from Part I - Overview
Published online by Cambridge University Press: 05 June 2013
Topics: pragmatic processes; varieties of inference; explaining inferences
Overview
We have now looked at how relevance theory developed from a critique of Grice's theory of conversation, at how relevance is defined within the theory, and at the two Principles of Relevance which make predictions about our expectations of relevance in cognition in general and in communication in particular. We can now see how relevance theory explains the inferential processes involved in understanding specific acts of verbal and nonverbal communication. This chapter begins with a reminder of what kinds of pragmatic processes we expect a pragmatic theory to explain. It then considers the nature of inferential processes in general and the kinds of inferences made by humans in thinking and communicating. The first kind of inference discussed is deductive inference. This is the kind of inference captured in formal logical languages. A key feature of deductive inference is that the conclusions generated by a deductive process are guaranteed to be true as long as the initial premises are true. The next section looks at some kinds of non-deductive, or non-demonstrative, inference (the terms ‘deductive’ and ‘demonstrative’ are not technically equivalent, but most authors treat these terms and their negative counterparts as synonymous and I will follow that here since nothing important follows from this). Non-demonstrative inferences are generally, but not totally, reliable in that on some occasions when the premises are true, the conclusions will turn out to be false. After looking at a few examples of each kind of inference, the next section considers the kinds of inferences humans tend to make. It is clear that our conclusions tend not to be 100 per cent guaranteed and that this is not simply because we can never be sure of our initial premises. After looking at some more general examples, we consider the kinds of inferences which are made in understanding communication. It seems that some of the inferences we make can be understood as deductive, but not all.
To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.
Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.
Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.
To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.
To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.