from Book Reviews
Published online by Cambridge University Press: 16 May 2018
The aim of Hannah Eldridge's monograph is to use Stanley Cavell's account of subjectivity and language in order to help “explain the extraordinarily ambitious claims Hölderlin and Rilke make for poetry: that it can create political communities, recast human relationships to death, or unite the sensual and intellectual components of human subjectivity” (2). In her introduction and “Epilogue,” Eldridge extends these explanations to the poetry of Paul Celan to demonstrate the continuation of Hölderlin's and Rilke's poetic ambitions after the Second World War.
While unifying the senses and intellect and coping with death are important themes in Eldridge's exploration of the three poets, she does not examine the specific “political community” they may envision, since her interest is, more generally, in how they respond to “modern alienation” through lyric representations, or “performances,” of “unification,” “wholeness,” “conversation,” or “poetic community.” These terms, which take up the poets’ own formulations, make their work as well as Eldridge's study sound rather Romantic. The author's intent, however, is the opposite: to distance poetry, in particular Hölderlin's, from specifically Jena/ Early Romanticism. While she finds that “[l]ike Hölderlin, the Jena romantics see the absolute as unreachable”; she believes that, unlike Hölderlin, the Romantics only “imagine” the absolute, resigning themselves to regard and enjoy language as “uncontrolled and self-referential play, leading to the interrelated themes of the fragment and irony or Witz (wit)” (49). Thus, Hölderlin's fragmentary texts are, in Eldridge's view, results of failing to “reach the absolute,” whereas the Romantics created fragments, deliberately.
The many texts that Hölderlin left incomplete, appear, in fact, to be fragmentary not by design, in contrast to the Athenaeum-Fragments, for example. However, against the long-standing criticism of Early Romanticism, embraced by Eldridge, one can argue that the young Friedrich Schlegel conceived of the “absolute” (or “totality” or “universality”) not as “unreachable,” but as immanent in the present, finite world. He realized this contradictory and paradoxical project through the similarly contradictory and paradoxical concepts of the fragment as simultaneously complete and incomplete (A206), of irony as a series of endless contradictions (A 51), and of wit as “fragmentary ingenuity” (L 9) or “chemical spirit” (A 366).
To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.
Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.
Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.
To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.
To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.