Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-m6dg7 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-02T20:35:48.050Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false
This chapter is part of a book that is no longer available to purchase from Cambridge Core

Theory of Parallels — Preliminary Theorems (1–15)

Seth Braver
Affiliation:
South Puget Sound Community College
Get access

Summary

Mathematical terms cannot be defined ex nihilo. The words that one uses in any given definition require further definitions of their own; these secondary definitions necessitate tertiary definitions; these in turn require still others. To escape infinite regress, geometers must leave a handful of socalled primitive terms undefined. These primitive terms represent the basic building blocks from which the first defined terms may be constructed. From there, one may build upward indefinitely; all subsequent development will be grounded upon the primitive terms, and circular definitions will be avoided.

Only in the late 19th-century was such clarity achieved in the foundations of geometry. Euclid never identifies his primitive terms and several of his early definitions founder in ambiguity. His vague definition of a straight line, “a line which lies evenly with the points on itself” is useless from a logical standpoint: since Euclid does not tell us what “lying evenly” means, we have no way of deciding whether a given curve is straight or not. Euclid has given us a description rather than a genuine definition of a line, and as such, he has given us something that is worthless in a strict logical development of geometry.

Mathematics encompasses more than logic, however. The very fact that Euclid attempts to describe a line has philosophical significance. It suggests that, for Euclid, straight lines are “out there”, capable of description. It implicitly asserts that straight lines exist independently of the mathematicians who study them. For one who accepts this Platonic concept of geometry, the logical gaps in The Elements are so superficial as to scarcely merit mention.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Mathematical Association of America
Print publication year: 2011

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×