Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-mkpzs Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-22T04:01:47.913Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Bibliography

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  02 February 2023

David Ebrey
Affiliation:
Universitat de Barcelona
Get access

Summary

Image of the first page of this content. For PDF version, please use the ‘Save PDF’ preceeding this image.'
Type
Chapter
Information
Plato's Phaedo
Forms, Death, and the Philosophical Life
, pp. 313 - 324
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2023

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Primary Sources

Unless otherwise indicated, the text followed is that of the most recent Oxford Classical Text (OCT).Google Scholar
Burnet, J. 1901–7. Platonis opera, vols. 2–5. Oxford: Clarendon.Google Scholar
Duke, E. A. et al. 1995. Platonis opera, vol. 1: Tetralogias I–II. Oxford: Clarendon.Google Scholar
Sharples, R. W. 2011. “Strato of Lampsacus: The Sources, Texts and Translations,” in Desclos, M.-L. and Fortenbaugh, W. W. (eds.), Strato of Lampsacus: Text, Translation and Discussion. New Brunswick, NJ: Transaction, 5−229.Google Scholar
Slings, S. R. 2003. Platonis Respublica. Oxford: Clarendon.Google Scholar

Secondary Sources

Ackrill, J. L. 1973. “Anamnesis in the Phaedo: Remarks on 73c–75c,” in Lee, Edward N., Mourelatos, Alexander P. D, and Rorty, Richard M. (eds.), Exegesis and Argument: Studies in Greek Philosophy Presented to Gregory Vlastos. Assen: Van Gorcum, 177–95.Google Scholar
Ademollo, F. 2011. The Cratylus of Plato: A Commentary. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Ademollo, F. 2018. “On Plato’s Conception of Change,” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 55, 3583.Google Scholar
Apolloni, D. 1996. “Plato’s Affinity Argument for the Immortality of the Soul,” Journal of the History of Philosophy 34, 532.Google Scholar
Annas, J. 1982. “Aristotle on Inefficient Causes,” Philosophical Quarterly 32, 311–26.Google Scholar
Bailey, D. T. J. 2005. “Logic and Music in Plato’s Phaedo,” Phronesis 50, 95115.Google Scholar
Bailey, D. T. J. 2014. “Platonic Causes Revisited,” Journal of the History of Philosophy 52, 1532.Google Scholar
Balla, C. 2001. “Sailing Away from Antilogic: Plato’s Phaedo 90b–101e,” Ancient Philosophy 41, 113.Google Scholar
Barnes, J. 1978. “Plato: Phaedo by David Gallop,” Canadian Journal of Philosophy 8, 397419.Google Scholar
Bedu-Addo, J. T. 1979. “On the Alleged Abandonment of the Good in the Phaedo,” Apeiron 13, 104–14.Google Scholar
Bedu-Addo, J. T. 1991. “Sense-Experience and the Argument for Recollection in Plato’s Phaedo,” Phronesis 36, 2760.Google Scholar
Beere, J. 2010. “Philosophy, Virtue, and Immortality in Plato’s Phaedo,” Boston Area Colloquium in Ancient Philosophy 26, 253301.Google Scholar
Benson, H. 2015. Clitophon’s Challenge: Dialectic in Plato’s Meno, Phaedo, and Republic. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Betegh, G. 2006. “Eschatology and Cosmology: Models and Problems,” in Sassi, M. M. (ed.), La costruzione del discorso filosofico nell’età dei presocratici / The Construction of the Philosophical Discourse in the Presocratic Period. Pisa: Edizioni della Normale, 2950.Google Scholar
Betegh, G. 2009. “Tale, Theology, and Teleology in the Phaedo,” in Partenie, C. (ed.), Plato’s Myths. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 77100.Google Scholar
Betegh, G. 2013. “On the Physical Aspect of Heraclitus’ Psychology (With New Appendices),” in Sider, D. and Obbink, D. (eds.), Doctrine and Doxography: Studies on Heraclitus and Pythagoras. Berlin: De Gruyter, 225–61.Google Scholar
Betegh, G. 2014. “Pythagoreans, Orphism, and Greek Religion,” in Huffman, C. A (ed.), A History of Pythagoreanism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 149–66.Google Scholar
Betegh, G. 2016. “Review of R. Edmonds, Redefining Ancient Orphism: A Study in Greek Religion,” Gnomon 88, 742–5.Google Scholar
Betegh, G. 2020. “Plato on Illness in the Phaedo, the Republic, and the Timaeus,” in Jorgenson, C., Karfik, F., and Spinka, S. (eds.), Plato’s Timaeus. Leiden: Brill, 228–58.Google Scholar
Betegh, G. 2021a. “The Ingredients of the Soul in Plato’s Timaeus,” in Leigh, F. (ed.), Themes in Plato, Aristotle, and Hellenistic Philosophy: Keeling Lectures 2011–2018, BICS Supplement 141, 83104.Google Scholar
Betegh, G. 2021b. “Thinking with Empedocles: Aristotle on Soul as Harmonia,” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 59, 144.Google Scholar
Betegh, G. 2022. “Plato on Philosophy and the Mysteries,” in Ebrey, D. and Kraut, R. (eds.), The Cambridge Companion to Plato, 2nd ed. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 233–67.Google Scholar
Betegh, G. unpublished. “Plato and the Origins of the Concept of Body.”Google Scholar
Blank, D. L. 1986. “Socrates’ Instructions to Cebes: Plato, ‘Phaedo’ 101de,” Hermes 114, 146–63.Google Scholar
Blondell, R. 2002. The Play of Character in Plato’s Dialogues. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Bluck, R. S. 1955. Plato’s Phaedo. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Bobonich, C. 2002. Plato’s Utopia Recast. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Bossi, B. 2018. “Back to the Cock: On Gratitude and Care,” in Cornelli, G., Robinson, T., and Bravo, F. (eds.), Plato’s Phaedo: Selected Papers from the Eleventh Symposium Platonicum. Baden Baden: Academia Verlag, 7483Google Scholar
Bostock, D. 1986. Plato’s Phaedo. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Boys-Stones, G. 2004. “Phaedo of Ellis and Plato on the Soul,” Phronesis 49, 123.Google Scholar
Brandwood, L. 1992. “Stylometry and chronology,” in Kraut, R. (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Plato. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 90120. Reprinted in Ebrey and Kraut 2022a.Google Scholar
Brisson, L. 1998Plato the Myth Maker, trans. Naddaf, G.. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Brisson, L. 2019. “Can One Speak of Teleology in Plato?” in Keeling, E. and Pitteloud, L. (eds.), Psychology and Ontology in Plato. Cham: Springer, 109–23.Google Scholar
Broackes, J. 2009. “αὐτὸς καθ’ αὑτὸν in the Clouds: Was Socrates Himself a Defender of Separable Soul and Separate Forms?Classical Quarterly 59, 4659.Google Scholar
Brown, E. 2012. “The Unity of the Soul in Plato’s Republic,” in Barney, R., Brennan, T., and Brittain, C. (eds.), Plato and the Divided Self. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 5373.Google Scholar
Brown, L. 1999. “Being in the Sophist: A Syntactical Enquiry,” in Fine, G. (ed.), Plato 1: Metaphysics and Epistemology. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 455–78.Google Scholar
Burger, R. 1984. The Phaedo: A Platonic Labyrinth. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Burkert, W. 1972Lore and Science in Ancient Pythagoreanism. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Burkert, W. 1983Homo necans: The Anthropology of Ancient Greek Sacrificial Ritual and Myth. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Burnet, J. 1911. Plato’s Phaedo. Oxford: Clarendon.Google Scholar
Campbell, I. 2019. Refutation, Deduction and the Demarcation of Philosophy from Sophistry. Doctoral dissertation, Princeton University.Google Scholar
Casadesús Bordoy, F. 2013. “On the Origin of the Orphic–Pythagorean Notion of the Immortality of the Soul,” in Cornelli, G., McKirahan, R., and Macris, C. (eds.), On Pythagoreanism. Berlin: De Gruyter, 153–76.Google Scholar
Caston, V. 1997. “Epiphenomenalisms, Ancient and Modern,” Philosophical Review 106, 309–63.Google Scholar
Clay, D. 1985. “The Art of Glaukos (Plato Phaedo 108D4–9),” American Journal of Philology 106, 230–6.Google Scholar
Cooper, J. M. 1989. “Greek Philosophers on Euthanasia and Suicide,” in Brody, B. A. (ed.), Suicide and Euthanasia: Historical and Contemporary Themes. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 2429.Google Scholar
Cooper, J. M. 2004. Knowledge, Nature, and the Good: Essays on Ancient Philosophy. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Cooper, J. M. and Hutchinson, D. S. 1997. Plato: Complete Works. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett.Google Scholar
Cornford, F. M. 1935Plato’s Theory of Knowledge: The Theaetetus and Sophist of Plato. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Craik, E. M. 2014. The “Hippocratic” Corpus: Content and Context. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Crooks, J. 1998. “Socrates’ Last Words: Another Look at an Ancient Riddle,” Classical Quarterly 48, 117–25.Google Scholar
Crotty, K. 2009. The Philosopher’s Song: The Poets’ Influence on Plato. Lanham, MD: Lexington Books.Google Scholar
Curd, P. Anaxagoras of Clazomenae: Fragments and Testimonia. Toronto: Toronto University Press.Google Scholar
Damascius, . 2009. Lectures on the Phaedo, ed. Westerink, L. G.. Wiltshire: Prometheus Trust.Google Scholar
Dancy, R. M. 2004Plato’s Introduction of Forms. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Darbo-Peschanski, C. 1999. “Aitia,” in S. Settis I greci: storia, cultura, arte, societa, vol. 2.2: Una storia greca: definizione. Turin: Enaudi, 1063–84.Google Scholar
Delcomminette, S. 2018. “Plato on Hatred of Philosophy,” Review of Metaphysics 72: 2951.Google Scholar
Denniston, J. D. 1960. Greek Prose Style. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Denyer, N. 2007. “The Phaedo’s Final Argument,” in Scott, D. (ed.), Maieusis: Essays in Ancient Philosophy in Honour of Myles Burnyeat. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 8796.Google Scholar
Derrida, J. 1968. “La Pharmacie de Platon,” Tel Quel, 32, 348, and 33, 18–59.Google Scholar
Devereux, D. T. 1994. “Separation and Immanence in Plato’s Theory of Forms,” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 12, 6390.Google Scholar
Dimas, P. 2003. “Recollecting Forms in the Phaedo,” Phronesis 48, 175214.Google Scholar
Dixsaut, M. 1991. Platon, Phédon. Paris: Flammarion.Google Scholar
Dorter, K. 1982. Plato’s Phaedo: An Interpretation. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.Google Scholar
Ebert, T. 2001. “Why Is Evenus Called a Philosopher at Phaedo 61c?Classical Quarterly 51, 423–34.Google Scholar
Ebert, T. 2004. Phaidon: Übersetzung und Kommentar. Göttingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht.Google Scholar
Ebrey, D. 2013. “A New Philosophical Tool in the Meno: 86e–87c,” Ancient Philosophy 33, 7596Google Scholar
Ebrey, D. 2014a. “Meno’s Paradox in Context,” British Journal for the History of Philosophy 22, 121.Google Scholar
Ebrey, D. 2014b. “Making Room for Matter: Material Causes in the Phaedo and the Physics,” Apeiron 47, 245–65.Google Scholar
Ebrey, D. 2015. “Why Are There No Conditionals in Aristotle’s Logic?Journal of the History of Philosophy 53, 185205.Google Scholar
Ebrey, D. 2016. Review of Hugh Benson Clitophon’s Challenge: Dialectic in Plato’s Meno, Phaedo, and Republic. Notre Dame Philosophical Review.Google Scholar
Ebrey, D. 2017a. “Plato’s Phaedo,” in Dee Clayman (ed.), Oxford Bibliographies in Classics. https://www.oxfordbibliographies.com/view/document/obo-9780195389661/obo-9780195389661-0272.xml.Google Scholar
Ebrey, D. 2017b. “The Asceticism of the Phaedo: Pleasure, Purification, and the Soul’s Proper Activity,” Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 99, 130.Google Scholar
Ebrey, D. 2021. “The Phaedo’s Final Argument and the Soul’s Kinship with the Divine,” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 61, 2562.Google Scholar
Ebrey, D. 2022a. “The Unfolding Account of Forms in the Phaedo,” in Ebrey, D. and Kraut, R. (eds.), The Cambridge Companion to Plato, 2nd ed. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 268–97.Google Scholar
Ebrey, D. 2022b. Review of A. Long, Death and Immortality in Ancient Philosophy. Nous.Google Scholar
Ebrey, D. 2023. “The Phaedo as an Alternative to Tragedy,” Classical Philology 118.Google Scholar
Ebrey, D. unpublished. “Forms and the Origin of Self-Predication.”Google Scholar
Ebrey, D. and Kraut, R. (eds.). 2022a. The Cambridge Companion to Plato, 2nd ed. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Ebrey, D. and Kraut, R. 2022b. “Introduction to the Study of Plato,” in Ebrey, D. and Kraut, R. (eds.), The Cambridge Companion to Plato, 2nd ed. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1–38.Google Scholar
Edmonds, R. G. 2004. Myths of the Underworld Journey: Plato, Aristophanes, and the “Orphic” Gold Tablets. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Edmonds, R. G. 2013. Redefining Ancient Orphism: A Study in Greek Religion. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Edmonds, R. G. 2017. “Alcibiades the Profane: Images of the Mysteries,” in Destrée, P. and Giannopoulou, Z. (eds.), Plato’s Symposium: A Critical Guide. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 194215.Google Scholar
El Murr, D. 2014. “Αὐτὸ καθ ̓ αὑτό : La Genèse et le sens d’un philosophème platonicien,” in Doucet, D. and Koch, I. (eds.), Autos, idipsum: aspects de l’identité d’Homère à Augustin. Aix-en-Provence: Presses Universitaires de Provence, 3956.Google Scholar
Elton, M. 1997. “The Role of the Affinity Argument in the Phaedo,” Phronesis 42, 313–16.Google Scholar
Emde Boas, E. van, Rijksbaron, A., Huitink, L., and de Bakker, M.. 2019The Cambridge Grammar of Classical Greek. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Fine, G. 1984. “Separation,” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 2, 3187.Google Scholar
Fine, G. 1986. “Immanence,” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 4, 7197.Google Scholar
Fletcher, E. 2022. “Cosmology and Human Nature in the Timaeus,” in Ebrey, D and Kraut, R. (eds.), The Cambridge Companion to Plato, 2nd ed. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 468–92.Google Scholar
Franklin, L. 2005. “Recollection and Philosophical Reflection in Plato’s Phaedo,” Phronesis 50, 289314.Google Scholar
Frede, D. 1978. “The Final Proof of the Immortality of the Soul in Plato’s Phaedo 102a–107a,” Phronesis 23, 2741.Google Scholar
Frede, D. 2005. Platon Phaidon. Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft.Google Scholar
Frede, D. 2011. “Das Argument aus den essentiellen Eigenschaften (102a–107d),” in Müller, J. (ed.), Platon, Phaidon. Berlin: Akademie Verlag, 143157.Google Scholar
Frede, M. 1980. “The Original Notion of Cause,” in Schofield, M., M. Burnyeat, and J. Barnes (eds.), Doubt and Dogmatism. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 217–49.Google Scholar
Frede, M. 1988. “Being and Becoming in Plato,” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy (suppl.), 3752.Google Scholar
Frede, M. 1992. “Introduction,” in Plato: Protagoras, trans. Lombardo, S. and Bell, K. (Indianapolis, IN: Hackett), vii–xxxiv.Google Scholar
Furley, D. J. 1976. “Anaxagoras in Response to Parmenides,” Canadian Journal of Philosophy (suppl. 2), 6185.Google Scholar
Furley, D. J. 1989. Cosmic Problems. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Furley, D. J. 2002. “Anaxagoras, Plato, and Naming of Parts,” in Caston, R. and Graham, D. (eds.), Presocratic Philosophy: Essays in Honour of Alexander Mourelatos. Aldershot: Ashgate, 119–26.Google Scholar
Gallop, D. 1975. Plato: Phaedo. Oxford: Clarendon.Google Scholar
Gentzler, J. 1991. “συμφωνεῖν in Plato’s Phaedo,” Phronesis 36, 265–76.Google Scholar
Gentzler, J. 1994. “Recollection and the Problem of the Socratic Elenchus,” Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium of Ancient Philosophy 10, 257–95.Google Scholar
Gill, C. 1973. “The Death of Socrates,” Classical Quarterly 23, 25–8.Google Scholar
Gonzales, F. 2018. “Why the Minotaur is Misology,” in Cornelli, G., Robinson, T., and Bravo, F. (eds.), Plato’s Phaedo: Selected Papers from the Eleventh Symposium Platonicum. Baden Baden: Academia Verlag, 90–5.Google Scholar
Gosling, J. C. B. 1965. “Similarity in Phaedo 73b seq.,” Phronesis 10, 151–61.Google Scholar
Gosling, J. C. B. and Taylor, C. C. W.. 1982. The Greeks on Pleasure. Oxford: Clarendon.Google Scholar
Gulley, N. 1963. Plato’s Theory of Knowledge. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Hackforth, R. 1955. Plato’s Phaedo. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Halliwell, F. S. 1984. “Plato and Aristotle on the Denial of Tragedy,” Proceedings of the Cambridge Philological Society 30, 4971.Google Scholar
Halliwell, F. S. 1999. “Plato’s Repudiation of the Tragic,” in Silk, M. S (ed.), Tragedy and the Tragic: Greek Theatre and Beyond. Oxford: Clarendon, 332–49.Google Scholar
Hankinson, R. J. 1998. Cause and Explanation in Ancient Greek Thought. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hobbs, A. 2000. Plato and the Hero: Courage, Manliness, and the Impersonal Good. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Horky, P. S. 2013. Plato and Pythagoreanism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Huffman, C. A. 1993. Philolaus of Croton: Pythagorean and Presocratic: A Commentary on the Fragments and Testimonia, with Interpretative Essay. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Huffman, C. A. 2010. “The Pythagorean Conception of the Soul, from Pythagoras to Philolaus,” in Frede, D. and Reis, B. (eds.), Body and Soul in Ancient Philosophy. Berlin: de Gruyter, 2143.Google Scholar
Huffman, C. A. 2018. “Pythagoras,” in E. N. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophyhttps://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2018/entries/pythagoras.Google Scholar
Hyland, D. A. 1993. “Philosophy and Tragedy in the Platonic Dialogues,” in Georgopoulos, N. (ed.), Tragedy and Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 123–38.Google Scholar
Irwin, T. 1977a. Plato’s Moral Theory: The Early and Middle Dialogues. Oxford: Clarendon.Google Scholar
Irwin, T. 1977b. “Plato’s Heracliteanism,” Philosophical Quarterly 27, 113.Google Scholar
Irwin, T. 1983. Review of Schofield, M., Burnyeat, M., and Barnes, J. (eds.), Doubt and Dogmatism: Studies in Hellenistic Epistemology. Nous 17, 126–34.Google Scholar
Irwin, T. 1999. “Plato’s Theory of Forms,” in Fine, G. (ed.), Plato, vol. 1: Metaphysics and Epistemology. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 143–70.Google Scholar
Irani, T. 2017. Plato on the Value of Philosophy: The Art of Argument in the Gorgias and Phaedrus. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Irani, T. 2021. “Perfect Change in Plato’s Sophist,” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 60, 4593.Google Scholar
Iwata, N. 2020. “The Attunement Theory of the Soul in the Phaedo,” Japan Studies in Classical Antiquity 4, 3552.Google Scholar
Jansen, S. 2013. “Plato’s Phaedo as a Pedagogical Drama,” Ancient Philosophy 33, 333–52.Google Scholar
Johansen, T. K. 2004. Plato’s Natural Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Johansen, T. K. 2017. “The Separation of Soul from Body in Plato’s Phaedo,” Philosophical Inquiry 41, 1728.Google Scholar
Johansen, T. K. 2020. “Plato’s Teleology,” in McDonough, J. K. (ed.), Teleology: A History. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1438.Google Scholar
Jones, R. and Marechal, P.. 2018. “Plato’s Guide to Living with Your Body,” in Sisko, J. (ed.), Philosophy of Mind in Antiquity. London: Routledge, 84100.Google Scholar
Jouanna, J. 1999. Hippocrates, trans. DeBevoise, M. B.. Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press.Google Scholar
Justin, G. 2020. “Opposites and Plato’s Principle of Change in the Phaedo Cyclical Argument,” Journal of the History of Philosophy 58, 423–48.Google Scholar
Kahn, C. H. 1996Plato and the Socratic Dialogue. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kahn, C. H. 2002. “On Platonic Chronology,” in Annas, J. and Rowe, C. (eds.), New Perspectives on Plato, Modern and Ancient. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 93128.Google Scholar
Kahn, C. H. 2004. “A Return to the Theory of the Verb Be and the Concept of Being,” Ancient Philosophy 24, 381405.Google Scholar
Kamen, D. 2013. “The Manumission of Socrates: A Rereading of Plato’s Phaedo,” Classical Antiquity 32, 78100.Google Scholar
Kamtekar, R. 2016. “The Soul’s (After-)Life,” Ancient Philosophy 36, 115–32.Google Scholar
Kanayama, Y. 2000. “The Methodology of the Second Voyage and the Proof of the Soul’s Indestructibility in Plato’s Phaedo,” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 18, 41100.Google Scholar
Kanayama, Y. 2019. “Socrates’ Humaneness: What His Last Words Meant,” Frontiers of Philosophy in China 14, 111–31.Google Scholar
Karfik, F. 2004. Die Beseelung des Kosmos: Untersuchungen zur Kosmologie, Seelenlehre und Theologie in Platons Phaidon und Timaios. Munich: K. G. Saur.Google Scholar
Kelsey, S. 2000. “Recollection in the Phaedo,” Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium of Ancient Philosophy 16, 91121.Google Scholar
Kelsey, S. 2004. “Causation in the Phaedo,” Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 85, 2143.Google Scholar
Kingsley, P. 1995. Ancient Philosophy, Mystery, and Magic: Empedocles and the Pythagorean Tradition. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kurke, L2011. Aesopic Conversations: Popular Tradition, Cultural Dialogue, and the Invention of Greek Prose. Martin Classical Lectures. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Laks, A. 2010. “Plato’s ‘Truest Tragedy’: Laws Book 7, 817a–d,” in Bobonich, C. (ed.), Plato’s Laws: A Critical Guide. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 217–31.Google Scholar
Ledbetter, G. M. 1999. “Reasons and Causes in Plato: The Distinction between αἴτιον and αἰτία,” Ancient Philosophy 19, 255–65.Google Scholar
Lee, D. C. 2012. “Drama, Dogmatism, and the Equals Argument in the Phaedo,” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 44, 139.Google Scholar
Lennox, J. G. 1985. “Plato’s Unnatural Teleology,” in O’Meara, D (ed.), Platonic Investigations. Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press, 195218.Google Scholar
Lescher, J. 1999. “Early Interest in Knowledge,” in Long, A. A. (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Early Greek Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999, 225–49.Google Scholar
Long, A. A. 1968. Language and Thought in Sophocles: A Study of Abstract Nouns and Poetic Technique. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Long, A. G. 2019Death and Immortality in Ancient Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Lorenz, H. 2006The Brute Within: Appetitive Desire in Plato and Aristotle. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Lorenz, H. 2008. “Plato on the Soul,” in Fine, G. (ed.), Oxford Handbook on Plato. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 243–66.Google Scholar
Loriaux, R. 1969. Le Phédon de Platon: commentaire et traduction, 1: 57a–84b. Namur: Presses Universitaires de Namur.Google Scholar
Loriaux, R. 1975. Le Phédon de Platon: commentaire et traduction, 2: 84b–118a. Namur: Presses Universitaires de Namur.Google Scholar
Madison, L. A. 2002. “Have We Been Careless with Socrates’ Last Words? A Rereading of the Phaedo,” Journal of the History of Philosophy 40, 421–36.Google Scholar
Mann, W-.G. 2000. The Discovery of Things: Aristotle’s Categories and their Context. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Mayhew, R. 2008. “On Prayer in Plato’s Laws,” Apeiron 41, 1−18.Google Scholar
Marechal, P. 2021. “Temperance and Epistemic Purity in Plato’s Phaedo,” Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie.Google Scholar
Martinelli Tempesta, S. 2003. “Sul significato di δεύτερος πλοῦς nel Fedone di Platone,” in M. Bonazzi and F. Trabattoni (eds.), Platone e la tradizione platonica: Studi di filosofia antica. Cisalpino: Milan, 89–125.Google Scholar
McDonough, J. 2020. “Introduction,” in McDonough, J. (ed.), Teleology: A History. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 113.Google Scholar
McKirahan, R. D. 2017. “Philolaus on the Soul,” in Renger, A.-B. and Stavru, A. (eds.), Pythagorean Knowledge from the Ancient to the Modern World: Askēsis – Religion – Science. Wiesbaden: Harrassowitz, 6476.Google Scholar
McPherran, M. L. 2003. “Socrates, Crito, and Their Debt to Asclepius,” Ancient Philosophy 23, 7192.Google Scholar
McQueen, E. I. and Rowe, C. J.. 1989. “Phaedo, Socrates, and the Chronology of the Spartan War with Elis,” Méthexis 2, 118.Google Scholar
Meinwald, C. 1991. Plato’s Parmenides. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Meinwald, C. 2016Plato. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Menn, S. 1995. Plato on God as Nous. Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press.Google Scholar
Menn, S. 2010. “On Socrates’ First Objections to the Physicists (Phaedo 95e8–97b7),” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 38, 3768.Google Scholar
Miller, T. 2015. “Socrates’ Warning against Misology (Plato, Phaedo 88c–91c),” Phronesis 60, 145–79.Google Scholar
Moore, C. 2019Calling Philosophers Names: On the Origin of a Discipline. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Morgan, K. A. 2010. “The Voice of Authority: Divination and Plato’s Phaedo,” Classical Quarterly 60: 6381.Google Scholar
Morgan, K. A. 2021. “Paying the Price: Contextualizing Exchange in Phaedo 69a–c,” Rhizomata 8, 239–67.Google Scholar
Moss, J. 2006. “Pleasure and Illusion in Plato,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 73, 503–35.Google Scholar
Most, G. W. 1993. “A Cock for Asclepius,” Classical Quarterly 43, 96111.Google Scholar
Mueller, I. 1998. “Platonism and the Study of Nature (Phaedo 95e ff.),” in Gentzler, G. (ed.), Method in Ancient Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 6789.Google Scholar
Nails, D. 2002. The People of Plato: A Prosopography of Plato and Other Socratics. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett.Google Scholar
Nehamas, A. 1975. “Plato on the Imperfection of the Sensible World,” American Philosophical Quarterly 12, 105–17.Google Scholar
Nehamas, A. 1979. “Self-Predication and Plato’s Theory of Forms,” American Philosophical Quarterly 16, 93103.Google Scholar
Nietzsche, F. 2015. Die Geburt der Tragödie aus dem Geiste der Musik: Unzeitgemäße Betrachtungen I–IV: Nachgelassene Schriften 1870–1873, edited by Colli, G. and Montinari, M.. Berlin: Deutscher Taschenbuch Verlag.Google Scholar
Nightingale, A. 1995. Genres in Dialogue: Plato and the Construct of Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Nightingale, A. 2021. Philosophy and Religion in Plato’s Dialogues. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Nussbaum, M. 1992. “Tragedy and Self-Sufficiency: Plato and Aristotle on Fear and Pity,” in Rorty, A. (ed.), Essays on Aristotle’s Poetics. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 107–59.Google Scholar
Nussbaum, M. 2001. The Fragility of Goodness: Luck and Ethics in Greek Tragedy and Philosophy (rev. ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Obdrzalek, S. 2021. “The Philosopher’s Reward: Contemplation and Immortality in Plato’s Dialogues,” in A. G. Long (ed.), Immortality in Ancient Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 66–92.Google Scholar
O’Brien, D. 1967. “The Last Argument of Plato’s Phaedo: I,” Classical Quarterly 17, 189231.Google Scholar
O’Brien, D. 1968. “The Last Argument of Plato’s Phaedo: II,” Classical Quarterly 18, 95106.Google Scholar
Ogihara, S. 2018. “Immortality and Eternity: Cebes’ Remark at Phaedo 106d2–4,” in Cornelli, G., Robinson, T., and Bravo, F. (eds.), Plato’s Phaedo: Selected Papers from the Eleventh Symposium Platonicum. Baden Baden: Academia Verlag, 199–204.Google Scholar
Olympiodorus, . 2009. Commentary on the Phaedo, ed. Westerink, L. G.. Wiltshire: Prometheus Trust.Google Scholar
Osborne, C. 1995. “Perceiving Particulars and Recollecting the Forms in the Phaedo,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 96, 211–33.Google Scholar
Owen, G. E. L. 1966. “Plato and Parmenides on the Timeless Present,” Monist 50, 317–40.Google Scholar
Pakaluk, M. 2003. “Degrees of Separation in the Phaedo,” Phronesis 48, 89115.Google Scholar
Palmer, J. 2021. The Method of Hypothesis and the Nature of Soul in Plato’s Phaedo. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Partenie, C. 2009. “Introduction,” in Partenie, C. (ed.), Plato’s Myths. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 127.Google Scholar
Patterson, C. 2018. “Metaphors of Body and Soul in the Phaedo – and Socrates’ Last Words,” in Cornelli, G., Robinson, T., and Bravo, F. (eds.), Plato’s Phaedo: Selected Papers from the Eleventh Symposium Platonicum. Baden Baden: Academia Verlag, 205–9.Google Scholar
Pelling, C. 2019Herodotus and the Question Why. Austin: University of Texas Press.Google Scholar
Pellò, C. 2018. “The Lives of Pythagoras: A Proposal for Reading Pythagorean Metempsychosis,” Rhizomata 6, 135–56.Google Scholar
Pender, E. 2012. “The Rivers of Tartarus: Plato’s Geography of Dying and Coming-Back-to-Life,” in Collobert, C. (ed.), Plato and Myth: Studies on the Use and Status of Platonic Myths. Leiden: Brill, 199233.Google Scholar
Penner, T. 1987. The Ascent from Nominalism: Some Existence Arguments in Plato’s Middle Dialogues. Dordrecht: Reidel.Google Scholar
Peterson, S. 2003. “An Authentically Socratic Conclusion in Plato’s Phaedo: Socrates’ Debt to Asclepius,” in Roshotko, N. (ed.), Desire, Identity, and Existence: Essays in Honor of Terry Penner. Edmonton: Academic Printing and Publishing, 3352.Google Scholar
Price, A. 1995. Mental Conflict. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Price, A. 2009. “Are Plato’s Soul-Parts Psychological Subjects?Ancient Philosophy 29, 115.Google Scholar
Race, W. 2012. Pindar, Olympian Odes, Pythian Odes. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Raphael, D. 1960. The Paradox of Tragedy. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.Google Scholar
Rashed, M. 2009. “Aristophanes and the Socrates of the Phaedo,” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 36, 107–36.Google Scholar
Reed, D. 2020. “Deficient Virtue in the Phaedo,” Classical Quarterly 70, 119–30.Google Scholar
Reed, D. 2021. “Bodily Desires and Afterlife Punishment in the Phaedo,” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 59, 4577.Google Scholar
Reeve, C. D. C. 2002. The Trials of Socrates: Six Classic Texts. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett.Google Scholar
Robinson, R. 1953. Plato’s Earlier Dialectic. Oxford: Clarendon.Google Scholar
Roochnik, D. 1990. The Tragedy of Reason: Towards a Platonic Conception of Logos. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Rowe, C. J. 1993. Plato: Phaedo. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Rowe, C. J. 1995. Plato: Statesman. Warminster: Aris & Phillips.Google Scholar
Rowe, C. J. 1998. Plato: Symposium. Warminster: Aris & Phillips.Google Scholar
Rowett, C. 2021. “Pre-Existence, Life after Death, and Atemporal Beings in Plato’s Phaedo,” in A. G. Long (ed.), Immortality in Ancient Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 93–117.Google Scholar
Russell, D. 2005. Plato on Pleasure and the Good Life. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Salles, R. 2018. “Soul as Harmony in Phaedo 85E–86D and Stoic Pneumatic Theory,” in Harte, V. and Woolf, R. (eds.), Rereading Ancient Philosophy: Old Chestnuts and Sacred Cows. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 221–39.Google Scholar
Santas, G. 1980. “The Form of the Good in Plato’s Republic,” Philosophical Inquiry 2, 374403.Google Scholar
Sassi, M. M. 2018. The Beginnings of Philosophy in Greece, trans. Asuni, M.. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Schaffer, J. 2016. “The Metaphysics of Causation,” in Zalta, E. N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2022/entries/causation-metaphysics.Google Scholar
Schiefsky, M. J. 2005. Hippocrates On Ancient Medicine. Leiden: Brill.Google Scholar
Schofield, M. 2012. “Pythagoreanism: Emerging from the Presocratic Fog: Metaphysics A 5,” in Steele, C. and Primavesi, O. (eds.), Aristotle’s Metaphysics Alpha: Symposium Aristotelicum. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 141–60.Google Scholar
Scott, D. 1995Recollection and Experience: Plato’s Theory of Learning and Its Successors. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Sedley, D. 1990. “Teleology and Myth in the Phaedo,” Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium in Ancient Philosophy 5, 359–83.Google Scholar
Sedley, D. 1995. “The Dramatis Personae of Plato’s Phaedo,” in Smiley, T. J (ed.), Philosophical Dialogues: Plato, Hume and Wittgenstein. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 126.Google Scholar
Sedley, D. 1998. “Platonic Causes,” Phronesis 43, 114–32.Google Scholar
Sedley, D. 2006. “Form–Particular Resemblance in Plato’s Phaedo,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 106, 311–27.Google Scholar
Sedley, D. 2007. “Equal Sticks and Stones,” in Scott, D. (ed.), Maieusis: Essays in Ancient Philosophy in Honour of Myles Burnyeat. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 6886.Google Scholar
Sedley, D. 2009. “Three Kinds of Platonic Immortality,” in Frede, D. (ed.), Body and Soul in Ancient Philosophy. Berlin: De Gruyter, 145–61.Google Scholar
Sedley, D. 2012. “Plato’s Theory of Change at Phaedo 70–71,” in Patterson, R., Karasmanis, V., and Hermann, A. (eds.), Presocratics and Plato: Festschrift at Delphi in Honor of Charles Kahn. Las Vegas, NV: Parmenides, 147–63.Google Scholar
Sedley, D. 2014. “The Unity of Virtue after the Protagoras,” in Collette-Dučić, B. and Delcomminette, S. (eds.), Unité et origine des vertus dans la philosophie ancienne. Bruxelles: Ousia, 6590.Google Scholar
Sedley, D. 2018. “The Phaedo’s Final Proof of Immortality,” in Cornelli, G., Robinson, T., and Bravo, F. (eds.), Plato’s Phaedo: Select Papers from the Eleventh Symposium Platonicum. Baden Baden: Akademia Verlag, 210–20.Google Scholar
Sedley, D. 2021. “Socrates’ Second Voyage (Phaedo 99–101),” in Leigh, F. (ed.), Themes in Plato, Aristotle, and Hellenistic Philosophy: Keeling Lectures 2011–18. London: Institute of Classical Studies, 4762.Google Scholar
Sedley, D. and Long, A. A.. 2010. Plato: Meno and Phaedo. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Sharma, R. 2009. “Socrates’ New Aitia: Causal and Metaphysical Explanations in Plato’s Phaedo,” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 36, 137–78.Google Scholar
Shorey, P. 1930. Plato, Republic, vol. 1: Books 1–5. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Shorey, P. 1935. Plato, Republic, vol. 2: Books 6–10. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Silverman, A. 2002The Dialectic of Essence: A Study of Plato’s Metaphysics. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Stemmer, P. 1992. Platons Dialektik: Die frühen und mittleren Dialoge. Berlin: De Gruyter.Google Scholar
Stone, S. 2018. “Μονάς and ψυχή in the Phaedo,” Plato Journal, 18, 5569.Google Scholar
Svavarsson, S. H. 2009. “Plato on Forms and Conflicting Appearances: The Argument of Phaedo 74a9–c6,” Classical Quarterly 59, 6074.Google Scholar
Svavarsson, S. H. 2020. “Justice and the Afterlife,” in Wolfsdorf, D. (ed.), Early Greek EthicsOxford: Oxford University Press, 593611.Google Scholar
Szabó, Á. 1978. The Beginnings of Greek Mathematics. Dordrecht: D. Reidel.Google Scholar
Taylor, C. C. W. 1983. “The Arguments in the Phaedo Concerning the Thesis that the Soul is a Harmonia,” in Anton, J. P. and Preus, A. (eds.), Essays in Ancient Greek Philosophy. Albany: SUNY Press, 217–31.Google Scholar
Tenkku, J. 1956. The Evaluation of Pleasure in Plato’s Ethics. Helsinki: Societas Philosophica.Google Scholar
Trabattoni, F. 1988. “La teoria dell’anima-armonia nel Fedone,” Elenchos 9, 5374.Google Scholar
Trabattoni, F. 2011. Fedone. Turin: G. Einaudi.Google Scholar
Trabattoni, F. 2016. Essays on Plato’s Epistemology. Leuven: Leuven University Press.Google Scholar
Trivigno, F. 2009. “Paratragedy in Plato’s Gorgias,” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 36, 73105.Google Scholar
Tuominen, M. 2014. “‘Tell Him to Follow Me as Quickly as Possible’: Plato’s Phaedo (60c–63c) on Taking One’s Own Life,” in Honkasalo, M.-L. and Tuominen, M. (eds.), Culture, Suicide, and the Human ConditionNew York: Berghahn Books, 77104.Google Scholar
Tuozzo, T. 2018. “‘Appearing Equal’ at Phaedo 74B4–C6: An Epistemic Interpretation,” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 54, 126.Google Scholar
Vasiliou, I. 2012. “From the Phaedo to the Republic: Plato’s Tripartite Soul and the Possibility of Non-philosophical Virtue,” in Barney, R., Brennan, T., and Brittain, C. (eds.), Plato and the Divided Self. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 932.Google Scholar
Vázquez, D. 2022. “The Last Natural Philosophers in Plato’s Phaedo 99b2-c6,” Mnemosyne (published online ahead of print).Google Scholar
Vegetti, M. 1999. “Culpability, Responsibility, Cause: Philosophy, Historiography, and Medicine in the Fifth Century,” in Long, A. A. (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Early Greek Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999, 271–89.Google Scholar
Verdenius, W. J. 1958. “Notes on Plato’s Phaedo,” Mnemosyne 11, 193243.Google Scholar
Vlastos, G. 1969. “Reasons and Causes in the Phaedo,” Philosophical Review 78, 291325.Google Scholar
Vlastos, G. 1991. Socrates, Ironist and Moral Philosopher. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Warren, J. 2001. “Socratic Suicide,” Journal of Hellenic Studies 121, 91106.Google Scholar
Waterfield, R. (trans.). 1998. Herodotus: The Histories. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Weiss, R. 1987. “The Right Exchange: Phaedo 69a6–c3,” Ancient Philosophy 7, 5766.Google Scholar
White, F. C. 2006. “Socrates, Philosophers and Death: Two Contrasting Arguments in Plato’s Phaedo,” Classical Quarterly 56, 445–58.Google Scholar
White, N. P. 1992. “Plato’s Metaphysical Epistemology,” in Kraut, R. (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Plato. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 277310.Google Scholar
Wiggins, D. 1986. “Teleology and the Good in Plato’s Phaedo,” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 4, 1–18.Google Scholar
Wilson, E. 2018. Homer: The Odyssey. New York: W. W. Norton.Google Scholar
Wolfsdorf, D. 2005. “Αἴτιον and αἰτία in Plato,” Ancient Philosophy 25, 341–48.Google Scholar
Wolfsdorf, D. 2008. “The Method ἐξ ὑποθέσεως at Meno 86e1–87d8,” Phronesis 53, 35–64.Google Scholar
Woolf, R. 2000. “Commentary on Kelsey,” Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium in Ancient Philosophy 16, 122–33.Google Scholar
Woolf, R. 2004. “The Practice of a Philosopher,” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 26, 97129.Google Scholar
Woolf, R. 2007. “Misology and Truth,” Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium in Ancient Philosophy 23, 116.Google Scholar
Young, C. 1988. “A Delicacy in Plato’s Phaedo,” Classical Quarterly 38, 250–1.Google Scholar
Young, D. 2013. “The Soul as Structure in Plato’s Phaedo,” Apeiron 46, 469–98.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Bibliography
  • David Ebrey, Universitat de Barcelona
  • Book: Plato's <I>Phaedo</I>
  • Online publication: 02 February 2023
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108787475.014
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • Bibliography
  • David Ebrey, Universitat de Barcelona
  • Book: Plato's <I>Phaedo</I>
  • Online publication: 02 February 2023
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108787475.014
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • Bibliography
  • David Ebrey, Universitat de Barcelona
  • Book: Plato's <I>Phaedo</I>
  • Online publication: 02 February 2023
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108787475.014
Available formats
×