Book contents
- Frontmatter
- Contents
- Acknowledgements
- Introduction: The resort to norms
- 1 Rules, norms, and actions: laying the conceptual foundations
- 2 Anarchy and the state of nature: the issue of regimes in international relations
- 3 The emergence and types of norms
- 4 The force of prescriptions: Hume, Hobbes, Durkheim, and Freud on compliance with norms
- 5 The discourse on grievances: Pufendorf and the “laws of nature” as constitutive principles for the discursive settlement of disputes
- 6 The notion of “right”
- 7 The question of “law”
- 8 The path of legal arguments
- Conclusion: The international legal order, international systems, and the comparative analysis of the practice of states
- Notes
- Index
4 - The force of prescriptions: Hume, Hobbes, Durkheim, and Freud on compliance with norms
Published online by Cambridge University Press: 01 June 2011
- Frontmatter
- Contents
- Acknowledgements
- Introduction: The resort to norms
- 1 Rules, norms, and actions: laying the conceptual foundations
- 2 Anarchy and the state of nature: the issue of regimes in international relations
- 3 The emergence and types of norms
- 4 The force of prescriptions: Hume, Hobbes, Durkheim, and Freud on compliance with norms
- 5 The discourse on grievances: Pufendorf and the “laws of nature” as constitutive principles for the discursive settlement of disputes
- 6 The notion of “right”
- 7 The question of “law”
- 8 The path of legal arguments
- Conclusion: The international legal order, international systems, and the comparative analysis of the practice of states
- Notes
- Index
Summary
RULE-TYPES AND EXPLAINING RULE-FOLLOWING
Why do actors follow rules? The argument developed in the previous chapter appears to provide an easy answer to this problem. Having stressed the problem-solving character of rules as their generic feature, we seem justified in arguing that all norms are simple instruments for arriving at a decision. By typifying and simplifying situations, rules serve as guides for action. The obvious example in this context was the instruction-type rule. Taking instruction-type rules as the prototype or model of all rules, however, would be seriously misleading because the grammar of “following a rule” is considerably wider than that of attaining one's goals through instrumental guidance. Different types of rules exist and function often “heteronomously,” i.e., instruct us what interest of others we have to take into account while making our choices. Under these circumstances instrumental explanations fail. Consider the precept of “do not lie,” which is supposed to counteract the powerful incentive “to have one's cake and eat it too.” While everybody agrees that everybody is better off in a world that works on the presumption of mutual veracity, it is obviously often to the advantage of the individual to lie. Attempts at explaining the adoption of such precepts in terms of the long-term “rational self-interest” of the actor run into serious difficulties, which already puzzled Hume.
Furthermore, unless one makes a whole host of additional (and often quite implausible) assumptions the adoption of a “regime” cannot be satisfactorily explained by utilitarian arguments.
- Type
- Chapter
- Information
- Rules, Norms, and DecisionsOn the Conditions of Practical and Legal Reasoning in International Relations and Domestic Affairs, pp. 95 - 128Publisher: Cambridge University PressPrint publication year: 1989