Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-2plfb Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-28T01:03:28.887Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

References

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 June 2012

Robert W. Lurz
Affiliation:
Brooklyn College, City University of New York
Get access

Summary

Image of the first page of this content. For PDF version, please use the ‘Save PDF’ preceeding this image.'
Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2009

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Ackers, S. H. and Slobodchikoff, C. N. (1999). Communication of stimulus size and shape in alarm calls of Gunnison's prairie dogs, Cynomys gunnisoni. Ethology, 105, 149–162.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Aizawa, K. (1997). Explaining systematicity. Mind & Language, 12, 115–136.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Akaike, H. (1973). Information theory as an extension of the maximum likelihood principle. In Petrov, B. and Csaki, F. (eds.), Second International Symposium on Information Theory. Budapest: Akademiai Kiado.Google Scholar
Allen, C. (1992). Mental content. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 43, 537–553.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Allen, C.(1999). Animal concepts revisited: the use of self-monitoring as an empirical approach. Erkenntnis, 51, 33–40.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Allen, C.(2006). Transitive inference in animals: reasoning or conditioned associations? In Hurley, S. and Nudds, M. (eds.), Rational Animals?Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Allen, C. and Bekoff, M. (1997). Species of Mind: The Philosophy and Biology of Cognitive Ethology. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Allen, C. and Bekoff, M. (2005). Animal play and the evolution of morality: an ethological approach. Topoi, 24, 125–135.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Allen, C. and Hauser, M. (1991). Concept attribution in nonhuman animals: theoretical and methodological problems in ascribing complex mental processes. Philosophy of Science, 58, 221–240.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Allen, C. and Saidel, E. (1998). The evolution of reference. In Cummins, D. and Allen, C. (eds.), Evolution of Mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Alp, R. (1997). “Stepping-sticks” and “seat-sticks”: new types of tools used by wild chimpanzees (Pan troglodytes) in Sierra Leone. American Journal of Primatology, 41, 45–52.3.0.CO;2-#>CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ambrose, (1961). Hexameron. In Savage, J. (trans.), The Fathers of the Church: A New Translation, vol. 42. New York: Fathers of the Church, Inc.Google Scholar
Anderson, A. and Kacelnik, A. (2004). Don't call me bird-brain. New Scientist, 12 June, 46–47.Google Scholar
Anderson, J. R. (1978). Arguments concerning representations for mental imagery. Psychological Review, 85, 249–277.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Aristotle, (1941). De Anima. In McKeon, R. (ed.), The Basic Works of Aristotle. New York: Random House.Google Scholar
Aristotle, (1980). Nicomachean Ethics. Translated by Ross, W. D., revised by Akrill, J. and Urmson, J.. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Armstrong, D. (1973). Belief, Truth and Knowledge. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Armstrong, D. (1997). What is consciousness? In Block, N., Flanagan, O., and Güzeldere, G. (eds.), The Nature of Consciousness. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Arnold, K. and Zuberbühler, K. (2006). Language evolution: semantic combinations in primate calls. Nature, 441, 303.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Arnold, K. and Zuberbühler, K. (2008). Meaningful call combinations in a non-human primate. Current Biology, 18, 202–203.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Babb, S. and Crystal, J. (2005). Discrimination of what, when, and where: implications for episodic-like memory in rats. Learning and Motivation, 36, 177–189.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baillargeon, R. (2004). Infants' reasoning about hidden objects: evidence for event-general and event-specific expectations. Developmental Science, 7, 391–424.
Balakrishnan, K., Bousquet, O., and Honavar, V. (1999). Spatial learning and localization in rodents: a computational model of the hippocampus and its implications for mobile robots. Adaptive Behavior, 7, 173–216.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bar-On, D. (2004). Speaking My Mind: Expression and Self-Knowledge. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bar-On, D. and Chrisman, M. (in press). Ethical neo-expressivism. Oxford Studies in Metaethics, Volume iv.
Bastian, J. R. (1965). Primate signalling systems and human languages. In Devore, I. (ed.), Primate Behavior: Field Studies in Monkeys and Apes. New York: Holt, Rinehart, and Winston.Google Scholar
Bekoff, M. (1995). Play signals as punctuation: the structure of social play in canids. Behavior, 132, 419–429.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bekoff, M. and Allen, C. (1992). Intentional icons: towards an evolutionary cognitive ethology. Ethology, 91, 1–16.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bekoff, M. and Jamieson, D. (1991). Reflective ethology, applied philosophy, and the moral status of animals. In Bateson, P. and Klopfer, P. (eds.), Perspectives in Ethology. New York: Plenum Publishing Corporation.Google Scholar
Beninger, R., Kendall, S., and Vanderwolf, C. H. (1974). The ability of rats to discriminate their own behaviours. Canadian Journal of Psychology, 28, 79–91.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bennett, J. (1988). Thoughtful brutes. Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, 62, 197–210.Google Scholar
Bermúdez, J. L. (1994). Peacocke's argument against the autonomy of nonconceptual representational content. Mind & Language, 9, 402–418.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bermúdez, J. L. (1998). The Paradox of Self-Consciousness. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Bermúdez, J. L. (2003a). Thinking Without Words. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bermúdez, J. L. (2003b). Nonconceptual content: from perceptual experience to subpersonal computational states. In Gunther, Y. H. (ed.), Essays in Nonconceptual Content. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Bermúdez, J. L. (2005). Philosophy of Psychology: A Contemporary Introduction. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Bermúdez, J. L. (in press). Cognitive Science: An Introduction to the Science of the Mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Blair, R. (1995). A cognitive developmental approach to morality: investigating the psychopath. Cognition, 57, 1–29.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Blaisdell, A., Sawa, K., Leising, K., and Walmann, M. (2006). Causal reasoning in rats. Science, 311, 1020–1022.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Boesch, C. (1991). Teaching in wild chimpanzees. Animal Behaviour, 41, 530–532.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boyd, R. (1990). Observations, explanatory power and simplicity. In Boyd, R., Glasper, J., and Trout, J. D. (eds.), The Philosophy of Science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Braddon-Mitchell, D. and Jackson, F. (1996). Philosophy of Mind and Cognition, 1st edn. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Braddon-Mitchell, D. and Jackson, F. (2007). Philosophy of Mind and Cognition, 2nd edn. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Brandom, R. (1994). Making it Explicit. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Breland, K. and Breland, M. (1951). A field of applied animal psychology. American Psychologist, 6, 202–204.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Breland, K. and Breland, M. (1961). The misbehavior of organisms. American Psychologist, 16, 681–684.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brown, A. S. (1991). A review of the tip-of-the-tongue experience. Psychological Bulletin, 109, 204–223.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Browne, D. (2004). Do dolphins know their own minds?Biology and Philosophy, 19, 633–653.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Burge, T. (2005). Truth, Thought, and Reason. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Burkart, J. and Heschl, A. (2007). Understanding visual access in common marmosets, Callithrix jacchus: perspective taking or behavior reading?Animal Behaviour, 73, 457–469.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Burnham, K. and Anderson, D. (2002). Model Selection and Multimodel Inference – a Practical Information-Theoretic Approach, 2nd edn. New York: Springer.Google Scholar
Byrne, A. (1998). Interpretivism. European Review of Philosophy, 3, 199–223.Google Scholar
Byrne, R. W. and Whiten, A. (1988). Machiavellian Intelligence. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Byrne, R. W. and Whiten, A. (1990). Tactical deception in primates: the 1990 database. Primate Report, 27, 1–101.Google Scholar
Byrne, R. W. and Whiten, A. (1991). Computation and mindreading in primate tactical deception. In Whiten, A. (ed.), Natural Theories of Mind: Evolution, Development, and Simulation of Everyday Mindreading. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Call, J. (2004). Inferences about the location of food in the great apes. Journal of Comparative Psychology, 118, 232–241.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Call, J. (2006). Descartes's two errors: reason and reflection in the great apes. In Hurley, S. and Nudds, M. (eds.), Rational Animals?Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Call, J. (2007). Apes know that hidden objects can affect the orientation of other objects. Cognition, 105, 1–25.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Call, J. and Carpenter, M. (2001). Do apes and children know what they have seen?Animal Cognition, 4, 207–220.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Call, J. and Tomasello, M. (2008). Does the chimpanzee have a theory of mind? 30 years later. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 12, 187–192.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Camp, E. (2004). The generality constraints and categorical restrictions. Philosophical Quarterly, 54, 209–231.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Camp, E. (2006). Contextualism, metaphor, and what is said. Mind & Language, 21, 280–309.Google Scholar
Camp, E. (2007). Thinking with maps. Philosophical Perspectives, 21, 145–182.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Camp, E. (2009). Putting thoughts to work: concepts, systematicity, and stimulus-independence. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 78.2, 275–311.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Campbell, J. (1993). The body image and self-consciousness. In Bermúdez, J., Marcel, T., and Eilan, N. (eds.), The Body and the Self. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Carnap, R. (1937). The Logical Syntax of Language. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Caro, T. M. and Hauser, M. D. (1992). Is there teaching in nonhuman animals?Quarterly Review of Biology, 67, 151–174.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Carruthers, P. (1989). Brute experience. The Journal of Philosophy, 86, 258–269.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carruthers, P. (2000). Phenomenal Consciousness: A Naturalistic Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carruthers, P. (2002). The cognitive functions of language. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 25, 657–726.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Carruthers, P. (2004). On being simple-minded. American Philosophical Quarterly, 41, 205–220.Google Scholar
Carruthers, P. (2005). Consciousness: Essays from a Higher-Order Perspective. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carruthers, P. (2006). The Architecture of the Mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carruthers, P. (2007a). The creative-action theory of creativity. In Carruthers, P., Laurence, S., and Stich, S. (eds.), The Innate Mind, Volume iii. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Carruthers, P. (2007b). The illusion of conscious will. Synthese, 159, 197–213.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carruthers, P. (2008). Meta-cognition in animals: a skeptical look. Mind & Language, 23, 58–89.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carruthers, P. (2009a). An architecture for dual reasoning. In Evans, J. and Frankish, K. (eds.), In Two Minds. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Carruthers, P. (2009b). Introspection: divided and partly eliminated. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 78.Google Scholar
Carruthers, P. and Smith, P. K. (eds.) (1996). Theories of Theories of Mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carver, S. C. and Scheier, M. F. (1998). On the Self-regulation of Behavior. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Casati, R. and Varzi, A. (1999). Parts and Places. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Cheney, D. and Seyfarth, R. (1990). How Monkeys See the World. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Cheney, D. and Seyfarth, R. (2007). Baboon Metaphysics. Chicago: Chicago University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Child, W. (1994). Causality, Interpretation, and the Mind. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Chittka, L., Kunze, J., Shipman, C., and Buchmann, S. L. (1995). The significance of landmarks for path integration in homing honeybee foragers. Naturwissenschaften, 82, 341–343.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Clark, A. (2003). Connectionism and cognitive flexibility. In Gunther, Y. (ed.), Essays in Nonconceptual Content. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Clark, A. (2005). Intrinsic content, active memory and the extended mind. Analysis, 65, 1–11.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Clarke, E., Reichard, , U., and Zuberbühler, K. (2006). The syntax and meaning of wild gibbon songs, PLoS One, 1, e73, doi: 10.1371/journal.pone.0000073.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Clayton, N., Bussey, T., and Dickinson, A. (2003). Can animals recall the past and plan for the future?Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 4, 685–691.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Clayton, N., Emery, N., and Dickinson, A. (2006). The rationality of animal memory: complex caching strategies of western scrub jays. In Hurley, S. and Nudds, M. (eds.), Rational Animals?Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Collett, M., Harland, D., and Collett, T. S. (2002). The use of landmarks and panoramic context in the performance of local vectors by navigating honeybees. The Journal of Experimental Biology, 205, 807–814.Google ScholarPubMed
Collett, T. and Collett, M. (2002). Memory use in insect visual navigation. Nature Reviews: Neuroscience, 3, 542–552.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Collett, T. S., Fry, S. N., and Wehner, R. (1993). Sequence learning by honey bees. Journal of Comparative Physiology A, 172, 693–706.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Connor, R. and Peterson, D. (1994). The Lives of Whales and Dolphins. New York: Holt.Google Scholar
Craik, K. (1943). The Nature of Explanation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Crockford, C. and Boesch, C. (2005). Call combinations in wild chimpanzees. Behavior, 142, 397–421.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cussins, A. (1992). Content, embodiment and objectivity: the theory of cognitive trails. Mind, 101, 651–688.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dacke, M., and Srinivasan, M. V. (2007). Honeybee navigation: distance estimation in the third dimension. The Journal of Experimental Biology, 210, 845–853.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Dally, J. M., Emery, N. J., and Clayton, N. S. (2006). Food-caching western scrub jays keep track of who was watching when. Science, 312, 1662–1665.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Damasio, A. R., Everitt, B. J., and Bishop, D. (1996). The somatic marker and hypothesis and the possible functions of the prefrontal cortex. Philosophical Transactions. Biological Sciences, 351, 1413–1420.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Davidson, D. (1980). Essays on Actions and Events. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Davidson, D. (1980). Mental events. In Essays on Actions and Events. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Davidson, D. (1982). Rational Animals. Dialectica, 36, 318–327.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davidson, D. (1983/1986). A coherence theory of truth and knowledge. In LePore, E. (ed.), Truth and Interpretation: Perspectives on the Philosophy of Donald Davidson. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
Davidson, D. (1984a). Inquiries into Truth and Interpretation. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Davidson, D. (1984b). Thought and talk. In Inquiries into Truth and Interpretation. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Davidson, D. (1985). Rational animals. In Lepore, E. and McLaughlin, B. (eds.), Actions and Events: Perspectives on the Philosophy of Donald Davidson. New York: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
Davidson, D. (1997). The emergence of thought. Erkenntnis, 51, 7–17.Google Scholar
Davidson, D. (2005). Problems of Rationality. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Davies, M. and Stone, T. (1995). Folk Psychology: The Theory of Mind Debate. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
Dawkins, M. S. (1993). Through Our Eyes Only?Oxford: Freeman Press.Google Scholar
Dawkins, R. and Krebs, J. R. (1978). Animal signals: information or manipulation? In Krebs, J. R. and Davies, N. B. (eds.), Behavioural Ecology: An Evolutionary Approach. Oxford: Blackwell Scientific Publications.Google Scholar
DeGrazia, D. (1996). Taking Animals Seriously: Mental Life and Moral Status. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Deigh, J. (2004). Primitive emotions. In Solomon, R. (ed.), Thinking about Feeling. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Dennett, D. (1969). Content and Consciousness. London: Routledge Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Dennett, D. (1971). Intentional systems. Journal of Philosophy, 8, 87–106.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dennett, D. (1975). Brain writing and mind reading. In Gunderson, K. (ed.), Language, Mind, and Knowledge. Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 7. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Dennett, D. (1978). Brainstorms. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Dennett, D. (1983). Intentional systems in cognitive ethology: the “Panglossian paradigm” defended. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 6, 343–390.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dennett, D. (1987). The Intentional Stance. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Dennett, D. (1990). The myth of original intentionality. In Said, K., Newton-Smith, W., Viale, R., and Wilkes, K. (eds.), Modeling the Mind. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Dennett, D. (1991a). Mother nature vs. the walking encyclopedia. In Ramsey, W., Stich, S., and Rumelhart, D. E. (eds.), Philosophy and Connectionist Theory. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.Google Scholar
Dennett, D. (1991b). Real patterns. Journal of Philosophy, 88, 27–51.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dennett, D. (1995). Do animals have beliefs? In Roitblat, H and Meyer, J.-A. (eds.), Comparative Approaches to Cognitive Science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Dennett, D. (1996). Kinds of Minds. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Dere, E., Kart-Teke, E., Huston, J., and Silva, D. (2006). The case for episodic memory in animals. Neuroscience and Biobehavioral Reviews, 30, 1206–1224.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Descartes, R. (1637/1988). Discourse on the method. In Cottingham, , Stoothoff, , and Murdoch, (trans.), Descartes: Selected Philosophical Writings. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Descartes, R. (1641/1984). Fourth objections. In Cottingham, , Stoothoff, , and Murdoch, (trans.), The Philosophical Writings of Descartes, Volume ii. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Descartes, R. (1644/1988). Principles of Philosophy. In Cottingham, , Stoothoff, , and Murdoch, (trans.), Descartes: Selected Philosophical Writings. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Devitt, M. (2006). Ignorance of Language. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dretske, F. (1981). Knowledge and the Flow of Information. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Dretske, F. (1988). Explaining Behavior. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Dretske, F. (1995). Naturalizing the Mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Dretske, F. (2000). Perception, Knowledge and Belief. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dummett, M. (1973). Frege: Philosophy of Language. London: Duckworth.Google Scholar
Dummett, M. (1993). The Seas of Language. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Dummett, M. (1996). Origins of Analytical Philosophy. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Dyer, F. C. (1985). Nocturnal orientation by the Asian honeybee, Apis dorsata. Animal Behaviour, 33, 769–774.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dyer, F. C. (2002). The biology of the dance language. Annual Review of Entomology, 47, 917–949.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Dyer, F. C. and Dickinson, J. A. (1994). Development of sun compensation by honey bees: how partially experienced bees estimate the sun's course. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences USA, 91, 4471–4474.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Edelman, G. and Tononi, G. (2001). A Universe of Consciousness: How Matter Becomes Imagination. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Edrich, W. (1981). Night-time sun-compass behaviour of honeybees at the equator. Physiological Entomology, 6, 7–13.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Eichenbaum, H., Fortin, N., Ergorul, C., Wright, S., and Agster, K. (2005). Episodic recollection in animals: “If it walks like a duck and quacks like a duck…”. Learning and Motivation, 36, 190–207.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Emery, N. and Clayton, N. (2001). Effects of experience and social context on prospective caching strategies in scrub jays. Nature, 414, 443–446.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Erdőhegyi, Á., Topál, J., Vrányi, Z., and Miklósi, Á. (2007). Dog-logic: inferential reasoning in a two-way choice task and its restricted use. Animal Behavior, 74, 725–737.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Evans, C. S. and Marler, P. (1995). Language and animal communication: parallels and contrasts. In Roitblat, H. L. and Meyer, J.-A. (eds.), Comparative Approaches to Cognitive Science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Evans, G. (1982). The Varieties of Reference. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Evans, J. and Over, D. (1996). Rationality and Reasoning. Hove, Sussex: Psychology Press.Google Scholar
Fitzpatrick, S. (2006). Simplicity, Science and Mind. Doctoral dissertation, Department of Philosophy, University of Sheffield.Google Scholar
Fitzpatrick, S. (2008). Doing away with Morgan's canon. Mind & Language, 23, 224–246.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Flavell, J. H. (2004). Theory-of-mind development: retrospect and prospect. Merrill-Palmer Quarterly, 50, 274–290.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Flombaum, J. and Santos, , , L. (2005). Rhesus monkeys attribute perceptions to others. Current Biology, 15, 447–452.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Floridi, L. (1997). Skepticism and animal rationality: the fortune of Chrysippus's dog in the history of Western thought. Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie, 79, 27–57.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fodor, J. (1975). The Language of Thought. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Fodor, J. (1981). Representations. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Fodor, J. (1983). The Modularity of Mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Fodor, J. (1987). Psychosemantics. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Fodor, J. (1991). Replies. In Loewer, B. (ed.), Meaning in Mind. Cambridge, MA: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Fodor, J. (1998). Where Cognitive Science Went Wrong. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fodor, J. (2003). Review of Bermúdez's Thinking Without Words. London Review of Books, 25, 16–17.Google Scholar
Fodor, J. and McLaughlin, B. (1990). Connectionism and the problem of systematicity. Cognition, 35, 183–204.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Fodor, J. and Pylyshyn, Z. (1988). Connectionism and the cognitive architecture of mind. Cognition, 28, 3–71.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fodor, J. and Pylyshyn, Z. (1995). Connectionism and cognitive architecture: a critical analysis. In MacDonald, C. and MacDonald, G. (eds.), Connectionism: Debates on Psychological Explanation. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Forster, M. and Sober, E. (1994). How to tell when simpler, more unified, or less ad hoc theories will provide more accurate predictions. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 45, 1–36.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fouts, R., Fouts, D., and Shoenfeld, D. (1984). Sign language conversational interactions between chimpanzees. Sign Language Studies, 34, 1–12.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frankish, K. (2004). Mind and Supermind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frege, G. (1892/1951). On concept and object, trans. Geach, P. T. and Black, M.. Mind, 60, 168–180.Google Scholar
Frisch, K. (1967). The Dance Language and Orientation of Bees. Cambridge, MA: Belknap/Harvard.Google Scholar
Fry, R. (2002). The engineering of cybernetic systems. Bayesian Inference and Maximum Entropy Systems in Science and Engineering: American Institute of Physics Conference Proceedings, 617, 497–528.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Galef, B. (1996). Tradition in animals: field observations and laboratory analyses. In Bekoff, M. and Jamieson, D. (eds.), Readings in Animal Cognition. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Galen, C. (1999). Sun stalkers: flowers and sun. Natural History, May.
Gallistel, C. R. (1990). The Organization of Learning. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Gallistel, C. R. (2003). Conditioning from an information processing perspective. Behavioural Processes, 62, 89–101.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Gallup, G. (1977). Self-recognition in primates: a comparative approach to the bidirectional properties of consciousness. American Psychologist, 32, 330–338.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gallup, G., Anderson, J., and Shillito, D. (2002). In Bekoff, M., Allen, C., and Burghardt, G. (eds.), The Cognitive Animal. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Gardener, R. A. and Gardener, B. (1969). Teaching sign language to a chimpanzee. Science, 165, 664–672.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gärdenfors, P. (2003). How Homo Became Sapiens: On the Evolution of Thinking. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Gennaro, R. (1993). Brute experience and the higher-order thought theory of consciousness. Philosophical Papers, 22, 51–69.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gennaro, R. (1996). Consciousness and Self-consciousness: A Defense of the Higher-Order Thought Theory of Consciousness. Amsterdam and Philadelphia: John Benjamins.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gennaro, R. (2004a). Higher-Order Theories of Consciousness. Amsterdam and Philadelphia: John Benjamins.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gennaro, R. (2004b). Higher-order thoughts, animal consciousness, and misrepresentation: a reply to Carruthers and Levine. In Gennaro, R. (ed.), Higher-Order Theories of Consciousness. Amsterdam and Philadelphia: John Benjamins.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gennaro, R. (2006). Review of Peter Carruthers' Consciousness: Essays From a Higher-Order Perspective. Psyche, 12, http://psyche.cs.monash.edu.au/book_reviews/carruthers3/Carruthers.pdf.Google Scholar
Gibson, J. (1966). The Senses Considered as Perceptual Systems. Boston: Houghton Mifflin.Google Scholar
Gibson, J. (1979). The Ecological Approach to Visual Perception. Boston: Houghton Mifflin.Google Scholar
Giurfa, M. (2007). Behavioral and neural analysis of associative learning in the honeybee: a taste from the magic well. Journal of Comparative Physiology A, 193, 801–824.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Glock, H.-J. (1999). Animal minds: conceptual problems. Evolution and Cognition, 5, 174–188.Google Scholar
Glock, H.-J. (2000). Animals, thoughts, and concepts. Synthese, 123, 35–64.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Glouberman, M. (1976). Prime matter, predication, and the semantics of feature-placing. In Kasher, A. (ed.), Language in Focus. Boston: Reidel.Google Scholar
Goldman, A. (2006). Simulating Minds. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goodall, J. (1986). The Chimpanzees of Gombe. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Gopnik, A. and Schulz, L. (2007). Causal Learning. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gould, J. (1986). The locale map of bees: do insects have cognitive maps?Science, 232, 861–863.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Gould, J. and Gould, C. (1988). The Honey Bee. New York: Science American Library.Google Scholar
Gould, J. and Gould, C. (1994). The Animal Mind. New York: Scientific American Library.Google Scholar
Grandin, T. and Johnson, C. (2005). Animals in Translation. New York: Scribner.Google Scholar
Grau, J. W. (2002). Learning and memory without a brain. In Bekoff, M., Allen, C., and Burghardt, G. M. (eds.), The Cognitive Animal. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Grice, H. P. (1957). Meaning. Philosophical Review, 66, 377–388.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Griffin, D. (1976). The Question of Animal Awareness. New York: Rockefeller University Press.Google Scholar
Griffin, D. (2001). Animal Minds: Beyond Cognition to Consciousness. Chicago: Chicago University Press.Google Scholar
Gruber, O. and Cramon, D. Y. (2003). The functional neuroanatomy of human working memory revisited. NeuroImage, 19, 797–809.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Grünwald, P. (2007). The Minimum Description Length Principle. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Gunther, Y. H (ed.) (2003). Essays on Nonconceptual Content. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.
Güzeldere, G., Nahmias, E., and Deaner, R. (2002). Darwin's continuum and the building blocks of deception. In Bekoff, M., Allen, C., and Burghardt, G. (eds.), The Cognitive Animal. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Hadley, R. F. (2004). On the proper treatment of semantic systematicity. Minds and Machines, 14, 145–172.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hampton, R. (2001). Rhesus monkeys know when they remember. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences U.S.A., 98, 5359–5362.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hampton, R.(2005). Can rhesus monkeys discriminate between remembering and forgetting? In Terrace, H. and Metcalfe, J. (eds.), The Missing Link in Cognition: Origins of Self-Reflective Consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hare, B., Addessi, E., Call, J., Tomasello, M., and Visalberghi, E. (2003). Do capuchin monkeys, Cebus apella, know what conspecifics do and do not see?Animal Behaviour, 65, 131–142.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hare, B., Brown, M., Williamson, C., and Tomasello, M. (2002). The domestication of social cognition in dogs. Science, 298, 1634–1636.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hare, B., Call, J., Agnetta, B., and Tomasello, M. (2000). Chimpanzees know what conspecifics do and do not see. Animal Behaviour, 59, 771–785.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hare, B., Call, J., and Tomasello, M. (2001). Do chimpanzees know what conspecifics know?Animal Behaviour, 61, 139–151.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hare, B. and Tomasello, M. (2004). Chimpanzees are more skilled in competitive than in cooperative cognitive tasks. Animal Behaviour, 68, 571–581.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hauser, M. D. (1996). The Evolution of Communication. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Hauser, M. D. (2000). Wild Minds. New York: Holt.Google Scholar
Hauser, M. D., Chomsky, N., and Fitch, W. (2002). The faculty of language: What is it, who has it, and how did it evolve?Science, 298, 1569–1579.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Herman, L. (2002). Exploring the cognitive world of the bottlenosed dolphin. In Bekoff, M., Allen, C., and Burghardt, G. (eds.), The Cognitive Animal. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Heyes, C. M. (1998). Theory of mind in nonhuman primates. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 21, 101–134.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Horgan, T. and Tienson, J. (1996). Connectionism and the Philosophy of Psychology. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Hume, D. (1739/1978). A Treatise of Human Nature, ed. Nidditch, P. H.. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hurley, S. (2003). Animal action in the space of reasons. Mind & Language, 18, 231–315.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hurley, S. and Nudds, M. (2006). Rational Animals?Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hyatt, C. W. and Hopkins, W. D. (1994). Self-awareness in bonobos and Chimpanzees: a comparative approach. In Parker, S., Mitchell, R., and Boccia, M. (eds.), Self-Awareness in Animals and Humans. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Inman, A. and Shettleworth, S. J. (1999). Detecting metamemory in nonverbal subjects: a test with pigeons. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Animal Behavioral Processes, 25, 389–395.Google Scholar
Jackson, R. and Li, D. (2004). One-encounter search-image formation by araneophagic spiders. Animal Cognition, 7, 247–254.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Jacob, P. and Jeannerod, M. (2003). Ways of Seeing: The Scope and Limits of Visual Cognition. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jamieson, D. (2002). Morality's Progress. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Jamieson, D. and Bekoff, M. (1993). On aims and methods of cognitive ethology. Philosophy of Science Association, 2, 110–124.Google Scholar
Jeffrey, R. (1985). Animal interpretation. In Lepore, E. and McLaughlin, B. (eds.), Actions and Events: Perspectives on the Philosophy of Donald Davidson. New York: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
Jensen, K., Hare, B., Call, J., and Tomasello, M. (2006). What's in it for me? Self-regard precludes altruism and spite in chimpanzees. Proceedings of the Royal Society B, 273, 1013–1021.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Johnson, K. (2004). On the systematicity of language and thought. The Journal of Philosophy, 101, 111–139.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Johnson-Laird, P. (1983). Mental Models. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Jolly, A. (1999). Lucy's Legacy. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Kahneman, D. (2002). Maps of bounded rationality: a perspective on intuitive judgment and choice. Nobel laureate acceptance speech, http://nobelprize.org/economics/laureates/2002/kahneman-lecture.html.
Kaye, L. (1995). The languages of thought. Philosophy of Science, 65, 92–110.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kennedy, J. (1992). The New Anthropomorphism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kinsbourne, M. (2005). A continuum of self-consciousness that emerges in phylogeny and ontogeny. In Terrace, H. and Metcalfe, J. (eds.), The Missing Link in Cognition: Origins of Self-Reflective Consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kitchin, R. (1994). Cognitive maps: what are they and why study them?Journal of Environmental Psychology, 14, 1–19.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Knill, D. and Richards, W. (1996). Perception as Bayesian Inference. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Koriat, A. (2000). The feeling of knowing: some metatheoretical implications for consciousness and control. Consciousness and Cognition, 9, 149–171.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Koriat, A. (2007). Metacognition and consciousness. In Zelazo, P., Moscovitch, M., and Thomson, E. (eds.), The Cambridge Handbook of Consciousness. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Koriat, A., Ma'ayan, H., and Nussinson, R. (2006). The intricate relationships between monitoring and control in metacognition: lessons for the cause-and-effect relation between subjective experience and behavior. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 135, 36–69.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kornell, N., Son, L., and Terrace, H. (2007). Transfer of metacognitive skills and hint seeking in monkeys. Psychological Science, 18, 64–71.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kort, S., Dickinson, A., and Clayton, N. (2005). Retrospective cognition by food-caching western scrub-jays. Learning and Motivation, 35, 159–176.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kosslyn, S. M., Thompson, W. L., and Ganis, G. (2006). The Case for Mental Imagery. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Krebs, J. R. and Dawkins, R. (1984). Animal signals: mind reading and manipulation. In Krebs, J. R. and Davies, N. B. (eds.), Behavioural Ecology: An Evolutionary Approach. Oxford: Blackwell Scientific Publications.Google Scholar
Kripke, S. (1982). Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Kummer, H. (1982). Social knowledge in free-ranging primates. In Griffin, D. (ed.), Animal Mind – Human Mind. Berlin: Springer-Verlag.Google Scholar
Laurence, S. and Margolis, E. (2001). The poverty of the stimulus argument. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 52, 217–276.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Laurence, S. and Margolis, E. (2007). The ontology of concepts: abstract objects or mental representations?Noûs, 41, 561–593.Google Scholar
Lemon, O. and Pratt, I. (1998). On the insufficiency of linear diagrams for syllogisms. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 39, 573–580.Google Scholar
Levin, D. T. (2004). Thinking and Seeing: Visual Metacognition in Adults and Children. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Liebenberg, L. (1990). The Art of Tracking: The Origin of Science. Cape Town: David Philip.Google Scholar
Lindauer, M. (1957). Sonnenorientierung der Bienen unter der Aequatorsonne und zur Nachzeit. Naturwissenschaften, 44, 1–6.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lindauer, M. (1960). Time-compensated sun orientation in bees. Cold Spring Harbor Symposia on Quantitative Biology, 25, 371–377.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Loewer, B. (1987). From information to intentionality. Synthese, 70, 287–317.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lurz, R. (2002). Neither HOT nor COLD: An alternative account of consciousness. Psyche, 9, http://psyche.cs.monash.edu.au/v9/psyche-9-01-lurz.html.Google Scholar
Lurz, R. (2004). Either FOR or HOR: a false dichotomy. In Gennaro, R. C. (ed.), Higher-Order Theories of Consciousness. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.Google Scholar
Lurz, R. (2006). Conscious beliefs and desires: a same-order approach. In Kriegel, U. and Williford, K. (eds.), Self-Representational Approaches to Consciousness. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Lurz, R. (2007). In defense of wordless thoughts about thoughts. Mind & Language, 22, 270–296.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lurz, R. (2008). Animal minds. Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy, www.utm.edu/research/iep/.
Lurz, R. (2009). If chimpanzees are mindreaders, could behavioral science tell? Toward a solution of the logical problem. Philosophical Psychology, 22, 305–328.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lycan, W. G. (1996). Consciousness and Experience. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Lycan, W. G. (2001). A simple argument for a higher-order representation theory of consciousness. Analysis, 61, 3–4.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Malcolm, N. (1972). Thoughtless brutes. Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, 46, 5–20.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mann, J., Connor, R., Tyack, P., and Whitehead, H. (2000). Cetacean Societies. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Marcus, G. (2001). The Algebraic Mind: Integrating Connectionism and Cognitive Science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Marler, P. (1989). Learning by instinct: birdsong. American Speech-Language-Hearing Association (AHSA), 31, 75–79.Google ScholarPubMed
Marler, P. (1992). Functions of arousal and emotion in primate communication: a semiotic approach. In Nishida, T., McGrew, W. C., Marler, P., Pickford, M., and Waal, F. B. (eds.), Topics in Primatology, Vol. I: Human Origins. Tokyo: University of Tokyo Press.Google Scholar
Matsuzawa, T. (1994). Field experiments on use of stone tools by chimpanzees in the wild. In Wrangham, R., McGrew, W. C., Waal, F. B. M., and Heltne, P. (eds.), Chimpanzee Cultures. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Matsuzawa, T. and Yamakoshi, G. (1996). Comparison of chimpanzee material culture between Bossou and Nimba, West Africa. In Russon, A., Bard, K., and Parker, S. (eds.), Reaching into Thought. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
McDowell, J. (1996). Mind and World, 2nd edn. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
McGrew, W. C. (1992). Chimpanzee Material Culture. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McLaughlin, B. (1998). Connectionism. In Craig, E. (ed.), Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Melis, A., Call, J., and Tomasello, M. (2006). Chimpanzees (Pan troglodytes) conceal visual and auditory information from others. Journal of Comparative Psychology, 120, 154–162.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Menzel, C. (2005). Progress in the study of chimpanzee recall and episodic memory. In Terrace, H. and Metcalfe, J. (eds.), The Missing Link in Cognition: Origins of Self-Reflective Consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Menzel, R., Brandt, R., Gumbert, A., Komischke, B., and Kunze, J. (2000). Two spatial memories for honeybee navigation. Proceedings of the Royal Society: London B, 267, 961–966.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Menzel, R., Geiger, K., Joerges, J., Müller, U., and Chittka, L. (1998). Bees travel novel homeward routes by integrating separately acquired vector memories. Animal Behaviour, 55, 139–152.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Menzel, R. and Giurfa, M. (2006). Dimensions of cognition in an insect, the honeybee. Behavioral and Cognitive Neuroscience Reviews, 5, 24–40.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Menzel, R., Greggers, U., Smith, A., Berger, S., Brandt, R., Brunke, S., Bundrock, G., Hülse, S., Plümpe, T., Schaupp, F., Schüttler, E., Stach, S., Stindt, J., Stollhoff, N., and Watzl, S. (2005). Honeybees navigate according to a map-like spatial memory. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences USA, 102, 3040–3045.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mercado, E., Murray, R., Uyeyama, R., Pack, A., and Herman, L. (1998). Memory for recent actions in the bottlenosed dolphin (Tursiops Truncates): repetition of arbitrary behaviors using an abstract rule. Animal Learning & Behavior, 26, 210–218.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Metcalfe, J. and Shimamura, A. P. (1994). Metacognition: Knowing about Knowing. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Miles, H. L. W. (1993). Language and the orang-utan: the old “person” of the forest. In Cavalieri, P. and Singer, P. (eds.), The Great Ape Project. New York: St. Martin's Press.Google Scholar
Millikan, R. G. (1984). Language, Thought, and Other Biological Categories. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Millikan, R. G. (1993). White Queen Psychology and Other Essays for Alice. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Millikan, R. G. (1995). Pushmi-Pullyu. Philosophical Perspectives, 9, 185–200.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Minsky, M. (1975). A framework for representing knowledge. In Winston, P. (ed.), The Psychology of Computer Vision. New York: McGraw-Hill.Google Scholar
Mitchell, R. (1994). Multiplicities of Self. In Parker, S. T., Mitchell, R., and Bocca, M. (eds.), Self-Awareness in Animals and Humans. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Mithen, S. (1996). The Prehistory of the Mind. London: Thames and Hudson.Google Scholar
Morgan, C. Lloyd (1894). An Introduction to Comparative Psychology, 1st edn. London: Walter Scott.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Morgan, C. Lloyd (1903). An Introduction to Comparative Psychology, 2nd edn. London: Walter Scott.Google Scholar
Murphy, D. and Stich, S. (2000). Darwin in the madhouse: evolutionary psychology and the classification of mental disorders. In Carruthers, P. and Chamberlain, A. (eds.), Evolution and the Human Mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Nagel, T. (1974). What is it like to be a bat? Philosophical Review, 83, 435–450.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nebel, B. (1999). Frame-based systems. In Wilson, R. A. and Keil, F. (eds.), MIT Encyclopedia of the Cognitive Sciences. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Nelson, K. (2005). Emerging levels of consciousness in early human development. In Terrace, H. and Metcalfe, J. (eds.), The Missing Link in Cognition: Origins of Self-Reflective Consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Nelson, T. O. and Narens, L. (1992). Metamemory: a theoretical framework and new findings. In Nelson, T. O. (ed.), Metacognition: Core Readings. New York: Allyn & Bacon.Google Scholar
Neu, J. (2000). A Tear is an Intellectual Thing. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Nichols, S. and Stich, S. (2003). Mindreading. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nisbett, R. and Wilson, T. (1977). Telling more than we can know. Psychological Review, 84, 231–295.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Norton, J. (2003). A material theory of induction. Philosophy of Science, 70, 647–670.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nowak, M. A., Plotkin, J., and Jansen, V. (2000). The evolution of syntactic communication. Nature, 404, 495–498.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Nussbaum, M. (2001). Upheavals of Thought: The Intelligence of Emotions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
O'Keefe, J. and Nadel, L. (1978). The Hippocampus as a Cognitive Map. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Panksepp, J. and Burgdorf, J. (2003). “Laughing” rats and the evolutionary antecedents of human joy? Physiology and Behavior, 79, 533–547.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Parker, S. T. (1994). Incipient mirror self-recognition in zoo gorillas and chimpanzees. In Parker, S. T., Mitchell, R., and Boccia, M. (eds.), Self-Awareness in Animals and Humans. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Patterson, F. and Gordon, W. (1993). The case for the personhood of gorillas. In Cavalieri, P. and Singer, P. (eds.), The Great Ape Project. New York: St. Martin's Press.Google Scholar
Peacocke, C. (1992). A Study of Concepts. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Peacocke, C. (1994). Content, computation and externalism. Mind & Language, 9, 303–335.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Peacocke, C. (1997). Concepts without words. In Heck, R. (ed.), Language, Thought, and Logic. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Peacocke, C. (2001). Phenomenology and nonconceptual content. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 62, 609–615.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pearle, J. (2000). Causality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Penn, D., Holyoak, K., and Povinelli, D. (in press). Darwin's mistake: explaining the discontinuity between human and non-human minds. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 31, 109–178.
Penn, D. and Povinelli, D. (2007a). Causal cognition in humans and non-human animals: a comparative, critical review. Annual Review of Psychology, 58, 97–118.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Penn, D. and Povinelli, D. (2007b). On the lack of evidence that non-human animals possess anything remotely resembling a “theory of mind.” Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B, 362, 731–744.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Phillips, H. (2006). Known unknowns. New Scientist, December 16, 28–31.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pietroski, P. and Rey, G. (1995). When other things aren't equal: saving ceteris paribus. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 46, 81–110.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pinker, S. and Bloom, P. (1990). Natural language and natural selection. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 13, 707–784.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Plotnik, J., Waal, F., and Reiss, D. (2006). Self-recognition in an Asian elephant. Proceedings of the National Academy of Science, 103, 17053–17057.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Plutarch, (1957). Moralia: De Solertia Animalium, vol. xii, trans. Cherniss, H. and Helmbold, W.. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Povinelli, D. (1996). Chimpanzee theory of mind? In Carruthers, P. and Smith, P. (eds.), Theories of Theories of Mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Povinelli, D. (2000). Folk Physics for Apes. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Povinelli, D. and Eddy, T. J. (1996). What young chimpanzees know about seeing. Monographs of the Society for Research in Child Development, 61, 1–152.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Povinelli, D. and Vonk, , , J. (2006). We don't need a microscope to explore the chimpanzee's mind. In Hurley, S. and Nudds, M. (eds.), Rational Animals?Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Pratt, I. (1993). Map semantics. In Frank, A. and Campari, I. (eds.), Spatial Information Theory: A Theoretical Basis for GIS. Berlin: Springer-Verlag.Google Scholar
Premack, D. and Premack, A. J. (1994). Levels of causal understanding in chimpanzees and children. Cognition, 50, 347–362.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Premack, D. and Woodruff, , , G. (1978). Does the chimpanzee have a theory of mind? Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 1, 515–526.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Proust, J. (1997). Comment l'Esprit Vient aux Bêtes, Essai sur la Représentation. Paris: Gallimard.Google Scholar
Proust, J. (1999). Mind, space and objectivity in nonhuman animals. Erkenntnis, 51, 41–58.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Proust, J. (2006). Rationality and metacognition in nonhuman animals. In Hurley, S. and Nudds, M. (eds.), Rational Animals?Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Proust, J. (2007). Metacognition and metarepresentation: is a self-directed theory of mind a precondition for metacognition? Synthese, 2, 271–295.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Proust, J. (2009). What is a mental function? In Brenner, A. and Gayon, J. (eds.), French Philosophy of Science. Boston: Springer.Google Scholar
Putnam, H. (1992). Renewing Philosophy. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Pylyshyn, Z. (1973). What the mind's eye tells the mind's brain: a critique of mental imagery. Psychological Bulletin, 80, 1–24.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pylyshyn, Z. (1981). The imagery debate: analogue media versus tacit knowledge. Psychological Review, 88, 16–45.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pylyshyn, Z. (1986). Computation and Cognition. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Pylyshyn, Z. (2003). Seeing and Visualizing. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Pylyshyn, Z. (2004). Seeing and Visualizing: It's Not What You Think. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Quine, W. V. O. (1960). Word and Object. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Raby, C., Alexis, D., Dickenson, A., and Clayton, N. (2007). Planning for the future by western scrub-jays. Nature, 445, 919–921.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Radick, G. (2007). The Simian Tongue: The Long Debate on Animal Language. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Reiss, D. and Marino, L. (2001). Mirror self-recognition in the bottlenose dolphin: a case of cognitive convergence. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 98, 5937–5942.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Rendall, D. and Owren, M. J. (2002). Animal vocal communication: say what? In Bekoff, M., Allen, C., and Burghardt, G. M. (eds.), The Cognitive Animal: Empirical and Theoretical Perspectives on Animal Cognition. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Rescorla, M. (in press a). Cognitive maps and the language of thought. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science.
Rescorla, M. (in press b). Predication and cartographic representation. Synthese.
Rescorla, R. A. and Wagner, A. R. (1972). A theory of pavlovian conditioning: variations in the effectiveness of reinforcement and nonreinforcement. In Black, A. H. and Prokasy, W. F. (eds.), Classical Conditioning II. New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts.Google Scholar
Rey, G. (1981). What are mental images? In Block, N. (ed.), Readings in the Philosophy of Psychology, Vol. ii. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Rey, G. (1995). A not “merely empirical” argument for a language of thought. Philosophical Perspectives, 9, 201–222.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rey, G. (2002). Physicalism and psychology: a plea for substantive philosophy of mind. In Gillet, C. and Loewer, B. (eds.), Physicalism and Its Discontents. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Rey, G. (2007). Resisting normativism in psychology. In Cohen, J. and McLaughlin, B. (eds.), Blackwell Debates in Philosophy of Mind. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Rey, G. (2008). Externalism and inexistence in early content. In Schantz, R. (ed.), Prospects for Meaning. New York: Walter De Gruyter.Google Scholar
Reynolds, A. M., Smith, A. D., Reynolds, D. R., Carreck, N. L., and Osborne, J. L. (2007). Honeybees perform optimal scale-free searching flights when attempting to locate a food source. The Journal of Experimental Biology, 210, 3763–3770.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Ridge, M. (2001). Taking solipsism seriously: nonhuman animals and meta-cognitive theories of consciousness. Philosophical Studies, 103, 315–340.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Riley, J. R., Greggers, U., Smith, A. D., Reynolds, D. R., and Menzel, R. (2005). The flight paths of honeybees recruited by the waggle dance. Nature, 435, 205–207.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Riley, J. R., Greggers, U., Smith, A. D., Stach, S., Reynolds, D. R., Stollhoff, N., Brandt, R., Schaupp, F., and Menzel, R. (2003). The automatic pilot of honeybees. Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B, 270, 2421–2424.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Ristau, C. (1996). Aspects of the cognitive ethology of an injury-feigning bird, the piping plover. In Bekoff, M. and Jamieson, D. (eds.), Readings in Animal Cognition. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Roberts, R. (1988). What an emotion is: a sketch. The Philosophical Review, 97, 183–209.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Roberts, R. (1996). Propositions and animal emotion. Philosophy, 71, 147–156.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Roberts, R. (2003). Emotions: An Essay in Aid of Moral Psychology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Roberts, R. (2009a). Emotions and the canons of evaluation. In Goldie, P. (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of the Philosophy of Emotion. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Roberts, R. (2009b). Emotional consciousness and personal relationships. Emotion Review.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Roberts, W. (2002). Are animals stuck in time?Psychological Bulletin, 128, 473–489.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Rosenthal, D. (1986). Two concepts of consciousness. Philosophical Studies, 49, 329–359.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rosenthal, D. (2005). Consciousness and Mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Ross, J. and McKinney, B. (1995). Dog Talk: Training Your Dog Through a Canine Point of View. New York: St. Martin's Press.Google Scholar
Rowell, T. E. and Hinde, R. A. (1962). Vocal communication by the rhesus monkey (Macaca mulatta). Proceedings of the Zoological Society of London, 138, 279–294.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Russell, B. (1919). Introduction to Mathematical Philosophy. New York: The Macmillan Company.Google Scholar
Russon, A. and Galdikas, B. (1993). Imitation in free-ranging rehabilitant orangutans (Pongo Pygmaeus). Journal of Comparative Psychology, 107, 147–161.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Saidel, E. (1998). Beliefs, desires, and the ability to learn. American Philosophical Quarterly, 35, 21–37.Google Scholar
Santos, L., Nissen, A., and Ferrugia, J. (2006). Rhesus monkeys, macaca mulatta, know what others can and cannot hear. Animal Behaviour, 71, 1175–1181.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Savage-Rumbaugh, S., Toth, N., and Schick, K. (2006). Kanzi learns to knapp stone tools. In Washburn, D. and Rumbaugh, D. (eds.), Primate Perspectives on Behavior and Cognition. Washington, DC: American Psychological Association.Google Scholar
Schwartz, B. L. (2005). Do nonhuman primates have episodic memory? In Terrace, H. and Metcalfe, J. (eds.), The Missing Link in Cognition: Origins of Self-Reflective Consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Schwartz, B. L., Hoffman, M., and Evans, S. (2005). Episodic-like memory in a gorilla: a review and new findings. Learning and Motivation, 36, 226–244.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schwartz, B. L., Travis, D. M., Castro, A. M., and Smith, S. M. (2000). The phenomenology of real and illusory tip-of-the-tongue states. Memory and Cognition, 28, 18–27.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Seager, W. (2004). A cold look at HOT theory. In Gennaro, R. (ed.), Higher-Order Theories of Consciousness. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.Google Scholar
Searle, J. (1983). Intentionality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Searle, J. (1994). Animal minds. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 19, 206–219.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sellars, W. (1963). Science, Perception, and Reality. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Seyfarth, R. M. and Cheney, D. L. (2002). The structure of social knowledge in monkeys. In Bekoff, M., Allen, C., and Burghardt, G. (eds.), The Cognitive Animal. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Seyfarth, R. M. and Cheney, D. L. (2003). Meaning and emotion in animal vocalizations. Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences, 1000, 32–55.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Seyfarth, R. M., Cheney, D. L., and Marler, P. (1980). Vervet monkey alarm calls: semantic communication in a free-ranging primate. Animal Behaviour, 28, 1070–1094.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shin, Sun-Joo (1994). The Logical Status of Diagrams. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Silk, J., Brosnan, S., Vonk, J., Henrich, J., Povinelli, D., Richardson, A., Lambeth, S., Mascaro, J., and Schapiro, S. (2005). Chimpanzees are indifferent to the welfare of unrelated group members. Nature, 437, 1357–1359.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Simmonds, M. (2006). Into the brains of whales. Applied Animal Behavior Science, 100, 103–116.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Skyrms, Brian (2004). The Stag Hunt and the Evolution of Social Structure. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Slobodchikoff, C. N. (2002). Cognition and communication in prairie dogs. In Bekoff, M., Allen, C., and Burghardt, G. M. (eds.), The Cognitive Animal. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Slobodchikoff, C. N., Fischer, C., and Shapiro, J. (1986). Predator-specific alarm calls of prairie dogs. American Zoologist, 26, 557.Google Scholar
Slobodchikoff, C. N., Kiriazis, J., Fischer, C., and Creef, E. (1991). Semantic information distinguishing individual predators in the alarm calls of Gunnison's prairie dogs. Animal Behaviour, 42, 713–719.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sloman, A. (1978). The Computer Revolution in Philosophy. Hassocks: The Harvester Press.Google Scholar
Sloman, S. (1996). The empirical case for two systems of reasoning. Psychological Bulletin, 119, 3–22.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sloman, S. (2002). Two systems of reasoning. In Gilovich, T., Griffin, D., and Kahneman, D. (eds.), Heuristics and Biases. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Smith, B. C. (1996). On the Origin of Objects. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Smith, J. D. (2005). Studies of uncertainty monitoring and metacognition in animals. In Terrace, H. and Metcalfe, J. (eds.), The Missing Link in Cognition: Origins of Self-Reflective Consciousness. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Smith, J. D., Beran, M. J., Redford, J. S., and Washburn, D. A. (2006). Dissociating uncertainty responses and reinforcement signals in the comparative study of uncertainty monitoring. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 135, 282–297.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Smith, J. D. and Schull, J. (1989). A failure of uncertainty monitoring in the rat (unpublished raw data). Cited in Shields, W., Smith, J. D., Guttmannova, K., and Washburn, D. (2005). Confidence judgments by humans and rhesus monkeys. Journal of General Psychology, 13, 165–186.Google Scholar
Smith, J. D., Shields, , Allendoerfer, W. E., Washburn, K. R., , D. A. (1998). Memory monitoring by animals and humans. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 127, 227–250.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Smith, J. D., Shields, W. E., and Washburn, D. A. (2003). The comparative psychology of uncertainty monitoring and metacognition. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 26, 317–373.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Smith, J. D. and Washburn, D. (2005). Uncertainty monitoring and metacognition by animals. Current Directions in Psychological Science, 14, 19–24.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smolensky, P. (1991). Connectionism, constituency and the language of thought. In Loewer, B. and Rey, G. (eds.), Meaning in Mind: Fodor and His Critics. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Smolensky, P. (1995). Reply: constituent structure and explanation in an integrated connectionist/symbolic cognitive architecture. In MacDonald, C. and MacDonald, G. (eds.), Connectionism: Debates on Psychological Explanation. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Sober, E. (1984). The Nature of Selection. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Sober, E. (1988). Reconstructing the Past: Parsimony, Evolution, and Inference. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Sober, E. (1990). Let's razor Ockham's razor. In Knowles, D. (ed.), Explanation and Its Limits. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Sober, E. (1998a). Black box inference: when should an intervening variable be postulated?British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 49, 469–498.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sober, E. (1998b). Morgan's canon. In Allen, C. and Cummins, D. (eds.), The Evolution of Mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Sober, E. (2000). Evolution and the problem of other minds. Journal of Philosophy, 97, 365–386.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sober, E. (2001). The principle of conservatism in cognitive ethology. In Walsh, D. (ed.), Naturalism, Evolution, and Mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Sober, E. (2005). Comparative psychology meets evolutionary biology: Morgan's canon and cladistic parsimony. In Daston, L. and Mitman, G. (eds.), Thinking with Animals: New Perspectives on Anthropomorphism. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Sober, E. (2008). Evidence and Evolution: The Logic Behind the Science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sober, E. and Wilson, D. (1998). Unto Others: The Evolution and Psychology of Unselfish Behavior. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Solomon, R. (1995). A Passion for Justice. Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield.Google Scholar
Solomon, R. (2003). Not Passion's Slave. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Son, L. K. and Kornell, N. (2005). Metaconfidence in rhesus macaques: explicit versus implicit mechanisms. In Terrace, H. S. and Metcalfe, J. (eds.), The Missing Link in Cognition: Origins of Self-Reflective Consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Sorabji, R. (1993). Animal Minds and Human Morals. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Stalnaker, R. (1984). Inquiry. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Stalnaker, R. (1999). Context and Content. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stanford, C. (2001). Significant Others: The Ape-Human Continuum and the Quest for Human Nature. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Stanovich, K. (1999). Who is Rational? Studies of Individual Differences in Reasoning. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.Google Scholar
Stich, S. (1979). Do animals have beliefs?Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 57, 15–28.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stich, S. (1983/1989). From Folk Psychology to Cognitive Science: The Case Against Belief. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Stoerig, P. (1996). Varieties of vision: from blind responses to conscious recognition. Trends in Neurosciences, 19, 401–406.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Strawson, P. F. (1959). Individuals. London: Methuen.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Struhsaker, T. T. (1967). Auditory communication among vervet monkeys (Cercopithecus aethiops). In Altman, S. A. (ed.), Social Communication among Primates. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Tautz, J., Zhang, S., Spaethe, J., Brockmann, A., Si, A., and Srinivasan, M. (2004). Honeybee odometry: performance in varying natural terrain. Public Library of Science: Biology, 2, 915–923.Google ScholarPubMed
Terrace, H. S. and Metcalfe, J. (2005). The Missing Link in Cognition: Origins of Self-Reflective Consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tetzlaff, M. J. (2006). Bee-ing There: The Systematicity of Honeybee Navigation Supports a Classical Theory of Honeybee Cognition. Dissertation Abstracts International, 67, no. 03A.
Thrun, S., Burgard, W., and Fox, D. (2005). Probabilistic Robotics. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Tinkelpaugh, O. (1928). An experimental study of representative factors in monkeys. Journal of Comparative Psychology, 8, 197–238.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tolman, E. (1948). Cognitive maps in rats and men. Psychological Review, 55, 189–208.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Tolstoy, L. (2007). War and Peace, trans. Pevear, R. and Volokhonsky, L.. New York: Knopf.Google Scholar
Tomasello, M. and Call, J. (1997). Primate Cognition. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Tomasello, M. and Call, J. (2006). Do chimpanzees know what others see – or only what they are looking at? In Hurley, S. and Nudds, M. (eds.), Rational Animals?Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Tomasello, M., Call, J., and Hare, B. (2003). Chimpanzees understand psychological states – the question is which ones and to what extent. Trends in Cognitive Science, 7, 153–156.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Toribio, J. (2007). Nonconceptual content. Philosophy Compass, 2, 445–460.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Travis, C. (1994). On constraints of generality. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 94, 165–188.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tschudin, A. (2001). “Mind-reading” mammals: attribution of belief tasks with dolphins. Animal Welfare, 10, S, 119–127.Google Scholar
Tulving, E. (1983). Elements of Episodic Memory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Tulving, E. (2005). Episodic memory and autonoesis: uniquely human? In Terrace, H. S. and Metcalfe, J. (eds.), The Missing Link in Cognition: Origins of Self-Reflective Consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Turing, A. (1950). Computing machinery and intelligence. Mind, 59, 433–460.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tye, M. (1997). The problem of simple minds: is there anything it is like to be a honey bee?Philosophical Studies, 88, 289–317.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tye, M. (2006). The thesis of nonconceptual content. European Review of Philosophy: The Structure of Nonconceptual Content, 6, 7–30.Google Scholar
Waal, F. (1991). Complimentary methods and convergent evidence in the study of primate social cognition. Behavior, 118, 297–320.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Waal, F. (2004). Brains and the beast. Natural History, 113, 53–56.Google Scholar
Waal, F. (2005). Our Inner Ape. New York: Riverhead Books.Google Scholar
Wei, C. A., Rafalko, S. L., and Dyer, F. C. (2002). Deciding to learn: modulation of learning flights in honeybees, Apis mellifera. Journal of Comparative Physiology A, 188, 725–737.Google ScholarPubMed
White, T. (2007). In Defense of Dolphins. Oxford: Blackwell.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Whiten, A. (1996). When does smart behavior-reading become mind-reading? In Carruthers, P. and Smith, P. (eds.), Theories of Theories of Mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Whiten, A. and Byrne, R. (1997). Machiavellian Intelligence II: Extensions and Evaluations. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Whiten, A. and Ham, R. (1992). On the nature and evolution of imitation in the animal kingdom: reappraisal of a century of research. In Slater, P., Rosenblatt, J., Beer, C., and Milinski, M. (eds.), Advances in the Study of Behavior, Vol. xxi. New York: Academic Press.Google Scholar
Wilson, B., Batty, R., and Dill, L. M. (2004). Pacific and Atlantic herring produce burst pulse sounds. Proceedings of the Royal Society of London Series B – Biological Sciences, 271, S95–S97.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Wilson, M. (1995). Animal ideas. Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, 69, 7–25.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wimsatt, W. C. (1986). Developmental constraints, generative entrenchment, and the innate-acquired distinction. In Bechtel, W. (ed.), Integrating Scientific Disciplines. Dordrecht: Martinus Nijhoff.Google Scholar
Wolpert, D. M. and Kawato, M. (1998). Multiple paired forward and inverse models for motor control. Neural Networks, 11, 1317–1329.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Wood, J., Glynn, D., Phillips, B., and Hauser, M. (2007). The perception of rational, goal-directed action in nonhuman primates. Science, 317, 1402–1405.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Wynne, C. D. L. (2004). Do Animals Think?Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Zentall, T. (2005). Animals may not be stuck in time. Learning and Motivation, 36, 208–225.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zhang, S., Schwarz, S., Pahl, M., Zhu, H., and Tautz, J. (2006). Honeybee memory: a honeybee knows what to do and when. The Journal of Experimental Biology, 209, 4420–4428.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zimmer, C. (2007). Time in the animal mind. The New York Times, April 3, F1, F6.Google Scholar
Zuberbühler, K. (2000). Referential labeling in Diana monkeys. Animal Behaviour, 59, 917–927.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • References
  • Edited by Robert W. Lurz, Brooklyn College, City University of New York
  • Book: The Philosophy of Animal Minds
  • Online publication: 05 June 2012
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511819001.017
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • References
  • Edited by Robert W. Lurz, Brooklyn College, City University of New York
  • Book: The Philosophy of Animal Minds
  • Online publication: 05 June 2012
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511819001.017
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • References
  • Edited by Robert W. Lurz, Brooklyn College, City University of New York
  • Book: The Philosophy of Animal Minds
  • Online publication: 05 June 2012
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511819001.017
Available formats
×