses perceived a real, known, and knowable world that remained an external and stable reference point.

This was true also for the prolonged discussion of realist, liberal, and Marxist paradigms by scholars of international relations in the 1980s and 1990s, which paralleled the discussion of rationalism, institutionalism, structuralism, and culturalism in the field of comparative and American politics.Footnote 101 Paradigmatic “isms” became the foundational worldviews or approaches for understanding world politics. Disagreements among analytical or substantive paradigms occurred on the firm ground of a single, real, stable world that was subject to law-like generalizations or mechanism-based analyses. The uncertainties of that world did not figure in the discussions. Furthermore, substantive political paradigms offered communities of purpose and value and focused on the problem of alternative consequences of action. With no single paradigm prevailing, each one asserted its own particular view as sacrosanct.Footnote 102 Indeed, each paradigm sought to “convey a world view more basic than theory”Footnote 103 and, following Kuhn (indeed, often directly inspired by him), viewed itself as incommensurable with all other paradigms. Hence, engagement with proponents of competing paradigms was viewed as a futile exercise. These paradigmatic worldviews were not dynamically competing but frozen in Newtonian time and space; and so too were the risk-based, theoretical worlds they generated.Footnote 104

Substantialism and Relationalism. Analytical and political paradigmsFootnote 105 deal with epistemological problems of the relation between the observing mind and the observed world. They can also embody substantive ontological claims about the world and objects in it.Footnote 106 Their more or less explicit epistemological and ontological claims take the form of substantialism or relationalism.

In Newtonianism, substantial entities such as individual objects or persons exist with their internal characteristics prior to interacting with other entities. Social entities are aggregates of individuals.Footnote 107 In short, substantialism takes pregiven entities as the starting point and imbues them with properties and agency. Strong versions assume that individual choices are driven by objective or intersubjective features of the world.Footnote 108 Substantialism thus includes actor-centered approaches that rely on the logic of appropriateness.Footnote 109 Norms, culture, and identity are structural features that shape individual and state action. Both rational choice and norm-based approaches view individual human action as the elementary unit of social life. For rational choice approaches, preexisting actors typically “generate self-action” that is consistent with preexisting interests and attributes. Similarly, many norm-based approaches view individuals as “self-propelling … entities” that follow internalized norms that are fixed for the timespan under investigation.Footnote 110 Substantialism expresses the Newtonian worldview in which classical conceptions of atoms as the smallest entities constitute the physical world, just as independent social entities are the building blocks of the social and political world.

Two key concepts in relationalism are processes and yoking.Footnote 111 Rescher defines processes as “coordinated group[s] of changes in the complexion of reality, an organized family of occurrences that are systematically linked to one another either causally or functionally.”Footnote 112 He emphasizes processes as prior (and irreducible) to substances, arguing that this allows for an approach that prioritizes change. Unowned processes, such as nuclear proliferation and the growth of economic interdependence, cannot be viewed as the product of any particular agent’s actions.Footnote 113 Rescher ties a process-oriented view of the world to quantum physics, which suggests that “at the microlevel, what was usually deemed a physical thing, a stably perduring object, is itself no more than a statistical pattern – a stability wave in a surging sea of process.”Footnote 114 He regards the shift away from the atom to particle physics in the understanding of the physical world as analogous to the shift from substantialism to relationalism.

Focusing on boundaries rather than entities, Abbott shares Rescher’s interest in relations.Footnote 115 According to his analysis, social entities come into existence when actors tie social boundaries together in specific ways. He defines boundaries as “difference[s] of character,” which are gradually sorted into two sides to form stable properties through social interactions.Footnote 116 The idea of yoking refers to the connection of such boundaries by social actors in a way that defines entities inhabiting one or the other side of the social boundary. Abbott offers the example of the concept of social work, which did not exist prior to the late nineteenth century. It was created by the yoking together of different boundaries related to gender, training, and prior professional attachments. Abbott’s description of relationalism thus stresses intersubjectivity and social context in a way that Rescher’s process-oriented philosophy does not.

Extending this perspective, Laura Zanotti follows Karen Barad’s lead by taking “quantum ontologies” as the starting point for her analysis of a strong version of relationalism.Footnote 117 The fundamental ontological indeterminacy in the natural world “can only be contingently resolved in the intra-action between the observer, and the observed, the human, and the non-human.” In giving relations rather than substances primary ontological status, this is similar to the approaches discussed earlier. But it goes beyond them in positing a specific relationship between human and nonhuman aspects of the world. Zanotti relies on the concept of “apparatus” – ways of engaging with the world – to refer to the means by which boundaries and properties of objects are determined and ontological closure is achieved. Agency should not be considered a property that individuals possess. It operates, rather, through the apparatuses we use “to bring about differentiated forms of materialization of matter and the social.”Footnote 118 Agency is not a free-floating means for humans to enact their will on the world. It is instead caught up in complex entanglements of the human and nonhuman.Footnote 119 This version of relationalism incorporates uncertainty even more fully into its analysis than versions that focus on processes or boundaries.

In the field of political economy, the Open Economy Politics (OEP) approach exemplifies some of the advantages and disadvantages of substantialism and relationalism. OEP is readily intelligible and generates useful baselines for what to expect in the world. But it lacks “sensitivity to the social fabric of international politics.”Footnote 120 That shortcoming was readily apparent after the financial meltdown of 2008–9. After the dust had settled, OEP had precious little to offer by way of analysis or interpretation to help in our understanding of the greatest uncertainty-induced calamity in the international political economy since the 1930s.Footnote 121 Similarly, international relations scholars often characterize international interdependence in substantialist terms. They describe international interdependence with a focus on the strategic interaction among purposive actors. According to Milner, under conditions of interdependence, states’ “actions and attainments of their goals are conditioned by others’ behavior and their expectations and perceptions of this.”Footnote 122 This conceptualization emphasizes preexisting entities with interactions that affect their ability to achieve various objectives. An alternative, relational account of interdependence might “focus on the ways in which trade and other networks are constitutive of boundary conditions of the state and other projects,” as Jackson and Nexon argue.Footnote 123 These examples highlight the differences between a substantialist approach that takes entities as the starting point for analysis and a relational approach that looks at how one set of relations gives rise to others. Indebted to Newtonianism, substantialist approaches tend to focus on the concept of risk and neglect uncertainty’s central place in world politics.

In short, substantialism expresses a Newtonian worldview. A wide range of outcomes in closed systems can be explained with reference to a few abstract, universal principles.Footnote 124 Autonomy refers to the notion that “actors are analytically distinguishable from the practices and relations that constitute them.”Footnote 125 Rational choice approaches seek to abstract from specific contexts. Models are generally transposable. This produces “timeless, context-free, and abstract knowledge,”Footnote 126 as opposed to a relational, practice-oriented Post-Newtonian worldview. It emphasizes an indeterminacy that can be resolved in contextually specific processes of materialization. Mayntz and Scharpf’s actor-centered relationalism combines actor autonomy with contextual factors.Footnote 127 It does not give explanatory primacy “to specific features of the immediate spatial-temporal environment in which actors operate.”Footnote 128 Instead, it assumes that social relations embed actors and constrain their autonomy. The relations in which actors are embedded generate key actor attributes, capacities, and characteristics. Contextualism can be either “thin” or “thick.” Thin contextualism allows for some level of generalization about actor relations and positions; actors and context are analytically separable. In contrast, “thick contextualism” focuses on immediate lifeworlds and the local experiences of actors; actors do not have a clear analytical status independent of their contexts and analysis is more resistant to generalization.Footnote 129

Yaqing Qin’s eclectic view of world politics draws on both substantialist and relationalist elements.Footnote 130 It is partly substantialist and Newtonian, as it highlights the importance of cultural background knowledge of civilizational communities. Culture for him is an indelible birthmark, a crystallized background knowledge of worldviews and all theoretical systems. Qin argues that practice theorists such as Adler and Pouliot limit their notion of communities of practice with shared background knowledge too severely to those that form around specific groups (such as activists, diplomats, and epistemic communities) operating in bounded issue areas (such as national security, the environment, or the economy).Footnote 131 He defines culture as “the way of life of a people who share a lot in terms of behaviors, values, beliefs, and perspectives without consciously knowing them … [A] cultural community is a group of people bound by background knowledge.”Footnote 132 According to Qin, the differences between, for instance, Western and Chinese cultures mean that scholars based in these cultures develop different social theories of how the world works.Footnote 133 Like Huntington, this formulation flirts with a reification of culture as a unified object neglecting contestation and conflict within and encounters and engagements between cultures and civilizational complexes.Footnote 134

Qin is also a Newtonian humanist. While Mustafa Emirbayer, like Jackson and Nexon, views relations as a “general term … [that] may involve human and non-human factors,” Qin’s approach specifically concerns relations between humans in a Newtonian manner;Footnote 135 the Confucian and Daoist philosophies Qin draws on understand relations between humans to be the foundation of social theory and ethics. Importantly, “state actors” are treated as humans and, apparently, as unitary actors. And so are civilizational complexes, as illustrated by Qin’s discussion of the relations between China and the Soviet Union.Footnote 136

The focus on human relations entails a focus on human agency. Qin critiques the concept of yoking as a “temporo-spatial chance with few human elements involved. In other words, nothing would happen if the necessary processes were not related, perhaps by chance.”Footnote 137 By contrast, his focus on human relations puts human agency at the center of relationalism. This is reflected in his discussion of Jackson and Nexon’s view of “relations before states,” by which they mean that relations are ontologically prior to states.Footnote 138 Qin does not believe that relations should be seen as prior to actors. Instead, relations and actors are constitutive of one another: actors are defined by their relations, and relations are always between actors. In this way, actors and relations are coconstitutive “processual simultaneities.”Footnote 139 The agency implicit in these relations between human actors is in turn important for harmony and balance, key concepts in Qin’s approach. He argues that “human agency provides the sufficient condition for harmony … When both the self and the other have learned through education and self-cultivation how to behave appropriately, their behavior is neither too aggressive nor too humble. … As a result, the relationship between the self and the other is harmonious and society is harmonious, too.”Footnote 140 Culture, harmony, balance, and human agency are indelibly linked in the production of social orders.

In his treatment of dialectics, in contrast, Qin leans toward processualism and articulates a relational Post-Newtonian worldview. He argues that Western notions of dialectics, typically relied on by both substantialist and relational approaches, are fundamentally different from the idea of “zhongyong dialectics” in Confucian and Daoist thought.Footnote 141 While Western notions of dialectics – drawn mainly from Hegel – emphasize difference, conflict, and irreconcilability, zhongyong dialectics are based on harmony and “immanent” relationships between polarities.Footnote 142 In Qin’s understanding of a dialectical relationship, each pole is inclusive of its opposite; they are both “always engaged with each other in the process of becoming the other.”Footnote 143 In contrast to Abbott, entities are not yoked – that is, socially constructed through the tying together of proto-boundaries – as much as each side of a boundary already includes the other.Footnote 144 The social world is thus marked by harmony or balance between different poles. Qin’s eclecticism works along the substantialist–relationalist continuum. His reliance on both Newtonian and Post-Newtonian worldviews remains implicit, and the potential for incorporating both risk and uncertainty into his analysis remains unexplored. In Qin’s approach, worldviews inform analytical perspectives more or less directly. Conversely, and less strongly, analytical perspectives can occasionally have a small impact on worldviews. Both are coevolving, competing, or complementary ways of understanding or engaging with the world. Since Newtonian concepts are baked into our conventional language, Qin’s anthropocentrism takes for granted absolute dimensions of time and space as a background into which political actors are placed and analysis is conducted at a distance. In contrast, Post-Newtonianism acknowledges no background, and time and space are active processes of becoming that shape politics and political analysis.

Students of world politics have relied on paradigms as the core construct to debate both analytical and substantive views of the world. With rare exceptions, the substantialism and relationalism that inform their approaches never question a deeply ingrained Newtonian worldview.Footnote 145 Typically, that worldview encompasses a substantialist ontology, a probabilistic epistemology, and a commitment to replicable techniques that can help in error reduction. As John Ruggie observed almost thirty years ago, “As for the dominant positivist posture in our field, it is reposed in deep Newtonian slumber wherein method rules.”Footnote 146 It is this Newtonian slumber that conceals the constitutive part of uncertainty in world politics.

1.3 Newtonianism vs. Post-Newtonianism (Quantum Mechanics)

To grasp more fully the implicit worldview that makes it so difficult for students of world politics to accept uncertainty as a constitutive factor of world politics, this and the next section discuss some salient differences between Newtonianism and Post-Newtonianism (quantum mechanics) on the one hand, and humanism and hyper-humanism (scientific cosmology) on the other. My discussion of quantum mechanics and scientific cosmology is selective. Many of the issues I touch on are considered either peripheral (by most experimental physicists) or contestable (by scientific cosmologists). That is not to say that there are no widespread agreements on the meaning of the stunning and rapidly accumulating experimental and observational findings in both fields, as is true, for example, of the broad support for the Copenhagen interpretation of quantum mechanics. I have tried to capture how both fields are thinking about the natural world, in sharp contrast to Newtonianism and the conventional view shared by most students of world politics, which leaves no space for uncertainty.

Although scientific discoveries often defy common sense, worldviews integrate them into social and political life.Footnote 147 In the analysis of world politics, the best Newtonian scientific knowledge searches for law-like correlational statements and causal mechanisms.Footnote 148 The external world is real. Representational knowledge is located in absolute dimensions of time and space. And knowledge has a status that is independent of the observer. The simple billiard ball model of international relations, conventionally taught to first-year college students, is a good example of a mechanistic application of cause-and-effect reasoning. Following the example of economics, many scholars of world politics look to Newtonian physics as their main source of scientific inspiration.Footnote 149 But after he had listened to a Nobel Prize economics lecture, physicist David Mermin observed pithily that with its integrals and derivatives, economics was just “like physics, except physics works.”Footnote 150

Newtonianism. Newton’s laws of motion articulate a universal set of principles to account for planetary movements: “The prototype for the order of universal natural law is universal gravitation, set forth in all its magisterial generality by Isaac Newton in his Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy.”Footnote 151 Newton assumed that movement occurs in relation to absolute space and time. Imagined as a large empty container or background, each bit of space is exchangeable. God invented matter and created the moving objects that fill this space. Nature is governed by objective principles. Thus, Newton arrived at the view of a clock-like universe: a consistently working machine that reflects a hidden order, captured by the universal laws of motion and accessible to human reason and observation.Footnote 152

A scientific Newtonian worldview began to replace a metaphysical religious one in sixteenth-century Europe. Knowable laws of a predictable Nature replaced the unknowable arbitrariness of an all-knowing God. Science encouraged self-organization and undermined existing hierarchies. In the hands of Kepler, Galileo, Descartes, Newton, Spinoza, and Leibniz, mathematics as the most knowable of the sciences was always also philosophical or even religious. The Newtonian worldview does not deny God as the creator of the world. But it does make God a mathematician and His logical plan becomes available for scientific interrogation. Human perception of the world is skewed; mathematics is not. It can fully understand and predict the linear interactions between the discrete objects of this world. Matter is dead; the human mind is not. And it can control and bend Nature to humanity’s will. Relying on an inherent universalism, linearity, and reductionism, and superseding Aristotle’s syllogistic logic and Descartes’ deductive tendencies, Newton’s inductive scientific methodology led him to the higher scientific truths articulated in his three laws:Footnote 153 “Newton, more than any other man, had banished mystery from the world by discovering a “universal law of nature,” thus demonstrating what others had only asserted: that the universe was rational and intelligible through and through, and capable, therefore, of being subdued to the uses of men.”Footnote 154

Newtonianism has a powerful grip on the social sciences, including important strands in political science and, specifically, international relations.Footnote 155 In the Newtonian worldview, “the world was considered to be deterministic. Blended with the atomized and axiomatic approaches to the study of science, reason had in many senses become rationalism. Society was there to be solved.”Footnote 156 It made “the world feel less anarchic and more predictable,” and “strengthened the commonsense belief in a world designed by a higher intelligence and a superior force” – for some God, for others the Laws of Nature.Footnote 157 The assumed order of the world held forth the promise of control. The sciences do not eliminate from our lives the irrational, mystical, and religious. Far from it. But, as illustrated by conventional scientific practices, the notion of control continues to have a powerful grip on students of world politics and the social sciences more generally, at times as a metaphor “with a quasi-poetic function.”Footnote 158 Since the eighteenth century, atomistic natural philosophy and, specifically, Newton’s image of the universe, has left an indelible mark on political thought.Footnote 159

As the reigning scientific worldview, Newtonianism thus informs the conventional understandings of world politics. For example, the mechanical foundations of Newtonianism have had a strong effect on the progressive imagination of the American Founding Fathers and modern theorists of a recurrent balance of power.Footnote 160 Liberalism and realism share the Newtonian view of the political universe as self-sustaining and self-regulating objects or actors. In both, the flux of events is viewed as subject to fixed laws or statistical regularities. Entities are knowable and can be governed by humans. And humans are set apart in nature by the power of their reason.Footnote 161

In search of intellectual simplicity, the analysis of world politics typically homogenizes reality by conflating a large number of diverse political phenomena and entities under a small number of concepts. It also adopts strong assumptions about how world politics works, using statistical analysis or experiments to support its search for simple causal relations. This approach to understanding the world hews closely to Newton’s own words: scientific truth is to be found, “in the simplicity, and not in the multiplicity and confusion of things.”Footnote 162 When we explain world politics by making simple distinctions – East and West, land and water, then and now – we follow Newton’s advice.

As a matter of fact, Newton encountered multiplicity and confusion in human affairs, and painfully so. In the spring of 1720 he sold his shares of the South Sea Company, pocketing a 100 percent profit of £7,000. The price of the shares continued to rise. Not wishing to lose out on this speculative frenzy, Newton bought shares back at three times the price of his original investment. The bubble burst a few months later and decimated Newton’s savings as he reportedly lost the equivalent of $3 million in today’s money. He subsequently lamented that “I can calculate the motion of heavenly bodies but not the madness of people.”Footnote 163 This “multiplicity and confusion of things” is central to a Post-Newtonian worldview.

Although students of world politics share Newton’s befuddlement about the unexpected, they hold fast to his orderly worldview. The typical response to the often shocking predictive and explanatory failures of their preferred constructs has been to reexamine their theories and models with the hope that, eventually, the Newtonian strategy of simplification will lead to the discovery of valid laws and causal mechanisms that generate compelling explanations and accurate predictions.Footnote 164 This, however, is not how it turned out in physics. Most physicists agree that quantum mechanics has superseded Newtonian physics and simply get on with their work.Footnote 165 Modern physics and cosmology have discarded Newton’s notion of absolute space and time. Although the classical model remains a convenient computational tool for many practical problems, it conveys a misleading view of nature as orderly and accessible to neutral observation, when the reality is rather disorderly and often barely accessible. Furthermore, despite its practical usefulness, the classical model is inadequate for understanding the subatomic world and thus fails to account for the many practical applications of particle physics. It does not offer a general explanatory framework.Footnote 166 To be sure, some physicists held tight to their belief in a Newtonian world. Slowly but surely, however, most acknowledged the failings in their worldview and moved on. This process became less difficult after a plausible alternative presented itself.

Post-Newtonianism. In the late nineteenth century, experimental physics began to probe the subatomic structure of matter. Electrons, quarks, photons, gluons, neutrinos, and a few “Higgs bosons” are the elementary particles studied by quantum mechanics.Footnote 167 It describes these particles and their movement. They are not real, like little pebbles; “They are the elementary excitations of a moving substratum … miniscule moving wavelets.”Footnote 168 Einstein’s special relativity theory of time and space, and relativistic quantum field theory more generally, opened up an invisible world of energy governed by randomness. Nineteenth-century philosophical relationalism inspired the first, philosophically informed generation of quantum physicists to think relationally about many of the new phenomena they discovered with ingenious experiments. Only subsequently did a materialist and quantized version of relationalism claim to be foundational because it was “real.” Although the weirdness of the quantum world has defied all attempts at explanation, the new theory became a marvel of predictive accuracy. It has generated technological innovations and applications that continue to revolutionize the social and political world despite the scant attention paid by students of world politics.Footnote 169

Early on, though, some prominent political scientists recognized the importance of new developments in physics. William Bennett Munro, President of the American Political Science Association, delivered his address on the topic of “physics and politics” in 1927, regretting that the study of government was “still in bondage to the eighteenth-century deification of the abstract, individual man.”Footnote 170 In Scientific Man vs. Power Politics, which he described toward the end of his career as his favorite among his voluminous writings, Hans Morgenthau explicitly recognized the significance of changes in physics for the analysis of world politics.Footnote 171 This work was published in 1946, a few decades after the quantum revolution, and Newtonian physics for Morgenthau already was “a ghost from which life has long since departed.”Footnote 172 Since the classical model had been disproven and rejected by physicists, it no longer could serve as an adequate guide for the social sciences and students of world politics. It needed to be replaced by the complex worldview of quantum mechanics. Morgenthau argued that the scientific studies of world politics would have to settle for a disquieting mixture of the knowable and the unknowable.Footnote 173 Quantum physics had introduced indeterminacy and thus radically transformed the calculable, determinist universe of the classical model.Footnote 174 Complete knowledge of either past or future had become a chimera, as scholars came to acknowledge that their current approach to understanding world affairs would never yield reliable predictions of individual events: “The next quantum jump of an atom is as uncertain as your life and mine.”Footnote 175 Out-of-equilibrium nature does not know its own future, and neither do we. And while probabilistic predictions and scientific laws can provide insights into the modal tendencies of statistical aggregates, they are like quantum physics in that they cannot provide any insight into individual units of observation. Morgenthau thus called for a thorough revision of simplified social science modeling.Footnote 176 He pleaded that the unification of the natural and the social sciences should be triggered by their shared ignorance when confronting the unknowable and the insuperable. We can thank Morgenthau for positing that, when we take quantum mechanics rather than the classical model as our guide, “the structure of the natural world finds its exact counterpart in the social world.”Footnote 177 Seventy-five years later, students of world politics are still trying to catch up.

Many baffling aspects occur in the subatomic world. Quantum physics cannot be visualized. It is not determinist. Quantum effects depend on the size of an object multiplied by its typical momentum; for electrons moving in an atom, quantum uncertainties predominate.Footnote 178 The world is not a causal machine but a creative generator of realized and unfolding propensities and potentialities.Footnote 179 The inventors of quantum theory also discovered the observer-created reality that flies in the face of notions of objectivity.Footnote 180 Quantum mechanics directs our attention to apparatuses of measurement and argumentation, and the performances and practices they entail.Footnote 181 They bring to light relational aspects of difference; the boundary-producing effects of measurement and argumentation; and the entanglements between objects and subjects, matter and meaning, and the natural and social worlds.Footnote 182

Life does not evolve in space and time conceived, respectively, as a collection of preexisting points in an empty container that matter inhabits and as a succession of evenly spaced intervals available as a referent for all bodies. Instead, following Einstein, life is an iterative evolution of four-dimensional spacetime.Footnote 183 Space is not empty. Far from being vacant, a vacuum teems with possibilities.Footnote 184 The fields that make up the world are subject to tiny fluctuations. Basic particles have ephemeral existences that are continually created and destroyed:Footnote 185 “The world is a continuous, restless swarming of things, a continuous coming to light and disappearance of ephemeral entities … A world of happenings, not of things.”Footnote 186 Indeterminacy provides the condition for an open future. Possibilities are not static. They are always reconfigured and reconfiguring.Footnote 187 New possibilities open up as others close down. Although the world’s presentation of an infinitude of relational possibilities cannot be controlled, it can be captured by conventional experiments and the imposition of isolated, efficient cause-and-effect chains. In this view, uncontrollable surprises are normal in a world of changing possibilities. Subatomic particles are wrapped up in infinities of possibilities that have changed our image of the atom and our practices of imagining.Footnote 188 Quantum mechanics puts uncertainty, indeterminacy, potentiality, and possibility, rather than constraint and necessity, at its center. It offers an alternative to Newtonianism that students of international relations are largely unaware of as they think about the nature of world politics and its many uncertainties.

A century of astoundingly successful experimental work has yielded no agreement about the meaning of quantum theory.Footnote 189 However, it has generated powerful experimental results establishing, for example, particle entanglement without any observable mechanisms, creating what Einstein called “spooky action at a distance.” Different approaches and interpretations illustrate that crucial aspects of the meaning of quantum physics remain unresolved.Footnote 190 But most physicists would agree with Rovelli that the key insight of quantum physics is “the relational aspect of things.”Footnote 191 Smolin goes so far as calling “the 20th-century revolution in physics the relational revolution … in full swing in the rest of science.”Footnote 192 Although it is not free of internal contradictions, what has come to be known as Niels Bohr’s Copenhagen interpretation remains the most widely accepted. This is not to deny the existence of important critics of Copenhagen, including Albert Einstein, David Bohm, Hugh Everett, and John Bell.Footnote 193 Disagreement centers on the nature of measurement.Footnote 194

“Quantum Realists” believe that the history of the world is a history of endless splits, which occur every time a macroscopic body is tied to a choice of quantum states. This view stipulates the existence of an inconceivably large number of uncorrelated multiverses. For David Mermin, this is “the reduction ad absurdum of reifying the quantum state.”Footnote 195 Its plausibility, furthermore, is impaired by the requirement that conditions in our universe have to be just right.Footnote 196 Realists are waiting for a post-quantum revolution that, perhaps, would make quantum mechanics a special case of a more general theory, such as “objective collapse models” or some other theory not yet invented. Such a revolution could thus repeat a new cycle in which quantum physics would be subsumed, just as it subsumed Newtonian physics in the early twentieth century. Physics Nobel Prize winner Steven Weinberg characterized that quest as interesting but also “to some extent whistling in the dark.”Footnote 197 And while physicists work, scholars of international relations wait and remain beholden to Newtonianism and the denial of uncertainty as a constitutive part of world politics.

“Quantum Instrumentalists” believe that measurements of the world taken by humans themselves affect that world at a most fundamental level. The world is therefore not governed by impersonal physical laws that control human behavior together with everything else. Discussed further in Chapter 10, Quantum Bayesianism (or QBism), for example, offers a radically subjective interpretation of quantum mechanics that provides a coherent, unconventional answer to the mysterious meaning of the subatomic world.Footnote 198 The probability that one or another quantum state will emerge is not regulated by firm Newtonian laws that are irrevocable and universal. Instead, individual human actors assign these probabilities on the basis of their private beliefs. Based on past experience, updating that experience with new information, and adhering to the rules of Bayesian statistics, individuals calculate what might happen next. This process does not involve any physical laws or mechanisms operating on the wave function conceived of as a mathematical abstraction, rather than as an objective entity existing out there in the real world. It involves only individual experience, belief, and updating. Individual experience is intrinsically private and cannot be accessed by others. This does not mean that the world exists only in an individual’s head. QBism is not solipsistic. Instead, each individual holds to the subjective belief, with the highest degree of confidence (p=1.0), that others experience the world as oneself does, and all rely on verbal or nonverbal communication to create the intersubjectivity and entanglement which, in turn, create a social world out of individual experience and belief. We are not free to make up our own individual world. QBism provides instead for a world that exists external to each actor without reifying that world as an extant, external entity.

QBism differs diametrically from Wendt’s pathbreaking book on quantum consciousness.Footnote 199 Wendt’s research program is foundational. He seeks to create a consistent, coherent, and complete system of knowledge, grounding human consciousness in the materiality of the world. His work is in line with the view of 2020 Nobel Prize–winning physicist Roger Penrose. QBism is pragmatic. It takes experience (or Wendt’s consciousness) as given before making its argumentative move. QBism works in the tradition of Dewey’s pragmatism.Footnote 200 Knowledge is not a set of securely anchored systematic propositions. “The claims to knowledge we can defend by our impressive scientific successes,” writes Nancy Cartwright, “do not argue for a unified world of universal order, but rather for a dappled world of mottled objects.”Footnote 201 Knowledge is a set of successive attempts to cope with problematic situations that are more or less successful in historically variable, polymorphic contexts.Footnote 202 Like all of physics, QBism is a product of human thought and culture. For QBism there is no “reality” out there; it is all in our heads and the world is created through individual experience, beliefs, information updating, apparatuses of measurement and argumentation, and the creation of intersubjectivity through communication. For QBism, human experience (or Wendt’s consciousness) is foundational and creates the quantum world; for Wendt, quantum physics is the foundation on which he grounds his far-ranging search for consciousness (or QBism’s experience). For QBism, the move is from individual experience (or consciousness) to the world; for Wendt, the move is from the world to individual consciousness (or experience). For QBism, worldviews are epistemologically grounded; for Wendt, individuals are ontologically walking wave functions. These research programs and argumentative moves are opposite but not necessarily antithetical. Chewing on different ends of the same stick, it is not a far-fetched hope that somewhere, sometime, someone will succeed in making them meet.

1.4 Humanism (Dilthey and Weber) vs. Hyper-Humanism (Scientific Cosmology)

The concept of worldview is tied indelibly to the names of two iconic humanists: Wilhelm Dilthey and Max Weber. Both were committed to empirical investigations of intellectual and social history, including the analysis of worldviews. Both tried to find regularities in human affairs, eschewing metaphysical certainties. Dilthey’s basis of historical processes is a feeling for and an attitude toward life as expressed in religious, artistic, and philosophical worldviews.Footnote 203 Max Weber focuses on the tensions introduced by modern capitalism into the civilizational legacies of the past, specifically the relationship between ideas and the structure of social action. Different in their intellectual focus and temperament as well as methods, both grappled with the issue of historical relativism: Dilthey retrospectively, by highlighting human self-analyses in history as acts of creativity; Weber prospectively, by inquiring into social necessities in history that increasingly came to circumscribe human existence.Footnote 204 For both, the analysis of worldviews is a part of their encompassing historical inquiries.

Hyper-humanism offers a different vision of the world. Hyper-humanism refers here to a worldview that goes “beyond” humanism.Footnote 205 It describes “the ‘more-than-human’ character of human existence.”Footnote 206 Conceptualizing the cosmos as an evolving set of processes and relations is quite common in, for example, biology, chemistry, and geology.Footnote 207 At the macro level, hyper-humanism can be found in scientific cosmology. It suggests our scientific theories and models are not representations of the universe but integral parts of its evolution.

Humanism. For Dilthey, worldviews touch on foundational questions about the meaning of life in the face of death.Footnote 208 He thus shifts the problem of history and philosophy from the universalism of concepts such as the world-in-itself (Welt an sich) to inherently partial and plural notions of worldviews (Welt-ansicht).Footnote 209 Emerging from the totality of life, worldviews serve as the foundation of religion, art, and philosophy.Footnote 210 Each of these three domains makes different demands on mental faculties. Religions mobilize will, art feeling, and philosophy thought. In the history of humankind, religion preceded the other two. Like prophets, poets and philosophers seek answers to the basic riddles of existence: its purpose and meaning, its transitory nature, and its beginning and end. Reality and its artifacts are texts that invite interpretation. For Dilthey, human existence is lived interpretation of these texts. He might well have agreed with Lucretius, for whom “our appetite for life is voracious, our thirst for life insatiable.”Footnote 211 For Dilthey, life is the basic root of all worldviews.

In a nutshell, Dilthey distinguishes between three phases of history that are expressed in the worldviews of the monotheistic Abrahamic religions, all of which envision salvation through communion with a living God. These contrast with the philosophies of Greece and Rome, which articulated universally valid patterns of thought and developed rules, laws, and obligations for the imperium and its people. This was turned on its head in the modern era of science, starting with the European Renaissance. For Dilthey, the modern European worldview contains elements of all three.Footnote 212 Dilthey also distinguishes between three philosophical worldviews: pluralistic naturalism (Democritus, Hobbes, Hume, and positivism), dualistic idealism of freedom (Plato, Descartes and Kant, with antecedents in Christian and Muslim doctrines), and monistic holism or, in Dilthey’s terminology, objective idealism (Spinoza, Leibniz, Hegel, and Chinese and Indian antecedents).Footnote 213

Worldviews are not purely rational constructions that explain the world scientifically. They try instead to understand the world synthetically, thus giving life a broader meaning.Footnote 214 Incorporating ideals and purposes, they offer insights into what is and postulates of what ought to be. Yet Dilthey develops a science of worldviews that operates at a higher level of abstraction than do worldviews themselves. It analyzes patterns of prescientific meaning that are reflected in major systems of thought. The science of worldviews is not seeking to specify causal laws, but offers instead descriptions of relationships.Footnote 215 In specifying types of worldviews, it generates conceptual knowledge and circumscribed generalizations. The science of worldviews seeks to overcome atomistic empiricism and monocausal explanations. It sidesteps both causal inference and transcendental values. For Dilthey, the science of worldviews is always heuristic and provisional: worldviews have an inner dialectic and are open to immanent critiques and thus remain always subject to change. Dilthey’s science of worldviews does not rest on a stable and timeless point of observation outside of history. Instead, worldviews allow for shifting perspectives and evaluations that affect them from both inside and outside. The limits and changeability of all worldviews take some sharp edges off the unavoidable conflicts between them.Footnote 216

For Dilthey, life and human experience in all of its richness is part of the ongoing reconfiguration of a world that is always becoming and always full of unexplored potentialities. Dilthey accords to the individual a central role in the world and in the (cultural) sciences. Individuals are both the starting point and the final goal of his investigations. Since he did not present an explicit theory concerning the nature of the individual’s formation, Amnon Marom has provided a synthetic interpretation based on a close reading of Dilthey’s voluminous writings. Marom’s synthesis consists of three ideas about universality, particularity, and potentiality that Dilthey developed at great length. First, human beings can understand only what already exists in their own personal experience. This content is not affected by historical or cultural differences. It is a faculty, or inner universal content, that, with the requisite effort, makes it possible for every human being to understand all humans and human creations from all cultures and eras. Second, all humans share a cross-cultural and ahistorical immanent human nature. Third, this commonality resides in nature and is built on human potentialities. Each of these ideas is of course debatable, but their synthesis, Marom argues, offers a “theory of subjectivity as a unique realization of universal possibilities … This actual fulfillment of different possibilities is what gives each individual their uniqueness.”Footnote 217 Dilthey was interested in discovering ways to transcend human limits and enable limitless human understanding. He tracked and theorized “limitless shared understanding” in the domains of religion, the arts and philosophy. QBism does the same for quantum physics and the sciences.

Dilthey’s core insight – an understanding of the world grounded in the interpretation of meaning – had a profound influence on Max Weber’s general approach to sociology as an interpretive science, and, specifically, on his cross-cultural and cross-civilization sociology of religion.Footnote 218 Since they are scattered throughout his writings, Weber’s ideas on the subject of worldviews are difficult to track. The comprehensive and highly regarded Max Weber dictionary, for example, does not contain a single entry under this subject heading.Footnote 219 My brief account relies on Stephen Kalberg’s authoritative summary guide and interpretation.Footnote 220 Generally for Weber, worldviews of an ethical universe are somewhat autonomous from other social and political realms of belief and practice. Specifically, they differ greatly from random and strategic, means–ends calculated action: “Orientation to this ethical universe involves an uprooting of action from its common random, pragmatic, and utilitarian flux and flow, and its guidance by a constellation of values.”Footnote 221

For Weber, worldviews offer answers to some of the most profound human questions about the meaning, purpose, and conduct of life. The main carriers of worldviews are charismatic, ethical, or exemplary prophets.Footnote 222 They make available to their followers “a unified view of the world derived from a consciously integrated meaningful attitude toward life.”Footnote 223 Prophets give social and cosmic events a systematic and coherent meaning that should govern man’s conduct if he aspires to salvation. Their work is a matter of practical evaluation, not logical consistency. It is a conscious effort to bring order into life’s variegated manifestations and to help organize man’s practices in ordinary life. The discrepancy between this coherent, religiously infused view of the world and empirical reality is the source of the strongest tensions between inner life and external relationships. Prophecy, priestly guidance, and secular philosophy are all concerned with alleviating such tensions.Footnote 224

Linking religion and secularism was Weber’s central contribution. In his seminal Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism, Weber develops a distinctive monocausal approach.Footnote 225 The economic ethic or spirit of capitalism was for Weber of central importance and required a cultural analysis, specifically of sixteenth and seventeenth century ascetic Protestant sects and churches, mainly Calvinist. The Protestant ethic furthered rationalization, especially in economic life but also in all other spheres, and set a standard that all other religions, including Catholicism, failed to meet. The economic practices of Protestant believers were ultimately shaped by answers they gave to the question of salvation rather than by utilitarian considerations. The faithful, Weber argues, came to believe that their capacity for methodical and profitable work and their success in accumulating wealth in this world served as evidence of their salvation. Faith convinced them, therefore, that the conditions of salvation were shaped by their personal conduct. Work acquired religious meaning. Methodical work became sanctified as a religious calling. Looking for signs of redemption sent by God, Protestants saw one such sign in economic success. Weber shows how believers arrived at their conclusions as they created a religious world and subjectively meaningful lives. Asceticism in this world gave the capitalist economy and the West a vital push to greater dynamism and efficiency. Eventually, the religious ethic of small groups of believers transformed into its secular successor: the spirit of capitalism.Footnote 226 The religious and magical basis of legitimacy of different religious traditions thus gave way, eventually, to different kinds of rationalisms. Although Weber’s analysis of Hinduism, Confucianism, and the three Abrahamic religions acknowledges that each experienced its own distinctive rationalization process, he does not extend that argument to civilizations that believe in magic rather than mastering worldly affairs through calculation. In Weber’s analysis, Western civilization remains unique and superior to many others.Footnote 227 Yet, the eventual disenchantment of life could not be stopped as science and technology eroded deeply held religious convictions and values, first in the West and eventually everywhere. As religious beliefs were increasingly replaced by beliefs in science and technology, durable worldviews were replaced by the thin veneer of custom and interest as the main motivation for individual and group interests and practices.

It is worth noting that Weber does not consider the implications of different scientific worldviews in the era of disenchantment he bore witness to.Footnote 228 This is ironic since Weber was writing at the dawn of the revolution in quantum physics. He could not know that the twentieth century would give physics a “Chinese face,” generating wonderfully precise predictions and practical applications without providing any convergent understanding of the meaning of quantum mechanics. In the social sciences and in international relations, Newtonian physics retains a strong grip on scholars whose research relies on the everyday technological products of the quantum revolution. Failing to consider the very possibility that modern physics offers a different worldview than the Newtonian one they take for granted is no small matter. It discourages the pursuit of non-Newtonian knowledge of and insights into the social and global world, including on matters of uncertainty.

Dilthey and Weber agree: worldviews express values. But they deployed that construct differently. In contrast to positivists who believe that social inquiry can be value-free, for Dilthey and Weber all inquiry is individually generated, historically shaped, and inescapably relative. On the issue of what constitutes truth, these two positions appear to be irreconcilable. When truth becomes a shared convention, “agreement makes truth, rather than truth inviting agreement.”Footnote 229 Since time scales matter, this contradiction is not inevitable: “Just as truth ultimately serves to create consensus, so in the short run does acceptability.”Footnote 230 Max Weber opted for an eclectic combination of both positions. He emphasizes how values shaped the selection of all objects of inquiry. He also argues for the possibility, though not necessity, of a value-free social science, emphasizing that worldviews are important for empirical theories, models, and hypotheses for three reasons: they shape the questions science pose by articulating the presuppositions that legitimize, define, and make such questions salient; they offer key concepts that become the building blocks for varieties of theoretical constructs and practices; and they provide the context in which information acquires political significance.

Hyper-humanism. Hyper-humanism includes the natural world in its animate and inanimate life forms. The human is a messy medley and the nonhuman is more than background.Footnote 231 This concept does not reject humanism altogether. Far from it.Footnote 232 But it rejects those elements of humanism that regard the human species as somehow exceptional or unique and distinct from the rest of nature.Footnote 233 Haraway, for example, argues that the universe consists of collectively produced systems rather than self-regulating ones.Footnote 234 Such systems lack self-defined spatial and temporal boundaries and rely on information and control provided by distributed components linked symbiotically in multiple, complex forms of relationships. Humans, as we are being taught once again in 2020, are not self-contained but are an inseparable part of others existing within (bacteria and viruses) and around (plants, animals and other humans) them.

All humans exist inside of this world, not outside of it, looking in. Kohn, among others, advocates an anthropology that stretches “beyond the human” and explores representational forms that go beyond conventional linguistic or symbolic forms.Footnote 235 Humans share with other living organisms semiotic modalities that pervade what he calls “the open whole.”Footnote 236 Similarly, a German forester and global bestselling author, Peter Wohlleben, describes forests as systems of complex interdependence among trees that share a resilient, communal life.Footnote 237 For him the forest is a site for the comfort offered by slow evolutionary change. No apocalyptic news disturbs Wohlleben’s forest. Below, soft-floor fungal bodies feed trees and extend themselves in skeins that bind roots, nurture organisms, and offer a collaborative, meshed net.Footnote 238 Feeling and thinking forests live relationally. In short, humans are not existing in special social settings apart from the natural world. They are porous and relationally connected, rather than self-contained and singular.

Broadly speaking, scientific cosmology shares this worldview.Footnote 239 It studies unfolding processes and relations in the cosmos, including the ideas, beliefs, and theories about the cosmos.Footnote 240 Contrary to the Newtonian worldview of the world as a closed system, scientific cosmology views the world as an open system and continuously interrogates many of its basic assumptions. Cosmology is “a human intellectual creation, not merely a collection of facts … [that] can be done differently by different peoples in different places at different times.”Footnote 241 It can change rapidly as it seeks to incorporate new data and speculations as they become available. To the question “how do we think without Newtonianism?” In Chapter 3 Kurki gives the laconic and understated answer “with some difficulty.” In scientific cosmology, the cosmos pushes back against the always imperfect and incomplete ideas and beliefs humans hold about it.

In the temporally understood postmodernity that Nau invokes in Chapter 6, the natural sciences are profoundly empirical and experimental. Yet modern natural sciences often do not line up with this characterization by students of politics. What postpositivists always suspected is now embraced as a cornerstone of “a new, emerging scientific worldview” built around the concept of emergence.Footnote 242 However, all too often, even now, laws or mechanisms express a mechanical view of the natural and political universe. International relations scholarship has not yet wrested itself from the Newtonian worldview. What is truly remarkable is how out-of-step with much of current scientific beliefs and practices this view is. This shift “makes the mechanical, ‘scientific’ construction of the social world in international relations appear like a superstitious oddity handed down from ancient times.”Footnote 243

Building on data that astronomers had collected through the ages, in the 1920s scientific cosmology started exploring various experimental and mathematical ways of solving Einstein’s field equations. This endeavor evolved subsequently into probing matter, energy, and the cosmos at large.Footnote 244 Mathematical, experimental, empirical, and non-testable inquiries have continued to define the history of scientific cosmology and its contemporary debates.Footnote 245 Vortex theory and cosmophysics then, string theory and multiverse models now are some of the examples of historical dead-ends and contemporary disagreements. New knowledge has rapidly accumulated as new technologies have permitted the generation of new data that support, for example, the theory of the existence of many flat galaxies in an expanding universe rather than the now-discarded belief in the existence of a one-layered galaxy existing in a steady-state universe. Cosmic Background Radiation points to the beginning of the universe as an explosion yielding many observable features, such as matter and energy linked in spacetime, dark matter, and dark energy. Scientific cosmology is forever open to new information and data that pushes back on existing theories and models. It is constituted by a set of processes and relationships that encompass all thinking observers. Scientific cosmology does not view science (in the singular) as an abstract enterprise gazing at its subject matter from a distance. In its practice, scientific cosmology embraces instead the sciences (in the plural) as an engaged human enterprise deeply entangled with their various subject matters.

The evolution of scientific cosmology over the last 400 years has yielded the Standard Model, often referred to as the Big Bang Model.Footnote 246 It incorporates both particle physics and cosmology, and is today accepted as the standard story informing theories in all of the natural sciences. It accepts the notion of the big bang, a moment of infinitely dense matter and energy about 13.6 billion years ago, followed by an expanding universe marked by smoothness and homogeneity in the distribution of matter and energy, with life emerging about 10 billion years later. Stars and galaxies evolved from the universe’s physical and chemical elements rather than from God’s will, as Newton believed. Elementary particles of matter waves with sixteen discernible properties make up atoms and electrons, and create the atomic level and everything beyond it that exists in the universe. Alternative theories – among them multiverse models, string theory, evolutionary and cyclic models, and variable law models – seek to address puzzles that the standard model cannot explain in its original form.

The greatest of these is how to theoretically and mathematically integrate relativity theories of gravity with the quantum world.Footnote 247 At the beginning of the universe, its moment of singularity, the very big and the very small, cosmology and quantum, were one. At the macro level of relativity theory, spacetime is viewed as curved and smooth; at the micro level of quantized spacetime, that smoothness disappears as discrete quanta jump over a flat spacetime governed by global symmetries:

The two towering achievements of 20th century physics are the general theory of relativity for the large-scale structure of gravity in the universe that replaced Newtonianism and quantum mechanics for the microscopic subatomic world. Both theories remain partial and contradict one another. In one world space is curved and everything is continuous. In the other, space is flat and made discontinuous by leaping quanta.Footnote 248

The hope is that, eventually, general relativity and quantum mechanics can be brought together and thus provide “the basis for cosmology, the study of the entire universe.”Footnote 249 That overarching theory runs under the label of “quantum gravity.” There, “time and space have disappeared altogether, and the world is dissolved into a swarming cloud of probability that the equations can, however, still describe.”Footnote 250 Like Escher’s famous picture Ascending and Descending, it is right now “an impossible construction which looks sensible in its local details but does not fit together into a coherent whole when using presently existing building materials.”Footnote 251 In the absence of such a unifying theory, acceptance of our imperfect knowledge and partial pattern recognition remain the most viable strategies for our understanding of the natural world.Footnote 252

Lee Smolin’s relational cosmology and loop quantum gravity theories attempt to meet at least some of these intellectual challenges.Footnote 253 It does not purport to offer scientific truth but a philosophically and conceptually productive perspective that supports a rethinking of science, knowledge, meaning, and humanity’s position in the evolving universe.Footnote 254 Relational cosmology is a wholistic critique of a Newtonianism that seeks to break all systems apart so as to fit its experimental methodology. The Newtonian approach is fundamentally ill-suited to approach questions of cosmology. Contra Newton, space is not a flat background condition with coordinates filled by thing-like objects, such as particles or planets, that move according to the logic of universal laws of motion and that are subject to human codification or control. Even though relativity and quantum theories have shown background-independent theorizing to be wrong, Smolin suspects that many scientists still hope to gain access to eternally valid laws of the universe; they have lost confidence in Newton’s laws but not in the idea of laws. Mathematics is a powerful tool in the endeavor to find the universal and the eternal. But the problem with mathematics is that it looks at things in the universe from the outside, as if things were moving against a neutral background. Relational cosmology and loop quantum gravity break with this implicit Newtonianism.Footnote 255 To be sure, while astronomers have developed many theories in recent decades, the cosmos itself existed for billions of years before the discipline of astronomy was “invented” or “evoked.”Footnote 256 Smolin argue that a single, open, and causally highly complex cosmos comprises the universe, but that nothing exists beyond it.Footnote 257 The universe is what it has evolved into being – specifically, networks of relationships in time. The relationships that have evolved in the universe cannot be explained by scientific laws any more than they can be explained by religious entities.Footnote 258 We are all in and of the universe – and not in or of anything else.

“That said, the Newtonian assumption about ‘background’ is deeply implanted into our conceptual vocabulary and continues to exercise a profound effect on social practices and social sciences.”Footnote 259 Scientific cosmology insists on the “simple fact that all possible observers are inside the system they study.”Footnote 260 And, in real time, that system is teeming with mini matters that are forever opening up and closing down new possibilities and thus constitute the universe as a history of its relationships.Footnote 261 Newton was brilliantly successful for many practical purposes. In contrast to quantum mechanics and relational cosmology, he told a coherent story about the world we experience with the five senses Newton was aware of. Newton’s lesson is that, for all intents and purposes, the universe is background and the world is a machine that is governed by simple laws – except, of course, when the uncertainties that inhere in that world trip up the predictions that are based on theories and models grounded in a Newtonian worldview.Footnote 262

By theorizing space and time without smuggling in Newtonian assumptions, loop quantum gravity complements the insights of relational cosmology at the micro level. Space is an integral part of the universe’s evolving relationships, rather than neutral background, and it is bumpy rather than smooth. Points in space have no existence in themselves but only as particular features of networks of relationships.Footnote 263 Made of mathematically described or imagined quanta, space consists of looped spin-networks. These networks are not things and do not exist in space. They are relationships that give rise to space. Time, in this view, is a measure of change in the evolution of the universe’s relationships. Everything changes in this relational universe, including change – that is, time. It is not only phenomena that change but also the observed regularities, the supposed laws and constants of nature.Footnote 264 In short, at both the micro and the macro levels and in both space and time, the evolution of the universe is relational. And since all we have of the universe is incomplete descriptions by various observers of various states of the universe, what we are left with is not a multiplicity of different worlds but multiple interpretations of the singular universe with nothing existing outside of it.Footnote 265 And that singular universe is constituted in part by an uncertainty that Newtonianism has great difficulty accepting as a central aspect of world politics.

1.5 Four Worldviews

Different configurations of Newtonian and Post-Newtonian as well as humanist and hyper-humanist worldviews implicate denial or acceptance of uncertainty as a constitutive factor of world politics. The two dimensions that map the analytical space for four worldviews in Figure 1.2 express different epistemological and ontological commitments that can be independent from one another – but might not be. All too often, people use various interpretations of common sense to distinguish between the physicality of the real world and the social constitution of the human world, separating clearly the two dimensions of Newtonianism and Post-Newtonianism and humanism and hyper-humanism. Most such interpretations presuppose an actor-independent reality in which the observer can be placed at a distance from the world. In short, common sense reflects an implicit Newtonian worldview. But, as Rovelli argues, most modern sciences acknowledge that the physical world is not what it appears to be.Footnote 266 If physics is a product of human thought and culture, as QBism and scientific cosmology hold, then this commonsensical view is mistaken, and the two dimensions in Figure 1.2 are not orthogonal. Instead, they capture the epistemological commitments of four different worldviews. The ontological aspect of worldviews is concerned with “being” rather than “viewing,” for example, with experiencing the overlapping, meaning-making domains of science and religion discussed at the end of Chapter 10.

Figure 1.2 Worldviews and analytical perspectives

Presented here as a heuristic device, Figure 1.2 summarizes schematically the four worldviews that typically inform the analysis of world politics: a “humanist substantialism” that focuses on discrete individuals, groups, states, and objects, and a “hyper-humanist relationalism” that emphasizes entangling processes. Humanist substantialism foregrounds individuals or things operating in a world of risk, hyper-humanist relationalism entangling processes unfolding under conditions of uncertainty. Figure 1.2 also yields two other worldviews: humanist relationalism and hyper-humanist substantialism. Each of the next four chapters exemplifies one of these four worldviews. The denial of uncertainty as a constitutive feature of the world is strongest in the most widely shared worldview: humanist substantialism.

Some worldviews put at their center substantial “entities”: individuals, groups, states, or “things.”Footnote 267 For example, the conventional idea of individual decision-making is based on the assumption that conscious, intentional desires and beliefs will lead to action in a world marked by risk.Footnote 268 Its substantialism is humanist and adheres to a Newtonian worldview that accommodates the assumptions of both “universal rationality” and “contextual reasonableness.” A strong form of substantialism can focus on “actor identity,” as in the analysis of ideology and foreign policy traditions that Mark Haas and Henry Nau offer in Chapter 2. An attenuated form might highlight “embedded agency,” as in Jairus Grove’s analysis of presidential war-making powers in Chapter 4. Other worldviews put “processes” at the center of their relationalism.Footnote 269 For example, indebted to scientific cosmology, Kurki’s hyper-humanism in Chapter 3 engages the world through “practices of knowing and doing” that sidestep issues of individual agency and the responsibilities that go with engaging the world.Footnote 270 This worldview contradicts the belief in the existence of objective, natural laws or causal mechanisms that are unaffected by scientific measurement apparatuses and practices. In this uncertainty-laden view, analysis focuses on causal forces “coming together in specific (and contingent) ways.”Footnote 271 Relationalism also takes different forms – “thicker” in its philosophical and quantum form and “thinner” in its sociological variant. Grove and Barnett illustrate that difference in Chapters 4 and 5.

Although Figure 1.2 presents dichotomies, it would be a mistake to conclude prematurely that the four types exist each one in a specific place in each quadrant and all in separate silos. Chapters 25 illustrate that worldviews are often fluid and can blend into one another. The complementarities between “either–or” and “both–and” logics are explored further in Chapters 69. Chapter 10 deepens that analysis. It relies on the metaphors of garden and forest to explore important differences between the practices of experiments and experimentation, and it deploys the metaphor of the park to inquire into the overlays of Newtonianism and Post-Newtonianism.

Humanist Substantialism: Haas and Nau (Chapter 2). Using ideologies and foreign policy traditions as their empirical material in an analysis of political worldviews, Mark Haas and Henry Nau build an argument for the centrality of “substantive and individualist ideas,” “human agency,” and individual responsibility and accountability: “Actors are free to imagine new or escape old group relationships. Above all, individuals are always responsible for the effect their ideologies have on the freedom of choice of other human beings.” Haas and Nau grant in passing that individuals and groups are never completely independent;Footnote 272 however, they strongly oppose a deep relationalism that reifies the whole, where the entanglement of a holistic world eliminates separate individual identities.

Their chapter examines two types of political worldviews: political ideologies coded along liberal and authoritarian party lines, and four universal foreign policy traditions arrayed along the substantialist–relationalist dimension: nationalism is close to the substantialist end and social constructivism to the relationalist end, with realism and institutionalism holding the two intermediary positions. The empirical discussion of domestic ideologies and foreign policy traditions focuses on the degree of overlap or divergence. Overlap points to peace or cooperation, divergence to conflict or war. Haas and Nau conclude that

our Weberian agency-oriented approach has important advantages that are eviscerated in more relationalist and holistic approaches … In holistic worlds, there is no contestation of political or religious perspectives. There is no good and evil. Nothing can be questioned because boundaries are uncertain and everything is in the process of becoming. There are no certainties, no firm truths. Seen critically, the holistic vision is an appeal to disarm intellectually, to abandon the pivot of individual inquiry and insight, to blur any distinction between points of view, and to lose choice which is the very essence of freedom.Footnote 273

Some of these arguments derive from the rhetorical strategy the chapter adopts. Haas and Nau are “splitters” while the relationalists they criticize are “lumpers.” The variable-based analysis of Haas and Nau is grounded firmly in the substantialist camp, which leaves no room for processes that are “all bundled together” with mutually constituted variables.Footnote 274 Thinking perhaps about Haas and Nau’s concession that complete independence of actors is a chimera, Grove asserts that “we are all relationalists, just some better and more explicit than others.”Footnote 275 In contrast to Kurki, who insists on the existence of many relationalisms, Haas and Nau write about relationalism in the singular.Footnote 276 They argue that Weber’s agency-oriented approach is “eviscerated” by relationalism, downplaying the relational elements of one of the founders of modern sociology. They also insist that relationalism denies the existence of an objective world, is relativist, and prevents the statement of firm truths.Footnote 277 This creates a strong disagreement with Kurki in particular, who draws on different kinds of relationalism and shows an interest in their varied cultural and scientific manifestations. Her discussion focuses prominently on Smolin’s holistic, objective, relational cosmology, which shares many aspects with Kauffman’s “new scientific worldview.”Footnote 278 For what it is worth, in my reading, Smolin’s and Kauffman’s twenty-first-century versions of relationalism are no less scientific than the seventeenth-century Newtonianism that informs Haas and Nau.

Haas and Nau do not shy away from stating the implications of their argument. The natural sciences study things lacking consciousness as it is conventionally understood; the social sciences study human beings and their groups or institutions. Like Dilthey, Haas and Nau thus make a sharp distinction between the human and the natural sciences.Footnote 279 Human science cannot eliminate that distinction – that is, not without the loss of personal freedom.Footnote 280 Kauffman’s “new scientific worldview” erases that difference. Nature is not predictable, law- or mechanism-governed lifeless matter but teeming processes of ever-changing possibilities which we meet with courage and faith moving forward as if we knew an unfathomable future.Footnote 281 Even though uncertainty appears to be perfectly compatible with their version of Weberianism, implicit in the Newtonianism of Haas and Nau is the neglect of uncertainty as a constitutive feature of world politics.

Hyper-Humanist Relationalism: Kurki (Chapter 3). In the form of quantum mechanics and scientific cosmology, hyper-humanism jettisons the distinction between humans and things. Insisting on the unity of all sciences implies that the cosmos extends to all aspects of nature and all forms of life. This can be viewed as undermining a belief in human agency and individual responsibility. But it can also be heard as a call for a radical “ethics of alterity,” an ethics that contests humanism, its privileging of sameness, and its exclusion of difference.Footnote 282

In her chapter, Milja Kurki draws on the insights of scientific cosmology to articulate a relational worldview that is radically at odds with Haas and Nau. She directly challenges core ontological, epistemological, and empiricist conceptions of humanist substantialism, most notably the separation of nature from society, and the urge to control people and things. For Kurki, the relational turn opens up “questions around religion, secularism, and indeed reason and affect in how we engage the world.” Kurki’s chapter does not offer definitive answers to pressing questions. Instead, it is a productive provocation for deliberation and dialogue.

For Kurki, relationalism appears as a singular only when compared to substantialism. Itself, it is cut by various dynamic tensions. “Explanation” becomes “explication”: the characterizing of processes rather than the specification of variables. And it shifts away from “how we do politics.” Kurki positions her argument against the humanist Newtonian worldview shared by most realist, liberal, constructivist, and critical theories. In that view, “humans” are separate from and stand above the “environment,” and the world is made up of distinct “things” operating against a background. Contra Haas and Nau’s Newtonian-grounded analysis, Kurki insists on giving up on a “God’s eye view.” Instead, she defines humanity as situated knowers in a relational universe.Footnote 283 The environment is not a background for Kurki, the climate crisis is not a human coordination problem, and global warming is not external to human communities and experiences and thus an issue to be managed. She points to the existence of polyphonic families of worldviews “with quite different orientations to substances and relations, human and nonhuman, nature and society.” Confronted with enormous ecological challenges, she argues, the conventional analysis of international relations has come to its limits and is failing; the study of world politics must be pushed to consider a radical shift.

In the relational universe there are no things, space is not empty background, history is a set of processes, and the categories and dichotomies with which we conventionally work do not operate. Worldviews are not so much views as fleeting moments of being in a world of becoming, filled with uncertainties. The conceptualization of practices in a thickly relational view of the world deviates from approaches commonly accepted in the analysis of world politics. To Lenin’s question “what is to be done?” Kurki offers no actionable answer. In her broader conception of the world, institutional frameworks, global governance structures, patterns of practice, and intersubjective narratives and discourses fail to capture the richness of life in a relational universe. Practice lies beyond policy and politics as conventionally understood. Instead, “the aim is to ‘loosen’ actors (at the boundaries) to understand co-being, entanglement and co-negotiation across ‘beings’, actors, species” in a universe built around immanent relationships between polarities in what Qin has called zhongyong dialectics that are antithetical to Western liberal and realist understandings of the world.Footnote 284 Kurki is agnostic as to whether this politics will save us, but she insists that it offers alternatives to the simplified political practices that have so miserably failed too many humans and nonhumans alike.Footnote 285 Kurki’s hyper-human relationalism has no difficulty accepting uncertainty as a constitutive aspect of world politics.

Hyper-humanist Substantialism: Grove (Chapter 4). Grove’s relationalism is empiricist and focuses on how people and things actually work, rather than making claims about how they should or would work. His approach is “characterized by inhuman encounters and deep relational processes across geographical scales.”Footnote 286 The human is not the sole focus of thinking and acting. And yet “we can de-center the human without letting go of the very specifically human and often national assemblages.”Footnote 287 In this formulation, human agency is neither autonomous, as in Haas and Nau, nor fully submerged in relational processes, as in Kurki; instead agency is embedded in thick processes. Problems of accessing the world (representation) and meaning-making (hermeneutics) coexist with other relations. Observation and interpretation are part of the relations that make the world, rather than standing apart from or above the world. Investigating emergent processes tells stories about complex and highly distributed formations and agencies rather than about agents and variables which, for Grove, are the effects of processes. Distinctions between dependent and independent variables or agents and structures are arbitrary. The causal relations between them are not bearing any essences but are an effect of the investigation, specifically of the scale at which a question is posed and an answer is sought. Methodological individualism is not a natural unit of analysis. It is instead the result of the feeling we have about the unity of the “I.” But relationalism goes all the way down in social as in natural processes. “We are not constituted by relations,” Grove writes, “we are relations.” In stressing the relationality of different elements within the individual, Grove’s reading of Weber thus differs sharply from Nau’s methodological and substantive Weberian individualism.Footnote 288

Grove applies his relational approach to the case of nuclear warfare. That case shows the world as marked by highly distributed agencies and thick relations. For Grove, violence as a relational process illustrates that no specific ethics is associated with relationalism:

the geopolitical project of planet Earth is a violent pursuit of a form of life at the cost of others – full stop. … [T]he violence of geopolitics is an ecological principle of world making that renders some forms of life principle and other forms of life useful or inconsequential … Geopolitics, enacted through global war, is itself a form of life.Footnote 289

In his rendering of nuclear violence, sovereignty is an assemblage which incorporates the office and person of the President who does not call the plays. He is “more like a mascot than a quarterback.”Footnote 290 Instead, various assemblages and networks are the sites where the play involves many distributed agents.

In his far-ranging account, Grove acknowledges that the reduction to unitary actors or instrumental logics is not necessarily useless. As is true of Newtonian physics, reductions and simplifications can yield insights even when they are inaccurate. For example, the President’s nuclear sovereignty appears in full sight only when methodological individualism primes the observer to look for an already constituted single decider. But a sovereign nuclear decision is not self-constituted or self-causal. It requires a field of relations and resonances. Yet, Grove does not seek simply to replace sovereignty with assemblages and networks. He insists, rather, that there are many scales of complexity and causality that such simplification conceals. His case study points to the limits that the conventional legal-moral and strategic anthropocentrism and anthropomorphism imposes on our view of nuclear politics and on possibilities of intervention in that domain of policy.

Grove’s stance is motivated by strong normative claims. Camping on the hill of liberal internationalism or “in the dark woods of political realism,” the field of international relations is in a weird state of denial of the horrors of the world and potentially apocalyptic change.Footnote 291 For Grove this is more than irrationalism or ignorance. It bears the stamp of a deep and corrosive nihilism stemming from a denial of experience in and of the world.Footnote 292 The moral engagement that Haas and Nau ask for in their critique of Kurki, Grove delivers in spades on conventional international relations scholarship, informed by his hyper-humanist substantialist worldview. Specifically, he calls out “these old white men [who] still strut around the halls of America’s ‘best’ institutions as if they saved us from the Cold War, even as the planet crumbles under the weight of their failed imperial dreams.”Footnote 293

Humanist Relationalism: Barnett (Chapter 5). Within a humanist worldview, Barnett focuses on relational and internal value tensions that can further both the integration and the destabilization of worldviews stretching from the supernatural to the earthly world. Worldviews themselves are constituted by bounded communities and thus are ontologically related to them. As concepts of analysis and practice, nationalism and cosmopolitanism qualify as worldviews for Barnett. Agency is relationally embedded. Politics can lead to change in as well as restabilization of worldviews, specifically how different Jewish communities imagine the relationship between nationalism and cosmopolitanism. In line with his sociological relationalism, the duality of nationalism and cosmopolitanism are intertwined and mutually constituted. Zero-sum and positive-sum views of their relationship are two analytical extremes. Pulls in both directions often occur simultaneously, involving unavoidable political contestations that are shaped by developments in the dominant Christian community; “As the Christians go, so go the Jews.”Footnote 294

Among the concentric circles of compassion that define the obligation of a political community to others, tribal nationalism’s is small, prophetic cosmopolitanism’s large. Tribal nationalism asks “is it good or bad for the Jews?” Prophetic cosmopolitanism insists that identity and duty extend to all of humanity.Footnote 295 Because Jewish people are diasporic and transnational, the reconciling of different identities and interests with different calls of obligations issued in different institutional contexts is an unending and unstable political process. Identification with the Jewish people and Israel pulls toward particularism and an inward-looking nationalism, while values associated with American identity pull Jewish communities there toward universalism and an outward-looking cosmopolitanism.Footnote 296 Survival, boundaries, the weight of external forces, and conditions of possibility are thus important and incessantly debated topics; “As the punchline to several Jewish jokes goes: two Jews, three synagogues.”Footnote 297

In sum, substantialist and relational analytical perspectives are grounded in four competing worldviews. The greatest difference exists between Haas/Nau and Kurki. Haas and Nau commit to a humanist Newtonianism of being and the individual accountability of taking a stance. Kurki’s hyper-humanist relationalism highlights the existence of distributed agencies with no apparent link to individual morality and resonates with the concept of becoming. Grove and Barnett operate in distinct, intermediary analytical spaces. The depth of commitments to these four different perspectives is not readily explicable without excavating the links to the worldviews that ground the analysis. The participants in this project learned this important lesson from each other during their intense discussions and interactions. And it is those worldviews which obliterate more or less compellingly, or acknowledge more or less explicitly, the constitutive role of uncertainty in world politics.

1.6 Conclusion

Why should we deny what is so striking in our everyday life and in all domains of world politics: the constitutive role of uncertainty? Why should we indulge ourselves with an exclusive preoccupation with probabilities in a world that is shaped also by uncertainty? Why should the scientific study of world politics, modelled after the natural sciences, remain stuck exclusively in Newtonian thinking when quantum mechanics and scientific cosmology, among others, began to move on more than a century ago? What, more specifically, might be gained by broadening our scientific worldview beyond conventional Newtonianism? I give here two illustrative answers to these questions: one focusing on the planetary politics of the environment, the other on complementary concepts of control and protean power.

Some Earth scientists argue that we are at the beginning of a new era: the Anthropocene. Humans have become geological agents. Their activities have become a great force that enmeshes natural and social processes.Footnote 298 Human activities are adding new biophysical factors that shape some of the Earth’s major systems. Old-style determinism and the concept of control no longer work as before. Everything now is simultaneously human and natural. Nonhuman “actans” (viruses, microbes, materials, and devices) can fundamentally alter human and natural possibilities;Footnote 299 “Humankind is no longer the anomaly, the freak of nature. We become the key to nature-as-a-whole.”Footnote 300 And in this process, the subjectivity of the individual Cartesian “I” will quite possibly be transformed into the collective planetary “We.” If this is a plausible conjecture, the consequences for world politics will be immense and contradictory. The tension between globalism and nationalism will acquire a new intensity and salience, and may come to encompass not only global and planetary politics, but local and national processes as well.

In the Anthropocene, Gaia is not inert matter that is moved by predictable, physical laws. Past experience of the Earth’s system no longer offers a reliable guide for predicting future developments. No place on Earth can now be considered “natural.” Man-made instead, nature is becoming “artificial.” Entangled with human practices, the universe is undergoing a process of destructive and creative becoming. Nature is not a pristine, unmoved, and balanced landscape that exists apart from man. Human practice is instead endowing nature with its own agency. It often acts with unpredictable effects upon humankind and other living organisms and the cosmos at large, possibly with catastrophic or even existential consequences for humanity.Footnote 301 For the most part, existing international relations scholarship is unaware of hyper-humanism, ignores new unpredictabilities, and fails to engage seriously with the possibility of civilizational collapse in the face of disasters of unimaginable scope and scale. And when a pandemic strikes, as it did in 2020 with the Covid-19 virus, it is once again speechless in its surprise.Footnote 302 Broadening our scientific worldview by moving the environment beyond the status of a discrete policy issue and an inert object of human control might help us think more capaciously and deeply about incorporating more aspects of the profound ecological challenges we confront under conditions of radical uncertainty.

Control over nature is only one manifestation of the tenacious grip that a Newtonian-inflected, Hobbesian notion of control power has over students of politics in general and world politics in particular. In the conventional understanding, power equals control: over nature, territory, people, risk, or political outcomes. Although this understanding is helpful in elucidating important aspects of the world, it is far from complete. The coronavirus crisis of 2020 is a vivid reminder that there also exists a second kind of power. The incalculable offers a context and experience for what Lucia Seybert and I have called protean power: “the effect of actors’ improvised and innovative responses to an incalculable environment or their experience of the world as filled with uncertainties.”Footnote 303 It cannot be harnessed consciously. Instead, not unlike the collapse of the wave function’s creation of one reality out of an infinity of possibilities, protean power effects emerge in specific moments as they circulate across different political domains. They are always an inextricable part of the admixture of uncertainty and risk that characterizes world politics, bypassing all attempts at control. For Emmanuel Adler, all control power is an illusion, an ephemeral phase of a constantly emerging and reconfiguring reality. In this view all forms of power are special, transient, and unstable instances of protean power effects. The indeterminate condition of the natural and social world rather than lack of perfect knowledge shapes politics.Footnote 304 Even without going this far, it is understandable that political analysts and actors are frustrated by the existence of protean power effects. But rather than live in denial, why not acknowledge the existence of such effects and thereby enrich political analysis? After all, Machiavelli theorized fortuna’s whims long before Hobbes reconceived power as Leviathan’s control and laid the foundation for a convention that has blinded us to the obvious: the role of uncertainty in world politics.

The four chapters in Part I of this book map the contours of four worldviews that resist or accept the importance of uncertainty in world politics. The most resistant one – humanist substantialism – is articulated by Mark Haas and Henry Nau in Chapter 2. Their style of analysis is familiar to most students of world politics, whatever their methodological proclivities may be. Three other worldviews round out Part I. In Chapter 3 Milja Kurki’s relational hyper-humanism offers a radical alternative to Haas and Nau. In Chapter 4 Jairus Grove analyzes the nuclear capacities of the United States. His analysis shares in Kurki’s thick relationalism, while leaving some space for the substantialism of Haas and Nau. Finally, Michael Barnett’s analysis of nationalism and cosmopolitanism of Jewish communities in Chapter 5 is both humanist and relational.

The two chapters in Part II offer disparate reflections on the chapters in Part I. In Chapter 6 Henry Nau mounts a strong attack on relational conceptualizations of world politics that are not rooted firmly in humanist substantialism. In sharp contrast, in Chapter 7 Prasenjit Duara develops a relational argument that incorporates a broad notion of individual and distributed agency by humans and nonhumans and looks toward the future through the prism of oceanic counterfinalities and environmental catastrophe.

The two chapters in Part III look at scientific and religious worldviews as different and possibly complementary ways of meaning-making in an uncertain world. Bentley Allan argues in Chapter 8 that scientific worldviews are always temporary and contested efforts at the political stabilization of cosmological elements. With a specific focus on Weber’s theory of science, Allan highlights how processes of disenchantment and rationalization have shaped materialism and object orientations as the foundation of understanding contemporary world politics. In Chapter 9, Timothy Byrnes argues that religion and politics are not separate variables but coconstitutive and relational ways of seeing and being in the world. More attuned to uncertainty than science, dogmatic and nondogmatic religions alike require a life-defining, faith-supported leap into the unknown.

The concluding Chapter 10 builds on the conjunctive “both–and” logic presented in Chapters 79 by tracking different worldviews through the use of garden, forest, and park metaphors. It critically examines the adoption of controlled experiments in the social sciences and the analysis of world politics as the latest manifestation of Newtonian gardens and their insistence on an orderly and predictable world. It contrasts this to forest-like practices of experimentations that point to a world marked by novelty and uncertainty. It explores complementarities and workarounds, relying on the metaphor of parks as zones of contact between garden and jungle, Newtonianism and Post-Newtonianism, and humanism and hyper-humanism. The chapter ends with a discussion of science and religion as meaning-making practices, of experiencing a world marked by both uncertainty and risk.

Footnotes

I thank Matthew Evangelista and Henry Nau for their careful read and invaluable comments on earlier drafts of this chapter; Robert Keohane and Chris Reus-Smit for their strategic advice how to position its argument; and Begüm Adalet, Peter Gourevitch, Patrick Jackson, Jonathan Kirshner, Stephen Krasner and Daniel Nexon for their general reactions.

7 For a rare exception, see Reference Enns and LagodnyEnns and Lagodny 2021, who predicted a Biden victory with 54.5 percent of the popular vote and who accurately predicted 49 of 50 states, missing only Georgia. Their forecast incorporated operational uncertainty by running 70,000 simulations, analysis of which suggested that the probability of a Biden win was 60 percent.

10 Classical realists are a notable exception. See Reference KirshnerKirshner 2022 for a far-ranging, critical discussion of structural realism and bargaining models and their neglect of uncertainty and contingency in world politics. For longer discussions of uncertainty and risk, see Reference Wenger, Jasper and CaveltyWenger, Jasper, and Cavelty 2020; Reference BeckettBeckert and Bronk 2018; Reference Katzenstein, Seybert, Katzenstein and SeybertKatzenstein and Seybert 2018b: 41–50; Reference Katzenstein, Nelson, Kahler and LakeKatzenstein and Nelson 2013a: 234–35, 238–42; Reference Katzenstein and NelsonKatzenstein and Nelson 2013b: 1103–109; Reference Nelson and KatzensteinNelson and Katzenstein 2014: 361–69.

25 Putting aside the question of unknowable unknowns, the most creative and important work on operational uncertainty and risk focuses on combining specific forecasting question clusters about the short term with broad scenarios about the long term, thus giving decision-makers an evolving sense of plausible futures that leaves unanalyzed inescapable, radical uncertainty. Reference Scoblic and TetlockScoblic and Tetlock 2020: 16–18. See also Reference Tetlock and GardnerTetlock and Gardner 2015.

26 Reference HamiltonHamilton 2019: 610 (emphasis in the original).

32 The Economist 2019.

35 The Ngram Viewer is a research tool for “quick-and-dirty heuristic analysis” (Reference Chumtong and KaldeweyChumtong and Kaldewey 2017: 8). It is worth remembering that this tool does not measure what people are talking about but what they are publishing about, only in English, and only in texts that Google has digitalized.

39 The term is coined by Reference SmolinSmolin 2013: xxviii.

40 “Whether all grow black, or all grow bright, or all remain grey, it is grey we need, to begin with, because of what it is, and of what it can do, made of bright and black, able to shed the former, or the latter, and be the latter or the former alone. But perhaps I am the prey, on the subject of grey, in the grey, to delusions.” Reference BeckettBeckett 1958: 17.

41 Reference GollwitzerGollwitzer 1980: 176–77; Reference GeussGeuss 2020: xiii. This section has benefitted enormously from discussions among this book’s authors in a series of Zoom meetings in June 2020.

50 Reference MeyerMeyer 2001: 1–2, 22–23.

55 Intergroup emotions theory has informed a number of clinical experiments (Reference SasleySasley 2011: 458–65). See also Reference WolfWolf 2012a, Reference Wolf, Lindemann and Ringmar2012b.

57 This line of thought is not pursued further here. For one example, see Reference DamasioDamasio 1994.

62 Reference SteinerSteiner 1983: 376–79, 382–83. Steiner’s distinction resonates with the Japanese one between tatemae (formally established rational principles) and honne (authentic feelings and desires that cannot be openly expressed).

63 Simon Reference Simon1956: 129, 136.

64 Reference SteinerSteiner 1983: 392–400, 409–12.

71 Jairus Grove made this point several times in our discussions. See also Reference DamasioDamasio 1994.

72 The distinction between Newtonianism and Post-Newtonianism focuses on the difference between the ontology and epistemology of classical and quantum physics, but also goes beyond it to incorporate other natural sciences, such as scientific cosmology, which have taken a relational turn in the twentieth century. Even though it went well beyond Newton, nineteenth-century energy physics was classical. I am concerned here with scientific worldviews rather than the science of worldviews Dilthey tried to develop, as I discuss in Section 1.4.

73 Reference WendtWendt (2015) is the notable exception.

75 Reference MerminMermin 1990: 175, 195; Reference BaeyerBaeyer 2016: 185, 192, 195. I justify my radical simplifications of an exceedingly complex analytical terrain because doing so highlights the central distinction I wish to make between two scientific worldviews (Reference BaeyerBaeyer 2016: 140). This discussion abstracts therefore from different interpretations of quantum mechanics, such as pilot-wave, spontaneous reduction, many-worlds, modal, consistent history, and spontaneous collapse (Reference BächtoldBächtold 2008: 843–44; Reference BaeyerBaeyer 2016: 235–39). For a general overview, see Reference LewisLewis 2016.

80 Allan, Chapter 8, this volume.

81 The concept of Weltanschauung is normally translated as “worldview” even though the German anschauen describes a conscious activity, while viewing can also be unconscious (Reference RöschRösch 2015: 11).

82 Reference Weber and WinckelmannWeber 1956: 253, 260, 414–17, 430; Reference NaugleNaugle 2002: xvi, 291–92, 297–303.

85 I thank Rudra Sil for commenting helpfully on this section.

90 Reference MorrisMorris 2011 part 3: 10; part 4: 1.

97 Reference WrightWright 1955: 484, 492–95.

104 Reference HamiltonHamilton 2017: 153; Reference JamesJames 2002: 215–21. In contrast to explicitly political paradigms, analytical perspectives such as rationalism and constructivism offer different discourse communities and a shared concern with the problem of alternative causes of action.

105 There exists a vast literature in different fields of scholarship that discusses different formulations of these two concepts (Reference EmirbayerEmirbayer 1997: 290–91). I provide here no more than stylized sketches to advance my argument. I thank Nina Obermeier for her excellent work in helping me draft this section, and Patrick Jackson for reading and commenting on an earlier draft. See also Reference Nordin and SmithNordin and Smith 2019.

110 Structural arguments focus on social aggregates and do not take individual human action as their starting point. But they, too, adhere to the view of “durable, coherent entities” as the starting point of analysis and therefore are further examples of substantialism (Reference EmirbayerEmirbayer 1997: 284–85).

114 Reference RescherRescher 1996: 98 (emphasis in the original).

130 I thank Yaqing Qin for checking the accuracy of my rendition of his book.

131 Reference QinQin 2018: 36–37.

141 Reference QinQin, 2018: 169–92. This is not an instance of Confucian or Daoist exceptionalism. For example, in his discussion of the Haitian revolution Reference ShilliamShilliam (2017: 279) speaks of “Vodou’s investment in the cosmological conceit of seminal relationality rather than fidelity towards the principle of categorical segregation embraced by colonial science.”

149 Reference MirowskiMirowski 1989: 4–5, 357, 366, 374–95. For the cosmological configuration that enabled this affinity, see Grove, Chapter 4, this volume.

164 Reference SearleSearle (1984: 75) argues that we must abandon the idea that the social sciences are like physics before Newton and that we are waiting for the arrival of a set of Newtonian laws of mind and society. Many students of world politics disagree. They subscribe to a scientific approach based on a Newtonian worldview, hoping that they are in the process of articulating scientific laws.

166 Reference BaradBarad 2007: 24, 134, 440 fn6; Reference Unger and SmolinUnger and Smolin 2015: 373–84, 391–92; Reference SmolinSmolin 1997: 125. Reference KauffmanKauffman 2008 extends that criticism to include all of physics, Newtonian and quantum.

167 Physicists who work on different portions within this broad perspective describe the new field of theory as quantum theory, quantum mechanics, quantum physics or particle physics. All four of these terms will be used (more or less) interchangeably in this chapter.

169 For a few notable exceptions, see Reference UphoffUphoff 1992; Reference BaradBarad 2007; Reference WendtWendt 2015, 2022a, 2022b; Reference ZanottiZanotti 2018; Reference Der Derian and WendtDer Derian and Wendt 2020. James Der Derian’s Project Q, housed at the University of Sidney, has tried to act as a catalyst.

173 Uncertainty was central to the work of economist Frank Knight, Morgenthau’s colleague at Chicago, whom he singles out for special thanks in the preface to his 1946 book.

180 Reference PagelsPagels 1982: 64–66, 72.

182 Reference BaradBarad 2007: 26, 72, 75–88, 93.

190 The online Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy is an excellent source for tracking some of these discussions: https://plato.stanford.edu/.

191 Reference RovelliRovelli 2017: 119 (emphasis in the original).

200 Sil and Katzenstein 2010: 43–48.

202 Reference GeussGeuss 2020: xii, 17–22, 28–30.

205 Reference MortonMorton 2013: 2; Cudworth and Hobden invoke “posthumanism” (Reference Cudworth and Hobden2018: 5, 7; 2013: 651–54). Reference FerrandoFerrando’s 2013 discussion of the many overlapping and contradictory strands and meanings of posthumanism, transhumanism, antihumanism, metahumanism, and new materialisms have made me choose hyper-humanism for the purpose of this discussion. It shares with much of Ferrando’s discussion the insistence on dismantling strict dualisms including between matter and language, as in Reference BaradBarad’s 2007 version of new materialism, and between humans, animals, and technology, as in Reference HarawayHaraway’s 1991 cyborgs. See also Reference Banerji and ParanjapeBanerji and Paranjape 2016.

206 Reference KurkiKurki 2020: 115–16, 124–26, 134–35.

211 Lucretius, Book III, line 1084, quoted in Reference RovelliRovelli 2016: 79.

218 Reference RickmanRickman 1979: 173–74; Byrnes, Chapter 9, this volume.

225 Reference WeberWeber 2009. In his subsequent comparative sociology of religion, Weber moves to a multi-causal analysis.

235 Reference KohnKohn 2013: 8–10, 224–25.

237 Reference WohllebenWohlleben 2017; Reference WeidermannWeidermann 2018. Suzanne Reference SimardSimard’s (2021) scientific work supports the same perspective with experimental work that raises the question of whether plants possess some kind of sentience or agency that might be interpreted as either collaborative or a form of reciprocal exploitation. See Reference JabrJabr 2020.

239 This section on scientific cosmology is greatly indebted to Reference KurkiKurki 2020.

240 Reference KurkiKurki 2020: 2–3, 14–16, 41–42.

242 Reference KauffmanKauffman 2008: ix, 5, 43, 231.

252 Reference PagelsPagels 1982: 127–34, 154.

258 This explains Reference SmolinSmolin’s (1997: 207–08) critique of the weak version of the anthropic principle, which in his view reflects the nostalgia for a world in which there is a divine or scientific stance outside of the world. See also Reference KraghKragh 2011: 224–25.

262 Reference Clarke and PrimoClarke and Primo 2012: 93–97 argue that prediction is usually the wrong standard by which to evaluate models.

272 Nau addresses this issue more fully in Chapter 6.

273 Chapter 2, this volume.

274 Chapter 2 .

275 Chapter 4, this volume.

276 Reference KurkiKurki 2020. In Chapter 6 Nau elaborates on the different worldviews discussed in this volume. Unlike Kurki, he refers to relationalism in the singular.

277 Chapter 2 .

279 Based on a subjective view of quantum physics and scientific cosmology, Chapter 10 suggests an argument that differs from their conventional adoption of Dilthey’s position.

280 Chapter 2 .

285 Reference AllanAllan 2017 conceptualizes how the climate became a distinct object through processes that over time came to constitute it. From this perspective the climate is not a pregiven natural system as typically treated in analytical perspectives building on a Newtonian worldview.

288 Chapter 4, this volume. See also Reference DamasioDamasio 1994.

290 Grove, Chapter 4 .

294 Barnett, Chapter 5, this volume.

296 Barnett, Chapter 5, also discusses diasporic nationalism and prophetic Zionism that global and local political developments sidelined in Israel and the United States.

297 Barnett, Chapter 5.

References

Abbott, Andrew. 1995. “Things of Boundaries,” Social Research 62, 4: 857–82.Google Scholar
Adler, Emanuel. 2019. World Ordering: A Social Theory of Cognitive Evolution. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Adler, Emanuel. 2020. “Control Power as a Special Case of Protean Power: Thoughts on Peter Katzenstein and Lucia Seybert’s Protean Power: Exploring the Uncertain and Unexpected in World Politics,” International Theory 12, 3: 422–34.Google Scholar
Allan, Bentley B. 2017. “Producing the Climate: States, Scientists, and the Constitution of Global Governance Objects,” International Organization 71, 1: 131–62.Google Scholar
Allan, Bentley B. 2018. Scientific Cosmology and International Orders. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Allison, Graham T. 1970. The Essence of Decision: Explaining the Cuban Missile Crisis. Boston, MA: Little, Brown & Company.Google Scholar
Andersson, Jenny. 2018. The Future of the World: Futurology, Futurists, and the Struggle for the Post-Cold War Imagination. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Arfi, Badredine. 2012. “Khȏra as the Condition of Possibility of the Ontological Without Ontology,” Review of International Studies 38, 1: 191207.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Axelrod, Robert, ed. 2015. Structure of Decision: The Cognitive Maps of Political Elites. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bächtold, Manuel. 2008. “Interpreting Quantum Mechanics according to a Pragmatist Approach,” Foundations of Physics 38, 9: 843–68.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baeyer, Hans Christian von. 2016. QBism: The Future of Quantum Physics. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Bain, William. 2020. Political Theology of International Order. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Banerji, Debashish and Paranjape, Makarand R., eds. 2016. Critical Posthumanism and Planetary Futures. New York: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Banks, Michael. 1984. “The Evolution of International Relations Theory,” in Banks, Michael, ed., Conflict in World Society: A New Perspective on International Relations. Brighton: Wheatsheaf Books, pp. 321.Google Scholar
Barad, Karen. 2007. Meeting the Universe Halfway: Quantum Physics and the Entanglement of Matter and Meaning. Durham, NC: Duke University Press.Google Scholar
Barber, Lionel and Chazan, Guy. 2020. “Angela Merkel warns EU: ‘Brexit is a Wake-Up Call’,” Financial Times (January 16). www.ft.com/content/a6785028-35f1-11ea-a6d3-9a26f8c3cba4. Accessed 01/16/20.Google Scholar
Barnett, Michael N. 2016. The Star and the Stripes: A History of the Foreign Policies of American Jews. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Becker, Adam. 2018. What Is Real? The Unfinished Quest for the Meaning of Quantum Physics. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Beckert, Jens and Bronk, Richard, eds. 2018. Uncertain Futures: Imaginaries, Narratives and Calculation in the Economy. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Beckett, Samuel. 1958. The Unnamable. New York: Grove Press.Google Scholar
Bergstraesser, Arnold. 1947. “Wilhelm Dilthey and Max Weber: An Empirical Approach to Historical Synthesis,” Ethics 57, 2: 92110.Google Scholar
Bernstein, Peter. 1996. Against the Gods: The Remarkable Story of Risk. New York: John Wiley.Google Scholar
Betz, Werner. 1980. “Zur Geschichte des Wortes ‘Weltanschauung,” in Kursbuch der Weltanschauungen. Frankfurt/M.: Ullstein, pp. 1828.Google Scholar
Bially-Mattern, Janice. 2014. “On Being Convinced: An Emotional Epistemology of International Relations,” International Theory 6, 3: 589–94.Google Scholar
Boulding, Kenneth E. 1959. “National Images and International Systems,” The Journal of Conflict Resolution 3, 2: 120–31.Google Scholar
Bulhof, Ilse N. 1980. Wilhelm Dilthey: A Hermeneutic Approach to the Study of History and Culture. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bunge, Mario. 1996. Finding Philosophy in Social Science. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Camilleri, Kristian. 2011. “Atom and Individual: The Trajectory of a Metaphor,” in Hege, Ghassan and Kowal, Emma, eds., Force, Movement, Intensity: The Newtonian Imagination in the Humanities and Social Sciences. Melbourne: Melbourne University Press, pp. 5155.Google Scholar
Cartwright, Nancy. 1999. The Dappled World: A Study of the Boundaries of Science. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Christianson, Gale E. 1984. In the Presence of the Creator: Isaac Newton and His Times. New York: The Free Press.Google Scholar
Chuang, Frank, Manley, Ed, and Petersen, Arthur. 2020. “The Role of Worldviews in the Governance of Sustainable Mobility,” PNAS 117, 8: 4034–42.Google Scholar
Chumtong, Jason and Kaldewey, David. 2017. “Beyond the Google Ngram Viewer: Bibliographic Databases and Journal Archives as Tools for the Quantitative Analysis of Scientific and Meta-Scientific Concepts.” University of Bonn, Forum Internationale Wissenschaft, FIW Working Paper 08.Google Scholar
Clarke, Kevin A. and Primo, David M.. 2012. A Model Discipline: Political Science and the Logic of Representation. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cudworth, Erika and Hobden, Stephen. 2018. The Emancipatory Project of Posthumanism. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Cushing, James T. 1994. Quantum Mechanics: Historical Contingency and the Copenhagen Hegemony. Chicago, IL: The University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Dahl, Robert A. 1957. “The Concept of Power,” Behavioral Science 2, 3: 201–15.Google Scholar
Damasio, Antonio R. 1994. Descartes’ Error: Emotion, Reason, and the Human Brain. New York: G.P. Putnam Sons.Google Scholar
Daston, Lorraine. 2019. Against Nature. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Der Derian, James and Wendt, Alexander. 2020. “‘Quantizing International Relations’: The Case for Quantum Approaches to International Theory and Security Practice,” Security Dialogue 51, 5: 399413.Google Scholar
Dewitt, Richard. 2004. Worldviews: An Introduction to the History and Philosophy of Science. Malden, MA: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Diamond, Jared. 2020. “Lessons from a Pandemic,” Financial Times (May 28). www.ft.com/content/71ed9f88-9f5b-11ea-b65d-489c67b0d85d. Accessed 07/13/2021.Google Scholar
Dilthey, Wilhelm. 1924. Gesammelte Schriften. Vol. 5. Einleitung in die Philosophie des Lebens. Erste Hälfte: Abhandlungen zur Grundlegung der Geisteswissenschaften. [Introduction to the Philosophy of Life. First Half. Treatise on the Foundations of the Humanities]. Leipzig: Teubner.Google Scholar
Dilthey, Wilhelm. 1931. Gesammelte Schriften. Vol. 8. Weltanschaungslehre: Abhandlungen zur Philosophie der Philosophie. [Worldview Analysis: Treatise on the Philosophy of Philosophy]. Leipzig: Teubner.Google Scholar
The Economist. 2015. “The Science of Swing” (August 29). www.economist.com/obituary/2015/08/27/the-science-of-swing. Accessed 2/2/2021.Google Scholar
The Economist. 2019. “Canada in the Global Jungle” (February 9). www.economist.com/the-americas/2019/02/09/canada-in-the-global-jungle. Accessed 2/2/2021.Google Scholar
The Economist. 2020. “What’s the Worst that Could Happen? The World Should Think Better about Catastrophic and Existential Risks” (June 25). www.economist.com/briefing/2020/06/25/the-world-should-think-better-about-catastrophic-and-existential-risks. Accessed 2/2/2021.Google Scholar
Emirbayer, Mustafa. 1997. “Manifesto for a Relational Sociology,” American Journal of Sociology 103, 2: 281317.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Enns, Peter K., and Lagodny, Julius. (2021). “Forecasting the 2020 Electoral College Winner: The State Presidential Approval/State Economy Model,” PS: Political Science & Politics 54, 1: 8185. https://doi.org/10.1017/S1049096520001407. Accessed 2/2/2021.Google Scholar
Erlanger, Steven. 2018. “Is the World Becoming a Jungle Again? Should Americans Care?” The New York Times (September 22). www.nytimes.com/2018/09/22/world/europe/trump-american-foreign-policy-europe.html. Accessed 01/28/20.Google Scholar
Ermarth, Michael. 1978. Wilhelm Dilthey: The Critique of Historical Reason. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Fearon, James, and Wendt, Alexander. 2002. “Rationalism v. Constructivism: A Skeptical View,” in Carlsnaes, Walter, Risse, Thomas, and Simmons, Beth A., eds., Handbook of International Relations. London: Sage Publications, pp. 5272.Google Scholar
Ferrando, Francesca. 2013. “Posthumanism, Transhumanism, Antihumanism, Metahumanism, and New Materialisms: Differences and Relations,” Existenz 8, 2: 2632.Google Scholar
Fierke, Karin M. 2013. Political Self-Sacrifice: Agency, Body and Emotion in International Relations. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Fisher, Max. 2020. “Coronavirus ‘Hits All the Hot Buttons’ for How We Misjudge Risk,” The New York Times (February 13). www.nytimes.com/2020/02/13/world/asia/coronavirus-risk-interpreter.html. Accessed 2/2/2021.Google Scholar
Foley, Michael. 1990. Laws, Men and Machines: Modern American Government and the Appeal of Newtonian Mechanics. London/New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Frei, Christopher. 2001. Hans J. Morgenthau: An Intellectual Biography. Baton Rouge: Lousiana State University Press.Google Scholar
Freire, Jr., Olival. 2015. The Quantum Dissidents: Rebuilding the Foundations of Quantum Mechanics (1950–1990). New York: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Friedman, Jeffrey A. 2019. War and Chance: Assessing Uncertainty in Politics. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gabriel, Jürg Martin. 1994. Worldviews and Theories of International Relations. New York: St. Martin’s.Google Scholar
Galbraith, John Kenneth. The Affluent Society. Boston, MA: Houghton Mifflin, 1998.Google Scholar
Gamio, Lazaro and Goldmacher, Shane. 2020. “Five Takeaways from a Super Tuesday that Changed the Democratic Race,” The New York Times (March 4). www.nytimes.com/interactive/2020/03/04/us/politics/super-tuesday-2020-results.html. Accessed 03/26/20.Google Scholar
Geuss, Raymond. 2020. Who Needs a World View? Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gilpin, Robert. 1975. US Power and the Multinational Corporation: The Political Economy of Foreign Direct Investment. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Gollwitzer, Helmut. 1980. “Weltanschauung als Massenproblem (am Beispiel der Bundesrpublik heute) [Worldview as a people problem (exemplified by today’s Federal Republic)],” in Kursbuch der Weltanschungen. Frankfurt/M.: Ullstein, pp. 171200.Google Scholar
Griffiths, Martin, ed. 2007. International Relations Theory for the Twenty-First Century: An Introduction. New York: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grove, Jairus Victor. 2019. Savage Ecology: Geopolitics at the End of the World. Durham, NC: Duke University Press.Google Scholar
Grove, Kevin and Chandler, David. 2017. “Introduction: Resilience and the Anthropocene: The Stakes of ‘Renaturalising’ Politics,” Resilience 5, 2: 7991.Google Scholar
Gunnell, John G. 2011. “Social Scientific Inquiry and Meta-Theoretical Fantasy: The Case of International Relations,” Review of International Studies 37: 1447–69.Google Scholar
Haas, Mark L. 2012. The Clash of Ideologies: Middle Eastern Politics and American Security. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Haas, Peter M. 1992. “Introduction: Epistemic Communities and International Policy Coordination,” International Organization 46, 1: 135.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hage, Ghassan and Kowal, Emma. 2011. “The Newtonian Fantasy and Its ‘Social’ Other,” in Hage, Ghassan and Kowal, Emma, eds., Force, Movement, Intensity: The Newtonian Imagination in the Humanities and Social Sciences. Melbourne: Melbourne University Press, pp. 17.Google Scholar
Hall, Peter. 1993. “Policy Paradigms, Social Learning, and the State: The Case of Economic Policymaking in Britain,” Comparative Politics 25, 3 (April): 275–96.Google Scholar
Hamilton, Scott. 2017. “A Genealogy of Metatheory in IR: How ‘Ontology’ Emerged from the Inter-Paradigm Debate,” International Theory 9, 1: 136–70.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hamilton, Scott. 2019. “I am Uncertain, but We are Not: A New Subjectivity of the Anthropocene,” Review of International Studies 45, 4: 607–26.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Haraway, Donna J. 1991. Simians, Cyborgs, and Women: The Reinvention of Nature. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Haraway, Donna J. 2016. Staying with Trouble: Making Kin in the Chthulucene. London: Duke University Press.Google Scholar
Harrington, Cameron. 2016. “The Ends of the World: International Relations and the Anthropocene,” Millennium 44, 3: 478–98.Google Scholar
Haukkala, Hiski. 2011. The EU–Russia Strategic Partnership: The Limits of Post-Sovereignty in International Relations. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Healey, Richard. 2017. The Quantum Revolution in Philosophy. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Henderson, Bob. 2020. “The Quantum Mechanic,” The New York Times Magazine (June 28): 3639, 5455.Google Scholar
Hetherington, Marc and Weiler, Jonathan. 2009. Authoritarianism and Polarization in American Politics. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Hetherington, Marc and Weiler, Jonathan. 2018. Prius or Pickup? How the Answers to Four Simple Questions Explain America’s Great Divide. Boston, MA: Houghton Mifflin Harcourt.Google Scholar
Hetherington, Norriss S. 1993. ed. Cosmology: Historical, Literary, Philosophical, Religious and Scientific Perspectives. New York: Garland.Google Scholar
Holsti, Ole R. 2006. Making American Foreign Policy. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Huntington, Samuel. 1996. The Clash of Civilizations and the Remaking of World Order. New York: Simon & Schuster.Google Scholar
Hurrell, Andrew. 2007. On Global Order: Power, Values, and the Constitution of International Society. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hutchison, Emma. 2016. Affective Communities in World Politics: Collective Emotions after Trauma. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Jabr, Ferris. 2020. “The Social Life of Forests,” The New York Times Magazine (December 6): 3241.Google Scholar
Jackson, Patrick T. 2010. The Conduct of Inquiry in International Relations: Philosophy of Science and Its Implications for the Study of World Politics. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Jackson, Patrick T. 2015. “Fear of Relativism,” International Studies Perspectives 16: 1322.Google Scholar
Jackson, Patrick T. and Nexon, Daniel H.. 1999. “Relations Before States: Substance, Process, and the Study of World Politics,” European Journal of International Relations 5, 3: 291332.Google Scholar
Jackson, Patrick T. and Nexon, Daniel H.. 2009. “Paradigmatic Faults in International Relations Theory,” International Studies Quarterly 53: 907–30.Google Scholar
Jackson, Patrick T. and Nexon, Daniel H.. 2013. “International Theory in a Post-Paradigmatic Era: From Substantive Wagers to Scientific Ontologies,” European Journal of International Relations 19, 3: 543–65.Google Scholar
James, Patrick. 2002. International Relations and Scientific Progress: Structural Realism Reconsidered. Columbus: The Ohio State University Press.Google Scholar
Jervis, Robert. 2017. “One World or Many?Critical Review 29, 2: 170–88.Google Scholar
Joas, Hans. 2012. “The Axial Age Debate as Religious Discourse,” in Bellah, Robert N and Joas, Hans, eds., The Axial Age and Its Consequences. Cambridge, MA: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, pp. 929.Google Scholar
Johnson, Alastair Iain. 1995. “Thinking about Strategic Culture,” International Security 19, 4 (Spring): 3264.Google Scholar
Kagan, Robert. 2003. Of Paradise and Power: America and Europe in the New World Order. New York: Random House.Google Scholar
Kagan, Robert. 2008. “New Europe, Old Russia,” The Washington Post (6 February): https://carnegieendowment.org/2008/02/06/new-europe-old-russia-pub-19898. Accessed 07/ 13/2021.Google Scholar
Kagan, Robert. 2018a. The Jungle Grows Back: America and Our Imperiled World. New York: Knopf.Google Scholar
Kagan, Robert. 2018b. “The Cost of American Retreat,” The Wall Street Journal (September 7). www.wsj.com/articles/thecost-of-american-retreat-1536330449. Accessed 01/27/20.Google Scholar
Kalberg, Stephen. 2012. Max Weber’s Comparative-Historical Sociology Today: Major Themes, Mode of Causal Analysis, and Applications. Burlington, VT: Ashgate.Google Scholar
Kalberg, Stephen. 2016. “Protestant Ethic,” in Ritzer, George, ed., The Blackwell Encyclopedia of Sociology. New York: Wiley. https://doi.org/10.1002/9781405165518.wbeos0826.Google Scholar
Katzenstein, Peter J., ed. 1996. The Culture of National Security: Norms and Identity in World Politics. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Katzenstein, Peter J. ed. 2010. Civilizations in World Politics: Plural and Pluralist Perspectives. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Katzenstein, Peter J. ed. 2012a. Sinicization and the Rise of China: Civilizational Processes beyond East and West. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Katzenstein, Peter J. ed. 2012b. Anglo-America and Its Discontents: Civilizational Identities beyond West and East. New York: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Katzenstein, Peter J. 2020. “Protean Power: A Second Look,” International Theory 12, 3: 481–99.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Katzenstein, Peter J. and Nelson, Stephen. 2013a. “Worlds in Collision: Uncertainty and Risk in Hard Times,” in Kahler, Miles and Lake, David, eds., Politics in the New Hard Times: The Great Recession in Comparative Perspective. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, pp. 233–52.Google Scholar
Katzenstein, Peter J. and Nelson, Stephen C.. 2013b. “Reading the Right Signals and Reading the Signals Right: IPE and the Financial Crisis of 2008,” Review of International Political Economy 20, 5: 1101–31.Google Scholar
Katzenstein, Peter J. and Seybert, Lucia A., eds. 2018a. Protean Power: Exploring the Uncertain and Unexpected in World Politics. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Katzenstein, Peter J. and Seybert, Lucia A.. 2018b. “Uncertainty, Risk, Power and the Limits of International Relations Theory,” in Katzenstein, Peter J. and Seybert, Lucia A., eds., Protean Power: Exploring the Uncertain and Unexpected in World Politics. New York: Cambridge University Press, pp. 2756.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Katzenstein, Peter J. and Seybert, Lucia A.. 2018c. “Power Complexities and Political Theory,” in Katzenstein, Peter J. and Seybert, Lucia A., eds., Protean Power: Exploring the Uncertain and Unexpected in World Politics. New York: Cambridge University Press, pp. 267301.Google Scholar
Kauffman, Sturt A. 2008. Reinventing the Sacred: A New View of Science, Reason, and Religion. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Kennan, George F. 1966[1954]. Realities of American Foreign Policy. New York: Norton.Google Scholar
Keohane, Robert O. 1984. After Hegemony: Cooperation and Discord in the World Political Economy. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Keohane, Robert O. 2002. Power and Governance in a Partially Globalized World. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Kinnvall, Catarina and Mitzen, Jennifer. 2020. “Anxiety, Fear and Ontological Security in World Politics: Thinking With and Beyond Giddens,” International Theory 12, 2: 240–56.Google Scholar
Kirshner, Jonathan. 2022. An Unwritten Future: Realism and Uncertainty in World Politics. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Kohn, Eduardo. 2013. How Forests Think: Toward an Anthropology Beyond the Human. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Koltko-Rivera, Mark E. 2004. “The Psychology of Worldviews,” Review of General Psychology 8, 1 : 358.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Koschut, Simon. 2018. “No Sympathy for the Devil: Emotions and the Social Construction of the Democratic Peace,” Cooperation and Conflict 53, 3: 320–38.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kragh, Helge. 2011. Higher Speculations: Grand Theories and Failed Revolutions in Physics and Cosmology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kragh, Helge. 2012. “Criteria of Science, Cosmology, and Lessons of History,” History and Philosophy of Physics, https://arxiv.org/abs/1208.5215. Accessed 2/2/2021.Google Scholar
Kragh, Helge. 2013. Conceptions of Cosmos: From Myths to the Accelerating Universe: A History of Cosmology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Krebs, Ronald R. 2015. Narrative and the Making of US National Security. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Krell, Gert. 2000. Weltbilder und Weltordnung: Einführung in die Theorie der Internationalen Beziehungen. [World images and world order: Introduction to the theory of international relations]. Baden-Baden: Nomos.Google Scholar
Kristensen, Peter Marcus. 2016. “Discipline Admonished: On International Relations Fragmentation and the Disciplinary Politics of Stocktaking,” European Journal of International Relations 22, 2: 243–46.Google Scholar
Kuhn, Thomas S. 1962. The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Chicago, IL: The University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Kurki, Milja. 2015. “Stretching Situated Knowledge: From Standpoint Epistemology to Cosmology and Back Again,” Millennium: Journal of International Studies 43, 3: 779–97.Google Scholar
Kurki, Milja. 2020. International Relations in a Relational Universe. Oxford/NewYork: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lakoff, George. 2002. Moral Politics: How Liberals and Conservatives Think. 2nd ed. Chicago, IL: The University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Latour, Bruno. 2014. “Agency at the Time of the Anthropocene,” New Literary History 45: 118.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Le Vine, Steve. 2018. “Rising European Fear: Strongman-Dominated Global ‘Jungle’,” Axios (September 12). www.axios.com/kagan-anti-establishment-movements-democracy-114b7f22-079e-4b70-875f-bef9d179bee5.html. Accessed 01/28/20.Google Scholar
Legro, Jeffrey W. 2005. Rethinking the World: Great Power Strategies and International Order. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Lehrer, Jonah. 2007. Proust Was a Neuroscientist. Boston, MA: Houghton Mifflin.Google Scholar
Leites, Nathan. 1951. The Operational Code of the Politburo. New York: McGraw-Hill.Google Scholar
Lepore, Jill. 2020. “All the King’s Data,” The New Yorker (August 3 & 10): 1824.Google Scholar
Lerer, Lisa and Epstein, Reid J.. 2020. “Abandon Trump? Deep in the GOP Ranks, the MAGA Mind-Set Prevails,” The New York Times (January 14). www.nytimes.com/2021/01/14/us/politics/trump-republicans.html. Accessed 02/02/21.Google Scholar
Levine, Daniel J. and Barder, Alexander D.. 2014. “The Closing of the American Mind: ‘American School’ International Relations and the State of Grand Theory,” European Journal of International Relations 20, 4: 863–88.Google Scholar
Lewis, Peter J. 2016. Quantum Ontology: A Guide to the Metaphysics of Quantum Mechanics. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lichbach, Mark Irving and Zuckerman, Alan S., eds. 2009. Rationality, Culture and Structure. 2nd ed. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Liik, Kadri. 2019. “Into the Jungle,” Berlin Policy Journal (January/February). https://berlinpolicyjournal.com/into-the-jungle/. Accessed 01/28/20.Google Scholar
Lijphart, Arend. 1974. “The Structure of Theoretical Revolution in International Relations,” International Studies Quarterly 18, 1: 4174.Google Scholar
Little, Richard. 1984. “Teaching International Relations: Working with Paradigms,” Interstate: A Journal of International Relations 1: 310.Google Scholar
Louth, Jonathan. 2011. “From Newton to Newtonianism: Reductionism and the Development of the Social Sciences,” Emergence: Complexity and Organization 13, 4: 6383.Google Scholar
Maas, Matthias, ed. 2018. The World Views of the Obama Era. New York: Palgrave.Google Scholar
Makkreel, Rudolf A. 2020. “Metaphysics and the Hermeneutical Relevance of Worldviews,” The Review of Metaphysics 74: 321–44.Google Scholar
March, James G. and Olsen, Johan P.. 1998. “The Institutional Dynamics of International Political Orders.” International Organization 52, 4: 943–69.Google Scholar
Marom, Amnon. 2014. “Universality, Particularity, and Potentiality: The Sources of Human Divergence as Arise from Wilhelm Dilthey’s Writings,” Human Studies 37, 1: 113.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Massumi, Brian. 2002. Parables for the Virtual: Movement, Affect, Sensation. Durham, NC: Duke University Press.Google Scholar
Masur, Gerhard. 1952. “Wilhelm Dilthey and the History of Ideas,” Journal of the History of Ideas 13, 1: 94107.Google Scholar
Maudlin, Tim. 2012. Philosophy of Physics: Space and Time. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Mayntz, Renate and Scharpf, Fritz W.. 1995. “Der Ansatz des akteurzentrierten Institutionalismus, [The actor-centered institutional approach]” in Mayntz, Renate and Scharpf, Fritz, eds., Steuerung und Selbstorganisation in staatsnahen Sektoren [Steering and Self-organization in Sectors Close to the State], pp. 3972. Frankfurt am Main: Campus.Google Scholar
McClosky, Herbert. 1956. “Concerning Strategies for a Science of International Politics,” World Politics 8, 2: 281–95.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McCourt, David M. 2016. “Practice Theory and Relationalism as the New Constructivism,” International Studies Quarterly 60, 3: 475–85.Google Scholar
McDermott, Rose. 1998. Risk-Taking in International Politics: Prospect Theory in American Foreign Policy. Ann Arbor, MI: University of Michigan Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Meldolesi, Luca. 1995. Discovering the Possible: The Surprising World of Albert O. Hirschman. Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press.Google Scholar
Mermin, N. David. 1990. Boojums All the Way Through: Communicating Science in a Prosaic Age. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Mermin, N. David. 2016. Why Quark Rhymes with Pork: And Other Scientific Diversions. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Mermin, N. David. 2019. “Making Better Sense of Quantum Mechanics,” Reports of Progress in Physics 82: 116.Google Scholar
Meyer, John M. 2001. Political Nature: Environmentalism and the Interpretation of Western Thought. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.Google Scholar
Milner, Helen. 1991. “The Assumption of Anarchy in International Relations Theory: A Critique,” Review of International Studies 17, 1: 6785.Google Scholar
Mirowski, Philip. 1989. More Heat than Light: Economics as Social Physics – Physics as Nature’s Economics. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mitchell, Audra. 2019. “Can International Relations Confront the Cosmos?” in Edkins, Jenny, ed., Routledge Handbook of Critical International Relations. Routledge: New York, pp. 5164.Google Scholar
Morgenthau, Hans J. 1946. Scientific Man vs. Power Politics. Chicago, IL: The University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Morris, Errol. 2011. “The Ashtray,” The New York Times Opinionator (March): 610.Google Scholar
Morton, Timothy. 2013. Hyperobjects: Philosophy and Ecology after the End of the World. London: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Mul, Jos de. 2004. The Tragedy of Finitude: Dilthey’s Hermeneutics of Life. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Munro, William Bennett. 1928. “Physics and Politics – An Old Analogy Revised,” The American Political Science Review 22, 1: 111.Google Scholar
Narang, Vipin and Staniland, Paul. 2012. “Institutions and Worldviews in Indian Foreign Security Policy,” India Review 11, 2: 7694.Google Scholar
Narlikar, Amrita and Narlikar, Aruna. 2014. Bargaining with a Rising India: Lessons from the Mahabharata. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Nau, Henry R. 2012. “Introduction: Domestic Voices of Aspiring Powers,” in Nau, Henry R. and Ollapally, Deepa M., eds., Worldviews of Aspiring Powers: Domestic Foreign Policy Debates in China, India, Iran, Japan, and Russia. New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 335.Google Scholar
Naugle, David K. 2002. Worldview: The History of a Concept. Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans.Google Scholar
Nelson, Stephen C. and Katzenstein, Peter J.. 2014. “Uncertainty, Risk, and the Financial Crisis of 2008,” International Organization 68: 361–92.Google Scholar
Nexon, Daniel H. 2010. “Relationalism and New Systems Theory,” in Albert, Mathias, Cederman, Lars-Erik, and Wendt, Alexander, eds., New Systems Theories of World Politics. New York: Palgrave, pp. 99126.Google Scholar
Ney, Alyssa and Albert, David Z.. 2013. The Wave Function: Essays on the Metaphysics of Quantum Mechanics. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Nisbett, Richard E. 2003. The Geography of Thought: How Asians and Westerners Think Differently … And Why. New York: Free Press.Google Scholar
Nordin, Astrid H. M. and Smith, Graham M, guest eds. 2019. “Towards Global Relational Theorizing,” Special Issue, The Cambridge Review of International Affairs 32, 5.Google Scholar
Norwine, Jim and Smith, Jonathan M., eds. 2000. Worldview Flux: Perplexed Values among Postmodern Peoples. Lanham, MD: Lexington Books.Google Scholar
Nussbaum, Martha. 1995. “Emotions and Women’s Capabilities,” in Glover, Jonathon and Nussbaum, Martha, eds., Women, Culture, and Development. New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 360–95.Google Scholar
Nussbaum, Martha. 2001. Upheavals of Thought: The Intelligence of Emotions. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Oliver, J. Eric and Wood, Thomas J.. 2018. Enchanted America: How Intuition and Reason Divide our Politics. Chicago, IL: The University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Orth, Ernst Wolfgang. 1985. “Einleitung: Dilthey und die Gegenwart der Philosophie [Introduction: Dilthey and contemporary philosophy],” in Roth, Ernst Wolfgang, ed., Dilthey und die Gegenwart der Philosophie. Freiburg: Karl Alber, pp. 727.Google Scholar
Pagels, Heinz R. 1982. The Cosmic Code: Quantum Physics as the Language of Nature. New York: Simon and Schuster.Google Scholar
Pelopidas, Benoît. 2020. “Power, Luck, and Scholarly Responsibility at the End of the World,” International Theory 12, 3: 459–70.Google Scholar
Phillips, Matt. 2020. “Trillions in Value Erased, and Then a Surge of Hope,” The New York Times (March 14): B1, B4.Google Scholar
Phillips, W. Gary, Brown, William E., and Stonestreet, John. 1991. Making Sense of Your World. Chicago, IL: Moody Press.Google Scholar
Plantinga, Theodore. 1980. Historical Understanding in the Thought of Wilhelm Dilthey. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.Google Scholar
Popper, Karl. 1995. A World of Propensities. Bristol: Thoemmes Press.Google Scholar
Pouliot, Vincent. 2008. “The Logic of Practicality: A Theory of Practice of Security Communities,” International Organization 62, 2: 257–88.Google Scholar
Putnam, Lara. 2020. “Rust Belt in Transition,” Democracy Journal 57 (Summer). https://democracyjournal.org/magazine/57/rust-belt-in-transition/. Accessed 2/2/2021.Google Scholar
Qin, Yaqing. 2018. A Relational Theory of World Politics. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Range, Willard. 1961. Jawaharlal Nehru’s World View: A Theory of International Relations. Athens, GA: University of Georgia Press.Google Scholar
Rescher, Nicholas. 1996. Process Metaphysics: An Introduction to Process Philosophy. Albany: State University of New York Press.Google Scholar
Rice, Susan. 2020. “Trump’s Hobbesian Jungle,” The New York Times (April 8): A25.Google Scholar
Rickman, H.P. 1979. Wilhelm Dilthey: Pioneer of the Human Studies. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Ridley, Matt. 2015. The Evolution of Everything: How New Ideas Emerge. New York: Harper Collins.Google Scholar
Roberts, Siobhan. 2020. “Embracing the Uncertainties of the Pandemic,” The New York Times (April 8): A4.Google Scholar
Rosenau, James N. 1990. Turbulence in World Politics: A Theory of Change and Continuity. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Rosenau, James N. 1997. Along the Domestic Foreign Frontier: Exploring Governance in a Turbulent World. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Rosenau, James N. and Durfee, Mary. 1995. Thinking Theory Thoroughly: Coherent Approaches to an Incoherent World. Boulder, CO: Westview Press.Google Scholar
Rösch, Felix. 2015. Power, Knowledge, and Dissent in Morgenthau’s Worldview. New York: Palgrave.Google Scholar
Rovelli, Carlo. 2016. Seven Brief Lessons on Physics. New York: Riverhead Books.Google Scholar
Rovelli, Carlo. 2017. Reality is Not What It Seems: The Journey to Quantum Gravity. New York: Riverhead Books.Google Scholar
Ruggie, John Gerard. 1993. “Territoriality and Beyond: Problematizing Modernity in International Relations,” International Organization 47, 1: 139–74.Google Scholar
Sabel, Charles F. 1984. Work and Politics: The Division of Labor in Industry. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Sanders, David 1989. Losing an Empire, Finding a Role: An Introduction to British Foreign Policy since 1945. New York: St Martin’s.Google Scholar
Sasley, Brent E. 2011. “Theorizing States’ Emotions,” International Studies Review 13: 452–76.Google Scholar
Scharpf, Fritz W. 1997. Games Real Actors Play: Actor-Centered Institutionalism in Policy Research. Boulder, CO: Westview.Google Scholar
Scoblic, J. Peter and Tetlock, Philip E.. 2020. “A Better Crystal Ball: The Right Way to Think about the Future,” Foreign Affairs (November–December): 1018.Google Scholar
Searle, John. 1984. Minds, Brains and Science. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Seybert, Lucia A. and Katzenstein, Peter J.. 2018. “Protean Power and Control Power: Conceptual Analysis,” in Katzenstein, Peter J. and Seybert, Lucia A., eds., Protean Power: Exploring the Uncertain and Unexpected in World Politics. New York: Cambridge University Press, pp. 326.Google Scholar
Sharma, Ritu. 1989. “Nehru’s World-View: An Alternative to the Superpowers’ Model of International Relations,” India Quarterly 45, 4: 324–32.Google Scholar
Shilliam, Robbie. 2009. German Thought and International Relations: The Rise and Fall of a Liberal Project. New York: Palgrave.Google Scholar
Shilliam, Robbie. 2017. “Race and Revolution at Bwa Kayiman,” Millennium 45, 3: 269–92.Google Scholar
Shiraishi, Takashi. 2020. “Between the ‘China Dream’ and the ‘Pacific Alliance’: Japanese Strategy in an Age of US–China Rivalry,” Discuss Japan – Japan Foreign Policy Forum 58 (June 8). www.japanpolicyforum.jp/diplomacy/pt20200608180915.html. Accessed 2/2/2021.Google Scholar
Sil, Rudra and Katzenstein, Peter J.. 2010a. Beyond Paradigms: Analytic Eclecticism in the Study of World Politics. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Sil, Rudra and Katzenstein, Peter J.. 2010b. “Analytic Eclecticism in the Study of World Politics: Reconfiguring Problems and Mechanisms across Research Traditions,” Perspectives on Politics 8, 2: 411–31.Google Scholar
Simard, Susan. 2021. Finding the Mother Tree: Discovering how the Forest is Wired for Intelligence and Healing. New York: Knopf.Google Scholar
Simon, Herbert A. 1956. “Rational Choice and the Structure of the Environment,” Psychological Review 63, 2: 129–38. https://doi.org/10.1037/h0042769. Accessed 2/2/2021.Google Scholar
Smith, Michael F 1991. “Letting in the Jungle,” Journal of Applied Philosophy 8, 2: 145–54.Google Scholar
Smolin, Lee. 1997. The Life of the Cosmos. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Smolin, Lee. 2000. Three Roads to Quantum Gravity. London: Phoenix.Google Scholar
Smolin, Lee. 2013. Time Reborn: From the Crisis in Physics to the Future of the Universe. Boston, MA: Houghton Mifflin Harcourt.Google Scholar
Snobelen, Stephen David. 2005. “Isaac Newton, Socinianism and the ‘One Supreme God’,” in Mulsow, Martin and Rohls, Jan, eds., Socinianism and Arminianism: Antitrinitarians, Calvinists and Cultural Exchange. Leiden: Brill, pp. 241–98.Google Scholar
Steiner, Miriam. 1983. “The Search for Order in a Disorderly World: Worldviews and Prescriptive Decision Paradigms,” International Organization 37, 3: 373413.Google Scholar
Suleman, Arsalan. 2017. “Return of the Clash: Operationalizing a Tainted Worldview,” The Washington Quarterly 40, 4: 4970.Google Scholar
Swedberg, Richard, with Ola, Agevall. 2005. The Max Weber Dictionary: Key Words and Central Concepts. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.Google Scholar
Tan, Paige Johnson. 2007. “Navigating and Turbulent Ocean: Indonesia’s Worldview and Foreign Policy,” Asian Perspective 31, 3: 147–81.Google Scholar
Terhalle, Maximilian. 2015. The Transition of Global Order: Legitimacy and Contestation. New York: Palgrave.Google Scholar
Tetlock, Philip and Gardner, Dan. 2015. Superforecasting: The Art and Science of Prediction. New York: Random House.Google Scholar
Tilford, Earl H. 1995. “World View: The 1995 Assessment from the Strategic Studies Institute.” Carlisle Barracks PA: US Army War College, Strategic Studies Institute (February 10).Google Scholar
Trownsell, Tamara A. , Tickner, Arlene B, Querejazu, Amaya, et al. 2020. “Differing about Difference: Relational IR from around the World,” International Studies Perspectives 22, 1: 2564.Google Scholar
Tsing, Anna Lowenhaupt. 2015. The Mushroom at the End of the World: On the Possibility of Life in Capitalist Ruins. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Underdal, Arild. 2017. “Climate Change and International Relations (After Kyoto),” Annual Review of Political Science 20: 169–88.Google Scholar
Unger, Roberto Mangabeira and Smolin, Lee. 2015. The Singular Universe and the Reality of Time. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Uphoff, Norman. 1992. Learning for Gal Oya: Possibilities for Participatory Development and Post-Newtonian Social Science. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Vennesson, Pascal. 2007. “European Worldviews: Ideas and the European Union in World Politics,” EUI Working Papers RSCAS 2007/07. Florence: European University Institute.Google Scholar
Wæver, Ole. 1997. “Figures of International Thought: Introducing Persons instead of Paradigms,” in Neumann, Iver B. and Wæver, Ole, eds., The Future of International Relations: Masters in the Making. New York: Routledge, pp. 137.Google Scholar
Wainer, Andrew. 2016. “Global Politics is Basically Anarchic – We’re Ruled by the Law of the Jungle,” The Guardian (July 2). www.theguardian.com/global-development-professionals-network/2016/jul/02/global-politics-is-basically-anarchic-were-ruled-by-the-law-of-the-jungle. Accessed 01/28/20.Google Scholar
Waldner, David. 2017. “Schroedinger’s Cat and the Dog that Didn’t Bark: Why Quantum Mechanics is (Probably) Irrelevant to the Social Sciences,” Critical Review 29, 2: 190233.Google Scholar
Waltz, Kenneth N. 1959. Man, State and War: A Theoretical Analysis. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Waltz, Kenneth N. 1979. Theory of International Politics. Boston, MA: McGraw-Hill.Google Scholar
Waters, Malcolm, ed. 1999. Modernity: Critical Concepts. 2 Volumes. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Weber, Max. 1946. “The Social Psychology of World Religions,” in Gerth, H.H. and Mills, C. Wright, eds., From Max Weber: Essays in Sociology. New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 267301.Google Scholar
Weber, Max. 1956. Soziologie, Weltgeschichtliche Analyse, Politik, ed. Winckelmann, Johannes. Stuttgart: Alfred Kröner.Google Scholar
Weber, Max. 1978. Economy and Society, Vol. 1, ed. Roth, Guenther and Wittich, Claus. New York: Bedminster Press.Google Scholar
Weber, Max. 2009. The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism with Other Writings on the Rise of the West, translated and introduced by S. Kalberg. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Weidermann, Volker. 2018. “Wald als Widerstand,” Der Spiegel 14 (March 31).Google Scholar
Weinberg, Steven. 1998. “The Revolution That Didn’t Happen,” The New York Review of Books (October 8). www.nybooks.com/articles/1998/the-revolution-that-didnt-happen. Accessed 9/10/2019.Google Scholar
Weinberg, Steven. 2015. “Eye on the Present – The Whig History of Science,” The New York Review of Books (December 17). www.hrstud.unizg.hr/_news/34443/Pages%20from%20New%20York%20Review%20of%20Books%20-%2017%20December%202015-2.pdf. Accessed 03/20/20.Google Scholar
Weinberg, Steven. 2017. “The Trouble with Quantum Mechanics,” The New York Review of Books (January 19). www.nybooks.com/articles/2017/01/19/trouble-with-quantum-mechanics/. Accessed 03/20/20.Google Scholar
Weinstein, Steven and Rickles, Dean. 2018. “Quantum Gravity,” The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2018 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2018/entries/quantum-gravity/. Accessed 2/2/2021.Google Scholar
Wendt, Alexander. 2015. Quantum Mind and Social Science: Unifying Physical and Social Ontology. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Wendt, Alexander. 2022a. “Why IR Scholars Should Care about Quantum Theory: Part I. Burdens of Proof and Uncomfortable Facts,” International Theory 14:1: 119129.Google Scholar
Wendt, Alexander. 2022b. “Why IR Scholars Should Care about Quantum Theory: Part II. Critics in the PITs,” International Theory 14:1: 193209.Google Scholar
Wenger, Andreas, Jasper, Ursula, and Cavelty, Myriam Dunn, eds. 2020. The Politics and Science of Prevision. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Wertheim, Margaret. 2011. Physics on the Fringe: Smoke Rings, Circlons and Alternative Theories of Everything. New York: Walker and Company.Google Scholar
Westfall, Richard S. 1980. Never at Rest: A Biography of Isaac Newton. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
White, Theodore W. 1961. The Making of the President 1960. New York: Atheneum.Google Scholar
Wiener, Norbert. 1948. Cybernetics: Or Control and Communication in the Animal and the Machine. New York: John Wiley.Google Scholar
Wight, Colin. 1996. “Incommensurability and Cross-Paradigm Communication in International Relations Theory: ‘What’s the Frequency Kenneth?’,” Millennium 25, 2: 291319.Google Scholar
Wilder, Matt and Howlett, Michael. 2014. “The Politics of Policy Anomalies: Bricolage and the Hermeneutics of Paradigms,” Critical Policy Studies 8, 2: 183202.Google Scholar
Wohlleben, Peter. 2017. The Hidden Life of Trees: What They Feel, How They Communicate – Discoveries from a Secret World. Vancouver: Greystone.Google Scholar
Wolf, Reinhard. 2012a. “Der ‘emotional turn’ in den IB: Plädoyer für eine theoretische Überwindung methodischer Engführung [The ‘emotional turn’ in international relations: appeal for a theoretical overcoming of methodological narrowing],” Zeitschrift für Außen-und Sicherheitspolitik 5: 605–24.Google Scholar
Wolf, Reinhard. 2012b. “Prickly States? Recognition and Disrespect Between Persons and People,” in Lindemann, Thomas and Ringmar, Erik, eds., International Politics of Recognition. London: Paradigm Publishers, pp. 3956.Google Scholar
Wright, Quincy. 1955. The Study of International Relations. New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts.Google Scholar
Zalloua, Zahi. 2009. “Introduction to Focus: Posthumanism,” American Book Review 30, 2: 34.Google Scholar
Zanotti, Laura. 2018. Ontological Entanglements, Agency and Ethics in International Relations. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Figure 0

Figure 1.1 Ngrams: worldview, theory, model

Figure 1

Figure 1.2 Worldviews and analytical perspectives

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×