Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-7cvxr Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-22T04:11:13.821Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

References

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 May 2022

Andreas Brekke Carlsson
Affiliation:
Inland Norway University of Applied Sciences
Get access

Summary

Image of the first page of this content. For PDF version, please use the ‘Save PDF’ preceeding this image.'
Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2022

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Adams, R. M. (1985). Involuntary sins. The Philosophical Review, 94(1), 331.Google Scholar
Adolphs, R. (2017a). How should neuroscience study emotions? By distinguishing emotion states, concepts, and experiences. Social Cognitive and Affective Neuroscience, 12(1), 2431.Google Scholar
Adolphs, R. (2017b). Reply to Barrett: Affective neuroscience needs objective criteria for emotions. Social Cognitive and Affective Neuroscience, 12(1), 3233.Google Scholar
Alicke, M. D. (2000). Culpable control and the psychology of blame. Psychological Bulletin, 126(4), 556574.Google Scholar
Alicke, M. D., Davis, T. L., & Pezzo, M. V. (1994). A posteriori adjustment of a priori decision criteria. Social Cognition, 12(4), 281308.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Alicke, M. D., Rose, D., & Bloom, D. (2012). Causation, norm violation, and culpable control. The Journal of Philosophy, 108(12), 670696.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Aristotle. (1954). Aristotle: Rhetoric. (Rhys Roberts, W., Trans.). Modern Library.Google Scholar
Arpaly, N. (2000). On acting rationally against one’s best judgment. Ethics, 110(3), 488513.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Arpaly, N. (2006). Meaning, merit, and human bondage. Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Arpaly, N., & Schroeder, T. (2014). In praise of desire. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Baier, A. (1990). What emotions are about. Philosophical Perspectives, 4(2), 129.Google Scholar
Baker, K. (2011). The myth of the home run that drove an angels pitcher to suicide. The Atlantic (October 27, 2011).Google Scholar
Barrett, L. F. (2017a). How emotions are made: The secret life of the brain. Houghton Mifflin Harcourt.Google Scholar
Barrett, L. F. (2017b). The theory of constructed emotion: An active inference account of interoception and categorization. Social Cognitive and Affective Neuroscience, 12(1), 123.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Barrett, L. F. (2017c). Functionalism cannot save the classical view of emotion. Social Cognitive and Affective Neuroscience, 12(1), 3436.Google Scholar
Bastian, B., Jetten, J., & Fasoli, F. (2011). Cleansing the soul by hurting the flesh: The guilt-reducing effect of pain. Psychological Science, 22(3), 334335.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Baumeister, R. F. (1990). Suicide as escape from self. Psychological Review, 97(1), 90113.Google Scholar
Baumeister, R. F., Stillwell, A. M., & Heatherton, T. F. (1994). Guilt: An interpersonal approach. Psychological Bulletin, 115(2), 243267.Google Scholar
Beardsley, E. L. (1970). Moral disapproval and moral indignation. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 31(2), 161176.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bell, M. (2013). The standing to blame. In Coates, D. J. & Tognazzini, N. (Eds.), Blame: Its nature and norms (pp. 263281). Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Benbaji, H. (2013). How is recalcitrant emotion possible? Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 91(3), 577599.Google Scholar
Bennett, C. (2002). The varieties of retributive experience. The Philosophical Quarterly, 52(207), 145163.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Björnsson, G. (2017a). Explaining (away) the epistemic condition on moral responsibility. In Robichaud, P. & Wieland, J. W. (Eds.), Responsibility: The epistemic condition (pp. 146162). Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Björnsson, G. (2017b). Explaining away epistemic skepticism about culpability. In Shoemaker, D. (Ed.), Oxford studies in agency and responsibility (pp. 141164). Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Björnsson, G. (2017c). Review of Rik Peels, responsible belief: A theory in ethics and epistemology. Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews. https://ndpr.nd.edu/reviews/responsible-belief-a-theory-in-ethics-and-epistemology/Google Scholar
Björnsson, G. (2020a). Being implicated: On the fittingness of guilt and indignation over outcomes. Philosophical Studies, 178, 35433560. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-021-01613-4Google Scholar
Björnsson, G. (2020b). Collective responsibility and collective obligations without collective agents. In Bazargan-Forward, S. & Tollefsen, D. (Eds.), The Routledge handbook of collective responsibility (pp. 127141). Routledge.Google Scholar
Björnsson, G. (n.d.). Skills, values, and demands: A map of blame and its surroundings. Manuscript.Google Scholar
Björnsson, G., & Persson, K. (2012). The explanatory component of moral responsibility. Noûs, 46(2), 326354.Google Scholar
Blanchfield, A. W., Hardy, J., De Morree, H. M., Staiano, W., & Marcora, S. M. (2014). Talking yourself out of exhaustion: The effects of self-talk on endurance performance. Medicine and Science in Sports and Exercise, 46(5), 9981007.Google Scholar
Boehm, C. (1999). Hierarchy in the forest: The evolution of egalitarian behavior. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Bok, H. (1998). Freedom and responsibility. Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Brady, M. S. (2007). Recalcitrant emotions and visual illusions. American Philosophical Quarterly, 44(3), 273284.Google Scholar
Brady, M. S. (2009). The irrationality of recalcitrant emotions. Philosophical Studies, 145(3), 413430.Google Scholar
Brink, D. O., & Nelkin, D. (2013). Fairness and the architecture of responsibility. In Shoemaker, D. (Ed.), Oxford studies in agency and responsibility Volume 1 (pp. 284313). Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Brink, D. O., & Nelkin, D. (in press). The nature and significance of blame. In Doris, J. & Vargas, M. (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of moral psychology. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Brown, J. (2020). What is epistemic blame? Noûs, 54, 389407.Google Scholar
Brownstein, M. (2018). Self-control and overcontrol: Conceptual, ethical, and ideological issues in positive psychology. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 9(3), 585606.Google Scholar
Bryant, R. A., & Guthrie, R. M. (2007). Maladaptive self-appraisals before trauma exposure predict posttraumatic stress disorder. Journal of Consulting and Clinical Psychology, 75(5), 812815.Google Scholar
Calhoun, C. (2004). Subjectivity and emotion. In Solomon, R. C. (Ed.), Thinking about feeling: Contemporary philosophers on emotions (pp. 107124). Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Callard, A. (2017). The reason to be angry forever. In Cherry, M. & Flanagan, O. (Eds.), The moral psychology of anger (pp. 123137). Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
Carlsson, A. B. (2017). Blameworthiness as deserved guilt. The Journal of Ethics, 21(1), 89115.Google Scholar
Carlsson, A. B. (2019). Shame and attributability. In Shoemaker, D. (Ed.), Oxford studies in agency and responsibility, Vol. 6 (pp. 112139). Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Caruso, G. D. (2021). Rejecting retributivism: Free will, punishment, and criminal justice. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Cherry, M. (2018). The errors and limitations of our ‘anger-evaluating’ ways. In Cherry, M. & Flanagan, O. (Eds.), The moral psychology of anger (pp. 4966). Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
Chislenko, E. (2019). Blame and protest. The Journal of Ethics, 23(2), 163181.Google Scholar
Clarke, R. (2013). Some theses on desert. Philosophical Explorations, 16(2), 153164.Google Scholar
Clarke, R. (2016). Moral responsibility, guilt, and retributivism. The Journal of Ethics, 20(1–3), 121137.Google Scholar
Clarke, R. (Forthcoming). Still guilty. Philosophical Studies.Google Scholar
Coates, D. J. (2017). A wholehearted defense of ambivalence. The Journal of Ethics, 21(4), 419444.Google Scholar
Coates, D. J., & Tognazzini, N. (2013). The contours of blame. In Coates, D. J. & Tognazzini, N. (Eds.), Blame: Its nature and norms (pp. 326). Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Coleman, J., & Sarch, A. (2012). Blameworthiness and time. Legal Theory, 18, 101137.Google Scholar
Connelly, K. (n.d.). Blame and respect. Manuscript.Google Scholar
Coplan, R. J., & Armer, M. (2005). Talking yourself out of being shy: Shyness, expressive vocabulary, and socioemotional adjustment in preschool. Merrill-Palmer Quarterly, 51, 2041.Google Scholar
Craig, T. K. J., & Brown, G. W. (1984). Goal frustration and life events in the aetiology of painful gastrointestinal disorder. Journal of Psychosomatic Research, 28(5), 411421.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Dancy, J. (2004). Ethics without principles. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
D’Arms, J. (2005). Two arguments for sentimentalism. Philosophical Issues, 15, 121.Google Scholar
D’Arms, J. (2013). Value and the regulation of the sentiments. Philosophical Studies, 163(1), 313.Google Scholar
D’Arms, J., & Jacobson, D. (1994). Expressivism, morality, and the emotions. Ethics, 104(4), 739763.Google Scholar
D’Arms, J., & Jacobson, D. (2000). The moralistic fallacy: On the ‘appropriateness’ of emotions. Philosophical and Phenomenological Research, 61, 6590.Google Scholar
D’Arms, J., & Jacobson, D. (2003). The significance of recalcitrant emotions (or, antiquasijudgmentalism). Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplements, 52, 127145.Google Scholar
D’Arms, J., & Jacobson, D. (2017). Whither sentimentalism? On fear, the fearsome, and the dangerous. In Debes, R. & Stueber, K. (Eds.), Ethical sentimentalism: New perspectives (pp. 230249). Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
D’Arms, J., & Jacobson, D. (Forthcoming). Rational sentimentalism. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Darwall, S. (2006). The second-person standpoint: Morality, respect, and accountability. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Darwall, S. (2010). But it would be wrong. Social Philosophy and Policy, 27(2), 135157.Google Scholar
Davidson, D. (1985). Incoherence and irrationality. Dialectica, 39(4), 345354.Google Scholar
Davidson, D. (2006a). How is weakness of will possible? In The essential Donald Davidson (pp. 7289). Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Davidson, D. (2006b). Paradoxes of irrationality. In The essential Donald Davidson (pp. 138152). Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
De Hooge, I. E. (2012). The exemplary social emotion guilt: Not so relationship-oriented when another person repairs for you. Cognition and Emotion, 26(7), 11891207.Google Scholar
Deigh, J. (1994). Cognitivism in the theory of emotions. Ethics, 104(4), 824854.Google Scholar
Dennett, D. (1984). Elbow room: The varieties of free will worth wanting. MIT Press.Google Scholar
Dennett, D. (2003). Freedom evolves. Viking.Google Scholar
Dennett, D., & Caruso, G. D. (2020). Just deserts. Polity Press.Google Scholar
Deonna, J. A., & Teroni, F. (2012a). From justified emotions to justified evaluative judgements. Dialogue, 51(1), 5577.Google Scholar
Deonna, J. A., & Teroni, F. (2012b). The emotions: A philosophical introduction. Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dill, B., & Darwall, S. (2014). Moral psychology as accountability. In D’Arms, J. & Jacobson, D. (Eds.), Moral psychology & human agency: Philosophical essays on the science of ethics (pp. 4083). Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Donohue, M. R., & Tully, E. C. (2019). Reparative prosocial behaviors alleviate children’s guilt. Developmental Psychology, 55, 21022113.Google Scholar
Döring, S. A. (2015). What’s wrong with recalcitrant emotions? From irrationality to challenge of agential identity. Dialectica, 69(3), 381402.Google Scholar
Driver, J. (1992). The suberogatory. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 70(3), 286295.Google Scholar
Duggan, A. P. (2018). Moral responsibility as guiltworthiness. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 21(2), 291309.Google Scholar
Duggan, A. P. (n.d.). A genealogy of retributive intuitions. Manuscript.Google Scholar
Duhigg, C. (2019). The real roots of American rage. The Atlantic. January/February. www.theatlantic.com/magazine/archive/2019/01/charles-duhigg-american-angerGoogle Scholar
Ebels‐Duggan, K. (2019). Beyond words: Inarticulable reasons and reasonable commitments. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 98(3), 623641.Google Scholar
Ellsworth, P. C., & Tong, E. M. (2006). What does it mean to be angry at yourself? Categories, appraisals, and the problem of language. Emotion, 6(4), 572586.Google Scholar
Enoch, D., & Marmor, A. (2007). The case against moral luck. Law and Philosophy, 26(4), 405436.Google Scholar
Fehr, E., & Gächter, S. (2002). Altruistic punishment in humans. Nature, 415(6868), 137140.Google Scholar
Feinberg, J. (1970). Justice and personal desert. In Doing & deserving: Essays in the theory of responsibility (pp. 55–94). Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Fischer, J. M. (1994). The metaphysics of free will. Blackwell.Google Scholar
Fischer, J. M. (2007). Compatibilism. In Fischer, J. M., Kane, R., Pereboom, D., & Vargas, M. (Eds.), Four views on free will. Blackwell.Google Scholar
Fischer, J. M., & Ravizza, M. (2000). Responsibility and control: A theory of moral responsibility. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Foot, P. (1978). Virtues and vices. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Frank, R. (1988). Passions within reasons. Norton.Google Scholar
Frankfurt, H. (1969). Alternate possibilities and moral responsibility. Journal of Philosophy, 68, 520.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Franklin, C. E. (2013). Valuing blame. In Coates, D. J. & Tognazzini, N. A. (Eds.), Blame: Its nature and norms (pp. 207223). Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Fricker, M. (2016). What’s the point of blame? A paradigm based explanation. Noûs, 50, 165183.Google Scholar
Frijda, N. H. (1986). The emotions. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Frijda, N. H. (1994). The lex talionis: On vengeance. In van Goozen, S., Van de Poll, N. E., & Sergeant, J. A. (Eds.), Emotions: Essays on emotion theory (pp. 263289). Psychology Press.Google Scholar
Gibbard, A. (1990). Wise choices, apt feelings: A theory of normative judgment. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Gintis, H., Smith, E. A., & Bowles, S. (2001). Costly signaling and cooperation. Journal of Theoretical Biology, 213(1), 103119.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Girodo, M., & Wood, D. (1979). Talking yourself out of pain: The importance of believing that you can. Cognitive Therapy and Research, 3(1), 2333.Google Scholar
Goldberg, J. H., Lerner, J. S., & Tetlock, P. E. (1999). Rage and reason: The psychology of the intuitive prosecutor. European Journal of Social Psychology, 29(5–6), 781795.Google Scholar
Gollwitzer, M., & Denzler, M. (2009). What makes revenge sweet: Seeing the offender suffer or delivering a message? Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 45(4), 840844.Google Scholar
Graham, P. A. (2014). A sketch of a theory of moral blameworthiness. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 88(2), 388409.Google Scholar
Greenspan, P. S. (1988). Emotions and reasons: An inquiry into emotional justification. Routledge & Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Greenspan, P. S. (1992). Subjective guilt and responsibility. Mind, 101(402), 287303.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Greenspan, P. S. (1995). Practical guilt: Moral dilemmas, emotions, and social norms. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Griffiths, P. (1997). What emotions really are. University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Gross, T. (2019). Conan O’Brien needs a friend’ is a joke name for a Podcast—Sort of. Fresh Air. NPR, 2 Oct. 2019. Radio.Google Scholar
Haidt, J. (2003). The moral emotions. In Davidson, R. J., Sherer, K. R., & Goldsmith, H. H. (Eds.), Handbook of affective sciences (pp. 852870). Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Haidt, J., Sabini, J., Gromet, D., & Darley, J. (2010). What exactly makes revenge sweet? How anger is satisfied in real life and at the movies [Unpublished manuscript]. Retrieved October 7, 2019, from https://bit.ly/35858c6Google Scholar
Haji, I. (1998). Moral accountability. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hanser, M. (2005). Permissibility and practical inference. Ethics, 115(3), 443470.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hardy, J. (2006). Speaking clearly: A critical review of the self-talk literature. Psychology of Sport and Exercise, 7(1), 8197.Google Scholar
Hardy, J., Hall, C. R., & Alexander, M. R. (2001). Exploring self-talk and affective states in sport. Journal of Sports Sciences, 19(7), 469475.Google Scholar
Harman, G. (2009). Guilt-free morality. In Shafer-Landau, R. (Ed.), Oxford studies in metaethics, Vol. 4 (pp. 203214). Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hatzigeorgiadis, A., Zourbanos, N., Goltsios, C., & Theodorakis, Y. (2008). Investigating the functions of self-talk: The effects of motivational self-talk on self-efficacy and performance in young tennis players. The Sport Psychologist, 22(4), 458471.Google Scholar
Helm, B. W. (2001). Emotional reason: Deliberation, motivation, and the nature of value. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Helm, B. W. (2015). Emotions and recalcitrance: Reevaluating the perceptual model. Dialectica, 69(3), 417433.Google Scholar
Hieronymi, P. (2001). Articulating an uncompromising forgiveness. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 62(3), 529555.Google Scholar
Hieronymi, P. (2004). The force and fairness of blame. Philosophical Perspectives, 18(1), 115148.Google Scholar
Howard, C. (2018). Fittingness. Philosophy Compass, 13(11), e12542.Google Scholar
Inbar, Y., Pizarro, D. A., Gilovich, T., & Ariely, D. (2013). Moral masochism: On the connection between guilt and self-punishment. Emotion, 13(1), 1418.Google Scholar
Izard, C. E. (1997). Emotions and facial expressions: A perspective from differential emotions theory. In Russell, J. A. & Dols, J. M. F. (Eds.), The psychology of facial expression, Vol. 10 (pp. 5777). Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Jäger, C., & Bartsch, A. (2006). Meta-emotions. Grazer Philosophische Studien, 73(1), 179204.Google Scholar
Jaggar, A. M. (1989). Love and knowledge: Emotion in feminist epistemology. Inquiry, 32(2), 151176.Google Scholar
James, W. (1894). Discussion: The physical basis of emotion. Psychological Review, 1(5), 516529.Google Scholar
Janoff-Bulman, R. (1979). Characterological versus behavioral self-blame: Inquiries into depression and rape. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 37(10), 17981809.Google Scholar
Jaworska, A. (2007). Caring and internality. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 74(3), 529568.Google Scholar
Jeppsson, S. (2016). Accountability, answerability, and freedom. Social Theory and Practice, 42(4), 681705.Google Scholar
Jones, K. (2003). Emotions, weakness of will, and the normative conception of agency. Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplements, 52, 181200.Google Scholar
Jones, W. H., & Kugler, K. (1993). Interpersonal correlates of the Guilt Inventory. Journal of Personality Assessment, 61(2), 246258.Google Scholar
Kalis, A. (2018). Self‐control as a normative capacity. Ratio, 31, 6580.Google Scholar
Kant, I. (17971963). The Metaphysical elements of justice, Ladd, John, tr. Bobbs-Merrill.Google Scholar
Kassinove, H., Sukhodolsky, D. G., Tsytsarev, S. V., & Solovyova, S. (1997). Self-reported anger episodes in Russia and America. Journal of Social Behavior and Personality, 12(2), 301324.Google Scholar
Ketelaar, T., & Tung Au, W. (2003). The effects of feelings of guilt on the behaviour of uncooperative individuals in repeated social bargaining games: An affect-as-information interpretation of the role of emotion in social interaction. Cognition and Emotion, 17(3), 429453.Google Scholar
Khoury, A. C. (2018). The objects of moral responsibility. Philosophical Studies, 175(6), 13571381.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Khoury, A. C., & Matheson, B. (2018). Is blameworthiness forever? Journal of the American Philosophical Association, 4(2), 204224.Google Scholar
King, M. (2019). Skepticism about the standing to blame. In Shoemaker, D. (Ed.), Oxford studies in agency and responsibility, Vol. 6 (pp. 265288). Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kneer, M., & Machery, E. (2019). No luck for moral luck. Cognition, 182, 331348.Google Scholar
Kolodny, N. (2005). Why be rational?. Mind, 114(455), 509563.Google Scholar
Korsgaard, C. (1996). The sources of normativity. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Korsgaard, C. M. (2009). Self-constitution: Agency, identity, and integrity. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Lamb, R. (1987). Objectless emotions. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 48(1), 107117.Google Scholar
Lane, A. M., Thelwell, R. C., Lowther, J., & Devonport, T. J. (2009). Emotional intelligence and psychological skills use among athletes. Social Behavior and Personality: An International Journal, 37(2), 195201.Google Scholar
Latus, A. (2001). Moral luck. In Feiser, J. (Ed.), The Internet encyclopedia of philosophy. ISSN 2161-0002, https://iep.utm.edu/Google Scholar
Lazarus, R. (1991). Emotion and adaptation. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Lazarus, R. S. (1982). Thoughts on the relations between emotion and cognition. American Psychologist, 37(9), 10191024.Google Scholar
Lenman, J. (2006). Compatibilism and contractualism: The possibility of moral responsibility. Ethics, 117(1), 731.Google Scholar
Lerner, J. S., Goldberg, J. H., & Tetlock, P. E. (1998). Sober second thought: The effects of accountability, anger, and authoritarianism on attributions of responsibility. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 24(6), 563574.Google Scholar
Lerner, J. S., & Keltner, D. (2001). Fear, anger, and risk. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 81(1), 146159.Google Scholar
Lewis, H. B. (1971). Shame and guilt in neurosis. International Universities Press.Google Scholar
Lewis, M. (1993). The development of anger and rage. In Glick, R. A. & Roose, S. P. (Eds.), The role of affect in motivation, development, and adaptation, Vol. 2. Rage, power, and aggression (pp. 148168). Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Lewis, M. (2000). Self-conscious emotions: Embarrassment, pride, shame, and suilt. In Lewis, M. & Haviland-Jones, J. M. (Eds.), Handbook of emotions, 2nd ed. (pp. 623636). Guilford.Google Scholar
Lewis, M., Alessandri, S. M., & Sullivan, M. W. (1990). Violation of expectancy, loss of control, and anger expressions in young infants. Developmental Psychology, 26(5), 745.Google Scholar
Litvak, P. M., Lerner, J. S., Tiedens, L. Z., & Shonk, K. (2010). Fuel in the fire: How anger impacts judgment and decision-making. In Potegal, M., Stemmler, G., & Spielberger, C. (Eds.), International handbook of anger (pp. 287310). Springer.Google Scholar
Luby, J. L., Barch, D. M., Whalen, D., Tillman, R., & Freedland, K. E. (2018). A randomized controlled trial of parent-child psychotherapy targeting emotion development for early childhood depression. American Journal of Psychiatry, 175(11), 11021110.Google Scholar
Macnamara, C. (2013). Taking demands out of blame. In Coates, D. J. & Tognazzini, N. (Eds.), Blame: Its nature and norms (pp. 141161). Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Macnamara, C. (2015a). Blame, communication and moral responsible agency. In Clarke, R., McKenna, M., & Smith, A. (Eds.), The nature of moral responsibility: New essays (pp. 211235). Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Macnamara, C. (2015b). Reactive attitudes as communicative entities. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 90(3), 546569.Google Scholar
Macnamara, C. (2020). Guilt, desert, fittingness, and the good. The Journal of Ethics, 24, 449468.Google Scholar
Markovits, J. (2010). Acting for the right reasons. Philosophical Review, 119(2), 201242.Google Scholar
Marušić, B. (2020). Accommodation to injustice. In Shafer-Landau, R. (Ed.), Oxford studies in metaethics, Vol. 15 (pp. 263283). Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Mason, E. (2019). Ways to be blameworthy. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Matheson, B., & Milam, P.-E. (2021). The case against non-moral blame. In Timmons, M. (Ed.), Oxford studies of normative ethics, Vol. x1.Google Scholar
McGeer, V. (2013). Civilizing blame. In Coates, D. J. & Tognazzini, N. (Eds.), Blame: Its nature and norms (pp. 162188). Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
McHugh, C. (2017). Attitudinal control. Synthese, 194(8), 27452762.Google Scholar
McKenna, M. (2008). Putting the lie on the control condition for moral responsibility. Philosophical Studies, 139(1), 2937.Google Scholar
McKenna, M. (2012). Conversation and responsibility. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
McKenna, M. (2013). Directed blame and conversation. In Coates, D. J. & Tognazzini, N. (Eds.), Blame: Its nature and norms (pp. 119140). Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
McKenna, M. (2019). Basically deserved blame and its value. Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy, 15, 255282.Google Scholar
McRae, E. (2012). A passionate buddhist life. Journal of Religious Ethics, 40, 99121.Google Scholar
Mele, A. R. (1987). Irrationality: An essay on Akrasia, self-deception, and self-control. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Mele, A. R. (1989). Akratic feelings. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 50(2), 277288.Google Scholar
Menges, L. (2017a). Grounding responsibility in appropriate blame. American Philosophical Quarterly, 54(1), 1524.Google Scholar
Menges, L. (2017b). The emotion account of blame. Philosophical Studies, 174(1), 257273.Google Scholar
Mikula, G. (1986). The experience of injustice: Toward a better understanding of its phenomenology. In Bierhoff, H. W., Cohen, R. L., & Greenberg, J. (Eds.), Justice in social relations (pp. 103124). Plenum.Google Scholar
Milam, P. E., & Brunning, L. (2018). Oppression, forgiveness, and ceasing to blame. Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy, 14(2), 143178.Google Scholar
Mill, J. S. (1991). [1861]. Utilitarianism. Reprinted in Robson, J. M. (Ed.), Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, Vol. 10 (pp. 203259). Routledge.Google Scholar
Millikan, R. G. (1984). Language, thought, and other biological categories: New foundations for realism. MIT Press.Google Scholar
Moore, M. (2009). Causation and responsibility: An essay in law, morals, and metaphysics. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Morris, H. (1976a). On guilt and innocence: Essays in legal philosophy and moral psychology. University of California Press.Google Scholar
Morris, H. (1976b). Guilt and suffering. In Morris, H. (Ed.), On guilt and innocence: Essays in legal and moral psychology (pp. 95125). University of California Press.Google Scholar
Murphy, J. (2005). Getting even: Forgiveness and its limits. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Na’aman, O. (2021). The rationality of emotional change: Toward a process view. Noûs, 55(2), 245269.Google Scholar
Nadelhoffer, T. (2006). Bad acts, blameworthy agents, and intentional actions: Some problems for juror impartiality. Philosophical Explorations, 9(2), 203219.Google Scholar
Nelissen, R., & Zeelenberg, M. (2009). When guilt evokes self-punishment: Evidence for the existence of a Dobby Effect. Emotion, 9(1), 118122.Google Scholar
Nelissen, R. M. (2012). Guilt-induced self-punishment as a sign of remorse. Social Psychological and Personality Science, 3(2), 139144.Google Scholar
Nelkin, D. K. (2011). Making sense of freedom and responsibility. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Nelkin, D. K. (2013a). Desert, fairness, and resentment. Philosophical Explorations, 16(2), 117132.Google Scholar
Nelkin, D. K. (2013b). Freedom and forgiveness. In Haji, I. & Caouette, J. (Eds.), Free will and moral responsibility (pp. 165188). Cambridge Scholars Press.Google Scholar
Nelkin, D. K. (2016). Accountability and desert. The Journal of Ethics, 20(1–3), 173189.Google Scholar
Nelkin, D. K. (2017). Blame. In Timpe, K., Griffith, M., & Levy, N. (Eds.), The Routledge companion to free will (pp. 374388). Routledge.Google Scholar
Nelkin, D. K. (2019). Guilt, grief, and the good. Social Philosophy and Policy, 36(1), 173191.Google Scholar
Nichols, S. (2007). After incompatibilism: A naturalistic defense of the reactive attitudes. Philosophical Perspectives, 21, 405428.Google Scholar
Nichols, S. (2013). Brute retributivism. In Nadelhoffer, T. (Ed.), The future of punishment (pp. 2546). Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Niedenthal, P. M., Tangney, J. P., & Gavanski, I. (1994). “If only I weren’t” versus “If only I hadn’t”: Distinguishing shame and guilt in counterfactual thinking. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 67(4), 585595.Google Scholar
Nussbaum, M. (2001). Upheavals of thought: The intelligence of emotions. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Nussbaum, M. (2004). Emotions as judgments of value and importance. In Solomon, R. (Ed.), Thinking about feelings: Contemporary philosophers on emotions (pp. 183199). Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Nussbaum, M. (2016). Anger and forgiveness. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
O’Connor, C. (2016). The evolution of guilt: A model-based approach. Philosophy of Science, 83(5), 897908.Google Scholar
Ohtsubo, Y., Matsunaga, M., Komiya, A., Tanaka, H., Mifune, N., & Yagi, A. (2014). Oxytocin receptor gene (OXTR) polymorphism and self-punishment after an unintentional transgression. Personality and Individual Differences, 69, 182186.Google Scholar
Ortony, A., Clore, G. L., & Collins, A. (1988). The cognitive structure of emotions. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Pagel, M. D., Becker, J., & Coppel, D. B. (1985). Loss of control, self-blame, and depression: An investigation of spouse caregivers of Alzheimer’s disease patients. Journal of Abnormal Psychology, 94(2), 169182.Google Scholar
Parkinson, B. (1996). Emotions are social. British Journal of Psychology, 87(4), 663683.Google Scholar
Parkinson, B. (2019). Heart to heart: How emotions affect other people. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Peels, R. (2016). Responsible belief: A theory in ethics and epistemology. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Pereboom, D. (1995). Determinism al dente. Noûs, 29(1), 2145.Google Scholar
Pereboom, D. (2001). Living without free will. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Pereboom, D. (2014). Free will, agency, and meaning in life. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Pereboom, D. (2015). A notion of moral responsibility immune to the threat from causal determination. In Clarke, R., McKenna, M., & Smith, A. M. (Eds.), The nature of moral responsibility: New essays (pp. 281296). Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Pereboom, D. (2017). Responsibility, regret, and protest. In Shoemaker, D. (Ed.), Oxford studies in agency and responsibility, Vol. 4 (pp. 121140). Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Pereboom, D. (2019). What makes the free will debate substantive? The Journal of Ethics, 23(3), 257264.Google Scholar
Pereboom, D. (2020). Forgiveness as renunciation of moral protest. In McKenna, M., Nelkin, D. K., & Warmke, B. (Eds.), Forgiveness. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Pereboom, D., & McKenna, M. (2022). Manipulation arguments. In Nelkin, D. & Pereboom, D. (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of moral responsibility. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Pickard, H. (2013). Irrational blame. Analysis, 73(4), 613626.Google Scholar
Plato. (1992). Republic. (Grube, G. M. A., Trans.). Revised by Reeve, C. D. C.. Hackett.Google Scholar
Polger, T. W. (2019). Functionalism. The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ISSN 2161-0002. Retrieved May 21, 2019, from www.iep.utm.edu/Google Scholar
Portmore, D. W. (2019a). Control, attitudes, and accountability. In Shoemaker, D. (Ed.), Oxford studies in agency and responsibility, Vol. 6 (pp. 732). Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Portmore, D. W. (2019b). Desert, control, and moral responsibility. Acta Analytica, 34(4), 407426.Google Scholar
Portmore, D. W. (2019c). Opting for the best: Oughts and options. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Price, C. (2006). Affect without object: Moods and objectless emotions. European Journal of Analytic Philosophy, 2(1), 4968.Google Scholar
Prinz, J. (2004). Gut reactions: A perceptual theory of emotion. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Prinz, J. (2005). Are emotions feelings? Journal of Consciousness Studies, 12(8–9), 925.Google Scholar
Prinz, J. J., & Nichols, S. (2010). Moral emotions. In Doris, J. M. (Ed.), The moral psychology handbook (pp. 111146). Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Quiles, Z. N., & Bybee, J. (1997). Chronic and predispositional guilt: Relations to mental health, prosocial behavior, and religiosity. Journal of Personality Assessment, 69(1), 104126.Google Scholar
Radzik, L. (2009). Making amends: Atonement in morality, law, and politics. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Räikkä, J. (2005). On irrational guilt. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 7(5), 473485.Google Scholar
Reis-Dennis, S. (2019). Anger: Scary good. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 97(3), 451464.Google Scholar
Richards, N. (1986). Luck and desert. Mind, 95(378), 198209.Google Scholar
Riek, B. M., Luna, L. M. R., & Schnabelrauch, C. A. (2014). Transgressors’ guilt and shame: A longitudinal examination of forgiveness seeking. Journal of Social and Personal Relationships, 31(6), 751772.Google Scholar
Roberts, R. C. (1988). What an emotion is: A sketch. The Philosophical Review, 97(2), 183209.Google Scholar
Roberts, R. C. (1991). What is wrong with wicked feelings? American Philosophical Quarterly, 28(1), 1324.Google Scholar
Roberts, R. C. (2003). Emotions: An essay in aid of moral psychology. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Rosch, E. (1972). Universals in color naming and memory. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 93, 1020.Google Scholar
Rosch, E. H. (1973). Natural categories. Cognitive Psychology, 4(3), 328350.Google Scholar
Rosen, G. (2015). The alethic theory of moral responsibility. In Clarke, R., McKenna, M., & Smith, A. (Eds.), The nature of moral responsibility: New essays (pp. 6588). Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Rosenstock, S., & O’Connor, C. (2018). When it’s good to feel bad: An evolutionary model of guilt and apology. Frontiers in Robotics and AI, 5(9), 114.Google Scholar
Ross, W. D. (1988). The Good and the right. Hackett.Google Scholar
Russell, P. (2004). Responsibility and the condition of moral sense. Philosophical Topics, 32(1/2), 287305.Google Scholar
Russell, P. (2017). The limits of free will. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Sartorio, C. (2016). Causation and free will. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Scanlon, T. M. (1998). What we owe to each other. Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Scanlon, T. M. (2008). Moral dimensions: Permissibility, meaning, blame. Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Scanlon, T. M. (2013a). Giving desert its due. Philosophical Explorations, 16(2), 101116.Google Scholar
Scanlon, T. M. (2013). Interpreting blame. In Coates, D. J. & Tognazzini, N. (Eds.), Blame: Its nature and norms (pp. 8499). Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Scarantino, A. (2010). Insights and blindspots of the cognitivist theory of emotions. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 61(4), 729768.Google Scholar
Scarantino, A. (2014). The Motivational theory of emotions. In D’Arms, J. & Jacobson, D., (Eds.), Moral psychology and human agency (pp. 156185). Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Scarantino, A., & Griffiths, P. (2011). Don’t give up on basic emotions. Emotion Review, 3(4), 444454.Google Scholar
Schwitzgebel, E. (2013). A dispositional approach to attitudes: Thinking outside the belief box. In Nottleman, N. (Ed.), New essays on belief: Constitution, content and structure (pp. 7599). Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
Seidman, J. (2016). The unity of caring and the rationality of emotion. Philosophical Studies, 173(10), 27852801.Google Scholar
Shabo, S. (2012). Where love and resentment meet: Strawson’s intrapersonal defense of compatibilism. Philosophical Review, 121(1), 95124.Google Scholar
Sharadin, N. (2016). Reasons wrong and right. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 97(3), 371399.Google Scholar
Shaver, P., Schwartz, J., Kirson, D., & O’Connor, C. (1987). Emotion knowledge: Further exploration of a prototype approach. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 52(6), 10611086.Google Scholar
Sher, G. (2006). In praise of blame. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Shoemaker, D. (2011). Attributability, answerability, and accountability: Toward a wider theory of moral responsibility. Ethics, 121(3), 602632.Google Scholar
Shoemaker, D. (2013). Blame and punishment. In Coates, D. J. & Tognazzini, N. (Eds.), Blame: Its nature and norms (pp. 100118). Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Shoemaker, D. (2015). Responsibility from the margins. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Shoemaker, D. (2017). Response-dependent responsibility; or, a funny thing happened on the way to blame. Philosophical Review, 126(4), 481527.Google Scholar
Shoemaker, D. (2018). You oughta know: Defending angry blame. In Cherry, M. & Flanagan, O. (Eds.), Moral psychology of the emotions. The moral psychology of anger (pp. 6788). Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
Shoemaker, D. (2019). Blameworthy but unblamable: A Puzzle of corporate responsibility. The Georgetown Journal of Law and Public Policy, 17, 897918.Google Scholar
Shoemaker, D. (2021). The forgiven. In McKenna, M., Nelkin, D., & Warmke, B. (Eds.), Forgiveness and it’s moral dimensions (pp. 2956). Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Shoemaker, D., & Vargas, M. (2019). Moral torch fishing: A signaling theory of blame. Noûs. https://doi.org/10.1111/nous.12316Google Scholar
Silfver, M. (2007). Coping with guilt and shame: A narrative approach. Journal of Moral Education, 36(2), 169183.Google Scholar
Smart, J. J. (1961). Free-will, praise and blame. Mind, 70(279), 291306.Google Scholar
Smith, A. M. (2004). Conflicting attitudes, moral agency, and conceptions of the self. Philosophical Topics, 32, 331352.Google Scholar
Smith, A. M. (2005). Responsibility for attitudes: Activity and passivity in mental life. Ethics, 115(2), 236271.Google Scholar
Smith, A. M. (2008). Control, responsibility, and moral assessment. Philosophical Studies, 138(3), 367392.Google Scholar
Smith, A. M. (2012). Attributability, answerability, and accountability: In defense of a unified account. Ethics, 122(3), 575589.Google Scholar
Smith, A. M. (2013). Moral blame and moral protest. In Coates, D. J. & Tognazzini, N. (Eds.), Blame: Its nature and norms (pp. 2748). Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Smith, A. M. (2015a). Attitudes, tracing, and control. Journal of Applied Philosophy, 32(2), 115132.Google Scholar
Smith, A. M. (2015b). Responsibility as answerability. Inquiry, 58(2), 99126.Google Scholar
Solomon, R. C. (1988). On emotions as judgments. American Philosophical Quarterly, 25(2), 183191.Google Scholar
Solomon, R. C. (2007). True to our feelings: What our emotions are really telling us. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Spelman, E. (1989). Anger and insubordination. In Garry, A. & Pearsall, M. (Eds.), Women, knowledge, and reality: Explorations in feminist philosophy (pp. 263274). Routledge.Google Scholar
Stocker, M. (1987). Emotional thoughts. American Philosophical Quarterly, 24(1), 5969.Google Scholar
Strabbing, J. T. (2019). Accountability and the thoughts in reactive attitudes. Philosophical Studies, 176(12), 31213140.Google Scholar
Strawson, G. (1986). Freedom and belief. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Strawson, P. F. (1962). Freedom and resentment. Proceedings of the British Academy, 48, 187211.Google Scholar
Stroud, S. (2006). Epistemic partiality in friendship. Ethics, 116(3), 498524.Google Scholar
Swannell, S., Martin, G., Page, A., Hasking, P., Hazell, P., Taylor, A., & Protani, M. (2012). Child maltreatment, subsequent non-suicidal self-injury and the mediating roles of dissociation, alexithymia and self-blame. Child Abuse & Neglect, 36(7–8), 572584.Google Scholar
Szigeti, A. (2015). Sentimentalism and moral dilemmas. Dialectica, 69(1), 122.Google Scholar
Talbert, M. (2012). Moral competence, moral blame, and protest. The Journal of Ethics, 16(1), 89109.Google Scholar
Tanaka, H., Yagi, A., Komiya, A., Mifune, N., & Ohtsubo, Y. (2015). Shame-prone people are more likely to punish themselves: A test of the reputation-maintenance explanation for self-punishment. Evolutionary Behavioral Sciences, 9(1), 17.Google Scholar
Tangney, J. P., & Dearing, R. L. (2002). Shame and guilt. Guilford.Google Scholar
Tangney, J. P., Stuewig, J., & Mashek, D. J. (2007). Moral emotions and moral behavior. Annual Review of Psychology, 58, 345372.Google Scholar
Tappolet, C. (2012). Emotions, perceptions, and emotional illusions. In Calabi, C. (Ed.), Perceptual illusions (pp. 205222). Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
Taylor, C. (1985). Self-interpreting animals. In Human agency and language: Philosophical papers, Vol. 1. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Teroni, F. (2007). Emotions and formal objects. Dialectica, 61(3), 395415.Google Scholar
Thomason, K. K. (2018). Naked: The dark side of shame and moral life. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Thomson, J. J. (1993). Morality and bad luck. In Statman, D. (Ed.), Moral luck. State University of New York Press.Google Scholar
Tierney, H. (2021a). Guilty confessions. In Shoemaker, D. (Ed.), Oxford studies in agency and responsibility, Vol. 7. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Tierney, H. (2021b). Hypercrisy and standing to self-blame. Analysis, 81, 262269.Google Scholar
Tilghman-Osborne, C., Cole, D. A., & Felton, J. W. (2012). Inappropriate and excessive guilt: Instrument validation and developmental differences in relation to depression. Journal of Abnormal Child Psychology, 40(4), 607620.Google Scholar
Todd, C. (2014). Relatively fitting emotions and apparently objective values. In Roeser, S. & Todd, C. (Eds.), Emotions and value (pp. 90104). Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Tognazzini, N. A. (2010). Persistence and responsibility. In Campbell, J., O’Rourke, M., & Silverstein, H. (Eds.), Time and identity. MIT Press.Google Scholar
Tognazzini, N., & Coates, D. J. (2018). “Blame.” Zalta, Edward N., ed. The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2018/entries/blame/Google Scholar
Tracy, J. L., & Robins, R. W. (2006). Appraisal antecedents of shame and guilt: Support for a theoretical model. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 32(10), 13391351.Google Scholar
Trost, Z., Vangronsveld, K., Linton, S. J., Quartana, P. J., & Sullivan, M. J. (2012). Cognitive dimensions of anger in chronic pain. Pain, 153(3), 515517.Google Scholar
Ullman, S. E. (1996). Social reactions, coping strategies, and self‐blame attributions in adjustment to sexual assault. Psychology of Women Quarterly, 20(4), 505526.Google Scholar
Van Kleef, G. A., De Dreu, C. K., & Manstead, A. S. (2004). The interpersonal effects of anger and happiness in negotiations. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 86(1), 5776.Google Scholar
Van Raalte, J. L., Brewer, B. W., Lewis, B. P., & Linder, D. E. (1995). Cork! The effects of positive and negative self-talk on dart throwing performance. Journal of Sport Behavior, 18(1), 50.Google Scholar
Van Raalte, J. L., Brewer, B. W., Rivera, P. M., & Petitpas, A. J. (1994). The relationship between observable self-talk and competitive junior tennis players’ match performances. Journal of Sport and Exercise Psychology, 16(4), 400415.Google Scholar
Vargas, M. (2004). Responsibility and the aims of theory: Strawson and revisionism. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 85(2), 218241.Google Scholar
Vargas, M. (2005). The trouble with tracing. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 29, 269291.Google Scholar
Vargas, M. (2013). Building better beings: A theory of moral responsibility. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Vargas, M. (2015). Desert, responsibility, and justification: A reply to Doris, McGeer, and Robinson. Philosophical Studies, 172(10), 26592678.Google Scholar
Vargas, M. (2019). Responsibility, methodology and desert. Journal of Information Ethics, 28(1), 131147.Google Scholar
Veling, H., Ruys, K. I., & Aarts, H. (2012). Anger as a hidden motivator: Associating attainable products with anger turns them into rewards. Social Psychological and Personality Science, 3(4), 438445.Google Scholar
Velleman, J. D. (2003). Don’t worry, feel guilty. Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplements, 52, 235248.Google Scholar
Vilhauer, B. (2004). Hard determinism, remorse, and virtue ethics. The Southern Journal of Philosophy, 42(4), 547564.Google Scholar
Walker, M. U. (1991). Moral luck and the virtues of impure agency. Metaphilosophy, 22(1/2), 1427.Google Scholar
Wallace, R. J. (1994). Responsibility and the moral sentiments. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Wallace, R. J. (2010). Hypocrisy, moral address, and the equal standing of persons. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 38(4), 307341.Google Scholar
Wallace, R. J. (2011). Dispassionate opprobrium: On blame and the reactive sentiments. In Wallace, R. J., Kumar, R., & Freeman, S. (Eds.), Reasons and recognition: Essays on the philosophy of T.M. Scanlon (pp. 348372). Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Wallace, R. J. (2019). The moral nexus. Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Waller, B. (1990). Freedom without responsibility. Temple University Press.Google Scholar
Waller, B. (2011). Against moral responsibility. MIT Press.Google Scholar
Watanabe, E., & Ohtsubo, Y. (2012). Costly apology and self-punishment after an unintentional transgression. Journal of Evolutionary Psychology, 10(3), 87105.Google Scholar
Watson, G. (1987). Responsibility and the limits of evil: Variations on a strawsonian theme. In Schoeman, F. (Ed.), Responsibility, character, and the emotions (pp. 256286). Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Watson, G. (1996). Two faces of responsibility. Philosophical Topics, 24(2), 227248.Google Scholar
Watson, G. (2004). Agency and answerability. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Watson, G. (2011). The trouble with psychopaths. In Wallace, R. J., Kumar, R., & Freeman, S. (Eds.), Reasons and recognition: Essays on the philosophy of T.M. Scanlon (pp. 307331). Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Watson, G. (2013). Standing in judgment. In Coates, D. J., & Tognazzini, N. (Eds.), Blame: Its nature and norms (pp. 282301). Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Wiggins, D. (1987). A sensible subjectivism. In Needs, values truth. Blackwell.Google Scholar
Williams, B. (1981). Moral luck. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Windsor, M. (2019). What is the uncanny? British Journal of Aesthetics, 59, 5165.Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. (1953). Philosophical investigations. Anscombe, G. E. M. & Rhees, R. (Eds.; Anscombe, G. E. M., Trans.). Blackwell.Google Scholar
Wolf, S. (2001). The moral of moral luck. Philosophic Exchange, 31(1), 1.Google Scholar
Wolf, S. (2011). Blame italian style. In Wallace, R. J., Kumar, R., & Freeman, S. R. (Eds.), Reasons and recognition: Essays on the philosophy of T. M. Scanlon (pp. 332347). Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Yang, S. (2016). Do emotions have directions of fit? Organon F, 23(1), 3249.Google Scholar
Young, L., Nichols, S., & Saxe, R. (2010). Investigating the neural and cognitive basis of moral luck: It’s not what you do but what you know. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 1(3), 333349.Google Scholar
Zeelenberg, M., & Breugelmans, S. M. (2008). The role of interpersonal harm in distinguishing regret from guilt. Emotion, 8(5), 589596.Google Scholar
Zhu, R., Shen, X., Tang, H., Ye, P., Wang, H., Mai, X., & Liu, C. (2017). Self-punishment promotes forgiveness in the direct and indirect reciprocity contexts. Psychological Reports, 120(3), 408422.Google Scholar
Zimmerman, M. J. (1987). Luck and moral responsibility. Ethics, 97(2), 374386.Google Scholar
Zimmerman, M. J. (1988). An essay on moral responsibility. Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×