Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-8bhkd Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-09T16:02:36.304Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Chapter 2 - Fundamentals in Suárez's metaphysics: transcendentals and categories

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 December 2011

Daniel Schwartz
Affiliation:
Hebrew University of Jerusalem
Get access

Summary

We think about the world in more or less general terms. Among the less general are terms such as ‘cat’ or ‘red,’ and among the more general, ‘animal’ or ‘color.’ Part of what philosophers do is to establish an order among the levels of generality expressed by these terms and determine their relations. The task is not very difficult at lower levels. It is easy to understand that red is a kind of color and therefore that ‘color’ expresses a higher level of generality than ‘red.’ But metaphysicians go beyond these lower levels of generality and try to establish an ordered list of the highest levels, turning to items such as substance, quality, being, and unity, and asking questions such as: How many of these most general levels are there? What are their members? And how are they related to each other and to lower levels? For example, they might ask whether substance and being belong to the same level of generality, and about the identity of the level or levels to which they belong. And they might do the same with unity and being, or quality and substance. Once metaphysicians find answers to these questions, they turn to more specific levels, such as red, color, cat, and animal, and inquire into how they are related to the more general ones.

Following the example of Aristotle, scholastic philosophers tried to establish a map of the most general levels of generality, while determining their interrelations, status, distinction, and the disciplines where they should be explored. During the Middle Ages and in the early modern period, two levels of generality in particular became the subject of considerable attention: transcendentals and categories. Most often scholastics thought of transcendentals as being and its properties and placed them at the top. Below this level, scholastics placed categories, which they understood to be divisions of being.

Type
Chapter
Information
Interpreting Suárez
Critical Essays
, pp. 19 - 38
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2011

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×