Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-rdxmf Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-23T12:49:37.187Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

4 - On Definite Descriptions: Can Familiarity And Uniqueness Be Distinguished?

from Part II - Describing and Referring

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  06 October 2022

Daniel Altshuler
Affiliation:
University of Oxford
Get access

Summary

Definite descriptions are an area where linguistics and philosophy have been intimately intertwined as long as they have been acquainted. But are we past all that now, in the modern era, as work on definite descriptions becomes less focussed on English, and more cross-linguistic? This chapter highlights one great unresolved issue in the theory of definite descriptions that persists even in this modern era of crosslinguistic comparison, a foundational (hence philosophical) one, pitting dynamic semantics against situation semantics. A prominent synthesis of these competing (though compatible) frameworks says that both are needed, for “strong” and “weak” articles, respectively. The strong vs. weak distinction has served as inspiration for much recent work on the crosslinguistic semantics of definiteness. While this new development has led to a much richer and more well-rounded picture of definiteness as a phenomenon, the predictions of the two analyses overlap too much, leading to spurious debate when fieldworkers go to analyze a new language. The chapter aims to clarify what is at stake empirically in the choice among analyses, and advocates for continued philosophical reflection as we operationalize our methods of discovery.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2022

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Aguilar-Guevara, A., Pozas-Loyo, J., & Maldonado, V. V. R. (Eds.). (2019). Definiteness across Languages: Studies in Diversity Linguistics. Berlin: Language Science Press.Google Scholar
Amfo, A. N. (2007). Akan demonstratives. In Payne, D. L. & Peña, J. (Eds.), Selected Proceedings of the 37th Annual Conference on African Linguistics (pp. 134–148).Google Scholar
Arkoh, R. (2011). Semantics of Akan bí and nʊ. MA thesis, University of British Columbia.Google Scholar
Arkoh, R., & Matthewson, L. (2013). A familiar definite article in Akan. Lingua, 123, 130. doi:10.1016/j.lingua.2012.09.012CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barker, C. (2005). Possessive weak definites. In Kim, Y.-Y., Lander, Y., & Partee, B. H. (Eds.), Possessives and Beyond: Semantics and Syntax (pp. 89113). Amherst: GSLA Publications.Google Scholar
Barker, C., & Shan, C.-C. (2008). Donkey anaphora is in-scope binding. Semantics and Pragmatics, 1(1), 140.Google Scholar
Barlew, J. (2014). Salience, uniqueness, and the definite determiner-tè in bulu. In Snider, T., D’Antoni, S., & Weigand, M. (Eds.), Semantics and Linguistic Theory (SALT), Vol. 24 (pp. 619–639).Google Scholar
Barwise, J., & Perry, J. (1983). Situations and Attitudes. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Beaver, D., & Coppock, E. (2015). Novelty and familiarity for free. In Proceedings of the 2015 Amsterdam Colloquium (pp. 50–59).Google Scholar
Bombi, C. (2018). Definiteness in Akan: Familiarity and uniqueness revisited. In Maspong, S., Stefánsdóttir, B., Blake, K., & Davis, F. (Eds.), Semantics and Linguistic Theory (SALT), Vol. 28 (pp. 141–160).Google Scholar
Bumford, D. (2017). Split-scope definites: Relative superlatives and Haddock descriptions. Linguistics and Philosophy, 40(6), 549593.Google Scholar
Bumford, D. (2018). Binding into superlative descriptions. In Maspong, S., Stefánsdóttir, B., Blake, K., & Davis, F. (Eds.), Semantics and Linguistic Theory (SALT), Vol. 28 (pp. 325344).Google Scholar
Carlson, G., & Sussman, R. (2005). Seemingly indefinite definites. In Kesper, S. & Reis, M. (Eds.), Linguistic Evidence: Empirical, Theoretical, and Computational Perspectives (pp. 2630). Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.Google Scholar
Charlow, S. (2014). On the Semantics of Exceptional Scope. Dissertation, New York University.Google Scholar
Chierchia, G. (1995). Dynamics of Meaning: Anaphora, Presupposition, and the Theory of Grammar. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Cooper, R. (1979). The interpretation of pronouns. In Heny, F. & Schnelle, H. (Eds.), Selected Papers from the Third Groningen Round Table: Syntax and Semantics 10 (pp. 6192). New York: Academic Press.Google Scholar
Cooper, R. (1996). The role of situations in generalized quantifiers. In Lappin, S. (Ed.), The Handbook of Contemporary Semantic Theory (pp. 86107). Malden: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Coppock, E., & Beaver, D. (2014). A superlative argument for a minimal theory of definiteness. In Snider, T. (Ed.), Semantics and Linguistic Theory (SALT), Vol. 24 (pp. 177–196).Google Scholar
Coppock, E., & Beaver, D. (2015). Definiteness and determinacy. Linguistics and Philosophy, 38(5), 377435. doi:10.1007/s1098Google Scholar
Coppock, E., & Champollion, L. (in preparation). Invitation to formal semantics. Ms., Boston University and New York University.Google Scholar
Dayal, V., & Jiang, J. (2021). The puzzle of anaphoric bare nouns in mandarin: A counterpoint to index! Linguistic Inquiry. doi:10.1162/ling_a_00433CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Déprez, V. (2016). Refining cross-linguistic dimension of definiteness: Variations on ‘la’. Talk presented at the Workshop on the Semantic Contribution of Det and Num, Barcelona, May 27–28.Google Scholar
Elbourne, P. (2005). Situations and Individuals. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Elbourne, P. (2008). Demonstratives as individual concepts. Linguistics and Philosophy, 31, 409466.Google Scholar
Elbourne, P. (2009). Bishop sentences and donkey cataphora: A response to Barker and Shan. Semantics and Pragmatics, 2(1), 17.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Elbourne, P. (2013). Definite Descriptions. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Evans, G. (1977). Pronouns, quantifiers, and relative clauses. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 7, 467536.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Evans, G. (1980). Pronouns. Linguistic Inquiry, 11, 337362.Google Scholar
von Fintel, K. (1994). Restrictions on Quantifier Domains. Dissertation, University of Massachusetts at Amherst.Google Scholar
von Fintel, K. (2004). Would you believe it? The King of France is back! (presuppositions and truth-value intuitions). In Bezuidenhout, A. & Reimer, M. (Eds.), Descriptions and Beyond (pp. 315342). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Frege, G. (1892). Über Sinn und Bedeutung. Zeitschrift für Philosophie und philosophische Kritik, 100, 2550. Translated as “On sense and reference” by M. Black, in Translations from the Philosophical Writings of Gottlob Frege, P. Geach and M. Black (eds. and trans.), 3rd ed. Oxford: Blackwell, 1980.Google Scholar
Glanzberg, M. (2007). Definite descriptions and quantifier scope: Some Mates cases reconsidered. European Journal of Analytic Philosophy, 3(2), 133158.Google Scholar
Haddock, N. J. (1987). Incremental interpretation and combinatory categorial grammar. In Proceedings of the 10 International Joint Conference on Artificial Intelligence, Vol. 2 (pp. 661663). San Mateo: Morgan Kaufmann.Google Scholar
Hanink, E. A. (2017). The German definite article and the ‘sameness’ of indices. University of Pennsylvania Working Papers in Linguistics, 23, 9. https://repository.upenn.edu/cgi/viewcontent.cgi?article=1949&context=pwplGoogle Scholar
Hawkins, J. A. (1978). Definiteness and Indefiniteness: A Study in Reference and Grammaticality. London: Croom Helm.Google Scholar
Heim, I. (1982). The Semantics of Definite and Indefinite Noun Phrases. Dissertation, University of Massachusetts at Amherst.Google Scholar
Heim, I. (1990). E-type pronouns and donkey anaphora. Linguistics and Philosophy, 13. 137177. doi:10.1007/bf00630732Google Scholar
Heim, I. (1991). Artikel und Definitheit. In von Stechow, A. & Wunderlich, D. (Eds.), Semantik: Ein internationales Handbuch der zeitgenössischen Forschung (pp. 487535). Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.Google Scholar
Heim, I. (1999). Notes on Superlatives. Ms., Massachusetts Institute of Technology.Google Scholar
Heim, I., & Kratzer, A. (1998). Semantics in Generative Grammar. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Horn, L. R. (2001). A Natural History of Negation. Stanford: CSLI Publications.Google Scholar
Horn, L. R., & Abbott, B. (2012). <the, a>: (in)definiteness and implicature. In Kabasenche, W. P., O’Rourke, M., & Slater, M. H. (Eds.), Reference and Referring (pp. 325355). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Jenks, P. (2015). Two kinds of definties in numeral classifier languages. In D’Antonio, S., Moroney, M., & Little, C. R. (Eds.), Semantics and Linguistic Theory (SALT), Vol. 25 (pp. 103–124).Google Scholar
Jenks, P. (2018). Articulated definiteness without articles. Linguistic Inquiry, 49, 501536.Google Scholar
Kadmon, N. (1987). On Unique and Non-unique Reference and Asymmetric Quantification. Dissertation, University of Massachusetts at Amherst.Google Scholar
Kamp, H. (2018). Entity representations and articulated contexts. Unpublished manuscript, to appear as part of a tribute to David Kaplan, with the preliminary title: “Sense, reference and use – Afterthoughts on Kaplan.”Google Scholar
Kamp, H., & Reyle, U. (1993). From Discourse to Logic. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.Google Scholar
Kaplan, D. (1977). Demonstratives: An essay on the semantics, logic, metaphysics, and epistemology of demonstratives and other indexicals. In Almog, J., Perry, J., & Wettstein, H. (Eds.), Themes from Kaplan (pp. 267298). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kripke, S. A. (2011). Philosophical Troubles: Collected Papers. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Landman, F. (2004). Indefinites and the Type of Sets. Malden, MA: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Löbner, S. (1985). Definites. Journal of Semantics, 4, 279326. doi:10.1093/jos/4.4.279Google Scholar
Löbner, S. (2000). Polarity in natural language: Predication, quantification and negation in particular and characterizing sentences. Linguistics and Philosophy, 23, 213308.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Maldonado, V. V. R., Fajardo, J. G., Gutiérrez-Bravo, R., & Loyo, J. P. (2018). The definite article in Yucatec Maya: The case of le… o’. International Journal of American Linguistics, 84, 207242. doi:10.1086/696197Google Scholar
Neale, S. (1990). Descriptions. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Oliver, A., & Smiley, T. (2013). Plural Logic. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Ortmann, A. (2014). Definite article asymmetries and concept types: Semantic and pragmatic uniqueness. In Gamerschlag, T., Gerland, D., Osswald, R., & Petersen, W. (Eds.), Frames and Concept Types: Applications in Linguistics and Philosophy (pp. 293321). Cham: Springer International. doi:10.1007/978-3-319-0541-5_13Google Scholar
Owusu, A. (2020). Clausal determiners and definite propositions. Talk presented at BU Linguistics Colloquium, November 13.Google Scholar
Prince, E. (1992). The ZPG letter: Subjects, definiteness and information status. In Thompson, S. & Mann, W. (Eds.), Discourse Description: Diverse Analyses of a Fund Raising Text (pp. 295325). Philadelphia/Amsterdam: John Benjamins.Google Scholar
Roberts, C. (2003). Uniqueness in definite noun phrases. Linguistics and Philosophy, 26, 287350.Google Scholar
Russell, B. (1905). On denoting. Mind, 14, 479493.Google Scholar
Schwarz, F. (2009). Two Types of Definites in Natural Language. Dissertation, University of Massachusetts at Amherst.Google Scholar
Soames, S. (1986). Incomplete definite descriptions. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 27, 349375.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stanley, J., & Szabó, Z. G. (2000). On quantifier domain restriction. Mind & Language, 15, 219261.Google Scholar
Strawson, P. F. (1950). On referring. Mind, 59(235), 320344.Google Scholar
Szabó, Z. G. (2000). Descriptions and uniqueness. Philosophical Studies, 101, 2957.Google Scholar
Szabó, Z. G. (2003). Definite descriptions without uniqueness: A reply to Abbott. Philosophical Studies, 114, 279291.Google Scholar
Szabolcsi, A. (1986). Comparative superlatives. In Fukui, N., Rapoport, T., & Sagey, E. (Eds.), Papers in Theoretical Linguistics (pp. 245265). Cambridge, MA: MITWPL.Google Scholar
Wespel, J. (2008). Descriptions and Their Domains: The Patterns of Definiteness Marking in French-Related Creoles. Dissertation, University of Stuttgart. doi:10.18419/opus-5708Google Scholar
Westerståhl, D. (1984). Determiners and context sets. In van Benthem, J. & ter Meulen, A. (Eds.), Generalized Quantifiers and Natural Language (pp. 4571). Dordrecht: Foris.Google Scholar
Yifrach, M., & Coppock, E. (2020). Defining definiteness in Ṭuroyo. Glossa: A Journal of General Linguistics, 6, 124. https://doi.org/10.16995/glossa.5874Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×