Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-dlnhk Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-23T23:18:33.607Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Bibliography

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  30 September 2022

Peter Furlong
Affiliation:
Valencia College, Florida
Leigh Vicens
Affiliation:
Augustana University
Get access

Summary

Image of the first page of this content. For PDF version, please use the ‘Save PDF’ preceeding this image.'
Type
Chapter
Information
Theological Determinism
New Perspectives
, pp. 264 - 275
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2022

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Adams, R. M. (1972). Must God Create the Best? The Philosophical Review 81(3), 317–332.Google Scholar
Adams, R. M. (1979). Existence, Self-Interest, and the Problem of Evil. Noûs 13(1), 53–65.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Adams, R. M. (1986). The Problem of Total Devotion. In Audi, R. and Wainwright, W., eds., Rationality, Religious Belief, and Moral Commitment. Cornell University Press, 108–132.Google Scholar
Adams, R. M. (1991). An Anti-Molinist Argument. In Tomberlin, J. E., ed., Philosophical Perspectives, Vol. 5. Ridgeview Press, 343–353.Google Scholar
Adams, M. M. (1999). Horrendous Evils and the Goodness of God. Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Adams, R. M. (2006). Love and the Problem of Evil. Philosophia 34(3), 243–251.Google Scholar
Anderson, J. N. (2016). Calvinism and the First Sin. In Alexander, D and Johnson, D., eds., Calvinism and the Problem of Evil. Pickwick Publications, 200–232.Google Scholar
Arpaly, N. (2003). Unprincipled Virtue: An Inquiry into Moral Agency. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Audi, P. (2012a). A Clarification and Defense of the Notion of Grounding. In Correia, F. and Schnieder, B., eds., Metaphysical Grounding: Understanding the Structure of Reality. Cambridge University Press, 101–121.Google Scholar
Audi, P. (2012b). Grounding: Toward a Theory of the In-Virtue-of Relation. The Journal of Philosophy 109(12), 685–711.Google Scholar
Baker, L. R. (2003). Why Christians Should Not Be Libertarians: An Augustinian Challenge. Faith and Philosophy 20(4), 460–478.Google Scholar
Barth, K. (1956). Church Dogmatics IV/1, The Doctrine of Reconciliation, Part 1. Trans. G. Bromiley. T&T Clark.Google Scholar
Bennett, K. (2017). Making Things Up. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Bignon, G. (2018). Excusing Sinners and Blaming God: A Calvinist Assessment of Determinism, Moral Responsibility, and Divine Involvement in Evil. Pickwick Publications.Google Scholar
Bishop, J. (1993). Compatibilism and the Free Will Defense. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 71(2), 104–120.Google Scholar
Bliss, R., and Trogdon, K. (2016). Metaphysical Grounding. In Zalta, E., ed., The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2016 edition). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2016/entries/grounding/.Google Scholar
Brien, A. (1989). Can God Forgive Us Our Trespasses? Sophia 28(2), 35–42.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bruce, J. E. (2016). Not the Author of Evil: A Question of Providence, Not a Problem for Calvinism. In Alexander, D. and Johnson, D., eds., Calvinism and the Problem of Evil. Pickwick Publications, 96–122.Google Scholar
Burrell, D. (1993). Freedom and Creation in Three Traditions. University of Notre Dame Press.Google Scholar
Byerly, T. R. (2017). Free Will Theodicies for Theological Determinists. Sophia 56(2), 289–310.Google Scholar
Calvin, J. (1997). Concerning the Eternal Predestination of God. Trans. J. Reid. Westminster John Knox Press.Google Scholar
Capes, J. (2019). Strict Moral Liability. Social Philosophy and Policy 36(2), 52–71.Google Scholar
Churchill, W. (1949). The Second World War. Houghton Mifflin Co.Google Scholar
Churchill, J. R. (2017). Determinism and Divine Blame. Faith and Philosophy 34(4), 425–448.Google Scholar
Cillis, M. (2013). Free Will and Predestination in Islamic Thought: Theoretical Compromises in the Works of Avicenna, al-Ghazali and Ibn ’Arabi. Routledge.Google Scholar
The Constitution of the Presbyterian Church (U.S.A.), Part I: Book of Confessions (2016). Office of the General Assembly.Google Scholar
Couenhoven, J. (2012). The Necessities of Perfect Freedom. International Journal of Systematic Theology 14(4), 396–419.Google Scholar
Couenhoven, J. (2013). Stricken by Sin, Cured by Christ: Agency, Necessity, and Culpability in Augustinian Theology. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Couenhoven, J. (2018). Predestination: A Guide for the Perplexed. T&T Clark.Google Scholar
Craig, W. L. (2019). Divine Forgiveness and Legal Pardon. In Bock, G., ed., The Philosophy of Forgiveness: Volume IV. Christian Perspectives on Forgiveness. Vernon Press, 1–22.Google Scholar
Crisp, O. (2009). Original Sin and Atonement. In Flint, T. and Rea, M., eds., The Oxford Handbook of Philosophical Theology. Oxford University Press, 430–451.Google Scholar
Crisp, O. (2015). On Original Sin. International Journal of Systematic Theology 17(3), 252–266.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Crisp, O. (2017). Libertarian Calvinism. In McCann, H., ed., Free Will and Classical Theism. Oxford University Press, 112–130.Google Scholar
Cyr, T. (2016). The Parallel Manipulation Argument. Ethics 126, 1075–1089.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cyr, T. (2018). Carving a Life from Legacy: Free Will and Manipulation in Greg Egan’s “Reasons to Be Cheerful.”’ Journal of Science Fiction and Philosophy 1, 1–15.Google Scholar
Cyr, T. (2019a). Moral Responsibility, Luck, and Compatibilism. Erkenntnis 84(1), 193–214.Google Scholar
Cyr, T. (2019b). Why Compatibilists Must Be Internalists. The Journal of Ethics 23(4), 473–484.Google Scholar
Cyr, T. (2020a). Manipulation and Constitutive Luck. Philosophical Studies 177(8), 2381–2394.Google Scholar
Cyr, T. (2020b). Manipulation Arguments and Libertarian Accounts of Free Will. Journal of the American Philosophical Association 6(1), 57–73.Google Scholar
Cyr, T. and Vicens, L. (forthcoming). Election and Human Agency. In van Driel, E., ed., The T&T Clark Companion to Election. T&T Clark.Google Scholar
Cyril of Alexandria. (2015). On the Unity of Christ. Trans. J. McGuckin. St Vladimir’s Press.Google Scholar
Davey, K., and Clifton., R. (2001). Insufficient Reason in the “New Cosmological Argument.” Religious Studies 37(4), 485–490.Google Scholar
Davies, B. (2011). Thomas Aquinas on God and Evil. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Deery, O., and Nahmias., E. (2017). Defeating Manipulation Arguments: Interventionist Causation and Compatibilist Sourcehood. Philosophical Studies 174(5), 1255–1276.Google Scholar
Della Rocca, M. (2010). PSR. Philosophers’ Imprint 10, 1–13.Google Scholar
Demetriou, K. (2010). The Soft-Line Solution to Pereboom’s Four-Case Argument. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 88, 595–617.Google Scholar
DePoe, J. (2014). On the Epistemological Framework for Skeptical Theism. In Dougherty, T. and McBrayer, J., eds., Skeptical Theism: New Essays. Oxford University Press, 32–44.Google Scholar
Dodds, M. (2012). Unlocking Divine Action: Contemporary Science & Thomas Aquinas. The Catholic University of America Press.Google Scholar
Dole, A. (2009). Schleiermacher on Religion and the Natural Order. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Drabkin, D. (1993). The Nature of God’s Love and Forgiveness. Religious Studies 29, 231–238.Google Scholar
Eagle, A. (2011). Deterministic Chance. Nous 45(2), 269–299.Google Scholar
Ekstrom, L. (2016). The Cost of Freedom. In Timpe, K. and Speak, D., eds., Free Will and Theism: Connections, Contingencies, and Concerns. Oxford University Press, 62–78.Google Scholar
Fergusson, D. (2018). The Providence of God: A Polyphonic Approach. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Finch, A. 2017. Revisiting the Mind Argument. In Keller, J. A., ed., Being, Freedom, and Method: Themes from van Inwagen. Oxford University Press, 118–139.Google Scholar
Finch, A. (forthcoming). Logical and Theological Fatalism. In Campbell, J., Mickelson, K. and White, V. A., eds., A Companion to Free Will. Wiley-Blackwell.Google Scholar
Fischer, J. M. (1994). The Metaphysics of Free Will: An Essay on Control. Blackwell.Google Scholar
Fischer, J. M. (2011). The Zygote Argument Remixed. Analysis 71, 267–272.Google Scholar
Fischer, J. M. (2012). Responsibility and Autonomy: The Problem of Mission Creep. Philosophical Issues 22, 165–184.Google Scholar
Fischer, J. M., and Ravizza, M. (1998). Responsibility and Control: A Theory of Moral Responsibility. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fischer, J. M., and Tognazzini, N. (2011). The Physiognomy of Responsibility. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 82, 381–417.Google Scholar
Flint, T. (1998). Divine Providence: The Molinist Account. Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Franks, W. P. (2012). Original Sin and Broad Free-Will Defense. Philosophia Christi 14(2), 353–371.Google Scholar
Freddoso, A. (1988). Introduction to L. Molina’s On Divine Foreknowledge: Part IV of De Concordia. Trans. A. Freddoso. Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Frost, G. (2014). Peter Olivi’s Rejection of God’s Concurrence with Created Causes. British Journal for the History of Philosophy, 22(4), 655–679.Google Scholar
Furlong, P. (2014). Is God the Cause of Sin? Faith and Philosophy 31(4), 422–434.Google Scholar
Furlong, P. (2019). The Challenges of Divine Determinism: A Philosophical Analysis. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Garrard, E., and McNaughton, D. (2010). Forgiveness. Acumen Publishing.Google Scholar
Gelman, A., and Nolan, D. (2002). You Can Load a Die, But You Can’t Bias a coin. The American Statistician 56, 308–311.Google Scholar
Geuras, D. (1992). In Defense of Divine Forgiveness: A Response to David Londey. Sophia 31, 65–77.Google Scholar
Gilson, E. (1956). The Christian Philosophy of St. Thomas Aquinas. Random House.Google Scholar
Glynn, L. (2010). Deterministic Chance. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 61(1), 51–80.Google Scholar
Goris, H. (1996). Free Creatures of an Eternal God: Thomas Aquinas on God’s Infallible Foreknowledge and Irresistible Will. Peeters.Google Scholar
Graham, G., and Horgan, T. (1994). Southern Fundamentalism and the End of Philosophy. Philosophical Issues 5, 219–247.Google Scholar
Grant, W. M. (2009). Aquinas on How God Causes the Act of Sin without Causing Sin Itself. The Thomist 73(3), 455–496.Google Scholar
Grant, W. M. (2010). Can a Libertarian Hold That Our Free Acts Are Caused by God? Faith and Philosophy 27(1), 22–44.Google Scholar
Grant, W. M. (2016). Divine Universal Causality and Libertarian Freedom. In Timpe, K. and Speak, D. J., eds., Free Will and Theism. Oxford University Press, 214–233.Google Scholar
Grant, W. M. (2019). Free Will and God’s Universal Causality: The Dual Sources Account. Bloomsbury Academic.Google Scholar
Green, C. (2016). A Compatibicalvinist Demonstrative-Goods Defense. In Alexander, D. and Johnson, D., eds., Calvinism and the Problem of Evil. Wipf & Stock Publishers, 233–247.Google Scholar
Grisez, G. (1975). Beyond the New Theism. University of Notre Dame Press.Google Scholar
Grössl, J. and Vicens, L. (2014). Closing the Door on Limited-Risk Open Theism. Faith and Philosophy 31(4), 475–485.Google Scholar
Haasis, H. (2013). Bombing Hitler: The Story of the Man Who Almost Assassinated the Führer. Simon and Schuster.Google Scholar
Hart, D. (2009). Providence and Causality: On Divine Innocence. In Murphy, F. A. and Ziegler, P., eds., The Providence of God: Deus Habet Consilium. T&T Clark, 34–56.Google Scholar
Hartman, R. (2017). In Defense of Moral Luck: Why Luck Often Affects Praiseworthiness and Blameworthiness. Routledge.Google Scholar
Hasker, W. (1992). The Necessity of Gratuitous Evil. Faith and Philosophy 9, 23–44.Google Scholar
Hasker, W. (1994). God the Creator of Good and Evil? In Tracy, T., ed., The God Who Acts. The Pennsylvania State University Press, 137–146.Google Scholar
Hawthorne, J. (2002). Deeply Contingent a Priori nowledge. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 65, 247–269.Google Scholar
Helm, P. (2010). God, Compatibilism, and the Authorship of Sin. Religious Studies 46, 115–124.Google Scholar
Hick, J. (1981). An Irenaean Theodicy. In Davis, Stephen T. et al., eds., Encountering Evil: Live Options in Theodicy. Atlanta: Westminster John Knox Press, 39–48.Google Scholar
Hieronymi, P. (2001). Articulating an Uncompromising Forgiveness. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 62, 529–555.Google Scholar
Hoefer, C. (2007). The Third Way on Objective Probability: A Sceptic’s Guide to Objective Chance. Mind 116(463), 549–596.Google Scholar
Howard-Snyder, F. (2006). “Cannot” Implies “Not Ought”. Philosophical Studies 130, 233–246.Google Scholar
Howsepian, A. (2007). Compatibilism, Evil, and the Free-Will Defense. Sophia 46, 217–236.Google Scholar
Hume, D. (2007). An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding. Ed. Millican, P.. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hunsinger, G. (1991). How to Read Karl Barth: The Shape of His Theology. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hütter, R. (2012). Dust Bound for Heaven: Explorations in the Theology of Thomas Aquinas. Eerdmans.Google Scholar
Irving, E. (1828). Sermons, Lectures, and Occasional Discourses: Vol. 1. The Doctrine of the Incarnation Opened in Six Sermons. R. B. Seeley and W. Burnside.Google Scholar
Jeffrey, R. (1969). Statistical Explanation vs. Statistical Inference. In Rescher, N., ed., Essays in Honor of Carl G. Hempel. Reidel, 104–113.Google Scholar
Jensen, A. (2014). Divine Providence and Human Agency: Trinity, Creation and Freedom. Routledge.Google Scholar
Johnson, D. (2016). Calvinism and the Problem of Evil: A Map of the Territory. In Alexander, D. and Johnson, D., eds., Calvinism and the Problem of Evil. Wipf and Stock, 19–55.Google Scholar
Johnson, D. (forthcoming). Doing All Things for God’s Glory, Acting So That it is God Who Acts: Kierkegaard, Edwards, and the Problem of Total Devotion. Religious Studies.Google Scholar
Judisch, N. (2012). Meticulous Providence and Gratuitous Evil. Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Religion 4, 65–83.Google Scholar
Kane, R. (1996). The Significance of Free Will. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kane, R. (2005). A Contemporary Introduction to Free Will. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kelsey, D. (2009). Eccentric Existence: A Theological Anthropology, 2 Vols. Westminster John Knox.Google Scholar
Kierkegaard, S. (1956). The Prayers of Kierkegaard. Ed. LeFevre, P. D.. University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Kierkegaard, S. (1962). Works of Love. Trans. H. and E. Hong. Harper and Row.Google Scholar
Kim, J. (1974). Noncausal Connections. Noûs 8(1), 41–52.Google Scholar
Kim, J. (1988). Explanatory Realism, Causal Realism, and Explanatory Exclusion. Midwest Studies in Philosophy 12, 225–239.Google Scholar
Kim, J. (1994). Explanatory Knowledge and Metaphysical Dependence. Philosophical Issues 5, 51–69.Google Scholar
Kittle, S. (forthcoming). God Is (Probably) a Cause among Causes. Theology and Science 22(2), 247–262.Google Scholar
Koons, R. (1997). A New Look at the Cosmological Argument. American Philosophical Quarterly 34, 193–211.Google Scholar
Koons, R. (2002). Dual Agency: A Thomistic Account of Providence and Human Freedom. Philosophia Christi 4(2), 397–410.Google Scholar
Koons, R. and Pruss, A. (2021). Skepticism and the Principle of Sufficient Reason. Philosophical Studies 178, 1079–1099.Google Scholar
Kraay, K. (2016). God and Gratuitous Evil (Part I). Philosophy Compass 11(12), 905–912.Google Scholar
Kuyper, A. (1898). Encyclopedia of Sacred Theology. Trans. J. DeVries. Charles Scribner’s Sons.Google Scholar
Kvanvig, J. (2011). Destiny and Deliberation: Essays in Philosophical Theology. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Lee, B. S. (2013). Christ’s Sinful Flesh: Edward Irving's Christological Theology Within the Context of His Life and Times. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Leftow, B. (2009). Aquinas, Divine Simplicity, and Divine Freedom. In Timpe, Kevin, ed., Metaphysics and God: Essays in Honor of Eleonore Stump. Routledge, 21–38.Google Scholar
Levy, N. (2011). Hard Luck: How Luck Undermines Free Will and Moral Responsibility. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Lewis, C. S. (1960). The Four Loves. Harcourt.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. (1981). Are We Free to Break the Laws? Theoria 47, 113–121.Google Scholar
Loewer, B. (2001). Determinism and Chance. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 32, 609–620.Google Scholar
Lonergan, B. (1971). Grace and Freedom: Operative Grace in the Thought of St. Thomas Aquinas. Herder and Herder.Google Scholar
Long, S., Nutt, R., and White, T. J., eds. (2017). Thomism and Predestination. Catholic University of America Press.Google Scholar
Lowe, E. J. (2008). Personal Agency. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Manela, T. (2016). Gratitude and Appreciation. American Philosophical Quarterly 53(3), 281–294.Google Scholar
Manela, T. (2019). Gratitude. In Zalta, E., ed., The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2019/entries/gratitude/.Google Scholar
Manis, Z. (2019). Sinners in the Presence of a Loving God: An Essay on the Problem of Hell. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Martin, G. (2002). A Game of Thrones. Bantam.Google Scholar
Matava, R. (2016). Divine Causality and Human Free Choice: Domingo Banez, Physical Premotion and the Controversy De Auxiliis Revisited. Brill.Google Scholar
Mawson, T. J. (1999). The Problem of Evil and Moral Indifference. Religious Studies 35(3), 323–345.Google Scholar
Mayes, G. (2021). Theories of Explanation. Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy, https://iep.utm.edu/explanat/.Google Scholar
McAleer, S. (2012). Propositional Gratitude. American Philosophical Quarterly 49(1), 55–66.Google Scholar
McBrayer, J. (2010). Skeptical Theism. Philosophy Compass 5, 611–623.Google Scholar
McCabe, H. (1987). God Matters. Templegate Publishers.Google Scholar
McCall, T. (2019). Against God and Nature: The Doctrine of Sin. Crossway.Google Scholar
McCann, H. (1995). Divine Sovereignty and the Freedom of the Will. Faith and Philosophy, 12(4), 582–598.Google Scholar
McCann, H. (2012). Creation and the Sovereignty of God. Indiana University Press.Google Scholar
McCann, H., and Johnson, D. (2017). Divine Providence. In Zalta, E., ed., Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/providence-divine/.Google Scholar
McGuckin, J. (2015). St Cyril of Alexandria and the Christological Controversy. St. Vladimir’s Seminary.Google Scholar
McKenna, M. (2008). A Hard-line Reply to Pereboom’s Four-Case Manipulation Argument. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 77, 142–159.Google Scholar
McKenna, M. and Coates, D. (2020). Compatibilism. In Zalta, E., ed., The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/compatibilism/.Google Scholar
McKenna, M., and Pereboom, D. (2016). Free Will: A Contemporary Introduction. Routledge.Google Scholar
Mele, A. (1995). Autonomous Agents. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Mele, A. (2006). Free Will and Luck. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Mele, A. (2010). Moral Responsibility for Actions: Epistemic and Freedom Conditions. Philosophical Explorations 13, 101–111.Google Scholar
Mele, A. (2019). Manipulated Agents: A Window to Moral Responsibility. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Mele, A. (2020). Moral Responsibility and Manipulation: On a Novel Argument Against Historicism. Philosophical Studies 177, 3143–3154.Google Scholar
Miller, B. (1996). A Most Unlikely God. University of Notre Dame Press.Google Scholar
Moo, D. (2013). Sin in Paul. In Morgan, C. and Peterson, R., eds., Fallen: A Theology of Sin. Crossway, 107–130.Google Scholar
Mooney, J. (2019). How to Solve the Problem of Evil: A Deontological Strategy. Faith and Philosophy 36, 442–462.Google Scholar
Murphy, J., and Hampton, J. (1988). Forgiveness and Mercy. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nagel, T. (1979). Mortal Questions. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Nahmias, E., Morris, S., Nadelhoffer, T., and Turner, J. (2006). Is Incompatibilism Intuitive? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 73, 28–53.Google Scholar
Nelkin, D. K. (2013). Freedom and Forgiveness. In Haji, I. and Caouette, J., eds., Free Will and Moral Responsibility. Cambridge Scholars Press, 165–188.Google Scholar
Nicene and Post Nicene Fathers, 2nd Series, vol 14 reprint edition (1994). Trans. and ed. H. Percival. Hendrickson Publishers.Google Scholar
O’Connor, T. (1995). Agent Causation. Reprinted in Watson, G., eds., Free Will: Second Edition. Oxford University Press, 257–284.Google Scholar
O’Connor, T. (2000). Persons and Causes: The Metaphysics of Free Will. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
O’Connor, T. (2009). Agent-Causal Power. In Handfield, T., ed., Dispositions and Causes, Mind Association Occasional Series. Oxford University Press, 189–214.Google Scholar
O’Connor, T. (2012). Theism and Ultimate Explanation: The Necessary Shape of Contingency. Wiley-Blackwell.Google Scholar
Parfit, D. (1984). Reasons and Persons. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Pawl, T., and Timpe, K. (2009). Incompatibilism, Sin, and Free Will in Heaven. Faith and Philosophy 26(4), 396–417.Google Scholar
Pelser, A. (2017). Heavenly Sadness: On the Value of Negative Emotions in Paradise. In Byerly, T. R. and Silverman, E., eds., Paradise Understood: New Philosophical Essays about Heaven. Oxford University Press, 113–135.Google Scholar
Percival, H. (ed) (1997). The Seven Ecumenical Councils of the Undivided Church. A Select Library of Nicene and Post-Nicene Fathers of the Christian Church, Second Series, vol. 14. T&T Clark.Google Scholar
Pereboom, D. (2001). Living without Free Will. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Pereboom, D. (2005). Free Will, Evil, and Divine Providence. In Dole, A. and Chignell, A., eds., God and the Ethics of Belief: New Essays in Philosophy of Religion. Cambridge University Press, 77–98.Google Scholar
Pereboom, D. (2008). Revising the Reactive Attitudes. In McKenna, M. and Russell, P., eds., Free Will and Reactive Attitudes. Routledge, 231–246.Google Scholar
Pereboom, D. (2011). Theological Determinism and Divine Providence. In Perszyk, Ken, ed., Molinism: The Contemporary Debate. Oxford University Press, 262–280.Google Scholar
Pereboom, D. (2014). Free Will, Agency, and Meaning in Life. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Pereboom, D. (2016). Libertarianism and Theological Determinism. In Timpe, K. and Speak, D., eds., Free Will and Theism: Connections, Contingencies, and Concerns. Oxford University Press, 112–131.Google Scholar
Pereboom, D. (2021). Forgiveness as Renunciation of Moral Protest. In Warmke, B., Nelkin, D., and McKenna, M., eds., Forgiveness and Its Moral Dimensions. Oxford University Press, 83–100.Google Scholar
Pereboom, D. (2021). Wrongdoing and the Moral Emotions. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Pittard, J. (2018). Evil and God’s Toxin Puzzle. Noûs 52, 88–108.Google Scholar
Pittard, J. (forthcoming). The Defeat of Evil and the Norms of Hope. Analytic Philosophy.Google Scholar
Plantinga, A. (1974a). God, Freedom, and Evil. Eerdmans.Google Scholar
Plantinga, A. (1974b). The Nature of Necessity. New York: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Plantinga, A. (1986). The Foundations of Theism: A Reply. Faith and Philosophy 3(3), 298–313.Google Scholar
Pruss, A. (2006). The Principle of Sufficient Reason: A Reassessment. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Pruss, A. (2013). Omnirationality. Res Philosophica 90(1), 1–21.Google Scholar
Pruss, A. (2016a). Divine Creative Freedom. Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Religion 7, 213–238.Google Scholar
Pruss, A. (2016b). The First Sin: A Dilemma for Christian Determinists. In Alexander, D. and Johnson, D., eds., Calvinism and the Problem of Evil. Pickwick Publications, 187–199.Google Scholar
Pruss, A. (2017). The Principle of Sufficient Reason and Probability. Oxford Studies in Metaphysics 10, 261–278.Google Scholar
Quinn, P. (2010). Sin and Original Sin. In Taliaferro, C., Draper, P., and Quinn, P., eds., A Companion to Philosophy of Religion, Second Edition. Blackwell Publishing, 614–621.Google Scholar
Railton, P. (1978). A Deductive-Nomological Model of Probabilistic Explanation. Philosophy of Science 45, 206–226.Google Scholar
Rea, M. (2007). The Metaphysics of Original Sin. In Zimmerman, D., ed., Persons: Human and Divine. Oxford University Press, 319–356.Google Scholar
Rescher, N. (1995). Satisfying Reason: Studies in the Theory of Knowledge. Kluwer.Google Scholar
Roberts, R. (2004). The Blessings of Gratitude: A Conceptual Analysis. In Emmons, R. and McCullough, M., eds., The Psychology of Gratitude. Oxford University Press, 58–79.Google Scholar
Rogers, K. (2012). The Divine Controller Argument for Incompatibilism. Faith and Philosophy 29, 275–294.Google Scholar
Rogers, E. (2015). Tanner’s Non-Competitive Account and the Blood of Christ: Where Eucharistic Theology Meets the Evolution of Ritual. In Carbine, R. and Koster, H., eds., The Gift of Theology: The Contribution of Kathryn Tanner. Fortress Press, 139–160.Google Scholar
Ross, J. (1983). Creation II. In Freddoso, A. J., ed., The Existence and Nature of God. University of Notre Dame Press, 115–141.Google Scholar
Rowe, W. (1979). The Problem of Evil and Some Varieties of Atheism. American Philosophical Quarterly 16, 335–341.Google Scholar
Ruben, D. (2012). Explaining Explanation: Updated and Expanded Second Edition. Routledge.Google Scholar
Rush, M. (2020). Motivating Propositional Gratitude. Philosophical Studies 177(5), 1191–1211.Google Scholar
Salmon, W. (2006). Four Decades of Scientific Explanation. University of Pittsburgh Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sartorio, C. (2016). Causation and Free Will. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Sayers, D. (1987). The Mind of the Maker. HarperCollins.Google Scholar
Schaffer, J. (2007). Deterministic Chance? British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 58(2), 113–140.Google Scholar
Schaffer, J. (2016). Grounding in the Image of Causation. Philosophical studies 173(1), 49–100.Google Scholar
Sehon, S. (2010). The Problem of Evil: Skeptical Theism Leads to Moral Paralysis. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 67(2), 67–80.Google Scholar
Sekatskaya, M. (2019). Double Defence Against Multiple Case Manipulation Arguments. Philosophia 47, 1283–1295.Google Scholar
Shanley, B. (1998). Divine Causation and Human Freedom in Aquinas. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 72(1), 99–122.Google Scholar
Shanley, B. (2007). Beyond Libertarianism and Compatibilism: Thomas Aquinas on Created Freedom. In Velkley, R., ed., Freedom and the Human Person. The Catholic University of America Press, 70–89.Google Scholar
Smith, A. (2007). On Being and Holding Responsible. Journal of Ethics 11, 465–484.Google Scholar
Sonderegger, K. (2009). The Doctrine of Providence. In Murphy, F. A. and Ziegler, P., eds., The Providence of God: Deus Habet Consilium. T&T Clark, 144–157.Google Scholar
Speak, D. (2013). Free Will and Soul-Making Theodicies. In McBrayer, J. and Howard-Snyder, D., eds., The Blackwell Companion to the Problem of Evil. Wiley-Blackwell, 205–221.Google Scholar
Speak, D. (2017). Free Will and the Problem of Evil. In Timpe, K., Griffith, M., and Levy, N., eds., The Routledge Companion to Free Will. Routledge, 489–499.Google Scholar
Spinoza, B. 1677 (1985). Ethics. In Curley, E., ed. and tr., The Collected Works of Spinoza, vol. 1. Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Steward, H. (2012). A Metaphysics for Freedom. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Strabbing, J. (2017). Divine Forgiveness and Reconciliation. Faith and Philosophy 34, 272–297.Google Scholar
Strabbing, J. (2020). Forgiveness and Reconciliation. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 98, 531–545.Google Scholar
Strawson, P. (1962). Freedom and Resentment. Proceedings of the British Academy 48, 1–25.Google Scholar
Strawson, G. (1998). Free Will. In Craig, E., ed., Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. www.rep.routledge.com/articles/thematic/free-will/v-1.Google Scholar
Stump, E. (2005). Aquinas. Routledge.Google Scholar
Stump, E. (2010). Wandering in Darkness: Narrative and the Problem of Suffering. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Swenson, P. (2019). Luckily, We Are Only Responsible for What We Could Have Avoided. Midwest Studies in Philosophy 43(1), 106–118.Google Scholar
Swenson, P. (forthcoming). Equal Moral Opportunity: A Solution to the Problem of Moral Luck. Australasian Journal of Philosophy.Google Scholar
Swinburne, R. (1989). Responsibility and Atonement. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Swinburne, R. (1998). Providence and the Problem of Evil. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Talbert, M. (2019). Moral Responsibility. In Zalta, E., ed., The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2019/entries/moral-responsibility/.Google Scholar
Talbott, T. (2008). Why Christians Should Not Be Determinists: Reflections on the Origin of Human Sin. Faith and Philosophy 25(3), 300–316.Google Scholar
Tanner, K. (1988). God and Creation in Christian Theology. Fortress Press.Google Scholar
Tanner, K. (1994). Human Freedom, Human Sin, and God the Creator. In Tracy, T., ed., The God Who Acts. The Pennsylvania State University Press, 111–135.Google Scholar
Tanner, K. (1998). God and Creation in Christian Theology: Tyranny or Empowerment? Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
Taylor, R. (1991). Metaphysics, 4th ed. Prentice Hall.Google Scholar
Three Forms of Unity (2011). The Reformed Church in the United States.Google Scholar
Timpe, K. (2014). Free Will in Philosophical Theology. Bloomsbury Academic.Google Scholar
Todd, P. (2011). A New Approach to Manipulation Arguments. Philosophical Studies 152, 127–133.Google Scholar
Todd, P. (2012). Manipulation and Moral Standing: An Argument for Incompatibilism. Philosophers’ Imprint 12(7), 1–18.Google Scholar
Todd, P. (2018). Does God Have the Moral Standing to Blame? Faith and Philosophy 35(1), 33–55.Google Scholar
Tomaszewski, C. (2016). The Principle of Sufficient Reason Defended: There Is No Conjunction of All Contingently True Propositions. Philosophia 44, 267–274.Google Scholar
Tracy, T. (1994). Divine Action, Created Causes, and Human Freedom. In Tracy, T., ed., The God Who Acts. Pennsylvania State University Press, 77–102.Google Scholar
Trakakis, N. (2006). Does Hard Determinism Render the Problem of Evil Even Harder? Ars Disputandi 6, 239–264.Google Scholar
Turner, J. (2013). Compatibilism and the Free Will Defense. Faith and Philosophy 30, 125–137.Google Scholar
Turner, D. (2013). Thomas Aquinas: A Portrait. Yale University Press.Google Scholar
van Inwagen, P. (1983). An Essay on Free Will. Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
van Inwagen, P. (1988). The Place of Chance in a World Sustained by God. In van Inwagen, P., ed., God, Knowledge, and Mystery. Cornell University Press, 42–65.Google Scholar
van Inwagen, P. (1989). When Is the Will Free? Philosophical Perspectives 3, 399–422.Google Scholar
van Inwagen, P. (2008). How to Think About the Problem of Free Will. The Journal of Ethics 12(3–4), 327–341.Google Scholar
van Inwagen, P. (2017). Thinking About Free Will. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Vargas, M. (2004). Libertarianism and Skepticism about Free Will: Some Arguments against Both. Philosophical Topics 32, 403–426.Google Scholar
Vicens, L. (2012a). Divine Determinism: A Critical Consideration. Ph. D. Dissertation, University of Wisconsin–Madison.Google Scholar
Vicens, L. (2012b). Divine Determinism, Human Freedom, and the Consequence Argument. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 71, 145–155.Google Scholar
Vicens, L. (2021). Theological Determinism. Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy, https://iep.utm.edu/theo-det/.Google Scholar
Vicens, L. (2022). Sin and the Faces of Responsibility. In Knight, J. and Markham, I., eds., The Craft of Innovative Theology. Wiley Blackwell.Google Scholar
Vicens, L., and Kittle, S. (2019). God and Human Freedom. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Vihvelin, K. (2013). Causes, Laws, and Free Will: Why Determinism Doesn’t Matter. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Vitale, V. (2012). Horrendous Evils and the Ethical Perfection of God. Ph.D. Dissertation, Worcester College, University of Oxford.Google Scholar
Vitale, V. (2021). Non-Identity Theodicy: A Grace-Based Response to the Problem of Evil. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Wallace, R. (1994). Responsibility and the Moral Sentiments. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Waller, R. (2014). The Threat of Effective Intentions to Moral Responsibility in the Zygote Argument. Philosophia 42, 209–222.Google Scholar
Warmke, B. (2016). The Economic Model of Forgiveness. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 97, 570–589.Google Scholar
Warmke, B. (2017). Divine Forgiveness II: Reconciliation and Debt-Cancellation Theories. Philosophy Compass 12(9).Google Scholar
Watson, G. (1987). Free Action and Free Will. Mind 96, 145–172.Google Scholar
Watson, G. (1996). Two Faces of Responsibility. Philosophical Topics 24, 224–248.Google Scholar
Watson, G. (1999). Soft Libertarianism and Hard Compatibilism. Journal of Ethics 3, 353–368.Google Scholar
Webster, J. (2009). On the Theology of Providence. In Murphy, F. A. and Ziegler, P., eds., The Providence of God: Deus Habet Consilium. T&T Clark, 158–176.Google Scholar
White, H. (2016). Theological Determinism and the “Authoring Sin” Objection. In Alexander, D. and Johnson, D., eds., Calvinism and the Problem of Evil. Pickwick Publications, 78–95.Google Scholar
White, H. (2019). Fate and Free Will: A Defense of Theological Determinism. University of Notre Dame Press.Google Scholar
Williams, R. (2000). On Christian Theology. Blackwell.Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. (2001). Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, trans. C. K. Ogden. Routledge Classics, 2nd ed. Routledge.Google Scholar
Woodward, J., and Ross., L. (2021). Scientific Explanation. In Zalta, E., ed., The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2021/entries/scientific-explanation/.Google Scholar
Zaibert, L. (2009). The Paradox of Forgiveness. Journal of Moral Philosophy 6, 365–393.Google Scholar
Zimmerman, M. (2002). Taking Luck Seriously. Journal of Philosophy 99(11), 553–576.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Bibliography
  • Edited by Peter Furlong, Valencia College, Florida, Leigh Vicens, Augustana University
  • Book: Theological Determinism
  • Online publication: 30 September 2022
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009249362.017
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • Bibliography
  • Edited by Peter Furlong, Valencia College, Florida, Leigh Vicens, Augustana University
  • Book: Theological Determinism
  • Online publication: 30 September 2022
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009249362.017
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • Bibliography
  • Edited by Peter Furlong, Valencia College, Florida, Leigh Vicens, Augustana University
  • Book: Theological Determinism
  • Online publication: 30 September 2022
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009249362.017
Available formats
×