Book contents
- Frontmatter
- Contents
- Acknowledgments
- Sources of the Translated Texts
- Notes on the Translations
- List of Abbreviations, Symbols, and Conventions
- Introduction:
- 1. Bonaventure (d. 1274), Commentary on the Sentences, book II, d. 24, a. 2, q. 1:
- 2. Albert the Great (d. 1280), Summa theologiae, book I, treatise 3, q. 15, chap. 2, a. 2, c. 1:
- 3. Thomas Aquinas (d. 1274), Commentary on the Sentences, book I, d. 3, q. 4, a. 2:
- 4. Henry of Ghent (d. 1293), Quodlibet III, q. 14 (excerpts):
- 5. Godfrey of Fontaines (d. ca. 1306), Quodlibet II, q. 4:
- 6. Thomas of Sutton (d. ca. 1315), Ordinary Question 4 (excerpts):
- 7. Peter of John Olivi (d. 1298), Questions on the Sentences, book II, q. 54 (excerpts):
- 8. John Duns Scotus (d. 1308), Commentary on the Sentences (Reportatio A), book II, d. 16:
- 9. James of Viterbo (d. 1308), Quodlibet I, q. 7, doubt 1:
- 10. Durand of St.-Pourçain (d. 1334), Commentary on the Sentences (Third Version), book I, d. 3, part 2, q. 2:
- 11. William Ockham (d. 1347), Commentary on the Sentences (Reportatio), book II, q. 20
- Glossary of Terms
- Glossary of Arguments
- Bibliography
- Index
5. - Godfrey of Fontaines (d. ca. 1306), Quodlibet II, q. 4:
Can a Created Substance Be the Immediate Principle of an Operation?
Published online by Cambridge University Press: 10 April 2025
- Frontmatter
- Contents
- Acknowledgments
- Sources of the Translated Texts
- Notes on the Translations
- List of Abbreviations, Symbols, and Conventions
- Introduction:
- 1. Bonaventure (d. 1274), Commentary on the Sentences, book II, d. 24, a. 2, q. 1:
- 2. Albert the Great (d. 1280), Summa theologiae, book I, treatise 3, q. 15, chap. 2, a. 2, c. 1:
- 3. Thomas Aquinas (d. 1274), Commentary on the Sentences, book I, d. 3, q. 4, a. 2:
- 4. Henry of Ghent (d. 1293), Quodlibet III, q. 14 (excerpts):
- 5. Godfrey of Fontaines (d. ca. 1306), Quodlibet II, q. 4:
- 6. Thomas of Sutton (d. ca. 1315), Ordinary Question 4 (excerpts):
- 7. Peter of John Olivi (d. 1298), Questions on the Sentences, book II, q. 54 (excerpts):
- 8. John Duns Scotus (d. 1308), Commentary on the Sentences (Reportatio A), book II, d. 16:
- 9. James of Viterbo (d. 1308), Quodlibet I, q. 7, doubt 1:
- 10. Durand of St.-Pourçain (d. 1334), Commentary on the Sentences (Third Version), book I, d. 3, part 2, q. 2:
- 11. William Ockham (d. 1347), Commentary on the Sentences (Reportatio), book II, q. 20
- Glossary of Terms
- Glossary of Arguments
- Bibliography
- Index
Summary
In this text, Godfrey asks whether a created substance can be the immediate principle of its operation. ‘Power’ and ‘immediate principle of operation’ are synonymous terms here. Hence, the question that Godfrey raises is this: is a substance a power? Godfrey’s answer is nuanced. Like Albert and Aquinas, Godfrey adheres to the view that powers like sight and the intellect are propria or necessary accidents distinct from the soul. However, he openly rejects Aquinas’ Category Argument for the distinction theory because he finds Henry’s regress argument against the claim that a power must be in the same category as its act convincing. The regress argument also leads Godfrey to argue that there is, in addition to such powers as the intellect and sight, what we might call a higher-order power of the soul. This higher-order power is the soul’s power to bear such powers as the intellect and sight. Unlike the intellect and sight, this power to bear powers is identical to the soul, Godfrey thinks. Thus, Godfrey defends the Thomistic distinction theory; but he also makes a concession to Henry by arguing that the soul is at least one power through its essence, namely, a higher-order power.
Keywords
- Type
- Chapter
- Information
- Medieval Philosophical Writings on the Powers of the SoulFrom Aquinas to Ockham, pp. 96 - 103Publisher: Cambridge University PressPrint publication year: 2025