Book contents
- Frontmatter
- Contents
- Introduction
- Note to the Reader
- Acknowledgements
- Theory of Parallels — Lobachevski's Introduction
- Theory of Parallels — Preliminary Theorems (1–15)
- Theory of Parallels 16: The Definition of Parallelism
- Theory of Parallels 17: Parallelism is Well-Defined
- Theory of Parallels 18: Parallelism is Symmetric
- Theory of Parallels 19: The Saccheri-Legendre Theorem
- Theory of Parallels 20: The Three Musketeers Theorem
- Theory of Parallels 21: A Little Lemma
- Theory of Parallels 22: Common Perpendiculars
- Theory of Parallels 23: The π-function
- Theory of Parallels 24: Convergence of Parallels
- Theory of Parallels 25: Parallelism is Transitive
- Theory of Parallels 26: Spherical Triangles
- Theory of Parallels 27: Solid Angles
- Theory of Parallels 28: The Prism Theorem
- Theory of Parallels 29: Circumcircles or Lack Thereof (Part I)
- Theory of Parallels 30: Circumcircles or Lack Thereof (Part II)
- Theory of Parallels 31: The Horocycle Defined
- Theory of Parallels 32: The Horocycle as a Limit-Circle
- Theory of Parallels 33: Concentric Horocycles
- Theory of Parallels 34: The Horosphere
- Theory of Parallels 35: Spherical Trigonometry
- Theory of Parallels 36: The Fundamental Formula
- Theory of Parallels 37: Plane Trigonometry
- Bibliography
- Appendix: Nicolai Ivanovich Lobachevski's Theory of Parallels
- Index
- About the Author
Theory of Parallels — Preliminary Theorems (1–15)
- Frontmatter
- Contents
- Introduction
- Note to the Reader
- Acknowledgements
- Theory of Parallels — Lobachevski's Introduction
- Theory of Parallels — Preliminary Theorems (1–15)
- Theory of Parallels 16: The Definition of Parallelism
- Theory of Parallels 17: Parallelism is Well-Defined
- Theory of Parallels 18: Parallelism is Symmetric
- Theory of Parallels 19: The Saccheri-Legendre Theorem
- Theory of Parallels 20: The Three Musketeers Theorem
- Theory of Parallels 21: A Little Lemma
- Theory of Parallels 22: Common Perpendiculars
- Theory of Parallels 23: The π-function
- Theory of Parallels 24: Convergence of Parallels
- Theory of Parallels 25: Parallelism is Transitive
- Theory of Parallels 26: Spherical Triangles
- Theory of Parallels 27: Solid Angles
- Theory of Parallels 28: The Prism Theorem
- Theory of Parallels 29: Circumcircles or Lack Thereof (Part I)
- Theory of Parallels 30: Circumcircles or Lack Thereof (Part II)
- Theory of Parallels 31: The Horocycle Defined
- Theory of Parallels 32: The Horocycle as a Limit-Circle
- Theory of Parallels 33: Concentric Horocycles
- Theory of Parallels 34: The Horosphere
- Theory of Parallels 35: Spherical Trigonometry
- Theory of Parallels 36: The Fundamental Formula
- Theory of Parallels 37: Plane Trigonometry
- Bibliography
- Appendix: Nicolai Ivanovich Lobachevski's Theory of Parallels
- Index
- About the Author
Summary
Mathematical terms cannot be defined ex nihilo. The words that one uses in any given definition require further definitions of their own; these secondary definitions necessitate tertiary definitions; these in turn require still others. To escape infinite regress, geometers must leave a handful of socalled primitive terms undefined. These primitive terms represent the basic building blocks from which the first defined terms may be constructed. From there, one may build upward indefinitely; all subsequent development will be grounded upon the primitive terms, and circular definitions will be avoided.
Only in the late 19th-century was such clarity achieved in the foundations of geometry. Euclid never identifies his primitive terms and several of his early definitions founder in ambiguity. His vague definition of a straight line, “a line which lies evenly with the points on itself” is useless from a logical standpoint: since Euclid does not tell us what “lying evenly” means, we have no way of deciding whether a given curve is straight or not. Euclid has given us a description rather than a genuine definition of a line, and as such, he has given us something that is worthless in a strict logical development of geometry.
Mathematics encompasses more than logic, however. The very fact that Euclid attempts to describe a line has philosophical significance. It suggests that, for Euclid, straight lines are “out there”, capable of description. It implicitly asserts that straight lines exist independently of the mathematicians who study them. For one who accepts this Platonic concept of geometry, the logical gaps in The Elements are so superficial as to scarcely merit mention.
- Type
- Chapter
- Information
- Lobachevski Illuminated , pp. 3 - 10Publisher: Mathematical Association of AmericaPrint publication year: 2011