Book contents
- Frontmatter
- Dedication
- Contents
- Preface
- Preface
- Translator's preface
- Part I Introduction: confrontation of analytical philosophy with traditional conceptions of philosophy
- Part II A first step: analysis of the predicative sentence
- 8 Preliminary reflections on method and preview of the course of the investigation
- 9 Husserl's theory of meaning
- 10 Collapse of the traditional theory of meaning
- 11 Predicates: the first step in the development of an analytical conception of the meaning of sentences. The dispute between nominalists and conceptualists
- 12 The basic principle of analytical philosophy. The dispute continued. Predicates and quasi-predicates
- 13 The meaning of an expression and the circumstances of its use. Dispute with a behaviouristic conception
- 14 The employment-rule of an assertoric sentence. Argument with Grice and Searle
- 15 Positive account of the employment-rule of assertoric sentences in terms of the truth-relation
- 16 Supplements
- 17 ‘And’ and ‘or’
- 18 General sentences. Resumption of the problem of predicates
- 19 The mode of employment of predicates. Transition to singular terms
- 20 What is it for a sign to stand for an object? The traditional account
- 21 The function of singular terms
- 22 Russell and Strawson
- 23 What is ‘identification’?
- 24 Specification and identification. Specification and truth
- 25 Spatio-temporal identification and the constitution of the object-relation
- 26 Supplements
- 27 Results
- 28 The next steps
- Bibliography
- Index of names
- Index of subjects
13 - The meaning of an expression and the circumstances of its use. Dispute with a behaviouristic conception
from Part II - A first step: analysis of the predicative sentence
Published online by Cambridge University Press: 05 August 2016
- Frontmatter
- Dedication
- Contents
- Preface
- Preface
- Translator's preface
- Part I Introduction: confrontation of analytical philosophy with traditional conceptions of philosophy
- Part II A first step: analysis of the predicative sentence
- 8 Preliminary reflections on method and preview of the course of the investigation
- 9 Husserl's theory of meaning
- 10 Collapse of the traditional theory of meaning
- 11 Predicates: the first step in the development of an analytical conception of the meaning of sentences. The dispute between nominalists and conceptualists
- 12 The basic principle of analytical philosophy. The dispute continued. Predicates and quasi-predicates
- 13 The meaning of an expression and the circumstances of its use. Dispute with a behaviouristic conception
- 14 The employment-rule of an assertoric sentence. Argument with Grice and Searle
- 15 Positive account of the employment-rule of assertoric sentences in terms of the truth-relation
- 16 Supplements
- 17 ‘And’ and ‘or’
- 18 General sentences. Resumption of the problem of predicates
- 19 The mode of employment of predicates. Transition to singular terms
- 20 What is it for a sign to stand for an object? The traditional account
- 21 The function of singular terms
- 22 Russell and Strawson
- 23 What is ‘identification’?
- 24 Specification and identification. Specification and truth
- 25 Spatio-temporal identification and the constitution of the object-relation
- 26 Supplements
- 27 Results
- 28 The next steps
- Bibliography
- Index of names
- Index of subjects
Summary
If the meaning of a linguistic sign cannot be understood in terms of the sign's standing for an object then the view which most readily suggests itself is that to understand a sign is to know in which circumstances it is to be used. At the end of the last lecture I tried to show that as regards the use of predicates at any rate this conception will not do; however I also raised the question of whether this conception might nevertheless be correct in the case of all independent utterances and hence in the case of whole assertoric sentences. Before we reject the thesis that the meaning of an expression consists in the circumstances of its use we must subject it to a more fundamental examination.
In §117 of his Philosophical Investigations Wittgenstein writes: ‘If, for example, someone says that the sentence … has meaning for him, then he should ask himself in what particular circumstances this sentence is actually used.’ And as Wittgenstein says in another place the use is thereby connected with our other activities. By way of explanation he presents, at the beginning of the Investigations, some examples of ‘languages more primitive than our own’ (§2). An example, which is further elaborated in the following paragraphs, is described in §2: ‘Let us imagine a language … which is meant to serve for communication between a builder A and an assistant B. A is building with building-stones: there are blocks, pillars, slabs and beams. B has to pass him the stones, and that in the order in which A needs them. For this purpose they use a language consisting of the words “block”, “pillar”, “slab”, “beam”. A calls them out; – B brings the stone which he has learnt to bring at such-and-such a call.’ Wittgenstein adds: ‘conceive this as a complete primitive language’. Somewhat later we read: ‘We can also think of the whole process of using words in §2 as one of those games by means of which children learn their native language. I will call these games “language-games” … I shall also call the whole, consisting of language and the actions into which it is woven, the “language-game”‘ (§7).
- Type
- Chapter
- Information
- Traditional and Analytical PhilosophyLectures on the Philosophy of Language, pp. 172 - 185Publisher: Cambridge University PressPrint publication year: 2016