Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-77c89778f8-vpsfw Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-21T10:26:28.552Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Chapter 1 - Proto-arithmetical Abilities

from Part I - Ontogeny

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  15 March 2024

Markus Pantsar
Affiliation:
Aachen University of Technology

Summary

In Chapter 1, I present empirical research on proto-arithmetical abilities, that is, subitising and estimating, and emphasise the importance of distinguishing them from arithmetical abilities. I review the empirical literature on the cognitive basis of proto-arithmetical abilities, focusing mostly on the core cognitive theory of the object tracking system (OTS) and approximate numerosity system (ANS). Although the topic requires further research, I proceed with the view that the OTS and ANS are different cognitive systems and are responsible for the subitising and estimating abilities, respectively.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2024

In the Introduction, I stressed the importance of distinguishing between proto-arithmetical and proper arithmetical abilities. I suggested that the term ‘number’ should be reserved for developed mathematical abilities dealing with exact number concepts. In particular, talk of natural numbers should be restricted to the exact number concepts associated with arithmetic. Any quantitative ability that is not properly arithmetical or mathematical should be described in terms of treating numerosities. In Section 1.3, I will make the distinction between proto-arithmetical and arithmetical fully explicit. But, in order to do that, we first need to have a good understanding of what kind of abilities comprise proto-arithmetical cognition.

1.1 Object Tracking System and Subitising

Recall the experiment reported by Wynn (Reference Wynn1992), in which five-month-old infants reacted to ‘unnatural’ numerosity of the dolls by a longer looking time (Figure I.1). This experiment has been replicated many times in different variations and it is strongly established that it is indeed the numerosity of the objects that the infants react to, instead of other variables such as total visible surface area (for a review study of the replications see Christodoulou et al., Reference Christodoulou, Lac and Moore2017). The methodology of Wynn’s experiment is also widely accepted. Infants have a limited range of reacting, so longer looking times are generally interpreted as a reaction to them having seen something surprising (Cantrell & Smith, Reference Cantrell and Smith2013). And the infants indeed did show significantly longer looking times in the trials in which one doll and one doll put behind the screen revealed only one doll in the end. They were apparently surprised by the ‘unnatural’ numerosity.Footnote 1 Indeed, one replication of the original experiment showed that the infants were more surprised by the unnatural numerosity than they were by the actual dolls changing (from the Sesame Street character Elmo to Ernie, or vice versa) (Simon et al., Reference Simon, Hespos and Rochat1995). The unnatural quantity of objects seemed to be more surprising than the unnatural changes in the identity of the objects. This suggests that not only is numerosity one factor in how infant observations are processed in their minds, but it is a particularly important factor. But the question is, were the infants really doing arithmetic – as claimed by Wynn – and if not, what was the cognitive capacity they were applying?

The first experiment to establish an infant ability with numerosities was reported by Starkey and Cooper (Reference Starkey and Cooper1980). They used the standard method of habituation to test whether infants (twenty-two weeks old) are sensitive to changes in numerosity. The infants were habituated to an array of two or three dots and then shown an array where the quantity of the dots had changed (either from three to two or from two to three). The children reacted by longer looking times. The experiment was controlled for other variables, such as the spatial arrangement of the dots, and Starkey and Cooper concluded that it was the numerosity that the infants were sensitive to. Importantly, they did not show the same ability to discriminate between the numerosity of the dots when it was increased to four and six. These results prompted Starkey and Cooper to conclude that the infants were subitising when discriminating between the numerosity of the dots.

The term ‘subitising’ was coined by Kaufman and colleagues (Reference Kaufman, Lord, Reese and Volkmann1949) and it refers to making fast, accurate judgements about the numerosity of observed items. The existence of this ability has been confirmed in many experiments and in adult humans it gives an alternative method to counting for determining the numerosity of objects reliably. Trick and Pylyshyn (Reference Trick and Pylyshyn1994) studied reaction times in determining the quantity of dots and saw a clear difference between one and four dots when compared to larger numerosities. While four and fewer items typically take 40–200 ms/item to enumerate, more than four items take 250–350 ms/item. As seen in Figure 1.1, there is a clear difference when the numerosity increases beyond four. This is because five is already beyond the subitising range. For numerosities from one to four, the subjects were able to subitise the answer, which is a much faster process. For numerosities larger than four, they needed to count to enumerate the objects.

Figure 1.1 Reaction time in enumeration tasks.*

* We can see a clear difference in the reaction time (y-axis, milliseconds) when the number of dots increases over the subitising range (one to four).

Data from Trick and Pylyshyn (Reference Trick and Pylyshyn1994).

What Starkey and Cooper (Reference Starkey and Cooper1980) established was that infants can already subitise. This ability seems to be behind the infant behaviour also in the experiment of Wynn (Reference Wynn1992). Infants lack the resources to count, as already suggested by their inability to discriminate between four and six dots in the experiment of Starkey and Cooper (Reference Starkey and Cooper1980), but they are able to subitise. So, what the infants could be doing in the doll experiment is subitising the numerosity of the visible dolls and then conducting calculations to create expectations concerning the numerosity of the dolls when the screen is lifted. This certainly appears to be Wynn’s (Reference Wynn1992) interpretation of the data: that subitising is a process that encodes numerical information. In short, according to her, the infants subitise the numerosity of the dolls and they possess numerical concepts that they can use to calculate expectations.

Others, however, are more sceptical. Uller et al. (Reference Uller, Carey, Huntley-Fenner and Klatt1999) have suggested that a cognitively simpler explanation can explain the infant behaviour. In contrast to the numerical concept model proposed by Wynn, they have suggested that an object file model can explain the same data. Object files refer to the way visual experience is processed cognitively to identify persisting objects (Kahneman et al., Reference Kahneman, Treisman and Gibbs1992; Noles et al., Reference Noles, Scholl and Mitroff2005). Kahneman and colleagues (Reference Kahneman, Treisman and Gibbs1992) introduced object files as theoretical concepts to explain how successive states of objects are connected in visual experiences. Noles and colleagues (Reference Noles, Scholl and Mitroff2005) have proposed that these object files can explain how our everyday perceptual experiences are formed in terms of persisting objects. The object files are closely connected to the ability to track multiple objects at once (Spelke, Reference Spelke2000; Trick & Pylyshyn, Reference Trick and Pylyshyn1994). Three dots in our field of vision, for example, are not represented as some kind of observed ‘threeness’ but rather in three distinct object files.

Susan Carey (Reference Carey2009) has argued that object tracking is a core cognitive ability. Core cognition refers to the way human cognition is thought to begin with ‘highly structured innate mechanisms designed to build representations with specific content’ (Carey, Reference Carey2009, p. 67). In this core cognitive framework, the object tracking system (OTS) is then considered to be the cognitive system responsible for the ability to subitise (Knops, Reference Knops2020). Each observed object occupies an object file and this makes it possible to determine the numerosity of observed items without counting them. Since the object tracking ability is closely connected to the ability to individuate objects in a parallel fashion, the OTS is often also referred to as the parallel individuation system in the literature (e.g., Carey, Reference Carey2009; Cheung & Le Corre, Reference Cheung and Le Corre2018; Hyde, Reference Hyde2011).

In Chapter 2, I will present in detail Carey’s account of how natural number concepts are acquired on the basis of the OTS, but for now the important point is that the object tracking system and the associated object files provide an alternative explanation for the infant behaviour in Wynn’s (Reference Wynn1992) experiment. What if the dolls simply occupied object files in the minds of the infants? They expected the dolls to be persisting objects and, when there was only one doll instead of two, this violated their object file occupancy. As I see it, this explanation can accommodate the Wynn experiment in a satisfactory manner. Importantly, there is no need to presuppose that the infants were engaging in arithmetical calculations, nor that they process true numerical concepts. They could simply expect to see the dolls as persisting objects.

But what about the change from Elmo to Ernie (or vice versa), as reported by Simon and colleagues (Reference Simon, Hespos and Rochat1995)? If the above suggestion about object files is along the right lines, should the children not have been more surprised by the changing identity of the dolls than the changing numerosity of the dolls? I believe that there is a good explanation also for this. The object tracking system, and hence the object files, are thought to be cognitively between low-level sensory processing and higher levels of cognition (Noles et al., Reference Noles, Scholl and Mitroff2005). The object files are not the kind of cognitive apparatus that is used for identifying dolls. They are much cruder, with the (putative) purpose of tracking objects across time and movement. Indeed, given the proposed character of the OTS, we would expect that infants are more sensitive to the changing numerosity than they are to the changing identity, at least as long as the latter is not more significant than a change from one doll to another.

The OTS, as should be clear by now, is not numerosity-specific. It is thought to be responsible for tracking objects and individuating them parallelly as persisting objects. However, since it makes the subitising ability possible, it is highly relevant for the topic of this book. Indeed, the OTS appears to be responsible for much of what is misleadingly called ‘infant arithmetic’ and ‘animal arithmetic’ in the literature. When infants in Wynn’s (Reference Wynn1992) experiment are supposed to do arithmetical calculations, what they could really be doing is simply applying the OTS in tracking parallel individual objects. When Hauser and colleagues observed similar behaviour in wild rhesus monkeys and Garland and Low with New Zealand robins, again the data could be explained as based on the OTS without postulating numerical concepts or arithmetical ability (Garland & Low, Reference Garland and Low2014; Hauser et al., Reference Hauser, MacNeilage and Ware1996).

I do not mean to downplay the cognitive abilities of infants and non-human animals, nor to suggest that they neither observe cardinalities nor discriminate between numerosities. While the OTS is not a numerosity-specific system, it enables the subitising ability that I consider to be proto-arithmetical. As such, as we will see, it is highly important for explaining the development of arithmetical cognition. But it is important not to postulate cognitive abilities beyond what is needed for explaining the observed behaviour. The problem is that the ascription of arithmetical abilities can initially seem so fitting for the kind of behaviour we have been discussing. The explanation according to which infants first calculate 1 + 1 = 2, and the unfolding situation then violates their expectations, describes their behaviour in a very palpable, dare I say exciting, way. Yet the foundation of my methodology is that we should fight every temptation to propose such explanations if there is another, cognitively less demanding explanation available.Footnote 2 In the OTS, there is such an explanation available for a lot of the observed infant and non-human animal behaviour. But not all, as we will see in Section 1.2.

1.2 Approximate Numerosity System

In Section 1.1, I have suggested that the infant behaviour in the experiment reported by Wynn (Reference Wynn1992) and its replications can be explained by the activation of the object tracking system. However, McCrink and Wynn (Reference McCrink and Wynn2004) designed a computerised version of the experiment in which, instead of one and two dolls, five or ten blobs showed on the screen. In their study, nine-month-old infants showed similar longer looking times in cases of unnatural numerosity (equivalent, for example, to the unnatural arithmetic of 5 + 5 = 5) as the infants did in the original Wynn (Reference Wynn1992) experiment and its many replications. But now the OTS hypothesis fails, because five and ten are both beyond the OTS range of numerosities. Certainly, the infants were not counting the items, so what was the cognitive capacity they were employing?

This area of research goes back to the nineteenth century, when the pioneering psychologists Ernst Weber and Gustav Fechner studied the way humans perceive physical stimuli. What they established was that the perception of many types of stimuli, related, for example, to brightness, loudness and weight, follows a similar law, according to which the noticeable difference between two stimuli is related to the overall magnitudes of the stimuli (Fechner, Reference Fechner and Dennis1860). For example, humans are able to detect the difference between weights of 100 and 120 grams, but not between 1,000 and 1,020 grams, although the absolute difference in the weights is the same. They can, however, distinguish between the weights of 1,000 grams and 1,200 grams, where the ratio is the same as in the former case (100 : 120 = 1000 : 1200). This logarithmic relationship between actual physical intensity and perceived intensity has become known in the literature as Weber-Fechner Law (or nowadays, more commonly, simply Weber’s Law) (Knops, Reference Knops2020).

What does the Weber-Fechner Law have to do with the McCrink and Wynn experiment? As it turns out, one of the stimuli that humans (and many non-human animals) perceive according to the Weber-Fechner Law concerns numerosity. Data show that there is an evolutionarily developed non-verbal capacity to estimate numerosities beyond the OTS range (Dehaene, Reference Dehaene2011). Dehaene has called this cognitive capacity number sense but more commonly in the literature it is referred to as the approximate number system (ANS) (e.g., Spelke, Reference Spelke2000). Here I will refer to this cognitive system as the approximate numerosity system (while retaining the same acronym ANS), in order to distinguish between the pre-verbal ANS-representations and exact number concepts.Footnote 3

In an influential experiment, Xu and Spelke (Reference Xu and Spelke2000) tested infants (six months of age) for the perception of numerosity stimuli. The infants were habituated to arrays of either eight or sixteen dots (Figure 1.2). When habituated to eight dots, infants reacted with surprise when presented with four or sixteen dots, but not when the array had twelve dots. When habituated to sixteen dots, they reacted to arrays of eight and thirty-two dots, but not twenty-four. This suggests that six-month-olds are sensitive to difference in numerosity when the ratio is 1:2. It has been shown that this ratio gets smaller with development. Lipton and Spelke (Reference Lipton and Spelke2003) showed that the ratio is 2:3 for nine-month-olds. This development in ANS-acuity continues all the way through pre-school and school years, normally peaking around thirty years of age (Halberda et al., Reference Halberda, Ly, Wilmer, Naiman and Germine2012). However, at all stages the ANS-based numerosity estimations remain approximate and follow the Weber-Fechner Law. This can be seen in the two standard signatures of ANS-based estimation (Dehaene, Reference Dehaene2003). First is the distance effect, meaning that distinguishing between numerosities becomes easier as the numerical distance between them increases. Second is the size effect, according to which the estimations become less accurate as the numerosities become larger.

Figure 1.2 Numerosity estimation by infants.*

* Xu and Spelke (Reference Xu and Spelke2000) habituated six-month-old infants to arrays of either eight or sixteen dots and tested their reactions to changing numerosity of dots.

Reproduced with permission.

In addition to visual stimuli, the ANS also activates from other kinds of sensory stimuli. Izard and colleagues (Reference Izard, Sann, Spelke and Streri2009) habituated neonates with a series of tones and then presented them with a visual array of items. As in experiments with purely visual stimuli, the infants looked longer when the visual array was different in numerosity from the tones. This suggests that the ANS representations are indeed about abstract numerosities, in the sense that they are not specific to any particular type of sensory stimulus.

Not everyone agrees with this. It has been argued that, instead of evoking abstract representations numerosities, the data can be explained by cognitive systems of sensory integration involving continuous magnitudes (Gebuis et al., Reference Gebuis, Cohen Kadosh and Gevers2016; Leibovich et al., Reference Leibovich, Katzin, Harel and Henik2017). The main reason for this criticism of the ANS is due to what Clarke and Beck (Reference Clarke and Beck2021) call the numerical congruency effect, which shows that judgements of numerosity are often influenced also by the perception of non-numerical magnitudes, such as object size. An instructive example of this was presented by Henik and Tzelgov (Reference Henik and Tzelgov1982), who showed that (adult) subjects show a numerical Stroop effect, that is, they have longer reaction times and lower accuracy in estimating which number is larger when the size of the physical numeral symbol was incongruent to the numerical value (e.g., the pair 5 3 was more difficult to process than the pair 5 3). However, as argued by Clarke and Beck (Reference Clarke and Beck2021), this kind of argument against the ANS is problematic, since congruency effects are also present in many judgements of magnitudes. For example, judgements of duration show a congruency effect on size, length and distance (Casasanto & Boroditsky, Reference Casasanto and Boroditsky2008; Sarrazin et al., Reference Sarrazin, Giraudo, Pailhous, Bootsma and Giraudo2004; Xuan et al., Reference Xuan, Zhang, He and Chen2007). Yet, duration is uncontroversially accepted as being perceptible and not derived from other magnitudes.

Another argument against the ANS is what Clarke and Beck (Reference Clarke and Beck2021) call the argument from confounds. As pointed out by Leibovich and colleagues (Reference Leibovich, Katzin, Harel and Henik2017), in the experiments with arrays of dots, for example, there are always confounding variables. When the array of dots is changed and one non-numerical variable (e.g., item size or cumulative area) is controlled for, at the same time some other variable (e.g., the cumulative area or density) also changes. How is it possible to control for all non-numerical variables and thus be certain that it is the numerosity that the subjects are sensitive to? The simple answer is that it is not. The best we can hope for is to get enough corroborating cross-modal evidence to support the hypothesis that the ANS is sensitive to numerosity. Here I cannot go into the details of the cumulating evidence, but it seems clear that in many criticisms the ANS hypothesis is put under unreasonable criteria. There are very few experiments that can be said to test sensitivity to only one property of sensory stimuli. The arguments from congruency and confounds are problematic because by the same criteria many other cognitive capacities in detaching one property (duration, size, luminance, etc.) would be in doubt. In this, the ANS does not fare any worse and, hence, I do not see a convincing reason to doubt that the ANS is indeed sensitive to numerosity.Footnote 4

Now the question is, if the ANS represents numerosity, how does it do it? As we have seen, the OTS is thought to represent numerosity implicitly in object files. What is the mechanism underlying the ANS? Following the work of Dehaene (Reference Dehaene2003), it is common to speak of the ANS as representing numerosities in a mental number line. Again, I want to correct the terminology to mental numerosity line. Dehaene argued that the Weber-Fechner Law of numerosity estimations can be explained from a neural basis by postulating an innate, logarithmic mental line on which numerosity estimations are represented (Dehaene, Reference Dehaene2003).Footnote 5

On a logarithmic number line, the distances between numbers become smaller as the numbers become larger. On a linear number line, which most students become familiar with on the primary level, numbers are evenly spaced. This question of ‘logarithmic or linear’ has been an important topic in research on numerical cognition. However, it is important to note that there are two different questions involved. First is whether the ANS-based estimations follow a logarithmic rather than linear structure. The second concerns how the ANS-based representations are realised in the brain. When it comes to the first question, there is little doubt (see, e.g., Nieder & Dehaene, Reference Nieder and Dehaene2009). In general, the ANS-based estimations are characterised by their logarithmic manner, following the Weber-Fechner Law: establishing the difference between, say, sets of six and seven objects is easier than that between sixteen and seventeen objects. Importantly, this is a property of the proto-arithmetical processing of numerosities. Empirical data show that, when asked to place numerosities on a line, people in cultures with limited or no proper numeral systems (such as the Pirahã and the Munduruku of the Amazon) place the numerosities in a way that is best modelled as logarithmic (Dehaene et al., Reference Dehaene, Izard, Spelke and Pica2008; Pica et al., Reference Pica, Lemer, Izard and Dehaene2004).Footnote 6

But the second question, how the ANS-based representations are realised in the brain, is more controversial.Footnote 7 The way the ANS represents numerosities has been debated ever since Meck and Church (Reference Meck and Church1983) proposed their ‘accumulator’ model in which numerosity information extracted from sensory input is represented on a linear scale. This account was first contested by Dehaene and Changeux (Reference Dehaene and Changeux1993), who proposed a neuronal model in which the ANS-based representations are logarithmic. This model has since received important support from new experiments, which show that the neuronal activity in the prefrontal cortex in primates is best described by a ‘nonlinear compressed scaling of numerical information’ (Nieder & Miller, Reference Nieder and Miller2003). In further research, Andreas Nieder (Reference Anderson2016) has established that the primate brain has dedicated ‘number neurons’ in the intraparietal sulcus (IPS), which are thought to encode the numerosity of items in a sensory stimulus. These neurons – better called ‘numerosity neurons’ in the present terminology – appear to activate in association with the same numerosity independently of the sensory modality, suggesting that they represent numerosity in an abstract manner.Footnote 8 The numerosity neurons carry some ‘noise’, that is, when the neurons associated with the observation of seven items activate, so do some of the neurons associated with six and eight. This noise increases as the numerosities become larger, thus reflecting the Weber-Fechner Law (Nieder, Reference Nieder2016).Footnote 9

If Nieder is correct, then ANS-based representations can be located in the brain, more specifically in the intraparietal sulcus. But how are the representations coded and organised neurally? A lot of further work is needed on both questions, but the data reported by Nieder suggests that the numerosity representations are in some way located in a spatially ordered fashion (Nieder, Reference Netz2006). Thus, the metaphor of a mental numerosity line may not be, to some degree, only a metaphor. The well-known phenomenon of spatial-numerical association of response codes (SNARC) seems to support this. The SNARC effect shows that Western subjects standardly respond more quickly to small numerosities if they are on the left extrapersonal hemiside of their perceived environment, whereas they respond faster to larger numerosities if they are on the right extrapersonal hemiside of their perceived environment. This suggests that there is a spatial association of small numerosities being on the left side and larger on the right side, as with the standard number line (Dehaene et al., Reference Dehaene and Changeux1993).Footnote 10

The SNARC effect has also been reported in non-human animals, even in new-born chicks that, like humans, seemed to place smaller numerosities on the left side and larger ones on the right (Rugani et al., Reference Rugani, Vallortigara, Priftis and Regolin2015). This has been seen as evidence for the early evolutionary origins of the mental number line (see, e.g., Knops, Reference Knops2020, p. 61). However, Beran and colleagues (Reference Beran, Evans, Leighty, Harris and Rice2008) failed to observe any space-numerosity association effect in rhesus and capuchin monkeys. It could well be that there is a missing factor in the experiment on chicks that made them associate smaller numerosities with the left side, and a mental number line was not responsible for this behaviour. Thus, with the present evidence, we should be careful about making inferences from the SNARC effect.

Finally, it should be noted that not all researchers agree that the ANS and the OTS are separate core cognitive systems. While this is the view held by most researchers (e.g., Agrillo, Reference Agrillo, Cohen Kadosh and Dowker2015; Carey, Reference Carey2009; Dehaene, Reference Dehaene2011; Feigenson et al., Reference Feigenson, Dehaene and Spelke2004; Hyde, Reference Hyde2011; Spelke, Reference Spelke, Dehaene and Brannon2011), recently Cheyette and Piantadosi (Reference Cheyette and Piantadosi2020) have proposed that there could in fact only be one innate numerosity system. One common argument for the existence of two systems is the discontinuity between identifying items in collections in the OTS range and those beyond that range. While collections of up to four items are identified almost perfectly, following the Weber-Fechner Law larger collections are identified increasingly inaccurately. Cheyette and Piantadosi, however, present a mathematical model which suggests that this difference between small and large numerosities would be part of an optimal representation of cardinal numerosities also in a single cognitive system. This question requires further study, but it is by no means certain that the OTS and ANS are indeed separate cognitive systems.Footnote 11

The question of whether there are one or two core cognitive systems sensitive to numerosity of course prompts the question of just what a core cognitive system is. Every cognitive system comparable to the OTS and the ANS is a higher-level abstraction of neuronal activity. As such, we should not be ontologically committed to cognitive systems beyond what is necessary for explanations. If Cheyette and Piantadosi are correct and there can be a mathematical model that necessitates only one system, with an Occam-like principle it would seem to be preferable over two-system models. However, a mathematical model should also be consistent with brain-imaging data. Supporting the two-system model, subitising and estimating have been reported to have different neural correlates in an fNIRS (functional near-infrared spectroscopy) study (Cutini et al., Reference Cutini, Scatturin, Moro and Zorzi2014).Footnote 12

In this book, I will follow the two-system model, but I recognise that this remains an open question. As of now, the evidence still appears to favour the existence of the OTS and the ANS as distinct systems, and the association of the subitising ability with the former and the estimation ability with the latter. It could be that this understanding of the core cognitive abilities needs to be adjusted, but for the present approach that would not make a dramatic difference. The account I will be developing is compatible also with a single-system account. Instead of the particular core cognitive systems, the present account makes important use of the subitising and estimating abilities. That these are two different abilities is much less controversial than the two cognitive systems being different.Footnote 13

1.3 Proto-arithmetic and Arithmetic

In Sections 1.1 and 1.2 we have seen that many experiments with infants and non-human animals can be explained by them employing the object tracking system or the approximate numerosity system (or perhaps both), with no reason to postulate more sophisticated numerical abilities to explain the behaviour. However, not all experimental data can be explained this way. Cantlon and Brannon (Reference Cantlon and Brannon2007) conducted an experiment in which macaques were shown two configurations of dots on a screen (for 500 milliseconds each, corresponding to, for example, Footnote 1 + 1 = 2 or 2 + 2 = 4) and then were made to choose between two options on a screen for the correct sum. What they observed was that the macaque performance was largely comparable to that of college students in the same non-verbal task. The conclusion of Cantlon and Brannon was that the ‘data demonstrate that nonverbal arithmetic is not unique to humans but is instead part of an evolutionarily primitive system for mathematical thinking shared by monkeys’ (Cantlon & Brannon, Reference Cantlon and Brannon2007, p. 1).

These data are difficult to explain by simple mental numerosity representations of cardinality. What the macaque were reported to be doing seem to be genuine operations on numerosities. What this suggests is that the OTS- and ANS-based numerosity representations can be manipulated mentally. This is an important finding and is corroborated by many experiments. Indeed, the macaque behaviour is far from the only reported infant and non-human animal behaviour concerning numerosities that is truly remarkable (see, e.g., Agrillo, Reference Agrillo, Cohen Kadosh and Dowker2015; and Pepperberg, Reference Pepperberg2012 for studies on new-born chicks and parrots, respectively). Furthermore, it seems that numerosity is the decisive factor in most of the reported cases. Yet, again, we should be cautious not to postulate more sophisticated cognitive abilities than is needed to account for the behaviour. That is why, also in this case, it is important to stick to the distinction between proto-arithmetic and arithmetic.

Due to the short reaction times required in the experiment reported by Cantlon and Brannon, the college students could not revert to their arithmetical ability. With more time, they could have easily counted the dots and outperform the macaques. One main point of the experiment was to deny them that chance, in order to test their ‘nonverbal arithmetic’ skills against those of the macaques. However, while it is possible that there are nonverbal arithmetical skills, the experiment of Cantlon and Brannon did not test them. What it tested was the way macaques and humans use their proto-arithmetical, evolutionarily developed, skills in cardinality processing tasks. As such, however, the results are highly important. They show that monkeys can process operational transformations of numerosities. Indeed, another study by Cantlon and colleagues showed that this monkey proto-arithmetical ability carries some of the same signatures as human (proper) arithmetical ability, like the problem size effect, according to which reaction times and error rates increase as the numerosity sizes become larger (Cantlon et al., Reference Cantlon, Merritt and Brannon2016).

Yet even this should not make us think of human arithmetical ability merely as a specification of evolutionarily developed proto-arithmetical abilities. The problem size effect, for example, is a common characteristic of both proto-arithmetic and arithmetic, but this can be due to different factors. While with the ANS the problem size effect is due to the Weber-Fechner Law, with mental arithmetic it can be due to the increasing computational and cognitive complexity of the task (Buijsman & Pantsar, Reference Buijsman and Pantsar2020; Pantsar, Reference Pantsar2019a, Reference Pantsar2021b). Due to limitations in working memory and attention span, for most people arithmetical calculations quickly become prohibitively complex to be carried out mentally (see, e.g., Imbo et al., Reference Imbo, Duverne and Lemaire2007). It is possible that there are some common grounds for the problem size effect for proto-arithmetical tasks and arithmetical tasks. But it is also likely that, due to the important differences in the tasks – for example, only the latter including verbal or symbolic processing – the two effects have partly different causes. For this reason, we cannot assume that arithmetical calculations are a developmental continuation of proto-arithmetical transformations of numerosities.

Nevertheless, there are important connections between arithmetical and proto-arithmetical processes. For example, consider the following extremely simple task: Which one of the numbers below is bigger?

45

Compare that to the task of finding out which of these numbers are bigger:

49

One would not expect arithmetically skilled humans to show differences in reaction times, but the data show that the top pairing takes considerably longer than the bottom pairing. This is consistent with the distance effect: the larger the numerical distance between two numbers, the faster we are in solving the problem (Dehaene, Reference Dehaene2011, pp. 62–64). It is interesting that the distance effect remains even when the test subjects are trained to solve the problem. It even remains when the quickest way of solving the problem only requires comparing the first digits of multi-digit numbers. For example, consider the pairing:

7165

Now compare it to the pairing:

7965

In this case, one would certainly expect the reaction times to be similar, given that in both cases it only needs to be established that 7 is bigger than 6. Yet the distance effect remains (Hinrichs et al., Reference Hinrichs, Yurko and Hu1981; Pinel et al., Reference Pinel, Dehaene, Riviere and LeBihan2001). It even remains when the task is to determine whether two numbers are the same, in which case it suffices to only determine that two physical shapes are different, as well as when numeral words replace numeral symbols (Dehaene & Akhavein, Reference Dehaene and Cohen1995).

The generally accepted explanation for all these results is that seeing numeral symbols (or numeral words) automatically activates the ANS and makes us process the numerosities as magnitudes (Dehaene, Reference Dehaene2011, p. 16). Conforming to the Weber-Fechner Law, when the numerical distance is larger, the task of choosing the bigger number gets easier. It is important to note that the distance effect, unlike the problem size effect, is not a characteristic of arithmetical cognition. But even in tasks where arithmetical skills would be all that is needed, and the proto-arithmetical skills indeed only delay the correct solution, it seems that we cannot escape our proto-arithmetical origins. Even when trained for particular tasks that do not require assessing the numerical size, subjects cannot help processing it.

What these, and many other, experimental data suggest is that there is a connection between proto-arithmetical abilities and arithmetical abilities that endures also in arithmetically skilled individuals. Thus, the question becomes how the proto-arithmetical abilities are employed in the development of arithmetical abilities and arithmetical knowledge. In early literature on the development of numerical cognition, it was thought that arithmetic is made possible by first forming semantic representations of numerals and numeral symbols (e.g., McCloskey, Reference McCloskey1992; McCloskey & Macaruso, Reference McCloskey and Macaruso1995). This was contrasted by the ‘triple-code’ model of Dehaene and Cohen (Reference Dehaene and Cohen1995), in which there are thought to be different representations of numerosities (visual symbolic, auditory verbal and approximate numerosity estimations). In the triple-code model, these representations have different roles in numerical cognition tasks. This model has been further refined by Campbell and colleagues (Campbell, Reference Campbell1994; Campbell & Epp, Reference Campbell and Epp2004), whose ‘encoding complex’ model includes interactions between the different kinds of representations.Footnote 14 In Chapter 2, we will focus on the issue of how the representations in the triple-code model are made possible. Indeed, so far with regard to the ANS, we have only focused on the third type of representation, that of the approximate numerosity estimations. Thus, the big question is how these proto-arithmetical representations – as well as those provided by the OTS – are employed in acquiring exact number concepts, that is, arithmetical representations of cardinalities.

Before we move on to that question, it should be noted that not everyone wants to make the present distinctions between proto-arithmetic and arithmetic, as well as numerosities and numbers, even when aware of the kind of problems I have been discussing. I assume that, by now, most empirical researchers have encountered the kind of criticism that I have presented against incongruent use of terminology, yet they do not seem to have a problem with continuing to write about ‘infant arithmetic’ or ‘animal arithmetic’. For the most part, such issues do not seem to be seen as particularly important among empirical researchers. Some authors, however, explicitly justify their choice of terminology. Carey, for example, writes:

In the literature on mathematical cognition, analogue magnitude number representations are sometimes called ‘numerosity’ representations, for they are representations of the cardinal values of sets of individuals, rather than fully abstract number representations. There is no evidence that animals or babies entertain thoughts about 7 (even approximately 7) in the absence of a set of entities they are attending to. Still, cardinal values of sets are numbers, which is why I speak of analogue magnitude number representations rather than numerosity representations.

(Carey, Reference Carey2009, p. 136)

I can understand the practical side of using the more familiar word ‘number’ instead of the technical term ‘numerosity’. But Carey’s reason for her use of vocabulary is hardly satisfactory. While it is correct that (cardinal) numbers are measures of cardinality of sets, so are (cardinal) numerosities in the sense used by myself and others (e.g., De Cruz et al., Reference De Cruz and De Smedt2010; Dos Santos, Reference Dos Santos2022). The entire point of introducing a new technical term such as ‘numerosity’ is to differentiate between two ways of representing the cardinal values of sets. Hence, Carey’s reasoning for sticking with the term ‘number’ is quite problematic.

Another explicit justification for speaking about numbers instead of numerosities in the context of the ANS has recently been given by Clarke and Beck (Reference Clarke and Beck2021). They argue that:

[T]he ANS represents numbers (i.e., that numbers serve as the referents of the ANS), but under a unique mode of presentation that respects the imprecision inherent in the ANS … This will allow us to avoid a commitment to exotic entities such as ‘numerosities’ without losing sight of the important differences between ANS representations and the precise numerical concepts that emerge later in development.

(Clarke & Beck, Reference Clarke and Beck2021, p. 5)

Like others – for example, Dutilh Novaes and dos Santos (Reference Dutilh Novaes and dos Santos2021) and Núñez et al. (Reference Núñez, d’Errico, Gray and Bender2021) – I find this justification equally unsatisfactory to Carey’s. In my terminology, the ANS represents cardinality in terms of numerosity representations. With these distinctions in place already in the terminology, it is impossible to lose sight of the differences between the ANS representations and precise numerical concepts. Knowing how often in the literature problems have arisen because the two have been confused, why not distinguish between them in the terminology? If the reason is simply that numerosities as entities are considered to be ‘exotic’, surely that is a weak justification. As Clarke and Beck concede, we need to distinguish between ANS representations and exact number concepts in any case. So, if there is an exotic entity involved, it is already included in the ANS representations. It only makes sense that we would use a different scientific term when introducing theoretically novel entities like that. Hence, to conclude this chapter, I believe it is more important than ever to distinguish between proto-arithmetic and arithmetic, as well as between numerosities and numbers. In Chapter 2, we will fully grasp why, as we tackle the question of how number concepts can arise on the basis of numerosity representations.

1.4 Summary

In this chapter, I presented the proto-arithmetical abilities, that is, subitising and estimating, and emphasised the importance of distinguishing them from arithmetical abilities. I reviewed the empirical literature on the cognitive basis of proto-arithmetical abilities, focusing on the core cognitive theory of the object tracking system (OTS) and approximate numerosity system (ANS). Although the topic requires further research, I proceed with the view that the OTS and ANS are different cognitive systems and responsible for subitising and estimating abilities, respectively.

Footnotes

1 By ‘unnatural’ I mean nothing more than behaviour of objects that would generally be considered to conflict with physical laws concerning macro-level objects.

2 In comparative psychology, this principle is known as Morgan’s Canon and it states roughly that animal activity should never be interpreted in terms of higher psychological processes if it can also be interpreted in terms of lower processes (Morgan, Reference Morgan1894). While Morgan’s Canon can be problematic when used as a blunt instrument, I believe that some form of this kind of parsimony principle is justified.

3 In the literature, ANS is also used as an acronym for analogue number system, referring to the same capacity (see, e.g., Geary et al., Reference Geary, Berch and Mann Koepke2014).

4 See Clarke and Beck (Reference Clarke and Beck2021) for a more thorough discussion on the topic. However, it is important to keep in mind that they explicitly argue that the ANS is sensitive to number, which I disagree with.

5 Interestingly, there is new research suggesting that already the pupil of the eye is sensitive to numerosity. According to a study reported by Castaldi and colleagues (Reference Castaldi, Pomè, Cicchini, Burr and Binda2021), numerosity modulates an automatic reflex in pupil dilation, ‘suggesting that numerosity is a spontaneously encoded visual feature’ (p. 1). If this is confirmed, it is reason to not approach ANS in a brain-centric manner but consider it in a wider context of our neural architecture connected to sensory organs.

6 However, this is not always the case (Núñez, Reference Núñez2011). Perhaps most importantly, Núñez points out that 37 per cent of the experimental runs on the Munduruku reported in Dehaene et al. (Reference Dehaene, Izard, Spelke and Pica2008) showed a bimodal response that used only the endpoints of the number line. Thus, the results reported by Dehaene and colleagues are better interpreted in a conditional manner: if people place numerosities on the entire number line in non-arithmetical cultures, it is in a logarithmic rather than linear manner.

7 Instead of representations, some authors write about ‘coding schemes’ (see, e.g., Dehaene, Reference Dehaene2001b). As mentioned earlier, I am not committed to a representationalist model of the brain, so a non-representationalist is welcome to interpret this part to concern coding schemes.

8 Not everybody agrees. Vandervert, for example, argues that given the association of the prefrontal and parietal brain regions also with movement in space and time, it ‘might therefore be more appropriate to suggest that the many research findings leading to Nieder’s “number neurons” are simply about differential magnitudes related to the dynamics and kinematics of cognition and movement associated with the perceptual–cognitive control of body movement that occurred in humans, for example during stone-tool evolution’ (Vandervert, Reference Vandervert2021, p. 125).

9 In addition to primate studies, brain imaging on humans show activation in the IPS connected to numerical tasks. Further evidence for the location of non-verbal numerosity representations in the brain comes from malfunctioning proto-arithmetical abilities in subjects who have suffered brain injury localised in the left parietal lobe, including the left intraparietal sulcus (Ashkenazi et al., Reference Ashkenazi, Henik, Ifergane and Shelef2008; Lemer et al., Reference Lemer, Dehaene, Spelke and Cohen2003). For more details on this topic, as well as a good general exposition of the research on non-verbal ability with numerosities, I refer the reader to Nieder (Reference Nieder2019).

10 The direction of SNARC effect does not vary with handedness, but it does change with the direction of writing. Iranian and Arabic subjects accustomed to right-to-left writing responded faster to larger numerosities on the left extrapersonal hemiside (Dehaene et al., Reference Dehaene, Bossini and Giraux1993; Zebian, Reference Zebian2005). Thus, the evidence points to spatial association with numerosity size being universal, but the direction depending on the cultural custom of writing.

11 In Pantsar (Reference Pantsar2014), I supported the one-system theory myself, but in the face of the state of the art in empirical research, in later works I have focused on the two-system model.

12 Recently there have also emerged results from AI research that have been interpreted to question the existence of a numerosity-specific system such as ANS. These results show that generic artificial neural networks going through unsupervised learning develop a human-like acuity in numerosity estimation, suggesting that, instead of ANS being numerosity-specific, it could be a more general characteristic of learning through visual observations (Stoianov & Zorzi, Reference Stoianov and Zorzi2012; Testolin et al., Reference Testolin, Zou and McClelland2020). While these results are very early and tentative, they could point to an interesting new research direction in the development of numerical cognition. For more on this topic, see Pantsar (Reference Pantsar2023a).

13 This state of affairs was very different at the turn of the century. Dehaene (Reference Dehaene1997), in the first edition of The Number Sense, for example, was a proponent of the view that the subitising ability is fundamentally a part of the estimation ability. See Section 2.3 for more.

14 That there are different representations is supported by data showing activation in different brain areas (Nieder, Reference Nieder2019, p. 211). In a particularly interesting finding, it has been established that seeing numeral symbols is associated with activation of a special area of the temporal lobe, the ventral occipito-temporal cortex, also called the ‘number form area’ in the literature (Shum et al., Reference Shum, Hermes, Foster, Dastjerdi, Rangarajan, Winawer, Miller and Parvizi2013). This area shows increased activity with numeral symbols compared to other symbols, which can also help explain why dyslexia and dyscalculia (difficulty in learning arithmetic) are distinct learning disabilities (Nieder, Reference Nieder2019, p. 188).

Figure 0

Figure 1.1 Reaction time in enumeration tasks.** We can see a clear difference in the reaction time (y-axis, milliseconds) when the number of dots increases over the subitising range (one to four).

Data from Trick and Pylyshyn (1994).
Figure 1

Figure 1.2 Numerosity estimation by infants.** Xu and Spelke (2000) habituated six-month-old infants to arrays of either eight or sixteen dots and tested their reactions to changing numerosity of dots.

Reproduced with permission.

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Proto-arithmetical Abilities
  • Markus Pantsar, Aachen University of Technology
  • Book: Numerical Cognition and the Epistemology of Arithmetic
  • Online publication: 15 March 2024
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009468862.004
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • Proto-arithmetical Abilities
  • Markus Pantsar, Aachen University of Technology
  • Book: Numerical Cognition and the Epistemology of Arithmetic
  • Online publication: 15 March 2024
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009468862.004
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • Proto-arithmetical Abilities
  • Markus Pantsar, Aachen University of Technology
  • Book: Numerical Cognition and the Epistemology of Arithmetic
  • Online publication: 15 March 2024
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009468862.004
Available formats
×