Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-gbm5v Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-27T10:08:28.217Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Bibliography

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  03 November 2023

Steven Wall
Affiliation:
University of Arizona
Get access

Summary

Image of the first page of this content. For PDF version, please use the ‘Save PDF’ preceeding this image.'
Type
Chapter
Information
Enforcing Morality , pp. 224 - 230
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2023

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Alexander, L. 2005. Is There a Right to Freedom of Expression? (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Alexander, L. 2013. “Voluntary Enslavement,” in Paternalism: Theory and Practice, eds. Coon, C. and Weber, M. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), pp. 231246.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Arneson, R. 1982. “Fairness and Free Rider Problems,” Ethics 92/4: 616633.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Arneson, R. 1989. “Paternalism, Utility and Fairness,” Revue Internationale de Philosophe 43/170: 409437.Google Scholar
Arneson, R. 2000. “Luck Egalitarianism and Prioritarianism,” Ethics 110/2: 339349.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Arneson, R. 2005. “Joel Feinberg and the Justification of Hard Paternalism,” Legal Theory 11/3: 259284.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Arneson, R. 2007. “Cracked Foundations of Liberal Equality,” in Dworkin and His Critics, ed. Burley, J. (London: Blackwell), pp. 7998.Google Scholar
Arneson, R. 2018. “Egalitarian Perspectives on Paternalism,” in The Routledge Handbook of the Philosophy of Paternalism, eds. Grill, K. and Hanna, J. (New York: Routledge), pp. 194205.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Austin, J. 1832 [1995]. The Province of Jurisprudence Determined, ed. Rumble, W. E. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).Google Scholar
Beale, S. 2005. “The Many Faces of Overcriminalization: From Morals and Mattress Tags to Overfederalization,” American University Law Review 54/3: 747782.Google Scholar
Beauchamp, T. 1977. “Paternalism and Biobehavioral Control,” The Monist 60/1: 6280.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Berger, F. 1984. Freedom, Morality and Happiness (Berkeley: University of California Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bickel, A. 1975. The Morality of Consent (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press).Google Scholar
Billingham, P. and Parr, T. 2020. “Enforcing Social Norms: The Morality of Public Shaming,” European Journal of Philosophy 28/4: 9971016.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bork, R. 1990. The Tempting of America (New York: Simon & Schuster).Google Scholar
Brink, D. 2008. “Mill’s Liberal Principles and the Freedom of Expression,” in Mill’s On Liberty: A Critical Guide, ed. Ten, C. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).Google Scholar
Brink, D. 2013. Mill’s Progressive Principles (Oxford: Oxford University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Burgess-Jackson, K. 1985. “Bad Samaritanism and the Pedagogic Function of Law,” Criminal Justice Journal 8: 127.Google Scholar
Burke, E. 1774. “Speech to the Electors at Bristol,” The Works of The Right Honourable Edmund Burke in Twelve Volumes: Volume the Second (London: John C. Nimmo).Google Scholar
Christiano, T. 1996. The Rule of the Many (Boulder, CO: Westview).Google Scholar
Christiano, T. 2008. “Does Religious Toleration Make Any Sense?” in Contemporary Debates in Social Philosophy (London: Blackwell).Google Scholar
Cohen, G. A. 1995. Self-Ownership, Freedom and Equality (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cohen, G. A. 2006. “Casting the First Stone: Who Can and Who Can’t Condemn the Terrorists?Political Philosophy, ed. A. O’Hare. Royal Institute of Philosophy supplement 58.Google Scholar
Cohen, G. A. 2008. Rescuing Justice and Equality (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Cohen, G. A. 2011. “Rescuing Conservatism: A Defense of Existing Value,” in Reasons and Recognition: Essays on the Moral Philosophy of T. M. Scanlon, eds. Wallace, R. Jay, Kumar, R. and Freeman, S. (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Darwall, S. 2006. The Second-Person Standpoint (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press).Google Scholar
Devlin, P. 1959. “The Enforcement of Morals,” Proceedings of the British Academy 45: 125.Google Scholar
Devlin, P. 1965. The Enforcement of Morals (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Dworkin, G. 1982. “Is More Choice Better Than Less?Midwest Studies in Philosophy 7: 4761.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dworkin, G. 1988. The Theory and Practice of Autonomy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dworkin, G. 2012. “Harm and the Volenti Principle,” Social Philosophy and Policy 29/1: 309321.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dworkin, R. 1976. Taking Rights Seriously (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press).Google Scholar
Dworkin, R. 1986. Law’s Empire (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press).Google Scholar
Dworkin, R. 1996. Freedom’s Law (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press).Google Scholar
Dworkin, R. 2000. Sovereign Virtue (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press).Google Scholar
Dworkin, R. 2008. Is Democracy Possible Here? (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press).Google Scholar
Dworkin, R. 2009. “Foreword,” in Extreme Speech and Democracy, eds. Hare, I. and Weinstein, J. (Oxford: Oxford University Press), pp. vix.Google Scholar
Dworkin, R. 2011. Justice for Hedgehogs (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press).Google Scholar
Edmundson, W. 2004. An Introduction to Rights (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Enoch, D. 2002. “A Right to Violate One’s Duty,” Law and Philosophy 21: 355384.Google Scholar
Enoch, D. 2018. “Against Utopianism: Noncompliance and Multiple Agents,” The Philosopher’s Imprint 18/6: 120.Google Scholar
Estlund, D. 2020. Utopophobia (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Eyal, N. 2017. “How to Keep High Risk Studies Ethical: Classifying Candidate Solutions,” Journal of Medical Ethics 43/2: 7477.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Feinberg, J. 1965. “The Expressive Function of Punishment,” The Monist 49/3: 397423.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Feinberg, J. 1974. “Noncomparative Justice,” Philosophical Review 83/3: 297338.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Feinberg, J. 1984. Harm to Others (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Feinberg, J. 1986. Harm to Self (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Feinberg, J. 1988. Harmless Wrongdoing (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Finnis, J. 1985. “Human Rights and Their Enforcement,” reprinted in Human Rights and the Common Good (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011).Google Scholar
Finnis, J. 1996. “Limited Government,” reprinted in Human Rights and the Common Good (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011).Google Scholar
Finnis, J. 2003. “Describing Law Normatively,” reprinted in Philosophy of Law (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011).Google Scholar
Frankfurt, H. 2004. Reasons of Love (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press).Google Scholar
Frey, B. and Jegen, R. 2001. “Motivating Crowding Theory: A Survey of Empirical Evidence,” Journal of Economic Surveys 15: 589611.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fried, C. 1981. Contract As Promise (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press).Google Scholar
Fried, C. 2007. Modern Liberty (New York: Norton).Google Scholar
Fuller, L. 1964. The Morality of Law (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press).Google Scholar
Galston, W. 1993. “On the Alleged Right to Do Moral Wrong,” Ethics 93/2: 320324.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gardner, J. and Shute, S. 2007. “The Wrongness of Rape,” in Offences and Defences (Oxford: Oxford University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gardner, J. and Tanguay-Renaud, F. 2011. “Desert and Avoidability in Self-Defense,” Ethics 122/1: 111134.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gaus, G. 2011. The Order of Public Reason (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).Google Scholar
George, R. 1993. Making Men Moral (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Gettier, E. 1963. “Is Justified True Belief Knowledge?Analysis 23/6: 121123.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gibbard, A. 1990. Wise Choices, Apt Feelings (Oxford: Oxford University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldman, A. 1996. Social Epistemology (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Goldman, A. and O’Connor, C. 2021. “Social Epistemology,” The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (winter edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2021/entries/epistemology-social.Google Scholar
Gray, J. 1983. Mill on Liberty: A Defence (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul).Google Scholar
Green, L. 2013. “Should the Law Improve Morality?Criminal Law and Philosophy 7/3: 473494.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Green, S. P. 1997. “Why It’s a Crime to Tear the Tag Off a Mattress: Overcriminalization and the Moral Content of Regulatory Offenses,” Emory Law Journal 46/4: 15531616.Google Scholar
Greenawalt, K. 1992. Speech, Crime and the Uses of Language (Oxford: Oxford University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Greenawalt, K. 1995. Fighting Words (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press).Google Scholar
Habermas, J. 1989. The Structural Transformation of the Public Sphere (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press).Google Scholar
Haidt, J. 2001. “The Emotional Dog and Its Rational Tail: A Social Intuitionist Approach to Moral Judgment,” Psychological Review 108/4: 814834.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hart, C. L. 2021. Drug Use for Grown Ups: Chasing Liberty in the Land of Fear (New York: Penguin Press).Google Scholar
Hart, H. L. A. 1955. “Are There Any Natural Rights?The Philosophical Review 64/2: 175191.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hart, H. L. A. 1959. “Immorality and Treason,” The Listener, July 30.Google Scholar
Hart, H. L. A. 1961 [1994]. The Concept of Law, ed. Green, L., 3rd ed. (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Hart, H. L. A. 1963. Law, Liberty and Morality (Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hart, H. L. A. 1982. “Commands and Authoritative Reasons,” in Essays on Bentham (Oxford: Oxford University Press), pp. 243268.Google Scholar
Hernstein, O. J. 2014. “A Legal Right to Do Legal Wrong,” Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 34/1: 2145.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hohfeld, W. 2001. Fundamental Legal Conceptions As Applied in Judicial Reasoning (New York: Ashgate).Google Scholar
Honore, A. 1961. “Ownership,” in Oxford Essays in Jurisprudence, ed. Guest, A. G. (Oxford: Oxford University Press), pp. 107147.Google Scholar
Hooker, B. 2000. Ideal Code, Real World (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Humboldt, W. von. 1969. The Limits of State Action, trans. J. W. Burrow (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hurd, H. 2009. “Paternalism on Pain of Punishment,” Criminal Justice Ethics 28/1: 4973.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hurka, T. 1987. “Why Value Autonomy?Social Theory and Practice 13/3: 361382.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hurka, T. 1995. “Indirect Perfectionism: Kymlicka on Liberal Neutrality,” Journal of Political Philosophy 3/1: 3657.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Husak, D. 1983. “The Presumption of Freedom,” Nous 17/3: 345362.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Husak, D. 2008. Overcriminalization (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Husak, D. 2013. “Penal Paternalism,” in Paternalism: Theory and Practice, eds. Coon, C. and Weber, M. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), pp. 3955.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jacobson, D. 2005. “Mill on Liberty, Speech and the Free Society,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 29/3: 276309.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kagan, S. 1991. The Limits of Morality (Oxford: Oxford University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kagan, S. 2009. “Well-Being As Enjoying the Good,” Philosophical Perspectives 23: 253272.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kagan, S. 2011. “Do I Make a Difference?Philosophy and Public Affairs 39/2: 105141.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kagan, S. 2019. How to Count Animals (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Kahneman, D. 2011. Thinking, Fast and Slow (New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux).Google Scholar
Kant, I. 1775–80 [1997]. Lectures on Ethics, eds. Heath, P. and Schneewind, J. B. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).Google Scholar
Kramer, M. 2003. The Quality of Freedom (Oxford: Oxford University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kramer, M. 2021. Freedom of Expression As Self-Restraint (Oxford: Oxford University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kristol, I. 1971. “Pornography, Obscenity, and the Case for Censorship,” The New York Times Magazine, March 28.Google Scholar
Kronman, A. 1983. “Paternalism and the Law of Contracts,” Yale Law Journal 92/5: 763798.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kymlicka, W. 1989. Liberalism, Community and Culture (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Labaton, S. 1989. “New Tactics in the War on Drugs Tilt Scales of Justice Off Balance,” The New York Times, December 29, p. A1.Google Scholar
Langton, R. 2009. Sexual Solipsism (Oxford: Oxford University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Larmore, C. 1986. Patterns of Moral Complexity (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).Google Scholar
Locke, J. 1685 [1983]. A Letter Concerning Toleration (Indianapolis, IN: Hackett).Google Scholar
Lyons, D. 1979. “Liberty and Harm to Others,” Canadian Journal of Philosophy supp. vol. V: 119.Google Scholar
Mackinnon, C. 1996. Only Words (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Marcuse, H. 1965. “Repressive Tolerance,” in A Critique of Pure Tolerance (Boston, MA: Beacon Press), pp. 81123.Google Scholar
Marneffe, Peter de. 2010. Liberalism and Prostitution (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Marneffe, Peter 2013. “Self-Sovereignty and Paternalism,” in Paternalism: Theory and Practice, eds. Coon, C. and Weber, M (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), pp. 5673.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Meiklejohn, A. 1960. Political Freedom: The Constitutional Powers of the People (New York: Harper and Brothers).Google Scholar
Mill, J. S. 1840 [1987]. “Essay on Coleridge,” reprinted in John Stuart Mill and Jeremy Bentham: Utilitarianism and Other Essays, ed. Ryan, A. (New York: Penguin), pp. 177227.Google Scholar
Mill, J. S. 1859 [1977]. On Liberty, in The Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, vol. XVIII, ed. Robson, J. (Toronto: University of Toronto Press), pp. 213310.Google Scholar
Mill, J. S. 1859 [1978]. On Liberty, ed. Rapaport, E. (Indianapolis, IN: Hackett).Google Scholar
Mill, J. S. 1861 [1969]. Utilitarianism, in The Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, vol. X, ed. Robson, J. (Toronto: University of Toronto Press), pp. 203260.Google Scholar
Mill, J. S. 1861 [1977]. Considerations on Representative Government, in The Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, vol. XIX, ed. Robson, J. (Toronto: University of Toronto Press), pp. 371578.Google Scholar
Milton, J. 1644. Areopagitica (Will Jonson).Google Scholar
Moore, G. E. 1903. Principia Ethica (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).Google Scholar
Moore, M. 1997. Placing Blame (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Murphy, M. 2006. Natural Law in Jurisprudence and Politics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Murray, C. and Hernstein, R. 1994. The Bell Curve (New York: The Free Press).Google Scholar
Nagel, T. 1991. Equality and Partiality (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Nathanson, S. 1985. “Does It Matter if the Death Penalty Is Arbitrarily Applied?Philosophy and Public Affairs 14/2: 149164.Google Scholar
Nozick, R. 1974. Anarchy, State and Utopia (New York: Basic Books).Google Scholar
Nozick, R. 1981. Philosophical Explanations (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press).Google Scholar
Nozick, R. 1993. The Nature of Rationality (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Parfit, D. 1984. Reasons and Persons (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Patton, A. 2014. Equal Recognition (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press).Google Scholar
Pereboom, D. 2001. Living without Free Will (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Perry, S. 1997. “Risk, Harm and Responsibility,” in Philosophical Foundations of Tort Law, ed. Owen, D. (Oxford: Oxford University Press), pp. 321346.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pettit, P. 2001. A Theory of Freedom (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Pitkin, H. 1967. The Concept of Representation (Berkeley: University of California Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Postema, G. 1994. “Public Faces and Private Places: Liberalism and the Enforcement of Morality,” in Harm and the Law, ed. Dworkin, G. (Boulder, CO: Westview Press), pp. 7690.Google Scholar
Proast, J. 1999. “The Argument of the Letter Concerning Toleration, Briefly Consider’d and Answer’d,” in The Reception of Locke’s Politics, vol. V, ed. Goldie, M. (London: Pickering and Chatto), pp. 41116.Google Scholar
Radzik, L. 2020. The Ethics of Social Punishment (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rashdall, H. 1907. The Theory of Good and Evil, vol. I (London: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Rawls, J. 1971. A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rawls, J. 1993. Political Liberalism (New York: Columbia University Press).Google Scholar
Raz, J. 1975. Practical Reason and Norms (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Raz, J. 1979. “The Rule of Law and Its Virtue,” in The Authority of Law (Oxford: Oxford University Press), pp. 210229.Google Scholar
Raz, J. 1982. “Right-Based Moralities,” in Theories of Rights, ed. Waldron, J. (Oxford: Oxford University Press), pp. 182200.Google Scholar
Raz, J. 1986. The Morality of Freedom (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Raz, J. 1988. “Liberalism, Skepticism and Democracy,” Iowa Law Review 74: 761786.Google Scholar
Raz, J. 1990. “Facing Diversity: The Case of Epistemic Abstinence,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 19/1: 346.Google Scholar
Raz, J. 1994. “Free Expression and Personal Identification,” in Ethics and the Public Domain (Oxford: Oxford University Press), pp. 146169.Google Scholar
Raz, J. 2009. “The Problem of Authority: Revisiting the Service Conception,” in Between Authority and Interpretation (Oxford: Oxford University Press), pp. 126165.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ripstein, A. 2006. “Beyond the Harm Principle,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 34/3: 215245.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ripstein, A. 2009. Force and Freedom (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ronson, J. 2015. So You’ve Been Publicly Shamed (London: Picador).Google Scholar
Ryan, A. 2012. “Mill’s Essay on Liberty,” in The Making of Modern Liberalism (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press), pp. 257278.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Scalia, A. 1997. A Matter of Interpretation (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press).Google Scholar
Scanlon, T. M. 1998. What We Owe to Each Other (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press).Google Scholar
Scanlon, T. M. 2003. “A Theory of Freedom of Expression,” in The Difficulty of Tolerance (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), pp. 625.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Scanlon, T. M. 2003. “Content Regulation Reconsidered,” in The Difficulty of Tolerance (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), pp. 151168.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Scanlon, T. M. 2003. “Freedom of Expression and Categories of Expression,” in The Difficulty of Tolerance (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), pp. 84112.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schauer, F. 1993. “The Phenomenology of Speech and Harm,” Ethics 103/4: 635653.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schauer, F. 2015. “Free Speech on Tuesdays,” Law and Philosophy 34: 119140.Google Scholar
Schauer, F. 2015. The Force of Law (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press).Google Scholar
Scheffler, S. 1982. The Rejection of Consequentialism (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Scheffler, S. 1992. Human Morality (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Scheffler, S. 2011. “Valuing,” in Reasons and Recognition: Essays on the Moral Philosophy of T. M. Scanlon, eds. Wallace, R. J. et al. (Oxford: Oxford University Press), pp. 2342.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shafer-Landeau, R. 1996. “The Failure of Retributivism,” Philosophical Studies 82: 289316.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sher, G. 2021. A Wild West of the Mind (Oxford: Oxford University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shiffrin, S. 2000. “Paternalism, Unconscionability Doctrine, and Accommodation,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 29/3: 205250.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shiner, R. 2009. “Crime and Criminal Law Reform: A Theory of the Legislative Response,” Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 12/1: 6384.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Simmons, A. J. 1979. “The Principle of Fair Play,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 8/4: 307337.Google Scholar
Simmons, A. J. 1996. “Philosophical Anarchism,” in For and Against the State, eds. Sanders, J. T. and Narveson, J. (Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield), pp. 1939.Google Scholar
Skorupski, J. 2006. Why Read Mill Today? (London: Routledge).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smith, M. 2004. “Internal Reasons,” in Ethics and the A Priori (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), pp. 1742.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stephen, J. Fitzjames. 1873. Liberty, Equality and Fraternity (New York: Holt & Williams).Google Scholar
Stone, G. 1983. “Content-Regulation and the First Amendment,” William and Mary Law Review 25/2: 189252.Google Scholar
Straus, D. 1991. “Persuasion, Autonomy and Freedom of Expression,” Columbia Law Review 91/2: 334371.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Strawson, P. F. 1961. “Social Morality and Individual Ideal,” Philosophy 36/136: 117.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Strossen, N. 1990. “Regulating Racist Speech on Campus: A Modest Proposal,” Duke Law Journal 39: 484573.Google Scholar
Strossen, N. 2018. Hate Speech (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Sunstein, C. 1994. “A New Deal for Speech,” Hastings Communications and Entertainment Law Journal 17: 137160.Google Scholar
Tadros, V. 2016. Wrongs and Crimes (Oxford: Oxford University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Temkin, L. 1995. “Justice and Equality: Some Questions about Scope,” Social Philosophy and Policy 12/2: 72104.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Temkin, L. 2000. “Equality, Priority, and the Leveling Down Objection,” in The Ideal of Equality, eds. Clayton, M. and Williams, A. (London: Macmillan), pp. 126161.Google Scholar
Titmus, R. 1970. The Gift Relationship (London: George Allen and Unwin, Ltd.).Google Scholar
Tocqueville, Alexis de. 1805–59 [1838]. Democracy in America (New York: G. Dearborn & Co.).Google Scholar
Valdman, M. 2010. “Outsourcing Self-Government,” Ethics 120/4: 761790.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
van den Haag, E. 1986. “The Ultimate Punishment: A Defence,” Harvard Law Review 99/7: 16621669.Google Scholar
Volokh, E. 1995. “Cheap Speech and What It Will Do,” Yale Law Journal 104: 18041850.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Waldron, J. 1981. “A Right to Do Wrong,” Ethics 92/1: 2139.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Waldron, J. 1987. “Mill and the Value of Moral Distress,” Political Studies 35/3: 410423.Google Scholar
Waldron, J. 1999. Law and Disagreement (Oxford: Oxford University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Waldron, J. 2014. The Harm in Hate Speech (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press).Google Scholar
Wall, S. 1998. Liberalism, Perfectionism and Restraint (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wall, S. 2009. “Self-Ownership and Paternalism,” Journal of Political Philosophy 17/4: 399417.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wall, S. 2010. “On Justificatory Liberalism,” Politics, Philosophy and Economics 9/2: 123150.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wall, S. 2015. “Introduction,” in The Cambridge Companion to Liberalism, ed. Wall, S. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), pp. 118.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wall, S. 2016. “Autonomy As a Perfection,” American Journal of Jurisprudence 16/2: 175194.Google Scholar
Wall, S. 2016. “Political Morality and the Authority of Tradition,” Journal of Political Philosophy 24/2: 137161.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wall, S. 2018. “Subjective Perfectionism,” American Journal of Jurisprudence 63/1: 109131.Google Scholar
Wall, S. 2019. “Rooted Reciprocity,” Journal of Moral Philosophy 16/4: 123.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wall, S. and Klosko, G. 2003. Perfectionism and Neutrality: Essays in Liberal Theory (Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield).Google Scholar
Wall, S. and Sobel, D. 2021. “A Robust Hybrid Account of Well-Being,” Philosophical Studies 178: 28292851.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wallace-Wells, B. 2021. “Is There a Case for Legalizing Heroin?” The New Yorker, August 29.Google Scholar
Walzer, M. 1983. Spheres of Justice (New York: Basic Books).Google Scholar
Watson, G. 2004. “Two Faces of Responsibility,” in Agency and Answerability (Oxford: Oxford University Press), pp. 260288.Google Scholar
Williams, B. 1981. “Internal and External Reasons,” reprinted in Moral Luck (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), pp. 101113.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wu, T. 2018. “Is the First Amendment Obsolete?Michigan Law Review 117/3: 547581.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Bibliography
  • Steven Wall, University of Arizona
  • Book: Enforcing Morality
  • Online publication: 03 November 2023
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009363808.011
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • Bibliography
  • Steven Wall, University of Arizona
  • Book: Enforcing Morality
  • Online publication: 03 November 2023
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009363808.011
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • Bibliography
  • Steven Wall, University of Arizona
  • Book: Enforcing Morality
  • Online publication: 03 November 2023
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009363808.011
Available formats
×