Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-tf8b9 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-24T06:07:17.898Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

References

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  08 July 2021

Sarah Broadie
Affiliation:
University of St Andrews, Scotland
Get access

Summary

Image of the first page of this content. For PDF version, please use the ‘Save PDF’ preceeding this image.'
Type
Chapter
Information
Plato's Sun-Like Good
Dialectic in the Republic
, pp. 226 - 234
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2021

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Adam, J. (1902). The Republic of Plato, Books I–V, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Adam, J. (1907). The Republic of Plato, Books VI–X, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Annas, J. (1981). An Introduction to Plato’s Republic, Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Annas, J. (1999). Platonic Ethics Old and New, Ithaca: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Annas, J. (2011). Intelligent Virtue, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Annas, J. (2017). Virtue and Law in Plato and Beyond, Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Arneson, R. (2010). Good, Period. Analysis 70, 731–44.Google Scholar
Austin, J. L. (1979). ‘The Line and the Cave in Plato’s Republic’. In Austin, J. L., Philosophical Papers, edited by Urmson, J. O. and Warnock, G. J., Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 189303.Google Scholar
Bailey, D. T. J. (2006). Plato and Aristotle on the Unhypothetical. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 30, 102–26.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bailey, D. T. J. (2008). Excavating Dissoi Logoi 4. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 35, 249–64.Google Scholar
Baltzly, D. (1996). To an Unhypothetical First Principle in Plato’s ‘Republic’. History of Philosophy Quarterly 13, 149–65.Google Scholar
Barnes, J. (1991). Le soleil de Platon vu avec des lunettes analytiques. Rue Descartes 1/2, 8192.Google Scholar
Barney, R. (2008). Eros and Necessity in the Ascent from the Cave. Ancient Philosophy 28, 357–72.Google Scholar
Bedu-Addo, J. T. (1978). Mathematics, Dialectic and the Good in the Republic VI–VII. Platon 30, 111–27.Google Scholar
Benson, H. (2012). The Problem is not Mathematics but Mathematicians: Plato and the Mathematicians Again. Philosophia Mathematica 20, 170–99.Google Scholar
Benson, H. (2015). Clitophon’s Challenge: Dialectic in Plato’s Meno, Phaedo, and Republic, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Benson, H. (forthcoming). Dialectic in the Cave. In McCabe, M. M. and Trépanier, S., eds., Re-Reading Plato’s Republic, Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.Google Scholar
Berti, E. (2002). l’idea del bene in relazione alla dialettica. In Reale, G. and Scolnicov, S., eds., New Images of Plato: Dialogues on the Idea of the Good, Sankt Augustin: Academia, pp. 307–17.Google Scholar
Bloom, A. (1991). The Republic of Plato, New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Blössner, N. (2007). The City-Soul Analogy (translated from the German by Ferrari, G. R. F.). In Ferrari, G. R. F., ed., The Cambridge Companion to Plato’s Republic, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 345–85.Google Scholar
Bordt, M. (2006). Platons Theologie. Freiburg-Munich: Karl Alber.Google Scholar
Boyle, A. J. (1974). Plato’s Divided Line: Essay II: Mathematics and Dialectic. Apeiron 8, 718.Google Scholar
Broadie, S. (2005). On the Idea of the summum bonum. In Gill, C., ed., Virtue, Norms, and Objectivity: Issues in Ancient and Modern Ethics, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 4158; repr. in S. Broadie (2007), Aristotle and Beyond: Essays on Metaphysics and Ethics, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 135–52.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Broadie, S. (2007). Why No Platonistic Ideas of Artefacts? In Scott, D., ed., Maieusis: Essays in Ancient Philosophy in Honour of Myles Burnyeat, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 232–53.Google Scholar
Broadie, S. (2011). Nature and Divinity in Plato’s Timaeus, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brown, L. (2007). Glaucon’s Challenge, Rational Egoism and Ordinary Morality. In Cairns, D., Herrmann, F.-H., and Penner, T., eds., Pursuing the Good: Ethics and Metaphysics in Plato’s Republic, Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, pp. 4260.Google Scholar
Burnyeat, M. F. (1987). Platonism and Mathematics: a Prelude to Discussion. In Graeser, A., ed., Mathematics and Metaphysics in Aristotle: Acts of the Xth Symposium Aristotelicum, Bern: Haupt, pp. 213–40; repr. in Burnyeat (2012), vol. II, pp. 145–72.Google Scholar
Burnyeat, M. F. (1992). Utopia and Fantasy: the Practicability of Plato’s Ideally Just City. In Hopkins, J. and Savile, A., eds., Psychoanalysis, Mind, and Art, Oxford: Oxford University Press; repr. in G. Fine, ed., Plato 2, Oxford: University Press, pp. 279–308.Google Scholar
Burnyeat, M. F. (1997–8). Culture and Society in Plato’s Republic, The Tanner Lectures on Human Values delivered at Harvard University, https://tannerlectures.utah.edu/.Google Scholar
Burnyeat, M. F. (1998). Dissoi Logoi. In Craig, E., ed., The Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy, London: Routledge; repr. in Burnyeat (2012), vol. II, pp. 346–8.Google Scholar
Burnyeat, M. F. (2000). Plato on Why Mathematics Is Good for the Soul. In Smiley, T. J., ed., Mathematics and Necessity: Essays in the History of Philosophy, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 182.Google Scholar
Burnyeat, M. F. (2012). Explorations in Ancient and Modern Philosophy, 2 vols., Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Chambry, E. (1946). Platon, Oeuvres complètes, tome 7: La République IV–X , Paris: Belles Lettres.Google Scholar
Cherniss, H. (1947). Some War-Time Publications Concerning Plato,1. American Journal of Philology 68, 113–46.Google Scholar
Cooper, J. (1977). The Psychology of Justice in Plato. American Philosophical Quarterly 14, 151–7; repr. in J. Cooper (1999), Reason and Emotion: Essays on Ancient Moral Psychology and Ethical Theory, Princeton: Princeton University Press, pp. 138–50.Google Scholar
Cornford, F. M. (1932a). Mathematics and Dialectic in the Republic VI—VII (I). Mind 41, 3752.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cornford, F. M. (1932b). Mathematics and Dialectic in the Republic VI–VII (II). Mind 41, 173–90.Google Scholar
Cornford, F. M. (1937). Plato’s Cosmology, London: Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Cornford, F. M. (1941). The Republic of Plato, Translated with Introduction and Notes, London: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Crisp, R. (2013). In Defence of Absolute Goodness. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 87, 476–82.Google Scholar
Crombie, I. M. (1962). An Examination of Plato’s Doctrines, vol. I, London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Crombie, I. M. (1963). An Examination of Plato’s Doctrines, vol. II, London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Cross, R. C., and Woozley, A. D. (1964). Plato’s Republic: a Philosophical Commentary, London: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Delcomminette, S. (2006). Le Philèbe de Platon: introduction à l’agathologie platonicienne. Leiden: Brill.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Denyer, N. (2007). Sun and Line: the Role of the Good. In Ferrari, G. R. F., ed., The Cambridge Companion to Plato’s Republic, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 284309.Google Scholar
Dixsaut, M. (2001). Métamorphoses de la dialectique dans les dialogues de Platon, Paris: Vrin.Google Scholar
Dixsaut, M. (2005). Encore une fois le bien. In Dixsaut, M., ed., Études sur la République de Platon, vol. II, Paris: Vrin, pp. 225–55.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
El Murr, D. (2014). Why the Good? Appearance, Reality and the Desire for the Good in Republic VI, 504B–06D. Méthexis 27, 4760.Google Scholar
Emlyn-Jones, C., and Preddy, W. (2014). Plato, Republic, Volume 2, Books 6–10, Loeb Classical Library 276, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Ferber, R. (2013). ho de diôkei men hapasa psuchê kai toutou heneka panta prattei. In Notomi, N. and Brisson, L., eds., Dialogues on Plato’s Politeia, Sankt Agustin: Academia, pp. 233–41.Google Scholar
Ferrari, F. (2007). Il problema dell’ esistenza di idee di artefacta. In Vegetti, M. (2007), pp. 151–71.Google Scholar
Ferrari, F. (2013). The Idea of the Good as Cause. In Vegetti, M., Ferrari, F., and Lynch, T., eds., The Painter of Constitutions: Selected Essays on Plato’s Republic, Sankt Augustin: Academia, pp. 155–72 = Essay E in Vegetti (2003), pp. 287–326.Google Scholar
Fine, G. (1978). Knowledge and Belief in Republic V. Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 60, 121–39.Google Scholar
Fine, G. (1999). Knowledge and Belief in Republic 5–7. In Fine, G., ed., Plato 1: Metaphysics and Epistemology, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 215–46.Google Scholar
Fink, J. (2012). Introduction. In Fink, J., ed., The Development of Dialectic from Plato to Aristotle, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 123.Google Scholar
Foley, R. (2008). Plato’s Undividable Line: Contradiction and Method in Republic VI. Journal of the History of Philosophy 46, 123.Google Scholar
Franklin, L. (2013). Commentary on Nails. Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium in Ancient Philosophy 28, 102–9.Google Scholar
Frede, D. (1993). Out of the Cave: What Socrates Learned from Diotima. In Rosen, R. and Farrell, R., eds., Nomodeiktes: Greek Studies in Honor of Martin Ostwald, Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press, pp. 397422.Google Scholar
Gaiser, K. (1980). Plato’s Enigmatic Lecture ‘On the Good’. Phronesis 25, 537.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gentzler, J. (2005). How to Know the Good: the Moral Epistemology of Plato’s Republic. Philosophical Review 114, 469–96.Google Scholar
Gerson, L. (1990). God and Greek Philosophy, London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Gerson, L. (2002). The Development of the Doctrine of the Good and Plato’s Development. In Reale, G. and Scolnikov, S., eds., New Images of Plato, Sankt Augustin: Academia, pp. 379–91.Google Scholar
Gerson, L. (2015). Ideas of Good? In Nails, D. and Tarrant, H., eds., Second Sailing: Alternative Perspectives on Plato, Helsinki: Societas Scientiarum Fennica, pp. 225–42.Google Scholar
Gerson, L. (2018). What are the Objects of Dianoia? Plato Journal 18, 4553.Google Scholar
Gerson, L. (2020). Platonism and Naturalism: the Possibility of Philosophy, Ithaca: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Gertken, J., and Kiesewetter, B. (2017). The Right and the Wrong Kind of Reasons. Philosophy Compass 12, no. 5.Google Scholar
Gosling, J. C. B. (1960). Republic 5: ta polla kala. Phronesis 5, 116–28.Google Scholar
Gosling, J. C. B. (1973). Plato, London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Griffith, T. (2000). Plato: The Republic, ed. Ferrari, G. R. F., Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Grube, G., revised by Reeve, C. (1997). Republic. In Plato, Complete Works, ed. Cooper, J., Indianapolis: Hackett.Google Scholar
Hare, R. M. (1965). Plato and the Mathematicians. In Bambrough, R., ed., New Essays on Plato and Aristotle, London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, pp. 2138.Google Scholar
Harte, V. (2008). Plato’s Metaphysics. In Fine, G., ed., The Oxford Handbook of Plato, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 191220.Google Scholar
Hobbs, A. (2007). Plato on War. In Scott, D., ed., Maieusis: Essays in Ancient Philosophy in Honour of Myles Burnyeat, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 176–95.Google Scholar
Irwin, T. H. (1977). Plato’s Heracliteanism. Philosophical Quarterly 27, 113.Google Scholar
Irwin, T. H. (1995). Plato’s Ethics, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Jenkins, M. (2015). Early Education in Plato’s Republic. British Journal for the History of Philosophy 23, 843–63.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Johansen, T. K. (2013). Timaeus in the Cave. In Boys-Stones, G., El Murr, D., and Gill, C., eds., The Platonic Art of Philosophy, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 90109.Google Scholar
Joseph, H. W. B. (1948). Knowledge and the Good in Plato’s Republic, London: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Jowett, B. (1892). The Dialogues of Plato, Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Kahn, C. (2012). The Philosophical Importance of the Dialogue Form for Plato. In Fink, J., ed., The Development of Dialectic from Plato to Aristotle, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 158–73.Google Scholar
Karasmanis, V. (1988). Plato’s Republic: the Line and the Cave. Apeiron 21, 147–21.Google Scholar
Karasmanis, V. (2004). Dialectic and the Good in Plato’s Republic. In Tsimbidaros, J., ed., Platon et Aristote: dialectique et métaphysique, Cahiers de Philosophie Ancienne 19, Brussels: Ousia, pp. 3150.Google Scholar
Krämer, H.-J. (1990). Plato and the Foundations of Metaphysics, ed. and tr. Catan, J., Binghamton: SUNY Press.Google Scholar
Kraut, R. (2003). Penner’s Anti-Paradeigmatism. Modern Schoolman 80, 235–43.Google Scholar
Kraut, R. (2011). Against Absolute Goodness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Lafrance, Y. (1980). Platon et la géometrie: la méthode dialectique en République 509d–511e. Dialogue 19, 4693.Google Scholar
Lear, G. R. (2006). Plato on Learning to Love Beauty. In Santas, G., ed., The Blackwell Guide to Plato’s Republic, Oxford: Blackwell, pp. 104–24.Google Scholar
Lee, D. (2007). Plato: Republic (revised edition), London: Penguin.Google Scholar
Leroux, G. (2004). Platon, La République: traduction, introduction et notes. Paris: Flammarion.Google Scholar
Lesher, J. (2010). The Meaning of ‘Saphēneia’ in Plato’s Divided Line. In McPherran, M., ed., Plato’s Republic: a Critical Guide, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 171–87.Google Scholar
Lesses, G. (1987). Weakness, Reason, and the Divided Soul in Plato’s Republic. History of Philosophy Quarterly 4, 147–61.Google Scholar
Lindsay, A. D. (1935). Plato’s Republic, London: Dent.Google Scholar
Lloyd, G. E. R. (1990). Demystifying Mentalities, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Long, A. A. (2020). Politics and Divinity in Plato’s Republic: the Form of the Good. In Leigh, F., ed., Forms, Language, and Education: S. V. Keeling Memorial Lectures in Ancient Philosophy, 2011–2018, BICS Supplement 141, London: Wiley, pp. 6987.Google Scholar
Long, A. G. (2013a). Conversation and Self-Sufficiency in Plato. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Long, A. G. (2013b). The Political Art in Plato’s Republic. In Harte, V. and Lane, M., eds., Politeia in Greek and Roman Philosophy, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 1531.Google Scholar
McCabe, M. M. (2006). Is Dialectic as Dialectic Does? The Virtue of Philosophical Conversation. In Reis, B., ed., The Virtuous Life in Greek Ethics, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 7099; repr. in McCabe (2015), Platonic Conversations, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 100–24.Google Scholar
McPherran, M. (2006). The Gods and Piety of Plato’s Republic. In Santas, G., ed., The Blackwell Guide to Plato’s Republic, Oxford: Blackwell, pp. 84103.Google Scholar
Mann, W.-R. (2006). Plato in Tübingen: a Discussion of Konrad Gaiser, Gesammelte Schriften. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 31, 349400.Google Scholar
Miller, M. (1985). Platonic Provocations: Reflections on the Soul and the Good in the Republic. In O’Meara, D., ed., Platonic Investigations, Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press, pp. 163–90.Google Scholar
Miller, M. (1999). Figure, Ratio, Form: Plato’s Five Mathematical Studies. Apeiron 32, 7388.Google Scholar
Miller, M. (2007). Beginning the ‘Longer Way’. In Ferrari, G. R. F., ed., The Cambridge Companion to Plato’s Republic, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 310–44.Google Scholar
Mohr, R. (2005). God and Forms in Plato. Las Vegas: Parmenides.Google Scholar
Molinelli, S. (2018). Dissoi Logoi: a New Commented Edition, doctoral thesis, Durham University. Available at http://etheses.dur.ac.uk/12451/.Google Scholar
Morrison, D. (2007). The Utopian Character of Plato’s Ideal City. In Ferrari, G. R. F., ed., The Cambridge Companion to Plato’s Republic, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 232–55.Google Scholar
Morrison, J. M. (1977). Two Unresolved Difficulties in the Line and Cave. Phronesis 22, 212–31.Google Scholar
Moss, J. (2008). Appearances and Calculations: Plato’s Division of the Soul. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 34, 3568Google Scholar
Moss, J. (2021). Plato’s Epistemology: Being and Seeming, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Mueller, I. (1992). Mathematical Method and Philosophical Truth. In Kraut, R., ed., The Cambridge Companion to Plato, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 170–99.Google Scholar
Nails, D. (2013). Colloquium 3: Two Dogmas of Platonism. Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium in Ancient Philosophy 28, 77101.Google Scholar
Nehamas, A., and Woodruff, P. (1997). Translation of the Phaedrus. In Cooper, J., ed., Complete Works of Plato, Indianapolis: Hackett.Google Scholar
Netz, R. (1998). Greek Mathematical Diagrams: Their Use and Their Meaning. For the Learning of Mathematics 18, 33–9.Google Scholar
Netz, R. (2003). How Propositions Begin: Towards an Interpretation of ὑπόθεσις in Plato’s Divided Line. Hyperboreus 9, 295318.Google Scholar
Netz, R. (2004). The Transformation of Mathematics in the Early Mediterranean World: From Problems to Equations, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Patterson, R. (1985). Image and Reality in Plato’s Metaphysics, Indianapolis: Hackett.Google Scholar
Patterson, R. (2007). Diagrams, Dialectic, and Mathematical Foundations in Plato. Apeiron 40, 133.Google Scholar
Penner, T. (1987). The Ascent from Nominalism, Dordrecht: Reidel.Google Scholar
Penner, T. (2007a). The Good, Advantage, Happiness and the Form of the Good: How Continuous with Socratic Ethics Is Platonic Ethics? In Cairns, D., Herrmann, F.-H., and Penner, T., eds., Pursuing the Good: Ethics and Metaphysics in Plato’s Republic, Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press. pp. 93121.Google Scholar
Penner, T. (2007b). What Is the Form of the Good the Form of? A Question about the Plot of the Republic. In Cairns, D., Herrmann, F.-H., and Penner, T., eds., Pursuing the Good: Ethics and Metaphysics in Plato’s Republic, Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, pp. 1541.Google Scholar
Penner, T. (2008). The Forms in the Republic. In Santas, G., ed., The Blackwell Guide to Plato’s Republic, Oxford: Blackwell, pp. 234–62.Google Scholar
Peterson, S. (2011). Socrates and Philosophy in the Dialogues of Plato, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Philoponus, J. (2004). Against Proclus on the Eternity of the World 1–5, trans. Kupreeva, I. and Share, M., London: Duckworth.Google Scholar
Press, G. (2002). Sun and Good from the Perspective of the History of Philosophy. In Reale, G. and Scolnicov, S., eds., New Images of Plato: Dialogues on the Idea of the Good, Sankt Augustin: Academia, pp. 237–49.Google Scholar
Price, A. W. (2011). Virtue and Reason in Plato and Aristotle, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Proclus, (1899). In Platonis Rem Publicam commentaria, vol. I, ed. Kroll, G., Leipzig: Teubner.Google Scholar
Reeve, C. (1988). Philosopher-Kings: the Argument of Plato’s Republic, Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Reeve, C. (2012). Blindness and Reorientation: Problems in Plato’s Republic, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Repellini, F. (2013). The Line and the Cave. In Vegetti, M., Ferrari, F., and Lynch, T., eds., The Painter of Constitutions: Selected Essays on Plato’s Republic, Sankt Augustin: Academia, pp. 173–98 = Essay G in Vegetti (2003), pp. 355–404.Google Scholar
Riel, G. van (2013) Plato’s Gods, Farnham: Ashgate.Google Scholar
Robinson, R. (1953). Plato’s Earlier Dialectic, 2nd ed., Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Rorty, A. (2012). The Use and Abuse of Morality. Journal of Ethics 16, 113.Google Scholar
Rose, L. (1966). Plato’s Unhypothetical Principle. Journal of the History of Philosophy 4, 169–98.Google Scholar
Rosen, S. (2005). The Good, the Divided Line, and the Cave. In Rosen, , Plato’s Republic: a Study, New Haven: Yale University Press, pp. 255302.Google Scholar
Ross, W. D. (1953). Plato’s Theory of Ideas, Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Rowe, C. (2005). What Difference Do Forms make for Platonic Epistemology? In Gill, C., ed., Virtue, Norms, and Objectivity, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 215–32.Google Scholar
Rowe, C. (2007a). The Form of the Good and the Good in Plato’s Republic. In Cairns, D., Herrmann, F.-H., and Penner, T., eds., Pursuing the Good: Ethics and Metaphysics in Plato’s Republic. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, pp. 125–53.Google Scholar
Rowe, C. (2007b). The Place of the Republic in Plato’s Political Thought’. In Ferrari, G. R. F., ed., The Cambridge Companion to Plato’s Republic, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 2734.Google Scholar
Rowe, C. (2007c). Plato and the Art of Philosophical Writing, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Rowe, C. (2012). Plato, Republic, trans. with an Introduction and Notes, London: Penguin.Google Scholar
Rowett, C (2016). Why the Philosopher Kings Will Believe the Noble Lie. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 50, 67100.Google Scholar
Rowett, C.. (2018). Knowledge and Truth in Plato: Stepping Past the Shadow of Socrates, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Rufener, R. (2011). Der Staat/Politeia: Griechisch – Deutsch, Platon, Berlin: Deutscher Taschenbuch Verlag.Google Scholar
Sachs, D. (1963). A Fallacy in Plato’s Republic. Philosophical Review 72, 141–58.Google Scholar
Santas, G (1980/1999). The Form of the Good in Plato’s Republic. Philosophical Inquiry (Winter 1980), 374–403; repr. in G. Fine, ed. (1999), Plato I: Metaphysics and Epistemology, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 247–74. Page references are to the reprint.Google Scholar
Santas, G (2001). Goodness and Justice, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Sattler, B. (2013). The Eleusinian Mysteries in Pre-Platonic Thought: Metaphor, Practice and Imagery for Plato’s Symposium. In Adluri, V., ed., Philosophy and Salvation in Greek Religion, Berlin: de Gruyter, pp. 151–90.Google Scholar
Sayre, K. (1995). Plato’s Literary Garden: How to Read a Platonic Dialogue, South Bend: University of Notre Dame Press.Google Scholar
Schofield, M. (1997). ΑΡΧΗ. Hyperboreus, 219–35.Google Scholar
Schofield, M. (2006). Plato, Political Philosophy, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Schofield, M.. (2007). Metaspeleology. In Scott, D., ed., Maieusis: Essays in Ancient Philosophy in Honour of Myles Burnyeat, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 216–31.Google Scholar
Scott, D. (2015). Levels of Argument: a Comparative Study of Plato’s Republic and Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Sedley, D. (2007). Philosophy, the Forms, and the Art of Ruling. In Ferrari, G. R. F., ed., The Cambridge Companion to Plato’s Republic, Cambridge: Cambridge University press, pp. 256–83.Google Scholar
Sedley, D. (2013). Socratic Intellectualism in the Republic’s Central Digression. In Boys-Stones, G., El Murr, D., and Gill, C., eds., The Platonic Art of Philosophy, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 7089.Google Scholar
Sedley, D. (2016). An Introduction to Plato’s Theory of Forms. Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 78, 322.Google Scholar
Shields, C. (2007). Forcing Goodness in Plato’s Republic. Social Philosophy and Policy 24, 2139.Google Scholar
Shields, C. (2008). Surpassing in Dignity and Power: the Metaphysics of Goodness in Plato’s Republic. Philosophical Inquiry 30, 117.Google Scholar
Shorey, P. (1895). The Idea of the Good in Plato’s Republic. Classical Philology 1, 188239.Google Scholar
Shorey, P. (1935). The Republic, with English translation, Loeb Classical Library, 2 vols., London: Heinemann.Google Scholar
Singpurwalla, R. (2006). Plato’s Defense of Justice in the Republic. In Santas, G., ed., Blackwell Guide to Plato’s Republic, Oxford: Blackwell, pp. 263–82.Google Scholar
Slings, S. (2003). Platonis Rempublicam recognovit brevique adnotatione critica instruxit. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Slings, S. (2005). Critical Notes on Plato’s Politeia, ed. Boter, G. and van Ophuisen, J., Leiden: Brill.Google Scholar
Smith, N. (2018). Unclarity and the Intermediates in Plato’s Discussions of Clarity in the Republic. Plato Journal 18, 97110.Google Scholar
Smith, N. (2019). Summoning Knowledge in Plato’s Republic, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Stocks, J. L. (1911). The Divided Line of Plato Rep. VI. Classical Quarterly 5, 7388.Google Scholar
Stroud, S. (2013). Good For’ supra ‘Good’. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 87, 459–66.Google Scholar
Szlezák, T. A. (2001). L’idée du bien en tant qu’archē dans la République de Platon. In Fattal, M., ed., La philosophie de Platon, vol. I, Paris: L’Harmattan, pp. 345–72.Google Scholar
Szlezák, T. A. (2003). Die Idee des Guten in Platons Politeia, Sankt Augustin: Academic Verlag.Google Scholar
Szlezák, T. A. (2015). Are There Deliberately Left Gaps in Plato’s Dialogues? In Nails, D. and Tarrant, H., eds., Second Sailing: Alternative Perspectives on Plato. Helsinki: Societas Scientiarum Fennica, pp. 243–56.Google Scholar
Taylor, C. C. W. (2008). Plato’s Epistemology. In Fine, G., ed., The Oxford Handbook of Plato. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 165–94.Google Scholar
Thomson, J. (2008). Normativity, Chicago: Open Court.Google Scholar
Vegetti, M (2000). Platone, Repubblica: traduzione a commento, vol. IV, Naples: Bibliopolis.Google Scholar
Vegetti, M (2001). Le règne philosophique. In Fattal, M., ed., La philosophie de Platon, vol. I, Paris: L’Harmattan, pp. 265–98.Google Scholar
Vegetti, M (2003) ed. La Repubblica: traduzione e commento, vol. V, Naples: Bibliopolis.Google Scholar
Vegetti, M (2005). Glaucon et les mystères de la dialectique. In Dixsaut, M. and Teisseranc, F., eds., Études sur la République de Platon 2. Paris: Vrin, pp. 2538.Google Scholar
Vegetti, M (2007) ed. La Repubblica: traduzione e commento, vol. VII, Naples: Bibliopolis.Google Scholar
Vegetti, M (2013a). Beltista eiper dunata: the Status of Utopia in the Republic. In Vegetti, M., Ferrari, F., and Lynch, T., eds., The Painter of Constitutions: Selected Essays on Plato’s Republic, Sankt Augustin: Academia, pp. 105–22 = Essay A in Vegetti (2000), pp. 107–49.Google Scholar
Vegetti, M (2013b). Dialectics: Configurations and Functions. In Vegetti, M., Ferrari, F., and Lynch, T., eds., The Painter of Constitutions: Selected Essays on Plato’s Republic, Sankt Augustin: Academia, pp. 199214 = Essay H in Vegetti (2003), pp. 405–34.Google Scholar
Vegetti, M (2013c), Megiston mathema: the Idea of the Good and its Functions. In Vegetti, M., Ferrari, F., and Lynch, T. eds., The Painter of Constitutions: Selected Essays on Plato’s Republic, Sankt Augustin: Academia, pp. 137–54 = Essay D in Vegetti (2003), pp. 253–86.Google Scholar
Vlastos, G. (1973). The Individual as Object of Love in Plato. In Vlastos, G., ed., Platonic Studies, Princeton: Princeton University Press, pp. 342.Google Scholar
Vlastos, G. (1988). Elenchus and Mathematics: a Turning-Point in Plato’s Philosophical Development. American Journal of Philology 109, 362–96.Google Scholar
Waterfield, R. (2008). Plato: Republic, a New Translation, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Weiss, R. (2012). Philosophers in the Republic, Ithaca: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
White, M. (2006). Plato and Mathematics. In Benson, H., ed., A Companion to Plato, Oxford: Blackwell, pp. 228–43.Google Scholar
White, N. (1976). Plato on Knowledge and Reality, Indianapolis: Hackett.Google Scholar
White, N. (2006). Plato’s Concept of Goodness. In Benson, H., ed., A Companion to Plato, Oxford: Blackwell, pp. 356–72.Google Scholar
Wiggins, D. (2009). What Is the Order among the Varieties of Goodness? A Question Posed by Von Wright; and a Conjecture Made by Aristotle. Philosophy 84, 175200.Google Scholar
Wolfsdorf, D. (2008). The Method ἐξ ὑποθεσέως at Meno 86e1–87d8. Phronesis 53, 3564.Google Scholar
Yang, M.-H. (2005). The Relationship between Hypotheses and Images in the Mathematical Subsection of the Divided Line of Plato’s Republic. Dialogue 44, 285312.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • References
  • Sarah Broadie, University of St Andrews, Scotland
  • Book: Plato's Sun-Like Good
  • Online publication: 08 July 2021
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009025379.006
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • References
  • Sarah Broadie, University of St Andrews, Scotland
  • Book: Plato's Sun-Like Good
  • Online publication: 08 July 2021
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009025379.006
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • References
  • Sarah Broadie, University of St Andrews, Scotland
  • Book: Plato's Sun-Like Good
  • Online publication: 08 July 2021
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009025379.006
Available formats
×