Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-gvvz8 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-19T12:53:50.580Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

VII - Nonintentionalist Interpretation

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 June 2012

Larry Alexander
Affiliation:
University of San Diego School of Law
Emily Sherwin
Affiliation:
Cornell University Law School, New York
Get access

Summary

We have argued to this point that the interpretation of canonical legal texts, whether those texts are authored by individual lawmakers or by multimember ones, is at bottom no different from interpreting demands or requests in other domains of life. Requests from Mom or the kids, memos from the boss, and indeed all communications that we take to be normative boil down to what the language in its context reveals about what the speaker intended for us to do. In other words, our question is always, What meaning did the speaker or speakers intend? And, we argued, given the role of legal authorities to settle what ought to be done and to do so with expertise and, in the case of legislatures, democratic warrant, the interpretation of legal rules should also be viewed as the search for the speaker's intended meaning.

If legal reasoning in the domain of interpreting canonical legal texts is to be “special” – a craft that only legal training and practice can provide – then the intentionalist position we endorse must be rejected. We are all “trained” to practice that, as all of us engage in it all the time. And, indeed, there are challengers to intentionalism in the legal literature. In this chapter we take up the two principal challengers: textualism and dynamic interpretation.

Textualism

Textualism is actually a family of theories of legal interpretation.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2008

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Marmor, Andrei, Interpretation and Legal Theory 132–39 (2d ed., Oxford: Hart Pub. 2005).Google Scholar
Scalia, Antonin, A Matter of Interpretation: Federal Courts and the Law (Princeton: Princeton University Press 1997).Google Scholar
Manning, John F., Textualism and the Equity of the Statute, 101 Colum. L. Rev. 1, 16–17 n. 65 (2001)Google Scholar
Greene, Abner S., The Missing Step of Textualism, 74 Fordham L.J. 1913, 1926–29 (2006)Google Scholar
Sinnott-Armstrong, Walter, Word Meaning in Legal Interpretation, 42 San Diego L. Rev. 465, 471–77 (2005)Google Scholar
Alexander, Larry, All or Nothing at All? The Intentions of Authorities and the Authority of Intentions, in Law and Interpretation: Essays in Legal Philosophy 336 (Marmor, Andrei, ed., Oxford: Clarendon Press 1995).Google Scholar
Alexander, Larry and Prakash, Saikrishna, “Is That English You're Speaking?” Why Intention Free Interpretation Is an Impossibility, 41 San Diego L. Rev. 967 (2004).Google Scholar
Arrow, Kenneth J., Social Choice and Individual Values, 2–8 (2d ed., New Haven: Yale University Press 1963)Google Scholar
Dworkin, Ronald, Law's Empire 348 (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press 1986).Google Scholar
Raz, Joseph, Dworkin: A New Link in the Chain, 74 Cal. L. Rev. 1103, 1103 (1986)Google Scholar
Posner, Richard, The Problems of Jurisprudence 130–32, 299–300 (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press 1990).Google Scholar
Eskridge, William, Gadamer/Statutory Interpretation, 90 Colum. L. Rev. 609, 633, 647–51 (1990)Google Scholar
Eskridge, William, Dynamic Statutory Interpretation, 135 U. Pa. L. Rev. 1479, 1483–84 (1987).Google Scholar
Eskridge, William and Frickey, Philip, Statutory Interpretation as Practical Reasoning, 42 Stan. L. Rev. 321, 351–52 (1990)Google Scholar
Frickey, Philip, Congressional Intent, Practical Reasoning, and the Dynamic Nature of Federal Indian Law, 78 Cal. L. Rev. 1137, 1140, 1208–9 (1990)Google Scholar
Farber, Daniel and Frickey, PhilipLegislative Intent and Public Choice, 74 Va. L. Rev. 423, 456 (1988)Google Scholar
Sunstein, Cass R., Interpreting Statutes in the Regulatory State, 103 Harv. L. Rev. 405, 497–98 (1989)Google Scholar
Moore, Michael S., A Natural Law Theory of Interpretation, 58 S. Cal. L. Rev. 277, 396–97 (1985).Google Scholar
Solum, Lawrence B., Pluralism and Public Legal Reason, 15 William & Mary Bill of Rts. J. 7, 15 (2006).Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×