Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-g8jcs Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-27T16:55:33.158Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

11 - The Fundamental Problem of Kant's Juridical Semantics

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 February 2013

Zeljko Loparic
Affiliation:
State University of Campinas
Frederick Rauscher
Affiliation:
Michigan State University
Daniel Omar Perez
Affiliation:
University of Parana, Brazil
Get access

Summary

The Concept of Practical Philosophy in Later Kant

Kant defines a philosopher as “the legislator of human reason” (Pure Reason, B867). The philosopher's legislation has two objects, nature and freedom, and therefore contains both the laws of nature (natural laws) and the laws of freedom (moral laws). The former determine a priori what is and comprise the system of nature; the latter determine a priori what should be and make up the system of freedom. Theoretical or speculative philosophy takes care of the former; practical philosophy takes care of the latter.

In Kant's later writings, practical philosophy is split into a “metaphysics of morals” and a “moral anthropology” (Doctrine of Right, 6:217). The former contains a priori the principles that dispose of “freedom in both the external and the internal use of choice” (Doctrine of Right, 6:214), and for that reason is also called “anthroponomy” (Doctrine of Virtue, 6:406). The latter, moral anthropology, comprises the study of subjective conditions, pertaining to human nature, that are either favorable or contrary to the execution of the laws of practical reason (Doctrine of Right, 6:217).

This distinction is a novelty relative to the first Critique. In the first Critique, Kant contrasts practical philosophy, especially pure morals, which deals with the principles that “determine action and omission a priori and make them necessary,” with anthropology, conceived as an empirical, scientific theory. He says, for example, that “the metaphysics of morals is really the pure morality, which is not grounded on any anthropology (no empirical condition)” (Pure Reason, B869–70).

Type
Chapter
Information
Kant in Brazil , pp. 206 - 235
Publisher: Boydell & Brewer
Print publication year: 2012

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×