The Epicureans defend a kind of social contract theory and so endorse the following three claims that other ancient social contract theorists also endorse:Footnote 1
There is an original condition of mankind, in which human beings do not yet live in a community.
There is some deficiency associated with the original condition that makes it necessary for human beings to unite and hence to form a community.
Human beings form a community by means of agreements (sunthēkai/foedera) and so remedy the deficiency of the original condition.
Furthermore, the Epicureans clearly distinguish between a pactum unionis and a pactum subiectionis in their theory. By the former, agents make agreements with each other to form communities (explaining the creation of justice), and by the latter agents make agreements with a ruler to form legal and political states (explaining the creation of the laws). This makes their theory quite complex, even if the focus of their theorizing lies on the agreements of the first kind that leads to the creation of justice.
This chapter provides a detailed account of the Epicurean social contract by focusing on the creation of justice and law. It shows that (1) agreements stand at the center of the Epicurean account, (2) both justice and law are historical products, and (3) human beings are not by nature social and political beings. As a result, the Epicureans side with defenders of nomos in the nomos-phusis debate. However, the chapter will also demonstrate that the Epicurean account of justice importantly depends on the common good or what is beneficial to everyone. In the end, then, a commitment to what is beneficial is at the heart of the process of cultural development that makes life in groups, on the one hand, and political and legal communities, on the other hand, possible and necessary. As a result of this, it would be incorrect to view the Epicureans only as defenders of nomos, but one should note that on their view, nomos is importantly constrained by certain natural features, that is, phusis.
By showing what kind of social contract theory the Epicureans defend, the chapter also aims at refuting some common beliefs about the Epicurean social contract. For instance, the Epicurean account is sometimes characterized as Hobbesian.Footnote 2 However, this chapter will argue that such a reading would be mistaken (even if Hobbes himself drew on Epicurean texts to develop his ideas). If the Epicurean account is to be assimilated to a modern position, the ideas of Jean-Jacques Rousseau are a much better fit.
Epicurus’ own ideas on how human communities came to be, which were perhaps found in book XII of On Nature, have unfortunately not come down to us.Footnote 3 Fortunately, though, the Roman Epicurean Lucretius’ account, which is probably closely modeled on Epicurus’ own version, can be found at On the Nature of Things V.925–1457.Footnote 4 This text will be the principal source in this chapter. Writing roughly 200 years after Epicurus and addressing a Roman audience, for whom Epicurean ideas are a bitter pill to swallow,Footnote 5 Lucretius likely adapts his account to the needs of his audience, thus making it necessary for the reader to be cautious of potential idiosyncrasies in comparison to orthodox Epicureanism. Accordingly, we are fortunate to have an (albeit severely) truncated Epicurean account of the development of political communities that is ascribed to the second head of the Garden, Hermarchus, which will at times serve as a counterpart to the Lucretian description and help to distill a unified account of how Epicurean justice and law come to be.Footnote 6
The following discussion will begin with some observations on the structure of Lucretius’ Kulturentstehungslehre (1.1). These observations will then structure the following three sections of this chapter, each of which will be devoted to a distinct part or phase of cultural development according to the Epicureans, corresponding to different phases of the development of justice and law (Sections 1.2–1.4). The final section of the chapter will then turn to the question of how Epicurean social contract theory as a whole is to be understood (Section 1.5).
1.1 The Structure of Lucretius’ Account of the Development of Political Communities
As many scholars have pointed out, Lucretius’ Kulturentstehungslehre does not proceed in a strict chronological way. Lucretius describes the development of prehistoric communities and then contrasts it with modern society, leaving out certain intermediate steps of this development and jumping back and forth between prehistoric times and the modern age. In addition to the much-discussed remarks on fire, which are out of order,Footnote 7 a good example for this is the discussion of the domestication of animals.Footnote 8 It precedes Lucretius’ prehistory proper and is discussed in the context of the survival of different species instead of being discussed later in the text in the context of human beings first forming communities. These oddities in Lucretius’ presentation of events may be due to the circumstances of the work’s composition. One of the few things we know about Lucretius’ life is that he died before finishing the poem as a whole. Since book V is one of the last books, the oddities in the text could thus be explained by Lucretius’ premature death.Footnote 9 Some scholars thus argue that certain parts of the text should be transposed to restore the real order of Lucretius’ thought or even that the poem contains two separate cultural histories: one that is more developed and one that is a less polished draft included by a conscientious editor.Footnote 10
While some later passages might not fit perfectly into a neat schema, the majority of scholars now agree that the section of the poem that deals with the creation of human communities can be roughly divided into three parts. These parts correspond to three stages of the development of human social life on the Epicurean view.Footnote 11 In the first part of his cultural history, Lucretius describes human beings and their primitive nature in their original condition or state (V.925–1010). In the second and third part, he expounds how civilization comes into being, distinguishing between two distinct phases of communal development (V.1011–104 and V.1105–457).
As Bernd Manuwald has suggested, this division is based on an important methodological distinction in Epicurean philosophy, which is most succinctly expressed in the Letter to Herodotus. The passage in question is in part corrupt, as the angle brackets in the below translation make clear, but the main point that is emphasized in the text is nonetheless sufficiently clear. According to Epicurus, who does not make an empirical claim here, but presents an inference to the best explanation, any process of cultural development really consisted of two distinct processes:
Ἀλλὰ μὴν ὑποληπτέον καὶ τὴν φύσιν πολλά καὶ παντοῖα ὑπὸ αὐτῶν τῶν πραγμάτων διδαχθῆναι τε καὶ ἀναγκασθῆναι· τὸν δὲ λογισμὸν τὰ ὑπὸ ταύτης παρεγγυηθέντα ὕστερον ἐξακριβοῦν καὶ προσεξευρίσκειν ἐν μὲν τισὶ θᾶττον, ἐν δὲ τισὶ βραδύτερον καὶ ἐν μὲν τισὶ περιόδοις καὶ χρόνοις [ἀπὸ τῶν ἀπὸ τοῦ ἀπεῖρου] … ἐν δὲ τισὶ καὶ ἐλάττους.
Further, one must suppose that [human] nature was taught a large number of different lessons just by the facts themselves, and compelled [by them]; and that reasoning later made more precise what was handed over to it [by nature] and made additional discoveries – more quickly among some peoples, and more slowly among others and in some periods of time <making greater advances> and in others smaller ones.Footnote 12
In other words, the first development is due to nature (phusis) and proceeds from the things themselves (hupo autōn tōn pragmatōn). The idea here is that things themselves make certain developments possible or indeed necessary while they preclude others. An example of this is the human larynx.Footnote 13 Although human beings did not develop a larynx in order to produce sounds and they were not designed to produce sounds, humans, in the course of time, start making more systematic sounds because of certain impressions (phantasmata) or feelings (pathē) they have. Human beings thus slowly learn to use this organ by a process that is gradual, but not systematic. However, the continual use of the natural capacities kicks off the development of what will later become language. In order for this to happen, though, a process of reasoning (logismos) is needed.Footnote 14 This second development is distinct from the first.Footnote 15 During this process, reasoning perfects what was started by nature – more quickly in some cases, more slowly in others. Reasoning intervenes after nature has already made a beginning. In this case, human reasoning adds linguistic conventions by systematizing the random sounds that were produced during the phusis phase. Furthermore, it helps posit (tethēnai) and fix meanings to get rid of ambiguities and facilitate communication.Footnote 16
The distinction between a phusis-development and a logismos-development in any developmental process yields three distinct stages of Lucretius’ Kulturentstehungslehre:
(1) an original state or condition of humanity, during which no development has yet taken place
(2) a phusis phase, during which the development of natural human capacities takes place as a result of a necessary and natural process (phusis-development)
(3) a logismos phase, during which human reasoning perfects the process of development that nature started (logismos-development).
This distinction is especially relevant for the questions about justice because the three stages of cultural development correspond to different degrees of knowledge and implementation of justice and the law. As we will see, justice and law do not yet exist, and human beings have no understanding of justice and laws in the original state. In the phusis phase, by contrast, human beings gain an understanding of the common good, and they implement this understanding by means of reciprocal agreements, which determine what is just. However, at this point in societal development, there are no laws. Finally, in the logismos phase, after some failed attempts to create political and legal states, the understanding of the common good is codified into laws. As a result, a human community at this stage will have not only reciprocal agreements that correspond to moral norms but also political and juridical institutions.Footnote 17 In short, then, justice and law come to be in separate, albeit related, processes.
In the next sections, let us turn to each of the three phases of development that were just distinguished and discuss them in detail in light of their significance for justice and law, especially in light of the question of whether justice and law come to be by nature or by convention on the Epicurean view.
1.2 The Original State
Book V of On the Nature of Things as a whole discusses the creation of the world on the basis of non-teleological principles, without the intervention of the divine. Prior to the discussion of human communities proper, Lucretius describes human beings as they were before they lived in communities. We can call this state of humanity as a whole prior to the emergence of communal life the “original state,” that is, the original condition of humankind in the sense of the state of nature of early modern theories of the social contract, not in the sense of a political or legal state that precedes the present-day political or legal state. The following analysis of the original state will make clear (1) that human beings are originally self-sufficient beings, that is, not social or political beings by nature and (2) that human beings lack the requisite ethical and political knowledge about what is good for everyone to live together with others in the original state and that justice and law do not yet exist at this point in time.
Inferring to the best explanation, Lucretius reasons that in order to have survived during the phase of pre-political existence, human beings must have been physically enduring. They must have had strong bones and sinews and have been resilient to heat and cold as well as to different kinds of diseases.Footnote 18 They must have lived the life of hunters and gatherers.Footnote 19 And they must not have had fixed homes, but slept under the open sky and worn no clothes.Footnote 20 In short, human beings must have been very hardy creatures that lived a rather primitive life. At this point in time, humankind as a whole cannot yet have possessed the arts that are an important part of human culture today. Lucretius explicitly names plowing, which is a requisite for farming and characteristic of a sedentary lifestyle.Footnote 21 Furthermore, human beings also must have lacked the ethical and political knowledge that is the prerequisite for human communities to come into being. As Lucretius writes, “Nor could they [primitive human beings] look to the common good, nor did they know to make mutual use of any moral norms or laws [nec commune bonum poterant spectare neque ulllis | moribus inter se scibant nec legibus uti].”Footnote 22
Let us look more closely at these important lines. At 958–9, Lucretius makes an epistemological claim (they “could not look [nec … poterant spectare]”) about the extent of moral knowledge in the original state. This claim distinguishes between moral norms (mores) and laws (leges), a distinction that will be mirrored in the separate descriptions of how moral norms and laws come to be later in the account. The most interesting part of the claim is the emphasis on the common good (commune bonum). Precisely what this is is not immediately clear. Lucretius does not define the term and does not repeat the expression elsewhere in his work. It could be understood in at least two ways. First, “common good” could merely refer to the good that is common to all. It would then be equivalent to the “natural good” that Epicurus mentions, for instance, at KD 7 and Letter to Menoeceus 128–9. This “natural good” is the Epicurean highest good or end that all agents pursue: pleasure (hedonē), understood as freedom from bodily pain (aponia) and mental distress (ataraxia), which according to the Epicureans in the cradle argument, all beings pursue from birth.Footnote 23 Yet such a reading is unsatisfactory. If the common good is the natural good, that is, Epicurean pleasure, it seems that human beings in the original state should also pursue it. But Lucretius claims as well that human beings in the original state cannot look to this good, which would result in a contradiction.
Let us therefore suggest a second, alternative reading. On this reading, the common good refers to the good of the group as a whole as opposed to the good of each individual. In other words, “commune bonum” at V.958 means that human beings in the original state have not yet grasped that there is an aspect to the good that pertains to life in community and that this good is a good that is beneficial to everyone. This is true regardless of which particular philosophy an agent ascribes to, although for the Epicureans, it will turn out to mean that for any given agent, being in a state of pleasure is compatible with the pleasure of the larger group as a whole.Footnote 24
In making the epistemological claim that human beings could not look to the common good and could not make use of moral norms and laws, Lucretius leaves open whether the common good, moral norms, and laws already exist at this point in the account. On a first reading, being able to use moral norms and laws seems to presuppose that moral norms and laws must already exist so that they can in fact be used. Alternatively, however, one might take “use moral norms and laws” not to mean “apply moral norms and laws,” but rather to set up moral norms in the first place. The latter reading seems to be the correct reading of Lucretius’ comment insofar as human beings will only later in the account agree on what is just and decide on laws by which to abide (see Sections 1.3 and 1.4). Justice and law are, as we will see in more detail below, historical achievements on the Epicurean view. In regard to the common good, it seems, by contrast, that there is no reason to think that human beings cannot make out the common good because there exists no common good to make out.Footnote 25
The main reason why Lucretius claims that human beings lack an understanding of the common good at this point in the development is that the first human beings, from a psychological perspective, have rather simple needs; what the earth produces is already enough to satisfy whatever human beings desire: “What the sun and rains had given them, what the earth had spontaneously produced, were gifts rich enough to content their hearts [quod sol atque imbres dederant, quod terra crearat | sponte sua, stais id placabat pectora donum].”Footnote 26 Accordingly, their individual, self-sufficient natures are completely enough to procure these individual needs; other people are not needed. As Lucretius puts it, in the original state, “Individuals seized whatever prize fortune had offered them, trained as they were to live and use their strength for themselves alone [quod cuique obtulerat praedae fortuna, ferebat | sponte sua sibi quisque valere et vivere doctus].”Footnote 27
The family, which is typically taken to be the basic unit of human community,Footnote 28 does not yet exist at this point in time. During this stage, men and women meet to have intercourse, but their encounters are fleeting and they do not form more lasting ties.Footnote 29 The power dynamic between the sexes seems generally to favor men insofar as Lucretius mentions not only the trade of food for sex and mutual love, but also rape, as the reasons why human beings unite. However, Lucretius does not claim that men establish a patriarchic dominance at this point in the account; this dominance was probably established only once the family comes to be during the next phase of societal development.
The most astonishing fact about this early stage, however, is that one wonders how children are raised and, in fact, if there are any children.Footnote 30 Lucretius only tells us at a later stage that men and women watched their children be born.Footnote 31 Do the early encounters between men and women also produce children? If they do, then they cannot be raised in a traditional family setting because, again, the family has not yet come into being. In this context we should recall that the very first human beings are literally children of the earth on the Epicurean view insofar as they, like all other animals, have emerged straight out of the earth.Footnote 32 Furthermore, the very first generation of human beings seems to come into existence in a relatively complete way, that is, as adults or – since we do not know anything about their exact age – at least as self-sufficient young beings; there is no description of them growing up. Given this account, one wonders whether human beings existed only in such a state for one generation or whether they were in this state for a longer period of time. This is again unclear since we do not have an indication of how long the original state actually lasted.
Democritus offers a similar account to the one we find in Lucretius.Footnote 33 The spontaneous generation of human beings directly from the earth in Lucretius echoes Democritus’ claim that human beings are created out of earth and moisture.Footnote 34 Furthermore, Democritus also comments that the first human beings lived an uncivilized and savage life,Footnote 35 which mirrors Lucretius’ observation that the first human beings “lived their lives in the roving manner of wild animals [vulgivago vitam tractabant more ferarum].”Footnote 36 Most importantly, however, Democritus also remarks that human beings at this point in time live “sporadēn,”Footnote 37 that is, “scattered,” and there is some debate on what the term means, which incidentally is also used by Protagoras’ account of how communities come to be in his Great Speech in Plato’s eponymous dialogue.Footnote 38 According to one reading, “scattered” means that human beings live completely isolated lives without anyone else. According to an alternative reading, “scattered” must mean that there exist at least some smaller family-sized units. However, if the Democritean and Epicurean accounts are alike, then the testimony in Lucretius supports the former reading: human beings during the first stage of their existence really do live lives that are independent of the lives of other human beings because they really were not in need of others to live their respective lives as they are not able to conceive of the benefit that a cooperative life would provide.
While the Epicurean anthropological observation that human beings live isolated lives without children may seem implausible from a modern perspective, we should remind ourselves that similar claims were likely defended by Democritus and Protagoras.Footnote 39 More importantly, we should note that this observation will not refute the Epicurean account as a whole, since one could, from a modern perspective, begin the account once the family has come about and still have a coherent account. Within the context, the claim that human beings are completely self-sufficient beings by nature also serves a very important argumentative function. It makes clear that the Epicureans do not endorse the Stoic and Aristotelian claim that human beings are social and political animals by nature.Footnote 40 This means that the Epicureans deny that human beings are by nature part of some community and that the life together with others is, under all circumstances, a prerequisite to achieve human fulfillment, as Aristotle and the Stoics claim. Such a reading is also supported by the overwhelming majority of other sources insofar as these sources clearly and unambiguously ascribe to the Epicureans the thesis that human beings are not social and political beings. In this vein, we read in fourth-century CE philosopher Themistius that Epicurus thinks that “human beings are not by nature sociable and cultivated [μὴ φύσει εἶναι τὸν ἄνθρωπον κοινωνικόν τε καὶ ἥμερον],”Footnote 41 and the Stoic Epictetus (first to second century CE) reports that
ὅταν ἀναιρεῖν θέλῃ τὴν φυσικὴν κοινωνίαν ἀνθρώποις πρὸς ἀλλήλους, αῦτῷ τῷ ἀναιρουμένῳ συγχρῆται. τί γὰρ λέγει; μὴ ἐξαπατᾶσθε, ἄνθρωποι, μηδὲ παράγεσθε μηδὲ διαπίπτετε· οὐκ ἔστι φυσικὴ κοινωνία τοῖς λογικοῖς πρὸς ἀλλήλους, πιστεύσατέ μοι· οἱ δὲ τὰ ἕτερα λέγοντες ἐξαπατιῶσιν ὑμᾶς καὶ παραλογίζονται.
when [Epicurus] wishes to get rid of the natural communion of human beings with each other, he makes use of the same thing that is gotten rid of. For what does he say? “Do not be deceived, men, nor led astray or cheated. There is no natural communion among rational beings with each other, believe me. Those who say other things deceive and delude you.”Footnote 42
The only prima facie piece of evidence that communal life is natural for the Epicureans is another passage in Epictetus: “Epicurus understands as well that we are by nature sociable [ἐπινοεῖ καὶ Ἐπίκουρος ὅτι φύσει ἐσμὲν κοινωνικοί].”Footnote 43 Reimar Müller convincingly argues, however, that this passage does not mean that Epicurus actually endorses the position that life in human communities is natural, but that he should do so (from Epictetus’ Stoic perspective), if he were more reasonable.Footnote 44 After all, Epictetus continues, “but once having placed our good in the body he cannot say anything different [ἀλλ’ ἅπαξ ἐν τῷ κελύφει θεὶς τὸ ἀγαθὸν ἡμῶν οὐκέτι δύναται ἄλλο οὐδὲν εἰπεῖν].”Footnote 45 As we will see in more detail below, the Epicureans do not deny that communal life becomes necessary at some point in the cultural development, namely, when human nature changes, but they do deny that it has always been so, and they would insist that the necessity is the result of a calculation of what is most beneficial, not part of an inherent drive to live with others.Footnote 46
In summary, then, communal life does not and cannot develop in the original state because human beings do not have any understanding of the common good and because such an understanding is necessary to form societies. Human beings are completely self-sufficient beings on the Epicurean view. Communities are not required at this point of development. First, they are not required because living in communion is not essential to human nature. And second, they are not required because communities do not provide goods that our primitive ancestors could not provide on their own. Accordingly, should communities come to be at some point, they – just as justice and the laws that accompany their emergence – will be a contingent historical achievement and as such not have been part of a greater design that in some way has always already been part of the human nature (as, for instance, on the Aristotelian and Stoic views).
1.3 The Phusis Phase
At V.1011, a new stage of development is described, one in which moral norms (mores) come to be and feature prominently as the social glue that makes life with other people possible. After all, mores are nothing other than the rules and principles that regulate human behavior in the interaction with other human beings, which is characteristic of life in groups. In particular, Lucretius now turns to describe the emergence of two forms of life with others: the life of men and women together in what might be called a family and the relationship of neighbors, that is, the relationship of families to each other in what might be called a community.Footnote 47 The moral norms that govern the first type of relationship are not explicitly named by Lucretius; the moral norms that pertain to the second relationship are called “justice.” At this point in the account, we thus see clearly how the Epicurean account of justice involves conventions and that justice is a contingent, historical product on their view. Furthermore, we also see that the emergence of the family precedes the emergence of the social contract, which indicates that even on the Epicurean view certain levels of sociality will precede the sociality that comes about as a result of the social contract. Thus, once the actual social contract comes to be, the Epicurean view does not assume pace other contractarian theories that completely isolated individuals make agreements with each other. Instead, on their view, individuals who already live in families make agreements with each other. Finally, at this stage of the account, we also get an initial characterization of the scope and contracting agents involved in the Epicurean social contract (which will also be discussed in greater detail in Chapter 2).
Because the circumstances in the original state did not require that human beings live together with other people, let us begin to work out the Epicurean account by looking more closely at what changes compared with the previous phase of development so that human beings now decide to live with others. After the relatively stable original condition has become unstable, human beings will decide to change their ways of life. (Here, it is important to emphasize that every new phase of development will in a sense be an improvement vis-à-vis the previous phase, but will also have shortcomings of its own. For instance, while the change to life in community will take care of certain needs human beings develop, it will also itself be accompanied by the deficiency, which in turn will lead to an unstable state that the logismos phase of development will address.)
Recall that the main hindrance to life together with other people in the original state is that human beings, as self-sufficient beings, are able to satisfy their needs by themselves. Consequently, human beings must have new needs and/or no longer be self-sufficient in regard to all their needs, and, likewise, the life with other human beings needs to be able to make up for the new needs and the loss of self-sufficiency in some way.
In line with these considerations, Lucretius opens the section that deals with the development of communal life with a comment related to human self-sufficiency. As we saw above, human beings in the original state are described as tough and enduring and they live the life of hunters and gatherers. Now, by contrast, human beings settle down and consequently their nature changes:
Next they provided themselves with huts and skins and fire, and woman, united to man, went to live in one <place with him. The advantages of cohabitation> were learned, and they saw the birth of their offspring. It was then that human beings first began to become gentle: The use of fire rendered their shivering bodies less able to endure the cold beneath the pavilion of the sky; Venus tamed their strength; and children with their charming ways easily broke down the stern disposition of their parents.Footnote 48
The change from isolated hunters and gatherers to a sedentary family mode of life is surprising because Lucretius does not explain precisely what caused the change from one mode of life to the other. What suddenly made human beings build huts, wear clothing, establish more lasting unions between the sexes, and have children that led to the formation of families? It seems that the transition is missing here; nothing in the description of the state of nature gives us readers the answer to this question.
However, it is possible to fill in Lucretius’ account. We merely need to assume that small changes ultimately can aggregate and so lead to a bigger and more significant change: the formation of a habit. Take an everyday case first. One might imagine that Scott the couch potato decides to become more active by taking a daily stroll through the park. After a while, he then expands the routine further by power walking. Furthermore, we might imagine him after another while to start running and to be out longer and, in the process, to change his dietary habits in order to accommodate his body’s increased need for calories. Ultimately, Scott might even compete in a 5k race. At that point at the latest, we would probably no longer refer to him as a couch potato.
Now, Lucretius may imagine a similar process happened to humankind as a whole, albeit in reverse. Human beings, chancing upon fire and skins and inventing huts, quickly see the advantages such innovations – and others similar to them – afford. Gradually, they begin to adopt these innovations and make them part of their daily lives. These innovations and changes may initially be independent of one another and not necessitated by each other. They may emerge one after the other and be small and insignificant at first. The pace of the development can thus appear to be rather slow. Eventually, a tipping point is reached; taken together, certain innovations, which individually altered the state of human beings only insignificantly, lead to bigger changes and ultimately result in a significant transformation of human nature. Human beings thus lose the nature they had in the original state and become gentle, having become accustomed to innovations that make their lives easier.Footnote 49 Constant dripping wears away a stone; this is the meaning of “tum … primum … coepit.”
Human nature, then, changes and human beings become gentle and softer according to Lucretius’ account. As a consequence, human beings are also no longer as self-sufficient as they originally were. This means that there are new needs that arise as a result of their changed nature, and the presence of children probably contributes to these needs as well insofar as it occasions the need to create a safe environment, in which these children can grow up.Footnote 50 The family comes to be and with it the requisite knowledge required to live with one’s family members. Note that “advantages of cohabitation” in the passage quoted above is Martin Smith’s addition, as the angle brackets make clear; the corresponding line in Lucretius’ text is missing. However, there are good reasons in favor of Smith’s suggestion or one similar in kind. Once relationships between the sexes are no longer casual, human beings need to acquire some understanding of how to live with a partner and, as a result, relationships become sustainable. As “cognita sunt” at V.1013 indicates, some intellectual act, some act of learning, takes place at this point of the development.Footnote 51 It seems very likely that this act pertains to some aspect of human interaction. Given the context of the passage that describes the first longer lasting relationships that are being formed, which probably amounts to the creation of the family, the lacuna probably contained the poem’s first instance of human beings developing moral norms in regard to these relationships.
The family on its own, however, either is not enough to take care of all newly arisen needs or also creates new needs that need to be addressed. This is especially true for the need for protection. As a result, Lucretius turns to a second new kind of relationship that emerges at this stage: that between neighbors or family units, whose purpose it will be to make everyone safer. These new relationships are accompanied by the historical emergence of moral norms, which brings us to the most important passage in Lucretius’ account of cultural development when it comes to justice:
It was then, too, that neighbors eagerly began to make amicitiaFootnote 52 one with another, not to hurt or to be harmed, and claimed protection for their children and womenfolk, indicating by means of inarticulate cries and gestures that it is fair [aequum] that the weak [imbecillorum] are pitied [misererier] by everyone. Although it was not possible for concord [concordia] to be achieved universally, the great majority kept their agreements [foedera] loyally. Otherwise, the human race would have been entirely extinguished at that early stage and could not have propagated and preserved itself to the present day.Footnote 53
It is possible that the “et … et …” at V.1019–27 indicates that the formation of ties between neighbors happens at the same time as the family comes into being; that is, men and women form more lasting ties with each other. This would indicate that the developmental process for Lucretius includes parallel developments. However, such a reading is not necessary insofar as the “et … et …” is still compatible with the idea that one relationship comes into being before the other; the sociality of the family precedes the sociality of the wider community and so in contrast to other contractarian theories, the Epicurean social contract is not the product of completely isolated individuals, but recognizes a preexisting form of sociality (the family).
The rich passage just quoted is the first to describe the historical emergence of justice (aequum) (1) in the full sense as (2) a kind of agreement. Both of these points can be or, in fact, have been challenged, though, and so it is worth defending both of them in more detail, starting with the second point.
Some commentators have objected that the contingently and historically arising ties between neighbors are forms of amicitia, that is, friendships, and not agreements.Footnote 54 According to such a reading, friendship rather than social agreements would thus stand at the beginning of the communal life for the Epicureans. This would be especially interesting because social contract theorists typically do not accord much significance to the notion of friendship, which, by contrast, is a feature of virtue-based approaches to the political, such as the one by Aristotle that even features a specific kind of political friendship. The reading just proposed would thus highlight the political importance of Epicurean friendship. The suggestion also gains additional plausibility insofar as Protagoras, in his account of how political communities come to be in Plato, claims that the move from an original condition to a state of society is characterized by the emergence of “bonds of friendship [desmoi philias]”Footnote 55 rather than more straightforwardly agreements of any kind. As is well known, Protagoras is from Abdera and his account of how political community comes to be shares some features with the account of his fellow Abderite Democritus, from whom, in turn, Epicurus is typically taken to have borrowed many ideas. In stressing the idea of friendship at this point, Lucretius could emphasize features of the Epicurean account that have an Abderite origin, but that are elsewhere not highlighted in extant Epicurean texts. Furthermore, there is evidence in Cicero’s On Ends that there were different accounts of friendship advanced by different Epicurean authors. Supposedly, “[t]here are also those [Epicureans],” of whom we do not know the identity, “who say that, among the wise, there is a kind of pact that they do not love friends less than themselves [sunt autem, qui dicant foedus esse quoddam sapientium ut ne minus amicos quam se ipsos diligant].”Footnote 56 This testimony does not allow us to infer that all types of friendship are indeed agreements, and it is an open question whether the friendship between sages that the Epicurean spokesperson Torquatus mentions in the passage is identical to the friendship we find in Lucretius. Nevertheless, Torquatus’ comment would support the idea that at least in some circumstances some Epicurean philosophers understood friendship as a kind of agreement.
Despite these considerations, there is no need for an “Abderite” reading of lines 1019–27. As some commentators point out, “amicitia” need not be translated or in fact be understood as “friendship.”Footnote 57 “Amicitia” can also mean “alliance” and so be a synonym for “foedus,” which is used in the same passage quoted above and is a Latin equivalent of the Greek term “sunthēkē,” which, as we shall see in more detail in Chapter 2, plays a prominent role in Epicurus’ writings on justice and law. In addition, as we have seen already, what complicates matters is the fact that some Epicureans themselves seem to have understood friendship as kinds of agreement, and it may also be possible that the Epicureans understand friendship as “fellowship” rather than intimate bonds between people, that is, take them to come with only very minimal obligations.Footnote 58 As a result, the passage may not be asserting anything grandiose about friendship that would be unusual in any way. Lucretius’ claim, by contrast, that the first alliance between neighbors concerns not harming and not being harmed (nec laedere nec violari) strongly echoes Epicurus’ claim in the Principal Doctrines that agreements that are the basis for justice are over “not harming and not being harmed” (mē blaptein mēde blaptesthai).Footnote 59
This brings us to the other point, the one regarding the use of the term “aequum.” At line 1023, Lucretius for the very first time in the account of development claims that human beings make use of moral vocabulary or, more specifically, communicate that something is “aequum.” In doing so, human beings communicate that one given course of behavior is preferable to another – in this case, pitying the weak is preferable to not doing so – or to other courses of behavior. However, it is unclear what Greek word the Latin term “aequum” translates. It could translate either “dikaion” (just) or “ison” (equal or fair). In the latter case, justice might have its beginnings in the idea of weighing and determining equal shares. The development of the notion of justice would thus begin with the equal, that is, with situations in which human beings apportion shares. According to this reading, the act of apportioning would be conveyed by simple language, perhaps even exclusively by pointing. In support of this suggestion, Lucretius claims that human beings at this point in the process of cultural development only communicate “by means of inarticulate cries and gestures.”Footnote 60 One could then argue that the understanding of justice that the first human beings have (and that is captured in their preconception)Footnote 61 gradually evolves over time, and that it is not simple insofar as it presupposes the concept of equality.
While such a reading has some appeal prima facie, it ultimately fails to convince. First, in Epicurus and other Epicureans writing in Greek, we do not find the term “ison” in connection with justice. Of course, it is possible that we merely lack the relevant texts. However, it seems unlikely that such a key distinction is extant only in Lucretius. Second, Lucretius uses “iustum” once in its technical sense as “just” at III.950.Footnote 62 And so it is all the more surprising that book V, which contains a discussion of justice and the law, does not again use “iustum,” but “aequum” instead. It thus seems more likely that Lucretius is using “just” and “equal,” “iustum” and “aequum,” as synonyms. This is also confirmed by looking at V.1149 where “aequum” is used to describe the laws (“legibus aequis”). The context is the final stage of communal development: here, it does not make sense to say that the laws are merely “fair” in the sense of a precursor to the full-fledged notion of justice (that is, the iustum or dikaion). At this point, the laws are just in the full sense precisely because they are in accordance with the preconception of justice, that is, the practical understanding of justice available to agents at the time. In short, then, “aequum” must translate “dikaion” at V.1023; for the Epicureans, human beings first make agreements about what is just during the first phase of development, and not merely think about apportioning shares.Footnote 63 Indeed, that justice, on their view, is more robust can also be seen by the fact that it includes provisions for the weak, who although not equal to contracting agents, are equally protected by the agreements. It is to these provisions that we turn to next, since they are quite revealing of the nature of the agreement that comes to be at this point in the account.
The historical agreements over harming and not being harmed are made by the heads of the families, according to Lucretius at line 1021; they include an additional provision to care for women and children, that is, household dependents, which is at odds with the idea that women generally are contracting partners.Footnote 64 Although this is not explicitly stated, this setup seems to imply that the political head of the household, the one who can negotiate with the neighbors, is likely male and, as a result, that a patriarchic hierarchy is established at this point in the account. That there is no mention of women making agreements here (or in fact in any other Epicurean text that is extant) might be considered a bit surprising insofar as the Garden had women as members and, thus, in contrast to other philosophical schools in antiquity, is often seen as having relatively progressive views on women.Footnote 65 For example, Leontion is supposed to have written a treatise against Theophrastus, which is unfortunately not extant.Footnote 66 Even if the treatise did not actually exist, the very mention of the treatise is predicated on the plausibility that on the Epicurean view, a woman could have been the author of such a treatise; otherwise, the polemic would not hit its mark. Accordingly, it seems possible that at least some women had the requisite mental capacities to make agreements on the Epicurean view. Yet we should also note in this context that the second- to first- century BCE Epicurean Zeno of Sidon is supposed to have categorically asserted the imperfection of the female sex.Footnote 67 As a result, there is no indication of (1) whether the Epicureans thought that the capability to make agreements extended to all women (if they in fact believed that women are able to make agreements) or (2) whether the Epicureans also thought that given the reality of gender dynamics in the ancient world and the dominance of men in general, women (or at least most women) would ever be in social situations – outside perhaps the communities of friends – that would enable them to make agreements
At 1023, Lucretius furthermore observes in regard to the dependents to whom protection is extended that it is part of the agreement that “it is just [aequum] that the weak [imbecillorum] are pitied [misererier] by everyone.” This comment pertains to the question of what is agreed upon. Who the weak are who are mentioned in this passage is not clearly defined, and “imbecillus” is a word used only here in Lucretius. On a first reading, Lucretius could also make the more sophisticated point that the weaker members of the community more generally, perhaps first and foremost the elderly but also those with bodily and mental disabilities, ought to be the object of pity. On this reading, the social contract would be very quickly extended to needy relatives and perhaps even all members of society rather than being limited only to the core family members. However, “imbecillus” on a more restricted and perhaps safer reading could also merely refer to the women and children who were mentioned previously, not the infirm more generally. Put differently, although it seems theoretically possible that the Epicurean social contract can very quickly be extended to all, whether it actually will be extended in such a way will depend on whether the weak are (1) a threat to members of the community in terms of harm and (2) associated with a family in some way. If they are not (which is likely given their designation as “weak”) and no one has an interest in them qua dependent, it seems that there is no requirement to include them in the agreements of justice on the Epicurean view.
Whoever the weak may exactly be, it is especially striking that Lucretius comments at 1023 that the weak are to be pitied. At this point, some commentators argue that this emotional reaction is wholly distinct from the benefit of not harming and not being harmed that is also mentioned as the content of the agreements that are being formed at this point.Footnote 68 Accordingly, the Epicurean account of how communities come to be would not only be a result of a calculation of what is beneficial, but also be driven by an independent feeling of compassion. However, this reading seems dubious. After all, line 1023 does not have to be taken as giving the reason why human beings act in a certain way in regard to the weak, but rather can be taken as an alternate description of the course of action that is decreed by the agreement. In other words, it is not the case that everyone is compassionate with the weak because they feel pity for them, but rather the agreement recognizes that compassionate behavior toward the weaker members of the community is the right or just (aequum) course of action. On this alternative reading, the reason why human beings behave benevolently toward the weak would still be wholly dictated by what is beneficial: it may be significantly better for human beings to live in a community in which the weak in general are not harmed, since such a community might be more stable overall and therefore safer than a community that antagonizes its weaker members, and human beings might prefer to live in a community in which they know that should they become injured or infirm, they will also not be harmed in any way.Footnote 69 In short, any kind of pity would still be grounded on what is beneficial, which, as we will see in more detail in the next chapter, functions as the natural ground of the Epicurean account.Footnote 70
Finally, On the Nature of Things V.1019–27 makes clear that the situation that is created as a result of the agreements is not stable. Agreements are kept most of the time, but – as we will see in light of Lucretius’ later account of the development of civilizationFootnote 71 – there is no way to sanction infringements at this stage. Here, we see once again Lucretius’ nuanced appreciation of the cultural achievements of this stage: although it is a deficit of this stage that concord (concordia) is not universal, it must – as Lucretius points out – at least be widespread, for otherwise, humankind as a whole would have died out. Put again differently, the historical process of the establishment of justice must therefore move into a last, final phase.
In his commentary on The Nature of Things V, Gordon Campbell points out that the observation that human beings almost died out at this point in the account is surprising because the description of the original state was not at all violent.Footnote 72 It therefore seems odd that suddenly violence is so widespread (even if not ubiquitous). Campbell explains this by referring to rational choice theory and changing evolutionary strategies among human beings:Footnote 73 what worked for primitive human beings no longer works for human beings in the first phase of cultural development. Human beings undergo a change in their nature, and as a result, there is more violence among them. And this violence needs to be kept at bay, which is the purpose of the newly made agreements.Footnote 74 However, these agreements are – as we saw – not always kept, and remedying or at least attenuating these injustices will thus be a major task for the next phase of development.
In reply to Campbell, one may remark that his criticism presupposes that agreements are made only to keep human beings from harming each other. But as we will see in more detail in the next chapter, this would mean to unduly restrict the content of the agreements. After all, there is much evidence for violence committed by animals and that wild animals are a huge threat to human beings during the early phase of cultural development.Footnote 75 A better reading of lines 1025–7 is thus that mankind would die out because some human beings do not always wholeheartedly participate in communal measures designed to ward off any kind of attack, which indeed would pose a great danger to human beings who are now weakened in their natures and thus even more vulnerable to such threats.
In summary, in this section, we have seen that both the family and the first human communities as aggregations of families arise at some point in history, and that the first human communities arise via agreements, which in turn decree which behaviors are just and which are not. It is thus clear that some sociality precedes the social contract, on the Epicurean view, and that the origin of Epicurean justice is conventional, even if we also already saw in the previous section that the commune bonum, which itself is not conventional, will also be important in making Epicurean agreements of justice. In the next section, we will see how the account is extended to the laws.Footnote 76
1.4 The Logismos Phase
During the third stage of development, justice is set on a more solid footing. It becomes codified into laws, which for the Epicureans are an extension of justice, bringing the developmental process that started in the original state to completion. Just like justice, the laws, on the Epicurean view, are thus a historical achievement. As a result, the Epicureans will also defend a kind of conventionalism in regard to the law, even if, just as in the case of justice, the conventional nature of the laws will ultimately be grounded in what is beneficial. By institutionalizing what is just and ultimately beneficial and putting in place enforcement mechanisms and punishments, the original agreements become binding in legal communities. While the deficit of the last phase (that agreements are often violated) is somewhat remedied, the resulting situation will not be perfect.
The development that leads to the establishment of the rule of law is not linear. In fact, it begins with the failure of the first attempts to set up government in the form of kingships:
And more and more every day those who excelled in intellect and were strong in mind showed the others how to exchange their former way of life for new practices and, in particular, for the use of fire. Kings began to build cities and to choose sites for citadels to be strongholds and places of refuge for themselves; and they distributed gifts of flocks and fields to individuals according to their beauty, strength, and intellect.Footnote 77
A problem in regard to this passage is whether “those who excelled in intellect and were strong in mind” of line 1107 are identical to the first kings of line 1109. This seems to be very likely, since a change in subject between the lines would be quite odd.Footnote 78 Understood in this way, then, the passage implies that the preeminent men/first kings use their superior capabilities to serve their own interest, not that of the public (see the pronouns ipsi … sibi). The preeminent men thus try to use their preeminence to circumvent the terms of the original contract. They try to create special privileges for themselves: They order cities and citadels to be built so they can have a safe residence. And this place of refuge is then used as a power basis in order to amass other privileges.
The attempt of the first kings to usurp power does not succeed. According to Lucretius, the initial kingships fail because the interests of all are not sufficiently taken into account.Footnote 79 In the process of accruing power, the kings use their wealth to persuade and deceive the many. As Lucretius writes, “no matter how much physical strength and beauty people possess, they follow in the train of the rich [divitioris enim sectam plerumque sequuntur | quamlibet et fortes et pulchro corpore creti].”Footnote 80 However, such a deception of the many is not successful for long. Strife and power struggles very soon result. These lead to the dethronement of the first kings.Footnote 81 This experience makes people aware of the necessity of introducing the rule of law:
At length some of them taught the others to create magistracies and established ordinances, so that [the others] might want to use laws.Footnote 82 The human race, utterly weary as it was of leading a life of violence and worn out with feuds, was the more ready to submit voluntarily to the restraint of laws and stringent ordinances. The reason why people were sick and tired of a life of violence was that each individual was prompted by anger to exact revenge more cruelly than is now allowed by just laws.Footnote 83
The passage above mentions both “laws” (leges) and “ordinances” (iura). According to standard Latin legal vocabulary, “ius” is a broader term, encompassing all kinds of moral norms, written and unwritten, while “lex” is narrower and refers to written law. However, both terms can also be used as synonyms. If Lucretius used the terms as distinct in meaning, he would claim that the new sanction mechanisms helped codify both written laws as well as the (unwritten) moral norms in human communities, which would make the latter more pervasive. This would be difficult to make sense of. In the case of norms, societal reprimanding can be effective to enforce them. In this vein, it might be effective to reprimand agents in regard to certain behavior, for instance, to shout at them to enforce a social norm. But it seems surprising that such a way of reprimanding agents was not available in the previous stage of societal development. After all, the problem of the previous phase is that there are no sanction mechanisms in place to create pervasive adherence to norms and that such pervasiveness can only come about by the punishments that are set down in conjunction with the law. It seems more likely, then, that Lucretius is using “lex” and “ius” as a hendiadys to express the same idea: codified law. This would also fit better with the Greek heritage of Epicurean thought. Epicurus, writing in Greek, had no way of distinguishing “lex” and “ius.” In Greek, the word “nomos” covers the meaning of both moral convention and law, both written and unwritten.
The passage thus makes it clear that for Lucretius, the rule of law (“codified law”) emerges as the result of a process that heavily involves trial and error and the recognition of what is best faute de mieux. Furthermore, as has been argued, Lucretius at this point draws on what seems like a theory of political change, according to which one form of government devolves into the next.Footnote 84 The original kingship deteriorates into a tyranny, the tyranny degrades into an oligarchy, and ultimately a form of government emerges that in virtue of its magistrate (magistratus) has some resemblance with the republican political order of Lucretius’ day. Such a description is notably different from one that would capture the political realities of Athens in Epicurus’ time, which lost at least some autonomy by becoming part of the empire of Alexander the Great. Therefore, Lucretius’ account at this point is very unlikely a direct adoption of Epicurus’ ideas, if indeed Epicurus himself dealt with this topic. (Unfortunately, no discussion is extant.) However, this is not to say that the idea of a change in forms of political order that is described in Lucretius is entirely novel, either. As is well known, other thinkers such as Plato, Aristotle, and – most systematically – the second-century BCE historian Polybius discuss the idea that certain forms of political order will decline into other forms, and it would be a desideratum of future scholarship to find out to what extent Lucretius may – either directly or indirectly – have found inspiration in these writers.
In this context, we should also note that it is even unclear which form of political order is truly the best on the Epicurean view and so which one Epicurus himself would have endorsed. While Abderite accounts of how political communities come to be, like those of Democritus and Protagoras, are often taken to be defenses of democratic ideology,Footnote 85 it is not clear that this is also true of the Epicureans. There is, for instance, some evidence that the Epicureans endorsed monarchical kingships at least on some occasions, namely, on the condition that these kingships further Epicurean ends,Footnote 86 even if generally Epicureans were advised to avoid contact with kings.Footnote 87 The basic idea here is very simple: if a king is able to free Epicurean agents to live the good life without having to worry about political matters, then such an arrangement seems very favorable. In the same vein, Philodemus wrote a treatise On the Good King According to Homer, which in part is a work of literary criticism. More importantly, however, the work can be seen as an outline of the characteristics of a good ruler, with the intention of providing a model that real-life rulers can follow, a kind of mirror of princes like Xenophon’s Education of Cyrus.Footnote 88 Moreover, Philodemus’ work was dedicated to the Roman senator Piso, who was Philodemus’ patron.Footnote 89 And, in the same vein, Plutarch also claims that the Epicurean Colotes (fourth to third century BCE) dedicated the treatise, in which he systematically refuted the doctrines of other philosophers, to Ptolemy II Philadelphus.Footnote 90 This again seems to indicate that the Epicureans at least in some instances had direct relationships with rulers and were favorable toward kingships. Nevertheless, as we will see in more detail in the course of this book, the Epicurean attitude toward the political is often dependent on particular circumstances. It therefore seems most prudent not to single out a given form of political organization as the preferred one, but rather to ascribe to the Epicureans a conditional attitude in regard to the question of which form of political order is best as well.
Having discussed the form of political order that is to be established, let us next turn to how the rule of law is established in Lucretius’ account. For the Roman author, even those who have intellect are prone to errors and thus to “forgetfulness” when it comes to what is best for society as a whole. As a result, different preeminent men are needed, who give the laws after the first kingships fail. These men are more mindful of what is beneficial to all than the first kings were, and so we see clearly at this point – more clearly than when the agreements of justice emerged – that Epicurean legal agreements are not purely conventional but importantly need to take into consideration what is beneficial for everyone.
Furthermore, in stark contrast to the previous phase of societal development when all human beings directly agreed on what was to be just, this phase is no longer characterized by a joint effort of all. Instead, the hallmark of this phase of development is that distinct individuals are the driving force behind development, namely, those who have superior intellectual capacities. The majority of the population is left out. Although all human beings have some capabilities to grasp the basic moral vocabulary in the first cultural phase (after all, this capability is part of their nature and a prerequisite for society to function), not all have the ability to teach others and lead the way to introduce new ways of life.Footnote 91 In order to do this, different, superior intellectual capabilities are required. These, Lucretius seems to assume, are not distributed in the same way as the basic ability to get along with each other and form basic alliances. Therefore, during this phase of the development of civilization, some preeminent individuals are the principal agents of change.
Yet it would be wrong to think that the many play no role whatsoever in establishing the rule of law. The many concur with the laws that are given by their own will (sponte sua), likely because they have instrumental reasons to do so.Footnote 92 The process of law-giving nevertheless involves a form of consent, namely, insofar as the many decide that it is right to adhere to certain laws; the laws are not merely imposed on them.Footnote 93 This observation is confirmed by Hermarchus, who uses the verb “assent [sugchōreō]” to describe what the many do: “From the outset, no force was used to establish any of the laws, written or unwritten, which are still in use and are suited for handing on: the people who would use them also assented to them [Οὐδὲν γὰρ ἐξ ἀρχῆς βιαίως κατέστη νόμιμον οὔτε μετὰ γραφῆς οὔτε ἄνευ γραφῆς τῶν διαμενόντων νῦν καὶ διαδίδοσθαι πεφυκότων, ἀλλὰ συγχωρησάντων αὐτῷ καὶ τῶν χρησαμένων].”Footnote 94
At this point, again, a comparison with Abderite theories of how the political communities come to be is interesting, even if these theories do not explicitly mention agreements as a means to move from the original state to a state of society.Footnote 95 Democritus very much stresses the idea of concord (homonoia) as an important principle of political unity in his philosophy, even if this term is not used in the account of cultural development.Footnote 96 Accordingly, one might understand the willingness of the people to come together and express their support for the new rulers that is described in Lucretius and Hermarchus as comparable to the concord that Democritus takes to be instrumental for the coming to be and functioning of the political communities.Footnote 97
It would be rash to conclude that the newly introduced laws are a hands-down triumph of justice for the Epicureans. During the phusis phase, human beings develop a notion of the aequum, but justice cannot triumph because it is not pervasive enough; there are many free-riders, which imperils the existence of human communities. During the logismos phase, the sanction mechanisms that accompany the law help establish the pervasiveness of justice. From now on, infringements against moral norms are prosecuted more effectively. This limits feuds and makes sure that there are clear ways of deescalating conflicts. But this positive aspect of the law is accompanied by the following downside according to Lucretius:
Ever since that time [when laws were introduced] fear of punishment has poisoned the blessings of life. Violence and hurtFootnote 98 enmesh all those who practice them: they generally recoil on the wrongdoers, and it is not easy for those who by their actions violate mutual pacts of peace to pass a placid and peaceful life; for even if their crime goes undetected in heaven and on earth, they are bound to fear that it will not remain hidden forever. And indeed many people, so it is said, by talking in their sleep or in the delirium of disease, have betrayed their own guilt and disclosed long hidden matters and their misdeeds.Footnote 99
In other words, a new kind of fear makes its appearance at this point of the process of societal development. It is true that the laws can first be said to offer advantages. For instance, those who abide by the law are surely better off than they would be in a society without laws, for it must be better for them to live in a society free from random violence. Likewise, those whose “blessings are poisoned by the laws” seem to be precisely those who do not abide by the law; those who abide, by contrast, can be thought to have nothing to fear. Yet laws introduce fear into the world, and if the goal of Epicurean philosophy is to remove fear overall, the laws, on the Epicurean view, cannot, as David Konstan rightly observes, be an unequivocally good thing, even if they yield certain advantages.Footnote 100 Most importantly, the introduction of the laws is linked with the coming to be of new irrational fears that were completely absent from the human life of the original condition. Recall here that the discussion of gods and religion immediately follows the discussion of the fear that results from punishments associated with the laws, and the fear connected with the laws is importantly linked with the fear of the gods.Footnote 101 Philodemus observes that there were different ways in which stories of the gods were introduced into the world.Footnote 102 One of these is that individuals tell stories about the gods to procure their own security. While this description is not explicitly linked to phases in human development and it is in fact unclear whether Philodemus is making a developmental claim at all, this description is reminiscent of the first kings in Lucretius who usurped power to be safe and of what the law-givers could have done in order to make sure that their laws are more widely obeyed.
In the same vein, Diogenes of Oenoanda discusses the connection between laws and divine punishments in what is today referred to as the “Theological Physics Sequence” of his inscription. He makes the related point that instilling the fear of the gods is not an effective means to prevent people from doing wrong. And this comment seems to be aimed at individuals who have attempted to do this or think that it is necessary:
φασὶ γάρ τινες μὴ συνφέρειν τῷ βίῳ τὸ δόγμα τοῦτο. τοὺς γὰρ ἀνθρώπους καὶ ἐπὶ τοῦ παρόντος μὲν ἀδικοπραγεῖν ἐφ᾽ ὅσον δή ποτε· ἂν μέντοι καὶ τῶν ἐκ θεῶν φόβων ἀπολυθῶσι, τελέως ἀδικοπραγήσειν, ἐγ δὲ τούτου συνχυθήσεσθαι τὸν ὅλον [βίον. tοιοῦτοι] μὲν καὶ ν[ῦν πε]φ[ύ]κασι[ν] οἱ μὴ [δ]ε[δ]οικότες τοὺς θεούς ([συ]νκεχωρημένον [εἴη τ]οῦτο· εἰ γὰρ ἐδεδοίκεσαν, οὐκ ἂν ἠδικουν)· [τ]ῶν δ᾽ ἄλλων ἀποφαίνομαι τοὺς μὲν φυσικῶν ἁπτομένου<ς> λόγων μὴ διὰ τοὺς θεοὺς εἶναι δικαίους, διὰ δὲ τὸ βλέπειν [ὀ]ρθῶς τάς τε ἐπιθυμίας τίν᾽ ἔχουσιν φύσιν κα[ὶ] τὰς ἀλγηδόνας καὶ τὸν θάνατον (πάντῃ τε γὰρ πάντως ἢ διὰ φόβον ἢ διὰ ἡδονὰς ἀδικοῦσιν ἄνθρωποι), τοὺς δ᾽ αὖ χυδαίους διὰ τοὺς νόμους εἶναι δικαίους, εφ᾽ ὅσον γέ εἰσιν δίκαιοι, καὶ τὰς ἀπὸ τούτων ἐπικρεμαμένας αὐτοῖς ζημίας. ἀλλὰ κἂν ὦσιν τινες ἐν αὐτοῖς διὰ τοὺς θεοὺς εὐγνώμονες, οὐ διὰ τοὺς νόμους, ὀλιγοι δὲ οὗτοι· καὶ δυ᾽ ἢ τρεῖς μόλις κατὰ μεγάλας πληθῶν ἀποτομὰς εὑρισκόμενοι, βεβαίως οὐδὲ οὗτοι διακαιοπραγοῦσιν.
For some say that this doctrine [that is, that the gods are not to be feared] does not benefit our life, for human beings even in the present situation act wrongly so far as they possibly can; that if, however, they are also released from their fears derived from the gods, they will act completely wrongly, and in consequence the whole [of life] will be confounded. However, [people of such behavior] are even now those who do not fear the gods ([let] this [be] agreed; for if they feared the gods, they would not do wrong). But, as for the others, I declare that those of them who grasp the arguments based on nature are not just on account of the gods, but on account of their having a correct view of the nature of desires and pains and death (for indeed invariably and without exception human beings do wrong either on account of fear or on account of pleasures), and that ordinary people on the other hand are just, insofar as they are just, on account of the laws and the penalties, imposed by the laws, hanging over them. But even if some of their number are conscientious on account of the gods, rather than on account of the laws, they are few; only just two or three individuals are to be found among great segments of multitudes, and not even these are steadfast in acting justly.Footnote 103
Accordingly, one may say that, on the Epicurean view, the fear of the gods, which is one of the worst fears that Epicureanism combats (as the Fourfold Remedy makes clear),Footnote 104 is at least in part connected to the introduction of the law, since the latter seems to have precipitated the necessity of the former. Again, then, this should make clear that the introduction of the law on the Epicurean view cannot be all positive.
In summary, we have seen that the laws, just like the agreements of justice, come to be by conventional means during a second phase of communal development. Likewise, the laws are a historical product on the Epicurean view. However, they are also established in light of what is beneficial to all, hinting at the natural side of Epicurean justice (that will be more fully explored in the next chapter).
1.5 Epicurean Social Contract Theory
This chapter showed that the Epicurean theory of the social contract clearly distinguishes between (1) an original state; (2) a phusis phase of development, during which human beings unite for the first time; and (3) a logismos phase, during which human beings create legal and political states. Accordingly, these three different stages of development correspond to different degrees of historical establishment and human knowledge of justice and the law, which according to the Epicureans do not exist by nature. While neither justice nor laws exist in the original state, the phusis phase features justice without laws. Finally, the logismos phase features both justice and laws.
The chapter also showed that for the Epicureans, human beings at the beginning of the account are not “by nature” social beings (as they are, for instance, for Aristotle or the Stoics), but rather self-sufficient beings who do not need to live with others. The transition from the original state of human beings to the life with others (during the phusis phase) is caused by a change in human nature and needs; a sedentary lifestyle, family ties, and technological achievements affect their nature gradually, but importantly, and this change is accompanied by new desires, for instance, of protecting both the agents themselves as well as their loved ones. Moral norms such as the just (aequum) first come into being at this stage of development, as a historical achievement, by means of an agreement, once the family as a more basic form of sociality has already emerged. As was emphasized above, while agreements do play a key role in the account, the agreement are made with an eye toward what is beneficial, which itself is not a conventional feature (as will be argued in more detail in the next chapter).
After the coming to be of justice, life in community is still fraught with difficulties, on the Epicurean view: preeminent men usurp political power in order to use it for their own ends, leading to a state of strife. As a response, laws are introduced as a check to those in power, but they are a mixed blessing: they introduce a new kind of fear into the world.
While more needs to be said about the natural feature of Epicurean justice to see how exactly the Epicureans argue for a middle position in the nomos-phusis debate, the Epicurean multistage developmental account of how justice and law come to be certainly invites comparisons to early modern conceptions of the social contract. Accordingly, the chapter will close with a few remarks on some commentators’ attempts to assimilate the Epicurean contractarianism to that of Thomas Hobbes, primarily on the strength of the idea that the original state in Epicurus is a violent or potentially violent state: a war of all against all.Footnote 105
On the basis of the close investigation of the textual evidence, one can easily show that such an assimilation to Hobbes’ theory of the social contract is unwarranted. First, Lucretius recognizes advantages and disadvantages of the original state, which is a wholly negative condition in Hobbes. In addition, the reference to Hobbes is misleading insofar as the latter does not discuss the creation of the society at all in his theory, but rather exclusively focuses on the creation of the state. Put differently, there is no separate discussion of a pactum unionis and a pactum subjectionis in Hobbes as there is in Epicurean authors, since the former does not at all discuss the emergence of the sociality prior to the social contract (as the Epicureans do). Furthermore, according to Hobbes, human nature is constant throughout his account: dominated by fear, man is a wolf to man. Yet this is not true according to the Epicureans: they stress that human beings undergo a change in human nature (prior to entering society) and only this change makes it necessary that societies come to be. Likewise, Epicurean agents are not motivated principally by fear. In fact, it is only the creation of the state and the connected emergence of religion that really instills human beings’ anxieties (especially in regard to the gods).
If one had to relate the Epicurean account of the social contract to a schema of an early modern account of the social contract, Jean-Jacques Rousseau’s version would be a much better fit than Hobbes’.Footnote 106 Rousseau endorses the key Epicurean idea that human beings undergo a change prior to entering society. And in addition to this, he not only assumes that the original state is an overall peaceful state of existence but he also distinguishes between the bad process of the formation of society (described in the Second Discourse) and the more positive and later project of creating a better society in On the Social Contract, which in some ways might be said to correspond to the Epicurean logismos phase that features the emergence of the rule of law.