Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-v9fdk Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-02T20:37:47.755Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

References

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  25 January 2011

Crawford L. Elder
Affiliation:
University of Connecticut
Get access

Summary

Image of the first page of this content. For PDF version, please use the ‘Save PDF’ preceeding this image.'
Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2011

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Armstrong, D. M., A World of States of Affairs (Cambridge University Press, 1997).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Armstrong, D. M., “The Causal Theory of Properties: Properties according to Shoemaker, Ellis, and Others,” Philosophical Topics, 1, no. 2 (1999): 25–38.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baker, Lynne Rudder, The Metaphysics of Everyday Life (Cambridge University Press, 2007).CrossRef
Baker, Lynne Rudder, Persons and Bodies: A Constitution View (Cambridge University Press, 2000).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Balashov, Yuri, “About Stage Universalism,” Philosophical Quarterly, 57 (2007): 21–39.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Balashov, Yuri, “On Vagueness, 4D and Diachronic Universalism,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 83 (2006): 523–31.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Balashov, Yuri, Persistence and Spacetime (Oxford University Press, forthcoming).CrossRef
Bennett, Jonathan, Events and Their Names (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1988).Google Scholar
Bigelow, John and Pargetter, Robert, Science and Necessity (Cambridge University Press, 1990).Google Scholar
Carter, W. R., “Will I Be a Dead Person?,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 59 (1999): 167–71.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davidson, Donald, “Emeroses by Other Names,” Journal of Philosophy, 63 (1966): 778–79.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davidson, Donald, “Mental Events,” in Foster, Lawrence and Swanson, J. W., eds., Experience and Theory (Amherst: University of Massachusetts Press, 1970), pp. 79–101.Google Scholar
Dennett, Daniel, “Quining Qualia,” in Marcel, A. and Bisiach, E., eds., Consciousness in Contemporary Science (Oxford University Press, 1988), pp. 42–77.Google Scholar
Elder, Crawford, “Conventionalism and Realism-Imitating Counterfactuals,” Philosophical Quarterly, 56 (2006): 1–15.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Elder, Crawford, “Conventionalism and the World as Bare Sense-data,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 85 (2007): 261–75.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Elder, Crawford, “A Different Kind of Natural Kind,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 73 (1995): 516–31.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Elder, Crawford, “On the Place of Artifacts in Ontology,” in Margolis, Eric and Laurence, Stephen, eds., Creations of the Mind: Theories of Artifacts and Their Representation (Oxford University Press, 2007), pp. 33–51.Google Scholar
Elder, Crawford, “Physicalism and the Fallacy of Composition,” Philosophical Quarterly, 50 (2000): 332–43.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Elder, Crawford, Real Natures and Familiar Objects (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 2004).Google Scholar
Findlay, J. N., Meinong's Theory of Objects and Values (Oxford University Press, 1963).Google Scholar
Gardner, Martin, The Ambidextrous Universe: Left, Right, and the Fall of Parity (New York and Toronto: New American Library, 1964).Google Scholar
Grandy, Richard, “Artifacts: Parts and Principles,” in Margolis, Eric and Laurence, Stephen, eds., Creations of the Mind: Theories of Artifacts and Their Representation (Oxford University Press, 2007), pp. 18–32.Google Scholar
Hall, Ned, “Two Concepts of Causation,” in Collins, John, Hall, Ned, and Paul, L. A., eds., Causation and Counterfactuals (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 2004).Google Scholar
Haslanger, Sally, “Persistence through Time,” in Loux, M. J. and Zimmerman, D., eds., The Oxford Handbook of Metaphysics (Oxford University Press, 2003), pp. 315–54.Google Scholar
Hawley, Katherine, How Things Persist (Oxford University Press, 2001).Google Scholar
Hawthorne, John, Metaphysical Essays (Oxford University Press, 2006).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hegel, G. W. F., Hegel's Science of Logic, trans. Miller, A. V. (London: George Allen & Unwin, 1969); originally 1831.Google Scholar
Hegel, G. W. F., The Logic of Hegel, Pt. i of The Encyclopaedia of the Philosophical Sciences, trans. Wallace, William, 2nd edn. (Oxford University Press, 1892); originally 1817.Google Scholar
Hegel, G. W. F., Philosophy of Nature, trans. Miller, A. V. (Oxford University Press, 1970); originally 1830.Google Scholar
Heil, John, and Mele, Alfred, eds., Mental Causation (Oxford University Press, 1993).
Hirsch, Eli, The Concept of Identity (Oxford University Press, 1982).Google Scholar
Hirsch, Eli, Dividing Reality (Oxford University Press, 1993).Google Scholar
Hirsch, Eli, “Physical-Object Ontology, Verbal Disputes, and Common Sense,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 70 (2005): 67–97.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hirsch, Eli, “Rules for a Good Language,” Journal of Philosophy, 85 (1988): 694–717.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hirsch, Eli, “Strange Thoughts of the Third Kind,” in French, Peter A., Uehling, Theodore E., Jr., and Wettstein, Howard K., eds., Midwest Studies in Philosophy, XII: Realism and Antirealism (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1988), pp. 3–24.Google Scholar
Hitchcock, Christopher, “The Intransitivity of Causation Revealed in Equations and Graphs,” Journal of Philosophy, 98 (2001): 273–99.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hitchcock, Christopher, “A Tale of Two Effects,” Philosophical Review, 110 (2001): 361–96.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Horgan, Terence, “Mental Quausation,” Philosophical Perspectives, 3 (Philosophy of Mind and Action Theory) (1989): 47–76.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Horgan, Terry, and Potrč, Matjaž, “Blobjectivism and Indirect Correspondence,” Facta Philosophica, 2 (2000): 249–70.Google Scholar
Husserl, Edmund, Cartesian Meditations, trans. Cairns, Dorion (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1970); originally 1929.Google Scholar
Johnston, Mark, “Hylomorphism,” Journal of Philosophy, 103, no. 12 (2006): 652–98.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jubien, Michael, Ontology, Modality, and the Fallacy of Reference (Cambridge University Press, 1993).Google Scholar
Kim, Jaegwon, Supervenience and Mind (Cambridge University Press, 1993).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Koslicki, Kathrin, “The Crooked Path from Vagueness to Four-Dimensionalism,” Philosophical Studies, 114 (2003): 107–34.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Laycock, Henry, Words without Objects (Oxford University Press, 2006).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, David, “Causation,” in Philosophical Papers, vol. II (Oxford University Press, 1986), pp. 159–213.Google Scholar
Lewis, David, Parts of Classes (Oxford: Blackwell, 1991).Google Scholar
Lewis, David, “Survival and Identity,” in Philosophical Papers, vol. I (New York: Oxford University Press, 1983), pp. 55–77.Google Scholar
Lowe, E. J., “In Defense of Moderate-Sized Specimens of Dry Goods,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 57 (2003): 705–10.Google Scholar
Lowe, E. J., Kinds of Being: A Study of Individuation, Identity and the Logic of Sortal Terms (Oxford: Blackwell, 1989).Google Scholar
Mackie, J. L., “Causes and Conditions,” American Philosophical Quarterly, 2, no. 4 (1965): 245–64.Google Scholar
Markosian, Ned, “Brutal Composition,” Philosophical Studies, 92 (1996): 211–49.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McDermott, Michael, “Redundant Causation,” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 46 (1995): 523–44.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McLaughlin, Brian, “On Davidson's Response to the Charge of Epiphenomenalism,” in Heil, and Mele, , eds., Mental Causation.
Merricks, Trenton, Objects and Persons (Oxford University Press, 2001).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Millikan, Ruth, Language: A Biological Model (Oxford University Press, 2005).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Millikan, Ruth, Language, Thought, and Other Biological Categories (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1984).Google Scholar
Millikan, Ruth, On Clear and Confused Ideas (Cambridge University Press, 2000).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Millikan, Ruth, Varieties of Meaning (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 2004).Google Scholar
Millikan, Ruth, White Queen Psychology and Other Essays for Alice (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1993).Google Scholar
Mills, Eugene, “Interactionism and Overdetermination,” American Philosophical Quarterly, 33 (1996): 105–17.Google Scholar
O'Leary-Hawthorne, John [see John Hawthorne], and Cortens, Andrew, “Towards Ontological Nihilism,” Philosophical Studies, 79 (1995): 143–65.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Parfit, Derek, Reasons and Persons (Oxford University Press, 1984).Google Scholar
Putnam, Hilary, “Realism and Reason,” Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, 50 (1977): 483–98.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Putnam, Hilary, Reason, Truth and History (Cambridge University Press, 1981).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Putnam, Hilary, “Why There Isn't a Ready-made World,” Synthese, 51 (1982): 141–67.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rea, Michael, “In Defense of Mereological Universalism,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 57 (1998): 347–60.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rea, Michael, World without Design (Oxford University Press, 2002).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rea, Michael, ed., Material Constitution: A Reader (Lanham, Md.: Rowman & Littlefield, 1997).
Rosen, Gideon, and Dorr, Cian, “Composition as a Fiction,” in Gale, Richard M., ed., The Blackwell Guide to Metaphysics (Oxford: Blackwell, 2003), pp. 151–74.Google Scholar
Sanford, David, “Fusion Confusion,” Analysis, 63 (2003): 1–4.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Saucedo, Raul, “Parthood and Location,” in Zimmerman, Dean, ed., Oxford Studies in Metaphysics (Oxford University Press, forthcoming).
Schwartz, Stephen, “The Essence of Essence,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 87 (2009): 609–23.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sidelle, Alan, “Modality and Objects,” Philosophical Quarterly, 60 (2010): 109–25.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sidelle, Alan, Necessity, Essence, and Individuation (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 1989).Google Scholar
Sidelle, Alan, “A Sweater Unraveled: Following one Thread of Thought for Avoiding Coincident Entities,” Noûs, 32 (1998): 423–48.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sider, Theodore, “All the World's a Stage,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 74 (1996): 433–53.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sider, Theodore, Four-Dimensionalism: An Ontology of Persistence and Time (Oxford University Press, 2001).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sider, Theodore, “What's So Bad About Overdetermination?,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 67 (2003): 719–26.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sosa, Ernest, “Existential Relativity,” in French, Peter A. and Wettstein, Howard K., eds., Midwest Studies in Philosophy, vol. XXIII: New Directions in Philosophy (Boston: Blackwell, 1999), pp. 132–43.Google Scholar
Spelke, Elizabeth, “Initial Knowledge: Six Suggestions,” Cognition, 50 (1994): 431–45.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Spelke, Elizabeth, “Principles of Object Perception,” Cognitive Science, 14 (1990): 29–56.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sturgeon, Scott, “Physicalism and Overdetermination,” Mind, 107 (1998): 411–32.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thomasson, Amie, Ordinary Objects (New York: Oxford University Press, 2007).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thomson, Judith Jarvis, “Parthood and Identity across Time,” Journal of Philosophy, 80 (1983): 201–20.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Unger, Peter, “I Do Not Exist,” in Macdonald, G. P., ed., Perception and Identity (Ithaca, N.Y: Cornell University Press, 1979), pp. 235–51.Google Scholar
Inwagen, Peter, “Can Mereological Sums Change their Parts?,” Journal of Philosophy, 103 (2006): 614–30.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Inwagen, Peter, Material Beings (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 1990).Google Scholar
Waterfield, Robin, The First Philosophers (Oxford University Press, 2000).Google Scholar
Wells, Alexander Frank, Structural Inorganic Chemistry (Oxford University Press, 1962).Google Scholar
Wheeler, Samuel, “On That Which Is Not,” Synthese, 41 (1979): 155–73.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wiggins, David, Sameness and Substance (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1980).Google Scholar
Wiggins, David, Sameness and Substance Renewed (Cambridge University Press, 2001).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Woodward, James, Making Things Happen (New York: Oxford University Press, 2003).Google Scholar
Woodward, James, and Hitchcock, Christopher, “Explanatory Generalizations, Part I: A Counterfactual Account,” Noûs, 37 (2003): 1–24.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Woodward, James, and Hitchcock, Christopher, “Explanatory Generalizations, Part II: Plumbing Explanatory Depth,” Noûs, 37 (2003): 181–99.Google Scholar
Zangwill, Nick, “Aesthetic Functionalism,” in Brady, Emily and Levinson, Jerrold, eds., Aesthetic Concepts: Sibley and After (Oxford University Press, 2001).Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • References
  • Crawford L. Elder, University of Connecticut
  • Book: Familiar Objects and their Shadows
  • Online publication: 25 January 2011
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511760129.011
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • References
  • Crawford L. Elder, University of Connecticut
  • Book: Familiar Objects and their Shadows
  • Online publication: 25 January 2011
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511760129.011
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • References
  • Crawford L. Elder, University of Connecticut
  • Book: Familiar Objects and their Shadows
  • Online publication: 25 January 2011
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511760129.011
Available formats
×