Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-p9bg8 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-28T14:16:05.649Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Part I - Theoretical Approaches to CIL and Its Interpretation

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  22 November 2024

Marina Fortuna
Affiliation:
Rijksuniversiteit Groningen, The Netherlands
Kostia Gorobets
Affiliation:
Rijksuniversiteit Groningen, The Netherlands
Panos Merkouris
Affiliation:
Rijksuniversiteit Groningen, The Netherlands
Andreas Føllesdal
Affiliation:
Universitetet i Oslo
Geir Ulfstein
Affiliation:
Universitetet i Oslo
Pauline Westerman
Affiliation:
Rijksuniversiteit Groningen, The Netherlands
Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2024
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BYCreative Common License - NCCreative Common License - ND
This content is Open Access and distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence CC-BY-NC-ND 4.0 https://creativecommons.org/cclicenses/

1 The Illusion of Gold-Digging: Interpretation of State Practice

Pauline Westerman
1 Introduction

Customary international law (CIL) is particularly vulnerable to the accusation that it is no more than ‘mere assertion’, a creation of the courts, if not downright fantasy.Footnote 1 Yet it is in CIL that one finds the strongest claim to objectivity in international law. It is expressed in the doctrine that one of the elements of CIL is state practice, which represents the ‘objective’ element of CIL. It is thought to supplement the ‘subjective’ or ‘psychological’ element of CIL: opinio juris.Footnote 2 Elsewhere, I have analysed opinio juris and concluded that it is much less ‘subjective’ than is commonly assumed.Footnote 3 Here, I will argue that state practice is much less ‘objective’ than is commonly assumed.

I will argue that the notion of state practice as a set of ‘material facts’ that should be ‘identified’ and from which customary norms can be ‘induced’ is grounded in obsolete epistemology. The identification of state practice is more adequately described as a selection of what deserves to be counted as state practice. I will argue that the starting point for this selective process is opinio juris. Opinio juris does not come after the fact, as a subjective feeling of obligation that is superadded to a set of otherwise objective facts. Opinio juris is the indispensable conceptual framework without which habits and usages cannot even be ‘seen’ as state practice.

2 Gold-Digging

It is unclear what the adjectives ‘objective’ and ‘subjective’ refer to. To the elements themselves or to the ways in which these elements are studied? The latter option is not very plausible, for why may the convictions of states (opinio juris) not be dealt with in an objective manner? Any sociologist can tell you that it is possible to examine convictions and beliefs. And even if that would not be the case, why would one officially announce that half of the process of CIL identification is carried out in a ‘subjective’ manner?

No, apparently these adjectives refer to the elements themselves and not to the investigator. But then the question arises, why is state practice labelled an ‘objective element’? In what sense can we say that acts, words, conventions and usages are objective elements? Can we speak at all about ‘objective elements’? Are molecules and stars objective elements? And again, what is so subjective in opinio juris if we understand that notion as the conviction that a certain norm is a legal one? The more one thinks about it, the stranger it is.

The only way to make sense of the use of these terms is to take into account another dichotomous pair of words by means of which the two elements are distinguished: the ‘normative’ and the ‘factual’. Apparently, the claim is that whereas opinio juris is the ‘normative’ element, state practice consists of ‘facts’. There are three interrelated assumptions at stake here.

  1. (1) The nature of the object that is investigated: facts.

    • Most authors understand practice as a heap of ‘material facts’. State practice is called ‘a sort of … raw material for custom’,Footnote 4 an ‘inert mass of accumulated usage’Footnote 5 or – in a modern version – a set of ‘raw data’.Footnote 6

  2. (2) The method to be followed: induction.

    • The account of state practice as a heap of social facts gives rise to the idea that the analysis of state practice can be conducted as any inquiry into ‘facts’. They can be collected as ‘data’, which should be ‘described’ and which forms the starting point of an inductive process of reasoning that moves from the described facts upwards to general statements about the rules that are followed.

  3. (3) The aim of the investigation: identification.

    • The assumption is that state practice should be investigated in such a way that possible candidates for CIL can be ‘identified’. The term ‘identification’ suggests that CIL is thus found rather than constructed.

The combination of these three related claims can be captured by the metaphor of gold-digging: the gold of CIL can be found by digging the inert material mass of sand and clay, and by bringing it upwards to the surface, after which it can be identified by sieving the sand.

Several authors have criticised this picture by criticising assumption (2). They think that an inductive description of the facts is only half of the work to be done. Roberts,Footnote 7 for instance, thinks that the ‘descriptive accuracy’ of an investigation of state practice should be complemented by a deductive method of searching for ‘substantive normativity’, starting with normative ideals and then descending to the formulation of rules. In a similar vein, TalmonFootnote 8 believes that we should make more room for deduction, especially where state practice is inconclusive, non-existent, contradictory or inconsistent with opinio juris. Finally, MerkourisFootnote 9 wants to complement the inductive method of rule identification with a deductive method of rule interpretation.

Although these authors have different objectives in mind, they are united in their view that describing practices is not enough to account for CIL, and that inductivism should be complemented by deductivism. They rightly point out that the problem of a merely inductivist investigation of state practice is both unrealistic and impossible, but they seek the solution of that problem by adding a normative or deductive approach. And through this search for an additional approach they leave intact the doctrinal picture of an initial investigation of state practice as a purely descriptive and inductive enterprise. Inductive ‘identification’ and deductive ‘interpretation’ are then seen as separate activities. Assumption (1) (practice as a collection of facts) as well as assumption (3) (identification of rules as the main aim of any investigation of state practice) remain untouched.

I will argue, however, that not only the assumption of induction (2), but the entire picture of gold-digging, is largely illusionary. I will start by addressing the assumption of induction (2) and take advantage of well-known insights that were developed in the philosophy of science. Consequently, I will criticise assumption (3), according to which identification is prior to interpretation. By using the insights of hermeneutics, I will argue that opinio juris is the starting point for any investigation of state practice and helps to define both state practice and CIL as a whole.

3 Loaded Perceptions: The Problem of InductivismFootnote 10

Let us put ourselves in the position of an international courtFootnote 11 which is confronted with the task of deciding a case or of delivering an advisory opinion by distilling or identifying rules from a raw heap of facts. Such a court has to carry out two types of translation. In the first place, it should proceed from particular instances to general statements that deal with categories; in the second place, it has to proceed from facts to norms. The activity of such a court can be understood as similar to the interpretative activities of a domestic court which is asked to apply a given statutory rule to a concrete fact situation. Both courts are confronted with the task of translation; but they walk in opposite directions. Whereas an international court moves from particular fact situations to general norms, the domestic court moves in the opposite direction by applying general norms to concrete fact situations.

The latter process of interpretation is beset by difficulties that are abundantly analysed in the literature on judicial interpretation and decision-making. But in one aspect these tasks are easier to accomplish than the inductive translation from particular facts into general norms, and that is that in interpretation one knows where to start. It is with a set of possible rules – general and normative statements – in mind that the facts are investigated. Did the defendant buy his knife before or not? Was the will drawn up in the presence of a notary or not? Rules guide the investigation and select the facts or the sets of facts that are relevant in the light of the rule. The rule highlights that part of factual reality which is possibly relevant. This is not to say that those parts that are not highlighted remain in obscurity forever. The outcome of interpretation may be downright undesirable and may provide reason to re-open the investigation and to search for other rules which may highlight other aspects which become relevant and which may generate a different outcome. This is what Llewellyn means when he talks about the necessary creativity of judges to erect alternative ladders through the legal material in order to arrive at the desired outcome. But alternative ladders also start with a rule that guides the investigation.Footnote 12

Such starting points are absent if we consistently think of an inductive investigation of state practice. Then, it is supposed, we start with the facts and nothing but the facts. But which facts? There are a multitude of facts, events, gestures, movements, usages, conventions, declarations and resolutions, and we do not know how to make sense of such facts without any preconception in mind about what we hope or expect to find.Footnote 13

This is obvious in even the most basic form of perception. As Hanson eloquently pointed out as early as 1958,Footnote 14 seeing involves recognising patterns. We can of course see black and white pixels and we can be sure everybody sees the same pixels. But as the well-known picture of rabbits and ducks illustrates, we can see these pixels in different ways, ordered in different patterns. And these ordering patterns are to a large extent informed by what we expect to see in a particular context as well as by our background knowledge. If I stare into the microscope, I might see beautiful colours but I do not really know what I see and I therefore see nothing at all. There is no simple observation, therefore, of ‘what is there’. Our perception is loaded with preconceptions, conceptions, expectations and patterns that all lurk in the background. They should not be shunned and avoided, for if we were to succeed in discarding them, we would no longer know what we see. Or, as Heidegger succinctly put it: ‘Only those who understand can hear.’Footnote 15

If it is already difficult to make sense of dots and lines without any context that guides expectation and makes meaningful observation possible, how would we be able to understand things as elusive as ‘acts’, ‘usages’ and ‘conventions’? I am not referring here to Hart’s emphasis on an internal point of view. My claim is that even researchers who take an external point of view and regard people’s doings like the movements of ants just have to start from some theory in order even to study such ants. As any sociologist or anthropologist knows, without a basic theoretical framework it would be impossible to select what kinds of phenomena are worth observing. If we add to this that international lawyers are supposed to investigate not only ‘practice’ (a complex phenomenon in itself) but ‘state’ practice, which is a legal notion, it is clear that the facts which are observed cannot possibly be considered as ‘raw data’ or ‘raw material’.

4 Law as Theory and Object

Fortunately, that is not what legal scholars or courts do. Just like natural and social scientists, they start with a theoretical hypothesis that provides for the patterns that order the sense data in a meaningful way. Physics conceptualises light as either ‘wave’ or ‘particle’ and hence we ‘see’ light as waves or particles. Psychological concepts such as ‘hysteria’ and ‘burn-out’ are not merely different terms for the same phenomena but constitute different phenomena because they order facts in a different way.

So, too, courts and legal scholars start from a background theory. But there are three important differences between the background theories of social scientists and those of legal experts.

  1. (1) Law as theoretical framework

    As I have argued elsewhere,Footnote 16 legal research also starts from a theoretical framework, but, unlike social scientists who develop a theoretical framework that is independent from the object they investigate, the framework for legal research is the law itself. Legal notions and conceptions form the framework and pattern by means of which facts are ordered. Not only terms such as ‘seabed’ but also ‘sovereignty’ or ‘specially affected’ are notions that guide the investigation and furnish the patterns that enable us to see a point in the ‘raw data’. Whereas in the social sciences there is a certain distance between theory and object, the peculiar feature of legal scholarship is that its theoretical framework and its object are identical. Of course, this does not apply to empirical legal studies or, for that matter, to philosophy of law, where the theoretical framework may (and should) be broader, but most doctrinal legal research revolves around the question of how certain novel social or technical developments or problems can be regulated such that they can be fitted into the legal system or in a way that is coherent with underlying principles, or, alternatively, how different legal arrangements from different legal orders can be integrated and harmonised. In all these studies, law is not only the object of research but also provides the theoretical framework consisting of legal concepts, standards and exemplars.

  2. (2) Definitional concepts

    The fact that the function of a theory is taken over by the law itself and that therefore the facts are examined by means of legal concepts entails another peculiarity, which has to do with the nature of legal concepts. Legal concepts are not descriptive but definitional. In law, such definitions are usually couched in terms of conditions, although one also encounters enumerative definitions.Footnote 17 When we say that some paper p is a ‘contract’, we say that this paper p meets the conditions that should be fulfilled in order to count as a contract. Legal general statements are of the form: For all X, if conditions a, b and c apply, they count as Y.

    This statement does not generate new knowledge but is a definition of Y.

    If we start investigating state practices by means of such definitional concepts and apply the filter of the law to the facts, we examine that factual reality by enquiring into whether reality can be categorised into these definitions. We differentiate between items that do and items that do not, or only partially, fulfil the conditions that are contained in the general statement.

    This strategy is applied at all levels. At the micro-level, we start for instance by investigating whether a certain contract x meets the conditions for ‘contract’ and can be considered a valid one; at the meso-level, we might ask whether conditions for ‘sovereignty’ are met; and at the most abstract level, we inquire into the degree to which a certain usage counts as ‘practice’. Definitional concepts are very useful in a deductive process in which particular instances are examined for their conformity to the conditions and thus ‘put to the test’, but they are emphatically not the result of generalisations from particular facts. They are the result of our decision or of convention that defines a concept in terms of conditions. Their existence cannot be tested by reference to empirical facts but by referring to these conditions. That is why Kelsen could say that ‘the existence of a legal norm is its validity’.Footnote 18 Contracts, sovereign states and practices exist insofar as they meet the conditions.

  3. (3) No falsification by facts

    This difference between descriptive and definitional concepts implies a third difference as well. Whereas scientific general statements can be refuted or falsified by recalcitrant facts, that is not the case in legal research. Scientific theory does not merely contain general statements such as ‘if light has a wavelength of 400 nm we call it “violet”’. If that were the case, science would be just like legal scholarship and would proceed by definitional concepts based on convention. But although science makes use of conventions, and although observations on colours cannot be conducted without such conventions on numerical values, its general statements express new – hypothesised – correlations: hypotheses like ‘violet flowers attract more butterflies than red ones’, which can be falsified when a species of butterflies is discovered preferring red flowers. In legal research, it is not the theory that is falsified but the facts that are proven to be deficient. If we encounter papers that fulfil only half of the conditions for contracts, we do not think that our general statement is falsified; we just say that those papers are not ‘proper’ or valid contracts.

Is there then no sense in the idea that rules can be inferred by means of induction? Could we not say, ‘Here is a contract which is signed and there is a contract which is not signed, so maybe signature is not a decisive condition’?

That can happen indeed. In international law (IL), the conditions for validity are often not clearly defined, are ambiguous or contested, and indeed it is possible to adjust our set of conditions somewhat to match reality, but that can be done only in the presence of other features that qualify a certain item as a suitable candidate for being examined as a potential ‘contract’. If none of the conventional conditions are fulfilled, we do not even start investigating whether a paper counts as a contract or whether we should adjust our notion of contract in light of such divergent practices. We may for instance investigate the practices around marriage and see how in different cultures marriages are conducted and eventually end up with a wider concept of marriage than we initially had in mind. But such practices at least should have a credible claim to be considered as ‘marriages’. If they do not even remotely look like marriages, we would not take the trouble to contemplate them as serious candidates for being considered as marriage.

This also applies to concepts such as ‘sexual slavery’. They do not have a claim to validity, of course, but it should be possible to claim or suggest that the term might be appropriate to the case at hand. Further investigation may lead to limitation or expansion of the concept (and may even be extended to such an extent that it borders on ‘marriage’), but again there should be some shared features in order to conduct such an investigation in the first place.

To say that rules cannot be inferred from facts is not the same as saying that rules cannot emerge out of facts. I think that this is very well possible and discernible in all those instances in which patterns of behaviour slowly develop into rules.Footnote 19 But we should make a difference between ontological views on how rules are formed and epistemological views on how they can be identified.Footnote 20

In investigating state practice, legal decision-makers necessarily see the practices, usages and customs through the filter of rules and definitional concepts that they already have in mind. It is not necessary that these rules have an unambiguous status or are already legally valid. As Hakimi remarked, it is more to the point to refer to them as ‘normative positions which may not be fully supported’.Footnote 21 But whether they are formally valid, endorsed by a majority, soft law or only half-baked rules in the making, they nevertheless function in the same way as theoretical hypotheses do in the sciences: they guide our perceptions and investigations by selecting the items that are ‘relevant’ and have ‘legal salience’.Footnote 22

At this point one may wonder, how is it possible to distil and identify rules if all we can do is to investigate the facts by means of … rules? The apparent circularity of opinio juris, much criticised on the ground that it presupposes the existence of law in order to identify law, seems to be repeated also in the examination of state practice! And indeed, circles abound. Any examination of practices or facts presupposes the guidance of rules. But which rules should be selected? In order to decide on the appropriate filter, the facts should be consulted. And how can the facts be consulted? By the guidance of rules. This treadmill is a well-known feature of interpretation and is called the hermeneutical circle.

According to Heidegger, such circles should not be shunned, as they reflect the structure of our existence.Footnote 23 But even without such metaphysics, it is important to see that it would be a misunderstanding to discard such circles as mistaken methodology or faulty logic. The preconceptions which are necessary to select that which is meaningful may be seen as ‘prejudice’, but it is a kind of prejudice which is essential for any understanding.Footnote 24 It is therefore worthwhile to be open about the inevitability of such circles. Instead of sweeping them under the carpet it is better to acknowledge them and to make clear where such circles arise and which points they cover. If we talk, therefore, about the identification of rules by examining state practice, we should acknowledge that such an examination can be carried out only if we have standards, rules and normative positions in mind as a background theory. This does not imply that we can only discover what we already have in mind. After the initial selection of the relevant material, its weight should still be assessed. But to represent this ‘material’ as a heap of objective facts is a mischaracterisation.

5 Common Law?

Schauer and Bradley suggested that this process is very similar to common law adjudication.Footnote 25 They rightly point out that the examination of state practice is not the kind of inductivist enterprise that is commonly and officially announced. They propose that the identification of rules by an investigation of state practice should be regarded as an attempt to construct chains of precedents. Schauer refers to the fact that different chains of precedents can be constructed, just as Llewellyn pointed out that different ladders can be built by means of which it is possible to motivate different outcomes.

At first sight, one may question the wisdom of the term ‘precedents’. State practice comprises not only precedents but acts, usages and conventions of all kinds. It is only in the eyes of a judicial decision-maker that such acts can be labelled as ‘precedents’: events that preceded a new case and might have a bearing on the ways in which a new case should be resolved. But this is not necessarily a problem. Both authors start from the perspective of the adjudicator and in such a perspective state practice is examined in the light of the theoretical framework of the law. The clear advantage of this comparison with common law adjudication is therefore that it openly concedes that the adjudicator runs in the hermeneutical circle. It makes clear that the examination of state practice is not just an investigation of raw material facts but presupposes a selective filter of possibly relevant legal perspectives, from which acts and usages are indeed regarded as ‘precedents’ for the case at hand. The plausibility of the perspectives is judged by means of a further investigation of the facts, which necessarily presupposes a theoretical background perspective, etc.

However, it seems to me that this account, although much more realistic than official objectivist inductivism, assumes too much: it presupposes that it is clear what counts as precedent. In domestic common law adjudication that may be indeed the case, at least to a certain degree. The legal material is to some extent clearly defined, although here, too, the weight of the precedents may vary. Yet, it is within the domain of this legal material that the interpreter can choose to construct different chains of precedents leading to the decision in the new case.

In CIL, the boundaries of the legal material are less clearly demarcated. The questions to be answered are therefore not only how to construct different chains of precedents. Before those questions can arise, a prior question must be answered and that is whether a certain usage may count as precedent: is a certain act, text, omission weighty enough to count? This is clear for instance from the wording of the 1969 North Continental Shelf case, in which it is argued that despite the fact that the principle of equidistance is used by the majority of states and in numerous cases, there are ‘several grounds which deprive them of weight as precedents in the present context’.Footnote 26 State practice is not examined in order to decide on the applicable chain of precedents and cannot merely be regarded as a matter of choice between various applicable chains. The court that examines state practice does so in order to find out which instances might qualify to be labelled ‘precedents’. Only after that can their respective weight be ascertained and the connecting chains constructed.

6 The Double Function of Opinio Juris

Surprisingly, this prior question is usually answered by referring to opinio juris. In the Asylum case between Colombia and Peru (1950), for instance, the ICJ asserts that all the instances of granting asylum, mentioned by Colombia, simply do not count as precedents:

The facts which have been laid before the Court show that in a number of cases the persons who have enjoyed asylum were not, at the moment at which asylum was granted, the object of any accusation on the part of the judicial authorities. In a more general way, considerations of convenience or simple political expediency seem to have led the territorial State to recognize asylum without that decision being dictated by any feeling of legal obligation.

If these remarks tend to reduce considerably the value as precedents of the cases of asylum cited by the Government of Colombia, they show, none the less, that asylum as practised in Latin America is an institution which, to a very great extent, owes its development to extra-legal factors. The good-neighbour relations between the republics, the different political interests of the governments, have favoured the mutual recognition of asylum apart from any clearly defined juridical system.Footnote 27

Institutions that arose in an extra-legal context lack legal relevance and do not count as ‘precedents’. In the Nicaragua case, too, state practice is examined by reference to opinio juris, where it is argued that intervention is not undertaken with a sense of a legal right:

The United States authorities have on some occasions clearly stated their grounds for intervening in the affairs of a foreign State for reasons connected with, for example, the domestic policies of that country, its ideology, the level of its armaments, or the direction of its foreign policy. But these were statements of international policy, and not an assertion of rules of existing international law.Footnote 28

The reader might observe that these passages show exactly what is expressed by the official doctrine, which requires the presence of both an objective and a subjective element. Opinio juris is explicitly invoked.Footnote 29

I would, however, say that the influence of opinio juris is much stronger than is officially conceded. The official claim is that there is first an – independent – examination of state practice, and that that practice can only be regarded as CIL if it is accompanied by opinio juris. What we see here, however, is that without opinio juris a recurrent and widespread usage simply does not count as legally relevant state practice. It counts as mere ‘convention’, as comity, etiquette or rules that are followed merely with a view to ‘expediency’ or ‘international policy’. Opinio juris is required in order to ‘see’ something as relevant practice instead of merely a heap of facts or usages.

Opinio juris, therefore, indeed ‘counts twice’:

  1. (1) A usage/act counts as ‘practice’ if carried out with a sense of legal obligation (opinio juris).

  2. (2) A practice counts as an element of CIL if carried out with a sense of legal obligation (opinio juris).

Opinio juris is a condition not only for ‘identifying’ CIL, but also for differentiating those usages that might be seen as legally relevant practice (‘precedents’) and those which are not.Footnote 30

This second function is usually not recognised in the official accounts of state practice as an objective element but it is in line with what I remarked on above about the necessity of a theory. In order to ‘see’ something as practice, the law functions as the indispensable theoretical searchlight – a searchlight which is only deemed fit if it has passed the test of opinio juris! That is why torture or pollution, although they are clearly practices that are widespread, uniform and consistent, do not ‘count’ as practices. That is why granting asylum can be regarded as legally irrelevant and as mere friendliness towards neighbours, as is maintained in the Asylum case. The objective element is therefore not only connected to the subjective element:Footnote 31 state practice cannot even be investigated without opinio juris. Opinio juris is the starting point for any meaningful investigation of state practice.

Of course, this is not to say that state practices cannot be normatively meaningful without opinio juris. As I noted above, we should be careful to distinguish the (ontological) formation of normative rules as emerging in and from practices from the (epistemological) identification of such rules. I am now just referring to how the courts in their investigation of state practice identify legally meaningful and relevant normative positions that might qualify as precedents in a certain case. And in order to do so, the opinio juris plays a major role as a theoretical searchlight.

7 A Practice of Claims

It seems then that my reading leads to an even more incongruous result than official doctrine. There, opinio juris is already troublesome because of its circularity. As is pointed out repeatedly, opinio juris identifies a rule of CIL by reference to the conviction of states that they are under an obligation to comply with that same rule. My contention seems to be even more bewildering than this: only those acts, usages and conventions that are carried out with a sense of legal obligation (opinio juris 1) count as state practice, as a set of potentially meaningful precedents, which can only give rise to CIL if coupled with opinio juris (2). There is not one circle; there are two – or more specifically, there is a spiral.

However, as I have pointed out elsewhere,Footnote 32 the circularity is not so devastating if we understand opinio juris not as a conviction or a belief that one is under a legal obligation but as an articulated and publicly accessible claim.Footnote 33 These claims are usually couched in general and descriptive terms: ‘this is the rule/law/principle we maintain and cherish’. Because of this particular descriptive form we might easily mistake them for descriptions of facts (we are under this legal obligation) and then circularity is indeed vicious. But in fact they are declarative statements: statements that constitute the law by means of a declarative form.Footnote 34 They are not expressions of legality but claims to legality.Footnote 35

If we understand that state practice can only be – and is only – investigated by means of such claims to legality that form the searchlight for the investigation of practices, a number of confusions can be clarified. In the first place, it has already been remarked that a lot of the ICJ’s judgements refer, not to state practice as it is traditionally defined,Footnote 36 but to resolutions, declarations and the like. In a fascinating article Choi and GulatiFootnote 37 presented statistics of the kind of evidence found by the ICJ under the banner of ‘state practice’. They found that acts and practices were hardly investigated at all, and the official sources of state practice (diplomatic correspondence, domestic legislation, etc.) in only a small minority of cases. Instead, in an overwhelming majority of cases treaties and other ‘aspirational and forward-looking documents’ were cited. The authors find that amazing: states enter into treaties in the absence of CIL and it would therefore be strange to cite treaties as proof of the CIL.

Choi and Gulati confirm empirically the uneasiness expressed by Mendelson more than two decades ago, who observed, while commenting on the Nicaragua case (Merits):

And even if we grant, for the sake of argument, that the resolutions represented the opinio juris, where then is the practice which, the Court seemed to be saying, is an independent element? If we say that the resolutions constitute verbal practice, then we are guilty of double-counting them – both as the objective and as the subjective elements.

And he adds to this:

It might be responded that all that is needed is for the act of practice to be accompanied by opinio juris; so that what is required is not two completely separate elements, but both combined; however, to count the act of voting for the resolution as practice still looks rather like pulling oneself up by one’s own bootstraps.Footnote 38

And indeed it is. This is exactly the case. To lift oneself up by one’s own bootstraps accurately describes the hermeneutic circle.

8 Interpretation Prior to Identification and Application

The observation that the identification of CIL is circular is hardly novel. Koskenniemmi had already observed that ‘doctrine about customary law is indeterminate because circular. It assumes behaviour to be evidence of the opinio juris and the latter to be evidence of which behaviour is relevant as custom.’Footnote 39 However, as we have seen, ‘behaviour’ and ‘evidence’ are not as unproblematic as even Koskenniemi assumes. As Bodansky correctly asserts,Footnote 40 if it were only behaviour that is investigated, sociologists would be much better equipped. Legal investigation revolves around texts: an abundance of claims to legality such as resolutions, conventions and treaties. They form the object of investigation.

And they figure at the two levels that we distinguished in Section 7. First of all, they are investigated in order to determine the legally relevant precedents, and secondly they are investigated in order to choose between potentially applicable precedents in order to apply them to a particular case. Both activities are usually conducted in one big sweep. In the judgments of the courts it is just pointed out which texts are considered legally relevant, weighty or convincing. They may be labelled differently, as either ‘state practice’ or ‘opinio juris’, but they are all just texts the relevance of which is assessed and weighed.Footnote 41

It is not possible to weigh precedents and to apply rules without prior interpretation. That interpretation can be grammatical or historical, but most importantly it is teleological. The texts should be interpreted as having a point. This is noticeable both in the attempt to determine the precedents and in the way in which chains of such precedents are constructed. To begin with the latter: it is obvious that in order to make a choice between different chains of precedents, as in common law adjudication, they should first be constructed as a chain. That can be done by discovering analogies or some aspects these precedents have in common. But this discovery of shared aspects can be conducted only by constructing an underlying principle or rationale. There are no shared features between ‘books’, ‘electricity’ and ‘personal data’. We can only construct their shared features as ‘goods’ to which property law can be applied. And usually this construction is carried out by hypothesising an underlying aim or rationale. Do we follow all those solemn prohibitions of weapons and conclude by analogy that nuclear weapons should be prohibited as well? Or do we follow all – equally solemn – declarations of sovereignty and conclude that such a prohibition of nuclear weapons is not part of CIL?

The same applies, however, also to the first round in which different official acts and texts are examined in order to establish the legally relevant precedents. Here, too, there are numerous candidates, and they can be linked together in different chains, each focusing on different shared features and different underlying principles. Those texts, rules and claims which are not constructed as precedents are denied legal relevance and figure as ‘technical rules’ or as rules of etiquette, comity and friendliness. These ‘legally irrelevant’ rules are obviously not found but interpreted as lacking legal relevance, and they are interpreted by reference to texts that embody claims to legality. Postema adequately described the process of such interpretation of practices and compared this to discerning a pattern: ‘the pattern is likely to be salient because it is meaningful within the practice, rather than meaningful because it is salient’.Footnote 42 The degree to which customs can be integrated in such a pattern is therefore decisive, according to Postema.

Although I distinguished for analytical reasons between the two rounds of legal interpretation in which legally relevant material is (a) determined and (b) applied, we should not think of determination and application as sequential in time. As noted above, they are usually carried out in one big sweep: both are the result of interpretation in the light of opinio juris, and they are intricately connected. The more successful the attempt in the first round to deny legal relevance to normative positions and, consequently, the narrower the selection of legally relevant material, the easier the task to choose a preferred ladder in the second round of application. Or, to put it differently, those normative positions that fail to be elevated to the status of ‘legally relevant’ state practice do not need to be examined as candidates for CIL. That is why the double-counting of opinio juris does not come to the surface. Opinio juris is usually already applied in the first round of determining relevant precedents and need not be re-emphasised in the determination of CIL.

It is important to see that both the determination of relevant precedents and the choice between rival chains of precedents presuppose interpretation of the normative material as material that is patterned around its point or telos. The degree to which a claim can be fitted into a pattern is to a large extent dependent on how we construct that telos. As Heidegger in his more lucid moments pointed out, it is not possible to identify something as something (‘Etwas als etwas’) without understanding it as something ‘in order to’ (‘Um-zu’).Footnote 43 Precedents, and also candidate-precedents, are constructed as parts of a Dworkinian chain-novel,Footnote 44 or at least – more modestly – as threads weaving a plot in a story.

We should not think of this telos as a set of intentions, the honesty of which can be examined on the basis of diplomatic correspondence between officials. Interpretation is different from grasping intentions at face value. It may very well be the case that the states which signed a treaty had no serious intention at all of furthering the aim of the treaty. They might simply have thought about the reputational costs of making reservations to that treaty, or they were mistaken in thinking that they would not be burdened too much, or had already seen gaps in the treaty that would allow them an exit. If we interpret such texts in terms of intentions, many of those texts can indeed be disregarded as specimens of ‘cheap talk’.Footnote 45

However, as Ricœur pointed out, a text (any text, whether novel or academic publication or treaty) gains a certain distance from its drafter or writer. It is this distance that harbours the possibility for the interpreter to discern and to reconstruct several meanings of such texts. According to Paul Ricoeur, ‘what must be interpreted in a text is a proposed world which I could inhabit and wherein I could project one of my ownmost possibilities’.Footnote 46

This does not merely apply to my interpretation of literary works; it also relates to how legal texts can be understood.Footnote 47 Interpretation is an activity to understand not only what exists but also what is possible.Footnote 48 In fact, legal texts – as well as communiqués – are also written with an eye to such possible readings. The importance of textual subtleties can only be understood on the basis of this distantiation. If it were a matter of just unravelling intentions, such care for texts would be unnecessary. But they are highly important in view of the fact that texts live a life of their own. Even if such texts do not reflect the serious intentions of the signatories and are indeed no more than ‘cheap talk’, they can be read as elements of a purposive pattern, that can be constructed as meaningful by the interpreter.

9 Conclusion: Possible Worlds

If we take seriously the notion of interpretation as delineating possible meanings, that means that different chains and patterns are conceivable that order the textual material in different ways. Depending on the choice of such patterns, a certain text is interpreted as a more or a less weighty claim, as a legally binding rule, as a normatively binding standard, as a technical standard or as just a convenient habit.

We should not think that there is one correct pattern. As I argued in my earlier article,Footnote 49 opinio juris should be understood in its plural form. There are different opiniones juris: official claims that propose different ordering patterns and which function as maps. The main function of such maps is not merely to represent reality. Maps typically highlight some elements at the expense of others. The cyclist map ignores the highways; underground maps emphasise the underground stations and may even be extremely unrealistic in the sense that they distort the physical distance between stations. The value of such maps does not depend on their realism but on the use – the ‘point’ – of such a map. The investigation of state practice, but also of CIL as a whole, can best be seen as a map drawn on a transparent sheet that is laid over the abundance of official documents and texts, by means of which this legal material is ordered in different ways.

All this implies that the claim cannot be justified that there is an objective examination of state practice and a neutral ‘identification’ of rules that precedes their interpretation. The transparent sheet cannot be removed without risking being plunged into a bewildering multitude of incomprehensible texts. But, and this is important, this does not imply that judgments are completely arbitrary. The courts are not ‘objective’, but neither are they ‘subjective’. They do not deal exclusively with the factual, but nor are they condemned to the realm of normative ideals. Their judgments are never completely apologetic or utopian, because the interpretation of legal texts is not exclusively limited to what is, nor to what ought to be. The task of courts is to choose a path among possible worlds.

This implies a somewhat nuanced answer to the common objection against CIL as mere fantasy. It seems exaggerated to speak of judicial discretion in the strong sense of the word, according to which the judge is simply not bound by any rules. In fact, even in the advisory opinions where the ICJ is just required to answer very open questions, there is always plenty of legal material that may or may not support the opinion. Courts do not fantasise. But neither are they unreservedly bound by that material. The texts are not determinate strongholds. Their weight is (co-)determined by the patterned transparent sheets. The plurality of these sheets leaves room for choice.Footnote 50

2 Addressing the Chronological Paradox of CIL From Good Faith to Opinio Juris, and Opinio Juris to New Customary Rules

Henrique Marcos
1 Introduction

Most social groups have rulesFootnote 1 about how the people in that group should behave. In many cases, these rules develop from custom; they are called ‘customary rules’. New customary rules arise from two elements: (i) the repeated practice of certain acts by the people in a group (diuturnitas); and (ii) a shared expectation that this practice will continue. This expectation leads people to sense or feel that they should act in a certain way. That is, people continue to engage in a particular practice because they believe they are obligated to do so (opinio juris sive necessitatis, or simply opinio juris). By contrast, practice without a sense of obligation leads to habits rather than customary rules.Footnote 2

Customary rules have become less important in domestic law, but the opposite is true in international law. International lawyers frequently rely on customary international law (CIL), and many of the most important rules of international law have come from CIL. The prohibition of genocide, torture, slavery, and piracy are relevant examples.Footnote 3 We can also see the importance of CIL for topics not yet regulated by treaties and topics addressed by treaties that are not universally ratified. The Law of the Sea ConventionFootnote 4 is a good example of this. The Convention has helped codify CIL rules already in place and blended them with treaty rules, smoothing some of the differences between CIL and non-CIL rules.Footnote 5

As a source of international law, CIL is not only important but also complex. Like international law in general, CIL results from a bottom-up process, where subjects of the law are also its makers. To complicate matters further, CIL develops informally and by implication. In CIL, unlike treaty law, there is no standard way for states to gather and decide on creating new rules. Instead, CIL rules seem to appear out of nowhere; they are just here, and it is sometimes unclear how long they have been with us.Footnote 6

Another complication that affects CIL is the well-known chronological paradox. Despite its name, the paradox is not merely chronological: it raises a broad conceptual issue that threatens the coherence of (customary) international law. The paradox lies in the fact that for a new CIL rule to be created states must believe that the law already requires them to act in a certain way (opinio juris), but until the rule is created they are not legally required to do so as the rule establishing such a requirement has yet to exist.Footnote 7

Since there does not seem to be any way out of the chronological paradox’s vicious circle, the making of a new CIL rule would seem impossible, or, at the very least, our understanding of CIL would appear incoherent. Given that we know CIL rules do exist, their creation is not impossible, so we must entertain the possibility that our understanding of CIL is incoherent.Footnote 8 This is critical, as the legitimacy of a legal system depends in part on its coherence. If legitimacy is what makes us want to carry out our legal obligations, then coherence – the intelligibility of such obligations – is a requirement for legitimacy. After all, we can only effectively comply with what we understand.

Given that CIL rules are being used more and more against states, the chronological paradox is both a theoretical and a practical problem.Footnote 9 If the paradox is true (and, thus, our understanding of CIL is incoherent), states may be less inclined to follow CIL rules, which would be a blow to international law. Given how critical the paradox is, there is reason to think that the International Law Commission (ILC) would have directly addressed it in its 2018 report on identifying CIL.Footnote 10 Unfortunately, this was not the case. Ignoring the paradox’s significance is problematic, as it casts a large shadow over CIL. In a landscape where CIL is a primary source of international law, practitioners should not be left stumbling in the dark.Footnote 11

This chapter tries to shed some light on this topic by addressing the paradox in a way that ensures the coherence, and thus legitimacy, of (customary) international law. It does so by offering an interpretation of CIL that accounts for the creation of CIL rules through distinct, non-paradoxical steps. The chapter argues that the belief in a legal obligation (opinio juris) derives from the general principle of good faith. Good faith leads to legal obligations, which compel a subgroup of states to engage in specific behaviour. Then, as a result of this subgroup’s repeated behaviour, a new CIL rule develops, obligating the entire community of states to follow that behaviour. In elucidating the shift from good faith to legal obligations and from legal obligations to CIL rules, this chapter draws on interpretivism, social ontology, and contemporary research on constitutive rules.

In terms of structure, the chapter is divided into four sections. Following this introductory section, Section 2 discusses CIL and the chronological paradox. Section 3 examines constructivism in legal interpretation. Section 4 then focuses on the application of rules and on constitutive rules, explaining the role of good faith and how constitutive (meta)rules create new CIL rules. Section 5 concludes the chapter by reaffirming earlier conclusions.

2 CIL and Its Paradox

Article 38(1)(b) of the Statute of the International Court of Justice (ICJ)Footnote 12 states that CIL rules evince general practices that are accepted as law. The Statute thus refers to the two constituent elements of customary rules mentioned in Section 1 – namely, (i) the existence of a general practice in the form of repeated acts (diuturnitas), and (ii) performance of these acts in the belief that they are required by law (opinio juris).

Scholarship traditionally considers practice (diuturnitas) to refer to the practice of states. There have been fruitful discussions about the contribution of non-state actors to CIL.Footnote 13 For instance, the ILC has recognised that ‘[i]n certain cases, the practice of international organizations also contributes to the formation, or expression, of rules of customary international law’.Footnote 14 For the purposes of this chapter, the question of whether non-state actors’ behaviour qualifies as ‘practice’ is beside the point; although an interesting debate, it has no bearing on the chapter’s explanation of how CIL rules are created. Thus, although the chapter addresses state practice, it can also be read as encompassing non-state practice.

Acceptance as law (opinio juris) means that states believe a specific action is required under the law. In other words, states believe that a particular practice is legally obligatory. It should be pointed out that the term ‘obligation’ is used in this chapter to designate a basic normative or deontic concept.Footnote 15 When we say that a particular behaviour is obligatory or required, or that someone must act or is responsible for acting, we mean that there is an obligation to act in a certain way. Some obligations, such as the obligation to pay taxes, are imposed by the law and legal rules. These are legal obligations. However, there are also non-legal obligations, like the obligation to honour a promise made to a friend. It is worth noting that obligations can be used as a basis from which to derive prohibitions or permissions.Footnote 16 A prohibition against using force, for example, is an obligation not to use force. Being permitted to use force in self-defence is tantamount to not being prohibited from using force in self-defence (a non-obligation not to use force in self-defence). Thus, while continuing to refer only to obligations, we use the term broadly to cover permissions and prohibitions, too.

When it comes to CIL, states act in the belief they are bound by a legal obligation (opinio juris). By belief, we to refer to a general acceptance of something as being the case.Footnote 17 Different beliefs move us in different ways. Some beliefs are about things we know for sure, while others are about things we only vaguely sense or feel. No matter how strong or weak, these are all beliefs. Besides, believing in something does not mean we have to think about it or do it all the time. For example, most of us believe that the moon is not made of cheese, but we do not usually think about it. Let it be said that there is nothing controversial about attributing beliefs to states: following Cassese, we can say that it is humans acting on behalf of states who believe that certain acts are obligatory.Footnote 18

Opinio juris allows us to distinguish practices that are merely habitual from those that create normative expectations in the community and consequently lead to the creation of CIL rules.Footnote 19 It should be borne in mind that what we are referring to here is the belief that a practice is required by law. States feel compelled to perform these acts because they consider them to be legally obligatory, not for any other, non-legal reason, no matter how strong it may be. As stated in Section 1, the chronological paradox suggests that CIL is caught in a vicious circle: to create a new CIL rule, states must believe that the law obligates them to act in a certain way (opinio juris), yet until this CIL rule is created the act in question is not required by law.Footnote 20

To add colour to this explanation, let us imagine that a group of wealthy states begins donating vaccines to developing states during a pandemic. Suppose this practice continues to the point where states believe that they are under a legal obligation to donate vaccines. Lawyers then identify a new CIL rule, according to which wealthy states are obligated to donate vaccines to developing states during pandemics. The problem is that if this new ‘vaccine donation CIL rule’ exists simply because states believe the practice to be legally obligatory, then the rule cannot as such impose the obligation to donate vaccines. For it actually to be a legal obligation, a legal rule imposing the obligation is needed. As Bradley puts it: ‘If State practices do not become binding as CIL until the States involved act out of a sense of legal obligation, how do the States develop that sense of legal obligation in the first place?’Footnote 21 In our example, if wealthy states are legally obligated to donate vaccines only by virtue of a CIL rule, how did they come to believe that the law obligates them to donate vaccines in the first place?

The paradox is disconcerting, because if it correctly accounts for the creation of new CIL rules, then CIL is fated to chase its tail. Such circular reasoning is problematic: it uses its conclusion as a premise, while giving us no reason to accept its premise other than that we already believe its conclusion. We have to assume that the law requires specific behaviour on the part of states (there must be a legal obligation) before we can conclude that a given CIL rule exists. But to assume that the law requires such behaviour of states (i.e. that there is indeed a legal obligation), we need a pre-existing CIL rule commanding such behaviour (i.e. we need a CIL rule to impose that legal obligation).

Gény gives a straightforward (but unsatisfactory) answer to the paradox. He says that states are wrong to think they are legally required to act: their opinio juris is mistaken.Footnote 22 That is, states have – or feign – a false view about what is happening,Footnote 23 whereas there is no obligation at all. Gény says that when this mistake is made repeatedly by a lot of states, it generates mutual expectations that turn into a legal obligation. Gény’s response admittedly short-circuits the paradox, but in avoiding one problem it falls into another, for if states are mistaken, then CIL is incoherent and its entire structure based on a delusion. As exposed in Section 1, such a workaround falls short of what this chapter sets out to do, which is to address the paradox in a way that preserves the coherence, and thus the legitimacy, of (customary) international law.

Some authors have made intriguing attempts to re-imagine opinio juris as more than just a description of the law, arguing that it helps to create the law. To put it differently, these authors claim that opinio juris goes beyond a descriptive stance on the existence of legal obligations, because it also plays a prescriptive role in determining the content of these legal obligations. In Westerman’s words: ‘Opinio juris can better be regarded as a map, which represents the law by selecting and highlighting those aspects that are deemed important. It describes and prescribes at the same time.’Footnote 24 When states believe that a certain act is legally obligatory, they are not simply describing a pre-existing reality. Their belief is effectively building reality as we know it. This – the constructive role of our collective beliefs – is a topic central to social ontology; as a field of study, it investigates how the combined action of our minds can shape the world around us. According to social ontology, our minds are not (just) describing reality; they are projecting meaning onto it.Footnote 25 For example, when people believe that a river marks the frontier between two communities, they are not only acknowledging that fact but also creating it. If it were not for people collectively believing that the river is a frontier, it would be just another watercourse.

The depiction of opinio juris as a belief with both descriptive and prescriptive functions does not contradict traditional views on CIL. In fact, the ILC’s explanation of acceptance as law (opinio juris) corresponds to social ontology’s account of collective acceptance. The ILC explains that acceptance as law implies there is a ‘subjective’ or ‘psychological’ dimension to the ‘binding character of the practice in question’, in the sense that ‘the practice must be undertaken with a sense of legal right or obligation.’Footnote 26 According to social ontology, collective acceptance is when the members of a social group come to share and maintain a relevant social attitude (a ‘we-attitude’) towards a certain practice.Footnote 27 Like the constructive role of beliefs in the river-frontier example mentioned above, when states believe they have an obligation to engage in a particular practice, this belief is both descriptive and prescriptive. It should be added that participants must be committed to what they believe, though their belief can range from enthusiastic endorsement to simply going along with the group.Footnote 28 As a result, the lines between passive acceptance and active support or desire are frequently blurred.

3 Constructive Interpretation

In Section 2, we discussed the two constituent elements of CIL, dissected the chronological paradox, and began to discuss how our collective beliefs can shape the social world. We saw that the crux of the paradox lies in the manner in which a new CIL rule is created: how can the existence of a CIL rule be dependent on a condition (belief in a legal obligation – opinio juris) that appears to be itself dependent on an already existing CIL rule? The challenging feature of the chronological paradox is thus the transition from the first point in time when a CIL rule does not yet exist to a second point in time when it does. To understand the transition between these two points, we must first understand how CIL rules are identified.

The identification of a CIL rule involves gathering evidence that its two constituent elements – repeated practice (diuturnitas) and a belief in legal obligation (opinio juris) – are present. Such evidence is sought in prior pronouncements and empirical data relating to state behaviour. Through observation of relevant materials (wherever these materials are found), the aim is to determine whether a specific CIL rule exists. If sufficient evidence of the two constituent elements is found, a new CIL rule is said to exist. If the evidence is insufficient, there is (as yet) no new CIL rule.

The search for corroborative materials should not be thought of as ‘gold-digging’ for evidence.Footnote 29 Far from being based on neutral observation, the identification of CIL rules is a highly interpretive activity. As philosophers have long recognised, no evidence is ‘given’ neutrally, because all observation is theory-laden:Footnote 30 the theoretical framework of the observer/interpreter determines the meaning of what they observe. Likewise, how people choose, see, and judge evidence is affected by the theories they hold.Footnote 31 In a legal context, as explained by Hart, ‘situations do not await us neatly labelled, creased, and folded; nor is their legal classification written on them to be simply read off by the judge.’Footnote 32 On the contrary, evidentiary materials call for purposeful interpretation: it is the responsibility of the interpreter to determine the import of the words and actions.Footnote 33

The question therefore arises as to what role and purpose interpretation has in relation to CIL rules. There are at least two possible answers to this question, for legal interpretation may be of two kinds: descriptive or constructive. The former simply describes what the law is and what rules exist. The latter not only tells us what the law is but also creates the law and its rules. The descriptivist viewpoint has ‘realist’Footnote 34 undertones, because it presupposes the existence of a legal reality independent of the interpreter, whose task is therefore merely to point out answers that are already there. By contrast, the constructivist viewpoint is based on the premise that legal interpretation is more than just a search for answers; it considers the interpreter to be engaging in an act of creation when assigning meaning to what they interpret.Footnote 35

This chapter discounts the descriptivist point of view for a number of reasons,Footnote 36 one of which is that descriptivism ignores the fact that observation is theory-laden. As previously stated, all observation, including interpretation, is coloured by the observer’s theoretical bias. Consequently, observation (or interpretation) can never be purely descriptive; it always has, to some extent, a constitutive role. Furthermore, the descriptivist viewpoint is unable to account for the necessary role argumentation plays in the interpreter’s efforts to solve ‘hard cases’.Footnote 37 Consider the discussions currently taking place over whether there is a customary rule that allows states to intervene in the territories of other states to stop human rights violations;Footnote 38 whether there is a level of gravity below which small-scale armed attacks are not considered acts of aggression under international law;Footnote 39 and whether it is illegal for states to conduct military exercises or manoeuvres in foreign exclusive economic zones.Footnote 40 The answers to these questions are not a ‘given’, but rather depend on the quality of the interpreters’ arguments. In other words, the ideas of those who interpret the law shape the contents of international law and international legal rules.

Dworkin took a similar constructivist approach to legal interpretation in saying that interpretation is a creative process in which meaning is imposed on the object of interpretation to make it the best instantiation of a given form or genre.Footnote 41 However, he did not think interpreters should be able to interpret sources however they wished. Although interpretation must allow for innovation to ensure that the object as interpreted best serves its purpose, its scope is limited by the object’s history.Footnote 42 Thus, legal interpretation is Janus-faced, looking both backwards and forwards.Footnote 43 While based on the observation of pre-existing materials, it is also creative in that it is not a mere reproduction of those materials; rather, it creates something new by giving them meaning. This is equally true of CIL interpretation, for once evidence of the two constituent elements of CIL has been established, CIL interpretation fulfils a constructive role by shaping and determining its content.

It is important to note that we can still talk about ‘interpreting’ CIL even when the evidence of its two constituent elements is not in textual form. True, interpretive activity in the legal sphere is often directed at pieces of text, as when we extract rules from the text of a treaty. This, for instance, happens when we read Article 8 of the Rome StatuteFootnote 44 to determine the content of the rule punishing aggression. But interpretation goes beyond textual hermeneutics. It is possible to distinguish between two types of interpretation – (i) source interpretation, which is the interpretation of (formal and material) sources of law; and (ii) rule-to-case interpretation, which is the classification of a case according to the conditions under which a given rule is applicable to it.Footnote 45 In both cases, interpretation may be directed at unwritten materials. For example, when lawyers identify a new CIL rule on the basis of empirical evidence (source interpretation), or determine, on the basis of visual evidence of armed conflict, that the crime of aggression has been committed (rule-to-case interpretation), they are relying on unwritten materials.

Both the ICJ and the ILC believe that CIL is susceptible to interpretation. In Nicaragua, the ICJ held that rules derived from CIL could be distinguished from those derived from international treaties by ‘reference to the methods of interpretation and application.’Footnote 46 Likewise, in North Sea Continental Shelf Judge Tanaka asserted that ‘[c]ustomary law … requires precision and completion about its content. This task, in its nature being interpretative, would be incumbent upon the Court.’Footnote 47 The ILC has taken a similar line: when commenting on materials that may be consulted to help identify CIL, it stated that specific ‘texts may assist in collecting, synthesizing or interpreting practice relevant to the identification of customary international law’.Footnote 48 It furthermore explained that ‘[e]ach of the forms [of state practice] listed is to be interpreted broadly to reflect the multiple and diverse ways in which states act and react’.Footnote 49 Therefore, it cannot be considered controversial to claim that CIL is interpretable.Footnote 50

To conclude this discussion of the interpretive nature of identifying CIL rules, it is crucial to keep in mind that there is no absolute separation in how evidence for the two CIL elements is interpreted. Although the ICJ held in the Asylum case that diuturnitas and opinio juris should be determined separately,Footnote 51 this view has gradually been replaced by one that allows evidence of both constituent elements to be extracted from the same act. D’Aspremont discerned signs of this change in the Gulf of Maine and Nicaragua cases.Footnote 52 The most recent rebuttal of the ICJ’s initial position came from the ILC in its 2018 Draft Conclusions. When defining what materials may serve as evidence of repeated practice and the belief that such practice is legally required, the ILC acknowledged that one and the same act may provide evidence of both.Footnote 53

4 The Formation of CIL Rules

This section will break down the formation of CIL rules into distinct steps. It is a process that begins with the principle of good faith, which leads to legal obligations, and these legal obligations in turn contribute to the development of a new CIL rule. But before we can discuss these steps, some general ideas must first be addressed – namely, rule applicability and application, constitutive rules, and rules about rules (metarules). Although these matters might not seem directly related to the chronological paradox, their elucidation is important to further discussion of the paradox. Given that problems are best solved when broken down into their most basic parts and then put it back together again, this section will focus on deconstructing and rebuilding the problem.

4.1 Rule Applicability and Rule Application

Section 3 distinguished between two types of interpretation: source interpretation, which, through an examination of formal and material sources, written and unwritten, allows us to determine the existence and content of legal rules; and rule-to-case interpretation, which, in situations where a rule already exists, allows us to determine whether that rule is applicable – and applies – to a particular case. When examining evidence of the existence of a CIL rule that holds states responsible for internationally wrongful acts, we are engaging in source interpretation.Footnote 54 When we then go on to consider whether that rule is applicable to a specific case in which Uganda commits a wrongful act against the Democratic Republic of the Congo (DRC), we are engaging in rule-to-case interpretation.Footnote 55

To say that a rule is applicable is not to say that it actually applies to a specific case.Footnote 56 In the example given above, there is a distinction to be drawn between admitting that the state responsibility rule is applicable to the case between Uganda and the DRC and concluding that this rule indeed applies to that case. If Uganda’s action against the DRC is wrongful, then the rule is applicable. If an international court decides that the rule applies to this case, Uganda is not only responsible for its actions but also obligated to make reparations to the DRC. In other words, a rule is applicable to a case when the conditions for its application are met; a rule applies when its consequences take effect in a case.Footnote 57

In practice, it is often hard to differentiate between the two types of interpretation and between a rule’s applicability and its application to a specific case. We tend to look at a source, decide whether a rule is applicable to a case, and conclude that it applies to the case, all in one go. For present purposes, however, it is relevant to distinguish between these different notions. One way to grasp the differences between the stages of interpretation is to remember that a rule and its source are distinct. For example, the ILC’s report on state responsibilityFootnote 58 is distinct from the rules holding states accountable for wrongful acts that are derived from that document (and other sources). We can further distinguish between applicability and application by framing rules as a conditions–conclusion formula.Footnote 59 For instance, the CIL rule on state responsibility can be simplified as follows:

Conditions: ‘X and Y are states’ and ‘X commits a wrongful act against Y’ – Conclusion: ‘X is obligated to make reparations to Y’

In this formula, ‘X’ and ‘Y’ are variables for states like Uganda and the DRC. The conjunction ‘and’ means that all conditional blocks must be satisfied for a case to meet that rule’s conditions. The dash separates the conditions from the conclusion, and the inverted commas mark out the conditional and conclusion blocks. If both Uganda and the DRC are states and Uganda has committed a wrongful act against the DRC, then when this rule applies, it obligates Uganda to make reparations to the DRC.

Before moving on, it is essential to note that the application of a rule presupposes interpretation. It is only after we have extracted a rule from its source (source interpretation) and inferred its applicability to a case (rule-to-case interpretation) that the rule will apply. Rule application, like interpretation, is a constructive exercise. When rules apply to cases, they create legal consequences. So, when the state responsibility rule applies to Uganda and the DRC’s case, this is not a mere description of the fact that Uganda must make reparations to the DRC; the rule’s application to the case puts Uganda under an obligation to make reparations to the DRC.

4.2 Constitutive Rules

As explained in Section 2, social ontology studies how our collective beliefs shape the world around us. We gave the example of a river, which can mark the frontier between two communities only if people believe it does. If no one held such a belief, the river would simply be a stretch of water. Rules are similar in that they exist only because people believe in them. Interestingly, unlike the river-frontier, which has a physical presence in the natural world, rules are abstract. Rules have no corporeal form that we can touch, but they still exist because people collectively believe they do.Footnote 60 Let us develop these ideas in the following paragraphs.

Anything that exists can be called an ‘entity’, and anything that exists because of people can be called a ‘social entity’.Footnote 61 A frontier is a social entity. A business, a state, and an international organisation are all examples of social entities. Lawyers, judges, obligations, and rules are all social entities. All of these things exist because of people. There would be no borders, businesses, states, international organisations, lawyers, judges, and, most importantly, no obligations or rules if people did not exist.

Social entities can be separated into two levels.Footnote 62 At the first level are what we may call ‘basic social entities’ – that is, entities that directly depend on people’s beliefs. We often find these basic social entities in simple groups. For instance, if two tribal groups use a river as a frontier to separate their respective territories, that frontier is a basic social entity. Its existence is directly dependent on a belief held by the members of a group. A rule stating that the eldest descendant of a deceased tribe leader becomes the new leader is another example of a basic social entity.

At the second level we find entities that are not directly grounded in people’s beliefs. Although they again exist because of what people believe, it is only in an indirect way, for these entities are based on other entities and are only secondarily grounded in a group’s collective beliefs. Suppose, for example, that when Chief Umoro dies, his firstborn son, Raoni, becomes the leader of his tribe, the Kayapo, by virtue of a rule according to which the deceased tribe leader is succeeded by the eldest descendant. Raoni’s position as the new leader is thus a direct result of that rule and is only indirectly grounded in the Kayapo’s collective beliefs.

These second-level entities are the result of rule application. Let us call them ‘rule-based entities’. To understand how rules can lead to the existence of social entities, we must first consider a few aspects of how rules work. To begin with, rules are not limited to the law;Footnote 63 Language, etiquette, games, and inferences rely frequently on rules, too. Consider the conceptual rule qualifying a plane figure with three straight sides and three angles as a triangle; or the etiquette rule dictating that guests should offer to lend a hand to the host; or the chess rule permitting the bishop to move diagonally in any direction; or the inference rule allowing ‘Q is true’ to be deduced from the premises ‘P implies Q’ and ‘P is true’. These are not legal rules in the strict sense, but they are still rules.

Most rules operate tacitly in the background without our being aware of them.Footnote 64 Consider chess: we think about the rules telling us how to move each piece only if we are still learning the game; once we know how to play, we focus on choosing the best moves and strategies to win. Even though we no longer think about the rules, they are still there in the background and affect how the game is played. As Wittgenstein pointed out, a person who follows rules does not usually think about or check them; when following a rule, they may even be unaware that they are doing so.Footnote 65

We often focus on how rules regulate behaviour (rules tell us our obligations, permissions, and prohibitions), but some rules also constitute social practices. Philosophers call them ‘constitutive rules’.Footnote 66 The rules for games are a good example: It is only thanks to its rules that we can play a game like chess; without them, chess would not exist. Legal rules are similarly constitutive; for example, together they may create a certain kind of political system that determines how people are put into power. Another way in which constitutive rules operate is by making something count as something else.Footnote 67 Chess rules make certain positions on the board count as checkmate. The rule according to which the eldest descendant becomes the new leader makes the eldest descendant count as the new leader when the incumbent dies. In this respect, constitutive rules can create social entities. For example, there is no such thing as checkmate without the rules of chess, so checkmate is a rule-based entity. The same goes for Raoni: he is the leader of the Kayapo tribe because of the rule that makes the eldest descendant of the deceased tribe leader the new leader.

Some second-level rule-based entities exist through the application of other rules called ‘metarules’.Footnote 68 A metarule is a rule about rules, meaning that a rule forms part of its conditions or conclusion. Certain metarules, when applied, create entities that are also rules. There are many examples in present-day legal systems. Think of the domestic rules enacted when parliament passes a bill into law or the international rules created when state representatives ratify treaties. These rules of law are directly based on the metarules that give members of parliament or state representatives the power to make rules of law. Second-level rules are still indirectly based on what people collectively believe, for they would not exist if it were not for people.

4.3 The CIL Metarule

This section argues that CIL rules exist as rule-based entities. It will explain that individual CIL rules are created through a metarule – the CIL metarule, or ‘M’ for short. But before discussing M, it is worth reiterating that, unlike Gény, this chapter does not suppose that states are mistaken in their opinio juris. On the contrary, it assumes they are correct in believing themselves to be under a legal obligatio. So, both the belief and the obligation to which the belief relates are taken as accurate. The rationale behind this assumption is simple: as pointed out in Section 2 when discussing Gény’s answer to the chronological paradox, if the belief held by states is wrong, then CIL is built on a delusion and is therefore incoherent. The alternative is that the belief is correct and that states have a legal obligation. After all, if we believe something (that today is Monday, for example) and that belief is correct, then what we believe is a fact (today is in fact Monday).

M’s conditions are the two elements needed to identify a CIL rule: the practice (diuturnitas) and the belief that this practice is legally obligatory (opinio juris). If M’s conditions are satisfied, M is applicable. If M applies, M leads to the consequence that a particular CIL rule exists. Let us call this generic CIL rule ‘R’. If ‘Φ’ stands for engaging in a named act or activity, such as ‘not using force’, ‘donating vaccines’, or ‘granting immunity to heads of state’, we can write M as the following conditions–conclusion formulation:

Conditions: ‘states generally Φ’ and ‘states are under the legal obligation to Φ’ – Conclusion: ‘there is a CIL rule R obligating states to Φ’

When M applies to a case, M gives rise to a CIL rule R. But R must still be interpreted in light of M’s application to a case (rule-to-case interpretation).Footnote 69 It is important to note that R is not derived directly from the formulation of M, but is the result of M’s application. Knowledge of R comes only from lawyers interpreting M’s application to a specific case. This frequently occurs when lawyers debate possible interpretations in cases where a court recognises that a specific CIL rule applies to the disputants.

How is it that M can lead to the creation of new CIL rules if no one has ever talked about M before? As previously stated, the truth is that many rules control what we do without us even realising it.Footnote 70 According to Wittgenstein, obeying a rule is a matter of practice, whereas understanding a rule is to know what counts as acting by it.Footnote 71 In 1920, Descamps implicitly described how M works when he said that CIL rules are ‘established by the continual and general usage of nations, which has consequently obtained the force of law’.Footnote 72 Despite not mentioning M or discussing constitutive (meta)rules, Descamps is unknowingly referring to M in this explanation of how a new CIL rule is created. As Russell stated, anyone who engages in a practice has some knowledge of the logical rules behind that practice, but this knowledge is in most cases implicit.Footnote 73

M works behind the scenes, much like many other rules that make up our world. As mentioned in Section 4.2, most rules operate implicitly in the background, and no conscious effort is required for their interpretation or application. Chess exists only because of its rules, but most people do not think about the rules when they play. In international law, the metarules that empower state representatives to ratify treaties and that make treaties legal sources are similar; whenever a rule from a specific treaty is recognised, both of these metarules are interpreted and applied, even if only implicitly. The same goes for M.

We should also consider the ICJ’s decision in North Sea Continental Shelf. When deciding if the equidistance principle was based on custom, the ICJ said: ‘It would in the first place be necessary that the provision concerned should, at all events potentially, be of a fundamentally norm-creating character, such as could be regarded as forming the basis of a general rule of law.’Footnote 74 This passage is important because it shows a rule-creating aspect of the standards used to find a CIL rule, which d’Aspremont calls the ‘third element’ for identifying CIL.Footnote 75 In relation to the present discussion, M is an example of such standards with rule-creating dimensions.

Framing M in terms of a conditions⇒conclusion formula helps to show the chronological paradox at work. For M to be applicable, states must Φ and be obligated to Φ. The consequence of M is that a CIL rule R will emerge, obligating states to Φ. The paradox is that for states to be obligated to Φ in the first place, we would need a CIL rule R obligating states to Φ. Let us recall the earlier example of a hypothetical CIL rule obligating wealthy states to donate vaccines. If wealthy states donate vaccines because of an obligation to donate vaccines, M is applicable. If M applies, M constitutes a CIL rule R that obligates wealthy states to donate vaccines. But how can wealthy states be obligated to donate vaccines if the rule that obligates them comes into existence only once M applies?

The answer is that this depiction of CIL needs to be revised. While M does constitute a CIL rule R that imposes an obligation to Φ, the initial obligation to Φ is imposed neither by M nor by R. There are two alternative explanations for the origin of the obligation to Φ.

4.3.1 First Explanation

The first explanation is straightforward. The obligation to Φ is a basic social entity with deontic content that comes directly from what states believe. A subgroup of states creates an obligation to Φ when these states believe they have an obligation to Φ. (This is similar to how groups of people create social entities by believing in them.Footnote 76) Since this subgroup of states believes that they are obligated to Φ, they engage in Φ. If states generally are engaging in Φ because they are obligated to Φ, M is applicable. If M applies, M constitutes a CIL rule R, the effect of which is that all states have an obligation to Φ.Footnote 77

This first explanation raises two problems. The first concerns the distinction between ‘is’ and ‘ought’.Footnote 78 It is unclear why states ought to Φ because of a social entity in which they have only recently started to believe. In other words, how can a social entity that exists as a matter of social fact (‘is’) be used to judge what states are obligated to do (‘ought’)? There have been some intriguing philosophical attempts to bridge the is/ought gap through reference to deontic entities.Footnote 79 It could be argued that states ought to Φ because a deontic entity has imposed on them an obligation to Φ. Deontic entities are social entities that are factual and normative at the same time. Although belonging to the sphere of what is, they can be used to judge what ought to be. As a result, they can bridge the gap between what is and what ought to be. So, an ‘ought judgement’ like ‘states ought to Φ’ could be derived from a factual entity that imposes an obligation to Φ, on condition that this factual entity is deontic.

The second problem with this first explanation is that it does not clarify how there can be a legal obligation to Φ before a legal rule imposes that obligation. As explained in Section 2, the paradox stems from the prerequisite that for a new CIL rule to be created states must believe that the law obligates them to act in a certain way (opinio juris). Yet, according to the first explanation, the obligation to Φ is a basic social entity sourced in states’ collective beliefs. Thus, a legal rule does not impose this obligation. However, it could be argued that the obligation to Φ acquires the status of a legal obligation due to the longstanding practice of engaging in Φ, which reinforces shared expectations within the international community. This argument follows Descamps’s explanation of CIL rules as rules set up by the continued use on the part of states, which, over time, would give these obligations the force of law.Footnote 80

If we agree that deontic entities can bridge the is/ought gap and that the legal nature of obligations can be derived from a longstanding practice, then this first explanation works. But we must admit that it can be challenged by those who contend there is an absolute separation between ‘is’ and ‘ought’, and by those who maintain that a legal rule must impose an obligation for that obligation to be legal. To address these challenges, an alternative explanation of the paradox is needed.

4.3.2 Second Explanation

The second explanation deals with the two problems the first explanation left unsolved by putting the legal obligation to Φ in the context of the general principle of good faith. Good faith is of fundamental importance to all contemporary legal orders, making it a general principle of law under Article 38(1)(c) of the ICJ Statute.Footnote 81 In fact, Grotius stated in De Jure Belli ac Pacis that good faith was one of the most significant legal standards. He also mentions how Aristotle and Cicero saw it as the foundation of all human interaction.Footnote 82 The general principle of good faith has a broad, value-oriented scope, allowing us to derive a variety of legal by-products from it. In similar vein, the ICJ declared in Nuclear Tests that good faith governs ‘the creation and performance of legal obligations, whatever their source’.Footnote 83 So it is safe to say that good faith is the basis for many rules of international law, including (meta)rules on how to interpret and apply legal rules.Footnote 84

One of the by-products of the general principle of good faith is that it protects legitimate expectations by prohibiting states from acting inconsistently with such expectations (or obligating states to act consistently with them).Footnote 85 There have been several precedents affirming the legal protection of legitimate expectations. In Certain German Interests in Upper Silesia, for instance, the Permanent Court of International Justice held that Germany could not act against good faith by frustrating expectations.Footnote 86 In the Megalidis award, the arbitral tribunal considered the prohibition on frustrating the object of a treaty before it enters into force to be linked to the protection of legitimate expectations, thereby acknowledging this prohibition as an expression of good faith.Footnote 87 We can find similar references to protecting legitimate expectations in the Preah Vihear and North Sea Continental Shelf judgments.Footnote 88 In the recent Obligation to Negotiate Access to the Pacific Ocean case, however, the ICJ ruled otherwise:

[R]eferences to legitimate expectations may be found in arbitral awards concerning disputes between a foreign investor and the host State that apply treaty clauses providing for fair and equitable treatment. It does not follow from such references that there exists in general international law a principle that would give rise to an obligation on the basis of what could be considered a legitimate expectation.Footnote 89

Consequently, there is some controversy over whether there is a general rule of international law protecting legitimate expectations. But that does not affect the second explanation’s account of how the legal obligation materialises. The legal obligation to Φ emerges from the general principle of good faith, particularly from a rule that obligates states to Φ if the practice of engaging in Φ generates legitimate expectations. Let us call this rule ‘L’. We can formulate it like this:

Conditions: ‘X is a state’ and ‘X engages in Φ’ and ‘X engaging in Φ generates legitimate expectations’ – Conclusion: ‘X is obligated to Φ’

The ICJ’s statement in Obligation to Negotiate Access to the Pacific Ocean puts us in a predicament. If we were to ignore its pronouncement, we could say that L is a rule of international law that creates an international legal obligation enforceable under international law, full stop. However, this is not the line taken in this chapter, which therefore contemplates that L may not be a general rule of international law. Even so, it is still possible to say that L leads to a legal obligation in a broad sense, because L is a by-product of the general principle of good faith.

According to the ICJ in Obligation to Negotiate Access to the Pacific Ocean, L alone does not create an obligation under general international law. Nonetheless, L can still create an enforceable obligation if a source can be found in a specific provision of international law. As pointed out by Judge ad hoc Daudet, invoking good faith to protect legitimate expectations is effective only when it comes with a clear legal underpinning.Footnote 90 Even if L’s obligation may not be directly enforceable under general international law, it is still a legal obligation because it results from good faith, which is a general principle of law. This is precisely why states feel they have a legal obligation even before a CIL rule exists. The obligation materialised in L is legal because it follows from the general principle of good faith. Even though the ICJ says that L is not a rule of general international law, this does not mean that L does not constitute law. If we can trace L back to a specific provision of international law (source interpretation), the obligation in L becomes enforceable under international law.

Saying that L is ‘outside’ general international law may even support the second explanation’s account of CIL. This is because this claim would match Fitzmaurice’s explanation about ‘outer rules’ being the basis for the coherence of international law:

The system of international law cannot be clothed with force by a principle that is part of the system itself; for unless the system already had force, that principle itself would have no validity, and there would be a circulus inextricabilis or viciosus.Footnote 91

If we try to solve the problem posed by the chronological paradox without using elements that are not part of international law, we might run into a problem similar to the ‘this sentence is false’ self-reference antinomy: if ‘this sentence is false’ is false, then it is true; if it is true, then it is false.Footnote 92 One way of dealing with such antinomies is to follow Tarski, who suggested separating elements into distinct, hierarchically arranged sets to prevent them from looping back on themselves.Footnote 93 Accordingly, if L lies above international law, then L is a legal rule about international law, but not of international law. This arrangement allows us to avoid the chronological paradox, because we are outside international law when adducing L. However, we are still within the law when L applies, because L is still part of a legal set. In other words, we are outside of international law but within the general framework of the law.Footnote 94

We are now in a position to understand how a CIL rule R is created according to the second explanation. Suppose that a state S1 engages in Φ and that S1’s engaging in Φ generates legitimate expectations among states S2, S3 … Sn that S1 will continue to Φ. Thus, L is applicable. If L applies, L imposes on S1 the obligation to Φ. L’s obligation is legal because it comes from the principle of good faith, a general principle of law. Now, imagine that, in addition to S1, a large group of other states also start to Φ. Their action creates legitimate expectations among the rest of the international community. L applies to each of these states, such that any state that engages in Φ is now obligated to Φ. So, M becomes applicable as states generally engage in Φ and (due to L) these states are obligated to Φ. If M applies, it creates a CIL rule R that imposes on all states the obligation to Φ.

There are two main differences between L and R. The first is that L applies only to states that are actively engaging in Φ. This means that, under L, only states that are actively engaging in Φ are obligated to Φ. Conversely, R applies to all states (not just those that are engaging in Φ). R obligates all states to Φ. In other words, L applies individually, and R applies universally. Nonetheless, an exception to R can be made for persistent objectors.Footnote 95 The ILC explains that if a state objects to a CIL rule while it is still being created, the rule does not apply to that state as long as it maintains its objection.Footnote 96 So, R does not apply to any objecting states. The exception to the exception is when R is a peremptory rule of international law (jus cogens),Footnote 97 in which case it will also apply to persistent objectors. The second difference between L and R is shown by the ICJ’s decision in the Obligation to Negotiate Access to the Pacific Ocean case. While L imposes a legal obligation to Φ, that obligation might not be enforceable within general international law. Conversely, when M applies and creates R, the obligation to Φ that R imposes is perfectly enforceable as this obligation is now sourced in (customary) international law. Because R is a CIL rule, it is fully enforceable by international courts and legal officials.

A simple illustration may help to clarify this explanation, highlighting how M, L, and R can address the chronological paradox. Let us go back to our vaccine donation example. Suppose a subgroup of wealthy states began donating vaccines to developing states during a pandemic. These wealthy states donate vaccines without any prior obligations. But these donations create legitimate expectations in developing states that vaccines will continue to be provided by wealthy states. L is thus applicable. If L applies, it imposes a legal obligation on that subgroup of wealthy states to continue donating vaccines to developing states. Because of the legal obligation imposed by L, that subgroup of wealthy states continues to donate vaccines. Suppose that an increasing number of wealthy states start to adopt this practice. Due to L’s application to each of these states, this practice becomes a general, legally obligatory practice. So, the two CIL elements (diuturnitas and opinio juris) are satisfied. M is now applicable. If M applies, a CIL Rule R is created, imposing on all wealthy states the obligation to donate vaccines to developing states. R, unlike L, is an enforceable rule of general international law.

5 Final Remarks

This chapter argued that CIL rules result from applying a constitutive metarule. A constitutive metarule is a metarule (a rule about rules) that creates another rule when applied. When the constitutive CIL metarule (which we call M) applies, it creates an individual CIL rule (referred to as R). This chapter has proposed two alternative explanations for how a belief in a legal obligation (opinio juris) can arise prior to the imposition of such an obligation by a CIL rule. In doing so, it assumes in both cases that states are correct in believing they are legally obligated. So there is not just a belief in a legal obligation; there actually is a legal obligation.

The first explanation presented the obligation as a basic social entity based directly on what states believe. Some may be satisfied with this explanation. However, others might criticise it for failing to bridge the gap between ‘is’ and ‘ought’. It could also be argued that this first explanation does not clarify how this basic social entity can impose a legal obligation. For these reasons, this chapter laid aside this first explanation and went on to develop an alternative explanation.

The second explanation addresses the chronological paradox by breaking down the creation of a new CIL rule R into three non-contradictory steps:

  • Step 1: A subgroup of states starts to act in a certain way. Their behaviour leads to legitimate expectations that they will continue acting that way. This subgroup of states is now obligated to continue acting pursuant to a rule derived from the principle of good faith (we call this rule L). However, because this obligation arises from a rule (L) outside general international law, its enforceability is questionable.

  • Step 2: The practice of this subgroup of states spreads among other states to the point where it becomes a general practice accepted as law. So, the two CIL elements – diuturnitas and opinio juris – are present. Therefore, the CIL metarule, M, is now applicable.

  • Step 3: M applies, thus creating a specific CIL rule, R. This CIL rule R imposes an obligation to act on all states except for persistent objectors (unless R is a jus cogens rule, in which case it applies even to persistent objectors).

The creation of a new CIL rule as a three-step process allows us to unravel the apparent circularity of the chronological paradox. It also allows the creation of CIL rules to be explained in such a way as not to jeopardise the coherence (and legitimacy) of (customary) international law.

Some of the claims made in this chapter might seem controversial, because it is unusual to think of CIL rules as being created through the application of a (meta)rule. We are more inclined to think that it is a matter of finding already formed CIL rules rather than creating them. But that intuition is not incompatible with the contention made in this chapter. For when we find CIL rules, we are doing more than just describing; we are giving meaning to the things being interpreted. In the case of CIL, these things are the proof of practice (diuturnitas) and belief in a legal obligation (opinio juris). We should consider the CIL metarule as an unspoken rule that operates behind the scenes. Even if its action is unannounced, this metarule helps international lawyers interpret the law to identify individual CIL rules. The point is that for lawyers in their daily work the three steps set out above occur simultaneously, giving the impression that CIL rules are paradoxical. By looking at CIL analytically, however, we have been able to pinpoint these separate steps and show that CIL is not flawed by circular reasoning.

Like the rules of chess, the CIL metarule operates in the background. When experts play chess, they do not have to keep referring to the rules and reminding themselves that, for example they are using the checkmate rule: when they look at the chessboard, they know it is checkmate. The same is true in international law, with the important difference, however, that law is an argumentative activity.Footnote 98 Unlike chess, it is not an activity where all the rules are laid down categorically. On the contrary, the law involves deploying and disputing the very rules that constitute it. Part of what it means to be a lawyer is the ability to understand and question the law itself. In this respect, one of the goals of legal philosophy is to make the implicit background rules of legal activity explicit.

3 Interpreting the Plural Sources of CIL

Harlan Grant Cohen
1 Introduction

When faced with the inevitable task of interpreting customary international law (CIL), what should a court do, and what should it consider? Should the court engage in an ‘inductive’ process of sifting through available evidence of state practice and opinio juris, or a deductive process designed to reason logically from principles embedded in the rule? Should the court invoke something like the rules of treaty interpretation with their focus on good faith, ordinary meaning, context, and object and purpose? How should it weigh available evidence of state practice, opinio juris, and prior interpretations – both its own and that of others? How concerned should the court be about fitting its interpretation into the broader corpus of international law?

This is where international law doctrine – particularly concerning sources – falls short. Figuring out how to interpret and apply custom requires a theory of custom. What is customary international law? Why is it worthy of being followed? How does custom acquire normative and legal authority? These are difficult and contentious questions we (and certainly courts) usually try to avoid.Footnote 1 The doctrine of sources does not answer them. Article 38 of the Statute of the International Court of Justice (arguably) lists the formal sources of international law – treaties, customary international law, and general principles. Its formulation ‘international custom, as evidence of a general practice accepted as law’Footnote 2 has been interpreted as implying a two-element test, requiring evidence of both state practice and opinio juris.Footnote 3 But it provides no account of why those elements would, together, create law or be deserving of normative authority. The International Law Commission (ILC) also studiously avoided these questions in its Draft Conclusions on Identification of Customary International Law.Footnote 4

This is perhaps not surprising. These theoretical questions are difficult and contentious. International actors disagree over the answers, sometimes deeply. And Article 38 and the two-element test might best be seen as an attempt to bridge such theoretical disputes. It encodes formal sources that we agree count as international law, without encoding why. Focused on method rather than theory, the doctrine provides a discursive convention – an agreed-upon framework for structuring claims about rules that is capacious enough to accommodate a range of views on where they come from. It acts as a normative compromise that allows us to operate on the basis of overlapping consensus while leaving room for a certain amount of normative pluralism. If Article 38 and the two-element test count as a rulebook,Footnote 5 it is a rulebook on how to argue.

Questions about interpretation, however, reveal the instability of this compromise. We simply cannot answer questions about how rules should be interpreted without some theory as to why certain interpretations would or would not be legitimate. And for an interpretation to be legitimate it must be able to trace its legitimacy to that of the international law source being interpreted and/or the legitimacy of the particular interpreter. Figuring out both requires looking behind the list of sources in Article 38 and asking why we treat each one as a source of normative authority. It requires us to focus on the normative stories we tell.

Such an inquiry, though, reveals that there is not just one story explaining why custom should be a source of law, but multiple stories, each legitimated in very different ways. In fact, if we started not with Article 38 but with our accounts of international law’s legitimacy, we would find, as I argue below, that what we call ‘custom’ may represent or draw from at least three different sources of law,Footnote 6 which I will refer to as ‘Negotiated Law’, ‘Legislated Law’, and ‘Adjudicated Law’.Footnote 7 Although we refer to nontreaty rules derived from each as ‘custom’,Footnote 8 they draw on different sources of legitimacy, operate according to different logics, dictate different methods of interpretation, and favour different methods for resolving disputes. Answering questions about any of those aspects of the rule thus requires us first to figure out the sort of custom we are talking about. The types of justification we start with dictate the answer to a range of other questions we might have about the rules emanating from them. And those debating how custom should be interpreted, I argue, are often arguing about different sources of law. Their disagreement is not over how custom should be interpreted, but over the ultimate authority of particular international law rules.

Some readers may bristle at the suggestion that these are distinct ‘sources’ of law. Do we really need to upend our categories of treaty, custom, and general principles? To the extent, though, that the rules seem to be emanating from entirely distinct sources of legitimacy and operating according to contradictory logics, it is hard to describe them as the same in any way other than form. As already noted, formal lip service to the features in Article 38 may play a role in anchoring discussions, but it is unlikely to capture deeper agreement about where these rules come from or what they represent.Footnote 9 These three models are meant to capture the true sources of these rules’ authority.Footnote 10 That said, even if one is unwilling to embrace the idea of plural sources of custom, recognizing that there may be different types of custom may help clarify the stakes involved in debates over interpretation and in interpretive choices.

This chapter starts in Section 2 with a reconstruction of international law’s sources built not on the forms described in Article 38 but instead on the legitimating stories we tell. Section 2 lays out three such stories and the types of law they describe. These three types of law – Negotiated Law, Legislated Law, and Adjudicated Law – each draw on distinct notions of legitimacy, follow distinct logics, and instantiate distinct values. Section 2 describes the very different notions of ‘custom’ emanating from each of these sources. Section 3 looks at each of these three new sources from the standpoint of interpretation. How are each of these sources interpreted? Section 3 explains how the justificatory story told about each of these sources flows through interpretation, requiring different approaches attentive to different concerns. Again, interpreting ‘custom’ will require very different approaches and operations depending on its ultimate source and justificatory logic. Finally, Section 4 shifts the vantage point to courts. How should courts approach the task of interpreting each of these sources? Each type of custom, this section argues, dictates not only its own interpretive rules but the specific role of the court in applying them and the weight to be given to the court’s judgments in the future. The hope is that this reconstruction of international law’s sources, including the identification of different types of custom, can put old arguments about custom and its interpretation in a new light, explain the intractability of certain fights, anchor phenomena that others have observed, and clarify the real stakes behind differing methods of interpretation.

2 Three Models of Custom

Article 38 largely describes international law’s forms – written agreements, customary practices, accepted principles. What if we defined international law’s sources instead according to their sources of legitimacy? What if we started by asking why we give international law rules normative force at all, listening more carefully to the explicit and implicit legitimating stories we tell? This section lays out three prominent stories we tell that cut across form, but for the purposes of this volume explains why nontreaty rulesFootnote 11 might carry the force of law. Each of the stories produces a different model of law – Negotiated Law, Legislated Law, and Adjudicated Law – drawing legitimacy from different sources, instantiating different values, and following its own logic.

2.1 This Argument Never Ends …

Negotiated Law, as a model, is imagined as the product of settlements hashed out over time. These are hard-fought rules, subject to back-and-forth wrangling between states that might range in form and forum from negotiations around a table to jawboning in the media to conflict on the battlefield.Footnote 12 The rules that emerge represent a form of compromise, a pragmatic accommodation of different interests. Particularly successful rules reflect a common acceptable balance between states’ freedom to take action now and the stability and predictability necessary to pursuing their interests generally.Footnote 13 But all of these rules are open-ended and tentative; they leave space for further negotiation and wrangling as circumstances and interests shift.Footnote 14 Negotiated Law, to use the words of Myres McDougal, is the product of ‘a process of continuous interaction, of continuous demand and response’.Footnote 15 Upheld by a level of consensus among states, these rules shift as that consensus shifts.

Negotiated Law might be seen as a solution to international law’s inherent fragmentation. How do we know what is expected of us and how do we guarantee that others know what we expect of them when the law’s meaning is not revealed in a document but trapped inside our respective heads?Footnote 16 We know what we think it requires, but does anyone else agree? The only way to forge common expectations and to guarantee commitment to them is to talk – a lot.Footnote 17 Actors need to constantly explain where their acts fit within the community’s rules, why their acts should be seen as conforming, why someone else’s acts fail to meet their understanding of the rule. Constant communication, through words and acts, is the structure on which the law remains elevated, the container in which it is held. Without that jostling, the law would collapse or float away into the ether.

This model of the law finds its clearest form in descriptions of ‘traditional’ custom and the ways that the iterative practice of states can slowly over time produce settlement over rules. It is a model of customary law that Gerald Postema describes as emerging from discursive normative practice.Footnote 18 It is the anti-formalist, anti-rulebook model of custom described by Monica Hakimi.Footnote 19 But this model also describes traditional bilateral treaty agreements, whose legitimacy emanates from the particulars of the negotiated deal and whose rules are interpreted in light of subsequent practice and agreement between parties.Footnote 20

Whether taking the form of traditional custom or ‘conventional’ treaties, Negotiated Law derives its purported authority from notions of consent, autonomy, pragmatism, and the lessons of experience.Footnote 21 It elevates values of flexibility and supports efforts at renegotiation. States have fought and have accepted these results. They will continue to fight and test their resiliency. Rules that emerge from this process have proven to ‘work’; rules that do not will be challenged. And the (perhaps only) theoretical ability to participate in this ongoing process of contestation and acceptance serves to legitimate the normative authority of settlements that emerge.Footnote 22 Rules are legitimated as much by the promise of future process as by the process that produced them.

2.2 But We Agreed …

But there are other stories we tell about both custom and treaties that sound far less like negotiated settlements than like forms of international legislation. In these stories, rules are propounded, proposed, and then accepted by some proportion of the community, whether by affirmative acts or by common, silent acquiescence. Rather than the iterative, open-ended, continuous process of acceptance reflected by Negotiated Law, this model assumes a moment in which a rule with particular elements is proffered, and a moment, or series of moments, in which affirmation is collected. Obviously, as with Negotiated Law, these justificatory stories are more metaphor than description.

What rules are described this way? The paradigmatic examples of international law rules described as Legislated Law are products of the ILC – both multilateral treaties, like the Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties (VCLT), and reports on custom, like the draft articles on state responsibility. As many have noticed, the particular codifications of rules in these ILC products are often treated as fixed points. After they are issued, the relevant question is how they are received. If states’ responses can generally be described positively (or at least not negatively), the rule as described by the ILC is taken as the rule of international law.Footnote 23 Only if the ILC’s efforts have failed to receive requisite acceptance (whatever that means)Footnote 24 are investigations begun into traditional custom’s elements of state practice and opinio juris.

But these stories of quasi-legislation are far more ubiquitous. Efforts at universalizing treaties have commonly been described this way, whether the Genocide Convention, the UN Charter’s rules on the use of force, or the Rome Statute’s codification of international criminal law. But key nonbinding declarations of international law rules have been described this way as well. This is, for example, how the International Court of Justice (ICJ) treats the UN General Assembly Declaration on Friendly RelationsFootnote 25 in the Nicaragua decision.Footnote 26 The Stockholm DeclarationFootnote 27 often receives similar treatment with regard to the prevention of transboundary environmental harm.Footnote 28 And sometimes customary international law, more broadly, is described and justified this way. Certainly, the way post-decolonization states were required to accept the full customary international acquis has this feel.Footnote 29 What was proffered in return for recognition was not participation in an ongoing process of jawboning and negotiation, but instead a supposedly set canon of established international law rules. But more generally, this model of Legislated Law seems implicit in how many people talk about customary international law in a modern world of 200 states. The old rough-and-tumble model, perhaps a fit for a small clique of states, seems neither practicable nor fair in this broader community. Footnote 30 Instead, proposed rules are tested by surveying reactions: where a sufficient number of states seem to have accepted the rule, it reflects custom; where a sufficient number object, the rule is rejected.

Deriving rules more from multilateral documents than from traditional state practice, Legislated Law seems to describe some of the phenomena others have described as ‘modern’ custom.Footnote 31 But Legislated Law focuses less on the normative content of the rule than on the justificatory story told. Human rights and humanitarian concerns are often described in ways that sound more like Legislated Law than Negotiated Law,Footnote 32 but they are often the rules most likely to be the subjects of universalizing treaty negotiations or attempts to declare custom. This is what these rules have in common with subjects like treaty interpretation or state responsibility, which are arguably less value-driven but seem to be derived in similar ways.

Crucially, this type of Legislated Law is a very different source from traditional notions of custom best described as Negotiated Law. Whereas Negotiated Law derives its authority from its flexible, open-ended, rough-and-tumble process and the battle-tested nature of current settlements, Legislated Law derives its authority from particular imagined moments of proposal and ratification. Whereas Negotiated Law elevates a type of specific consent associated with settlements, Legislated Law relies on a more democratic type of consent associated with voting. The open-ended, never-ending give-and-take of Negotiated Law (supposedly) promises any state the ability to participate in shaping or reshaping the rule over time; the fixed point of Legislated Law guarantees a type of majority rule, freed from the whim of powerful states. And whereas Negotiated Law celebrates flexibility and renegotiation; Legislated Law promotes the stability and predictability of recognized rules.

2.3 Use Your Best Judgment …

Finally, we have a model of Adjudicated Law. This is law produced or articulated through judicial or judicial-like decision-making. This justificatory story emphasizes the value of neutral, reasoned articulation of the rules, removed from power politics. This model comes closest to notions of common law and, like common law, looks to third-party decision-makers to fill the inevitable gaps in prior agreements and practice.Footnote 33 It imagines delegation to courts as a type of preemptive hand-tying, requiring states to live up to the principles of their agreements, even as their politics might suggest otherwise. In this model, courts are there not just to resolve disputesFootnote 34 but to apply the law. The law, not the wishes of the parties, prevails.Footnote 35

Various international courts and court-like bodies – the European Court of Human Rights, the Inter-American Court of Human Rights, the World Trade Organization Appellate Body, the UN Human Rights Committee – have told such stories about themselves to justify interpretations less deferential to state views. Some investment tribunals have as well.Footnote 36 These stories may or may not resonate with all of those bodies’ stakeholders. But Adjudicated Law also describes a range of rules that exist only in and for courts. International criminal tribunals could not rely on state practice to develop rules of mens rea or forms of liability; a type of common law articulation, attentive to commonly held principles of justice, was all that was available. International courts also need to be attentive to concerns about procedural fairness and fairness to parties, irrelevant outside the courtroom, producing procedural or evidentiary rules distinct to adjudication.

Justifying or legitimating this kind of court-made law requires recourse to different values. Adjudicated Law derives its authority from implied or explicit delegation; the authority of the decision-maker; the power of reasoned exposition; and neutral, even-handed consideration. In contrast to Negotiated Law, which emphasizes values like pragmatism, open-endedness, flexibility, and continued negotiation, Adjudicated Law emphasizes uniformity of treatment,Footnote 37 even-handedness, finality, and justice.Footnote 38

2.4 Talking With, and Yet Past, One Another …

To put it another way, in Negotiated Law authority flows from the collective results of innumerable dyads of negotiating actors, who come to settle on particular rules; in Legislated Law authority flows from common, collective will; and in Adjudicated Law authority flows from judge or court (see Table 1). Putting form aside and focusing on these justifications, it becomes clear these are really different, and in some ways irreconcilable, sources. A particular rule might be traceable to multiple potential sources, but interpreting that rule requires identifying the right one.

Table 1 Justification-based sources of international law

Negotiated LawLegislated LawAdjudicated Law
Underlying logicProduct of settlements hashed out over timeBroad (precisely how much unclear) acquiescence to some stated propositionProduct of reasoned elaboration and application by experts
JustificationSpecific consent, autonomy, pragmatic experience, flexibilityCommon consent, certainty, predictable planningDelegation, expertise, neutrality, finality, justice
ExamplesTraditional custom, bilateral treaties such as BITsArticles on State Responsibility, VCLT, Genocide ConventionRegime-specific precedents, general public international law (PIL) precedents

This is not to suggest that identifying that source is easy or obvious. We each may slip between them as we talk about a rule. And while certain rules may often be associated with one source or another, disagreements over the ultimate source of these rules are common, reflected in the types of justifications used.Footnote 39 Meant to provide common rules across a range of states and cultures, international law is deeply pluralistic, accommodating significant disagreement even over the ultimate source of the law’s authority. Such disagreements may help explain some of the most difficult and intractable fights over rules. Take, for example, fights over a potential ‘unwilling or unable’ standard for self-defense against non-state actors. Those supporting such a rule often draw from a Negotiated Law model, arguing that the rules must pragmatically respond to reality and focusing on the rules being hashed out by those taking these actions; under this model those states responding to attacks by non-state actors are a specially affected group, whose actions and interactions help define the resulting rule.Footnote 40 For many of those opposed, the argument seems derived from a Legislated Law model; looking to fixed points like the UN Charter, they question whether the ‘unwilling or unable’ standard is what was agreed on or whether, now proffered, sufficient states have accepted it.Footnote 41 Others focus on Adjudicated Law, placing heavy weight on the ICJ’s prior reasoned articulation of customary international law of self-defense;Footnote 42 for them, ignoring the ICJ’s views would violate notions of rule of law, coherence, predictability, and fairness.

Immunity presents another good example. Disagreements over whether states or officials should retain their immunity in the face of alleged international crimes seem fuelled by competing models of where those rules would come from. While a majority of the ICJ looks to state practice,Footnote 43 others look to quasi-legislative moments like Nuremberg,Footnote 44 or seek to reason from broader principles of international law.Footnote 45 These disagreements are often coded as doctrinal or interpretative, but they seem to run much deeper; those arguing over immunity are actually arguing over the ultimate source of those rules.

And while these three models do reflect different sources of international law, they are not hermetically sealed. Rules can over time be translated from one source to another – a rule developed through Negotiated Law may over time be rearticulated as a form of Legislated Law. This process is most explicit with many ILC productsFootnote 46 but may happen more implicitly as particular rules becomes canonized through repetition in declarations, judgments, and treatises.Footnote 47 As some have noted, when rules seem to become ‘established’ in this way, they take on new characteristics and are interpreted in a different way, as explained in Section 3. Alternatively, a customary international law rule developed through adjudication can become an input into the process of negotiation, its development and articulation moved out of the realm of judicial reasoning and into Negotiated Law’s ‘bid and barter’ system.Footnote 48

3 Interpretive Paths

Negotiated Law, Legislated Law, and Adjudicated Law each have their own sources of legitimacy and operate according to attendant logics. Each reflects a coherent story as to why a rule developed and operating in a particular way should carry normative authority, why it deserves to be treated as law. For interpretations of those rules to benefit from those rules’ legitimacy, they must be able to fit within those same stories. What legitimates the rule should also legitimate interpretation. This means that interpretation will look different, involving different processes and considerations, depending on the asserted source of the rule. These divergent methods of interpretation also help explain why the interpretability of custom remains so controversial: those taking opposing views may simply be focused on different sources, all unfortunately labelled ‘custom’.

3.1 Interpreting Arguments

Negotiated Law, or traditional custom, is what scholars likely have in mind when they argue that customary international law cannot be interpreted.Footnote 49 As explained in Section 2.2, Negotiated Law imagines the law as a product of a constant, never-ending discursive dance between states. Every interaction involves claims about the nature, scope, and application of the rule that may or may not be accepted by others.Footnote 50 In the Negotiated Law model, rules are constantly being made and remade through arguments and actions. Even when relatively stable, the rule is not static; whether it will change or remain the same are both determined by the arguments states have made, are making, or will make.Footnote 51 As Postema writes: ‘No one, not even the entire community, has unchallengeable, final say on what the norms of the practice are.’Footnote 52 Authoritative interpretation is an inapposite concept. Interpretations of the rule melt into the process of argumentation, becoming a ‘bid’ for what the rule is that can be accepted, modified, or rejected as states dance or wrestle (depending on the mood) over the rule.Footnote 53

This, though, does not mean that Negotiated Law is not interpreted. On the contrary, it is and must be constantly interpreted. As Orfeas Chasapis Tassinis observes, deriving rules from practices requires more than just observation.Footnote 54 It requires the ‘imposition of meaning’Footnote 55 on those observations, a process that requires theorizing and categorizingFootnote 56 – in other words, interpretation. But in Negotiated Law this theorizing goes in both directions.Footnote 57 Practices are themselves arguments, reflecting views on what rules do or should require.Footnote 58 Actors committed to being part of a rule-based community must assess how and where their actions will fit within others’ expectations of what the rules mean and require.Footnote 59 In the model of Negotiated Law, actors’ interactions are structured by their understanding of the rules. Interpretation is embedded in every action and interaction.Footnote 60

This, though, is where interpretation of Negotiated Law diverges from the more textual methods of interpretation. Negotiated Law is intersubjective. Its meaning is a function, not of a particular formulation, written or unwritten, but of the networked expectations of members of the community. The questions one must ask in interpreting the law are not ‘what does this rule mean?’ but ‘what do others think the rule is and how would others apply it to my potential conduct?’ As Postema writes ‘Caught in the net of interactions, one must know not only what others have done, but also how they understand what they have done, what they expect one to do, and so how they expect one to understand what one has done and what they have done.’Footnote 61

Nor does Negotiated Law imagine any interpretation as an end point. Instead, interpretation and action are embedded in an ongoing dance, a give-and-take over the rules. For Negotiated Law, interpretation is thus both a form of second-person thinking – a prediction of what others think the rule is – and a first-person assertion – a proffer of a desired interpretation going forward.Footnote 62

The ever forward-looking nature of this enterprise also means that interpretation is somewhat open-ended and tentative, an attempt to discern the space open for action, the negative space between prior negotiations. While actors must determine what actions are definitively forbidden, they do not need to determine the four corners of a particular rule. Quite the contrary, interpretation should foster the same values of flexibility, pragmatism, and renegotiation that the rules themselves are thought to promote. Interpreting away the rules’ frayed edges may make future negotiations more difficult.

All of this, as I will explain in Section 4 (and have explained elsewhereFootnote 63), is a difficult, perhaps impossible, task for courts, whose mandate and institutional role may conflict with the logic and legitimacy of Negotiated Law. But courts are not the paradigmatic interpreters in this model.Footnote 64 Instead, they are sometime interlopers, used more for ad hoc dispute settlement than for rule development: ‘authoritative determinations analogous to umpires’ rulings are the exception’.Footnote 65 In Negotiated Law, interpretation is part of the daily life of living in an international community, practiced in every interaction, by all members of the community.Footnote 66

3.2 Interpreting Agreement

The interpretation of Legislated Law, by contrast, comes much closer to the textual methods familiar to treaty law. Partly, this is because Legislated Law is often tied to texts – broad multilateral treaties, codification efforts, international organization declarations, judicial opinions, even treatises. Even if these are not directly binding, they nonetheless establish commonly accepted baselines that can be interpreted. But the analogy to treaties runs deeper. Legislated Law is meant to create common baselines and consensus around rules. It is meant to supersede the uncertainty and power politics of Negotiated Law/traditional custom. And it is meant to foster predictability and encourage planning. Predictability is both the point and the justification. Legislated Law is also legitimated by notions of ratification, in which states are imagined to have agreed, at least implicitly, to a specific rule. This notion of ratification, in turn, requires greater attention to what specifically was ratified.

Scholars endorsing the interpretability of custom often seem to have the model of Legislated Law in mind. It should perhaps not be surprising that many of their examples involve customary rules said to be reflected in multilateral treaties, ILC codification efforts, or declarations of international organizations. (Such efforts themselves have often been described as more legislative than contractual.Footnote 67) Panos Merkouris, for example, focuses in on the customary rules of interpretation and the ways they are interpreted in parallel with the VCLT.Footnote 68 But Legislated Law’s justificatory stories seem also to run just below the surface of these arguments, which often attempt to distinguish between the period when rules are forming and the period after they ‘come into existence’Footnote 69 or are ‘established’. It imagines identification of a rule and interpretation as separate temporal stages (even if just for the purposes of theorizing).Footnote 70 This sort of description does not fit well with notions of Negotiated Law, in which the process never ends, rules are always debatable, and complete agreement over the rule is ephemeral at best.

Whereas interpreting Negotiated Law involves prediction and thus looks to the future (how will others respond?), interpreting Legislated Law is backward-looking, requiring excavation of what actually has been agreed, with help from ordinary meaning, context, and object and purpose. Along with other applicable rules from the VCLT, interpreting Legislated Law is also a good fit for the principle of systemic integration.Footnote 71 Imagined as the product of a concerted attempt at codification, it makes sense to imagine these rules as part of a more cohesive international law fabric. It makes sense to interpret them against the backdrop of other international rules, particularly other rules imagined to be similarly established within the international community.

3.3 Interpreting Decision

Interpretation of Adjudicated Law can look somewhat similar – in part, because judges often prefer to rely on state-created, rather than judge-made, law and may try to squeeze the latter into the rhetoric of the former whenever possible.Footnote 72 But following the alternative logic and justifications of Adjudicated Law, interpretation will look somewhat different. For one, designed to resolve disputes with some finality, Adjudicated Law is specifically meant to fill gaps, rather than leave them open. This contrasts interpretation of Adjudicated Law most starkly with Negotiated Law. Negotiated Law’s open-ended interpretations are pushed aside in favour of binary ones, in which one side wins and one side loses, or one side’s view of the law is right and the other’s is wrong. But Adjudicated Law goes beyond mere dispute settlement. Adjudicated Law imagines courts playing a systemic role: Adjudicated Law should not just resolve present disputes but avoid future ones as well. This requires developing rules for prospective application: rules that states can rely on, and interpretations they can predict. But how are those gaps to be filled where the rules before them seem to run out? Adjudicated Law might be seen as a mandate, perhaps even an obligation, to find and apply broader principles of law that can fill the gaps. ‘[A]s Judge Higgins pointed out, it is “an important and well-established principle that the concept of non-liquet … is no part of the Court’s jurisprudence”.’Footnote 73

Adjudicated Law thus dovetails well with some of the instances Stefan Talmon identifies, in which the ICJ uses deduction rather than induction to discern the content of customary international law. Talmon notes the ICJ’s deduction from ‘axiomatic principles such as sovereignty, sovereign equality or territorial sovereignty’Footnote 74 in cases like the Jurisdictional Immunities of the State, or ‘general and well-recognized principles’ in cases like Corfu Channel.Footnote 75 He also observes that the ‘ICJ deduces rules from general considerations concerning the function of a person or organization’Footnote 76 in cases like Reparations for Injuries, South West Africa, and Arrest Warrants. But the logic of Adjudicated Law is visible in instances of what Talmon calls ‘assertion’ as well. In those decisions, regardless of evidence, the ICJ often justifies its interpretation on assertions of common knowledge.Footnote 77

Courts also derive some of their authority to apply these rules from their respect for procedural and substantive fairness. They draw legitimacy from their ability to treat parties equally before the law and from their promise to treat like cases alike. These become especially weighty in international criminal law contexts, in which fairness and due process become matters of human rights. Predictability, for example, merges with the legality principle of nullum crimen sine lege. All of this creates incentive and pressure for courts to look to their own prior judgments and to adopt some notion of precedent.Footnote 78 Whatever pressure they feel to have their decisions cohere with the broader corpus of international law will face countervailing pressure to guarantee that their current interpretation coheres with their own prior interpretations.

At the same time, as Adjudicated Law relies on explicit or implicit delegation for its legitimacy, judges will also have to be attentive to their specific mandate in interpreting the rules. When they understand their mandate broadly as international courts within an international legal system, treating like cases alike may point to the work of other courts interpreting similar rules. When they understand their mandate more narrowly as extending only to a specific regime, they may feel pressure to hew closely to their own decisions even where courts outside the regime have decided differently.

In sum, though, the interpretative process of adjudicative law will focus much more on reasoned gap-filling and court-specific predictability. Adjudicated Law should make it easier for actors to know what to expect, both to avoid the courtroom and once inside it.

4 The Quandary of Courts

Negotiated Law, Legislated Law, and Adjudicated Law are thus best seen as distinct sources, with their own legitimating logics, favoring different interpretive techniques. These differences highlight the problem for courts of interpreting custom (or really any source of international law). Although ostensibly focused on one formal source in Article 38 – custom – courts are faced with a choice between divergent paths, a fork in the road, that will dictate the factors they should consider and the weight they should give them. These choices can be stark, resulting in contradictory interpretations of what custom requires. As such, courts need a theory, whether explicit or implicit, of what ‘custom’ is and where it comes from before they can interpret any particular rule before them.

The challenge for courts can be illustrated well by the problem of coherence. We might want courts to worry about coherence,Footnote 79 but coherence with what? The different possible sources described here – Negotiated Law, Legislated Law, and Adjudicated Law – point to different concepts of coherence favoring different outcomes in specific cases. Here, we can go in the opposite order, moving from the source easiest for courts to interpret to the hardest.

Courts will have the easiest time with Adjudicated Law. Adjudicated Law maps what courts do (or at least imagine themselves doing) well: asking judges (or other decision-makers) to resolve arguments about the meaning and requirements of the law by reasoning their way to definitive answers. It leans on their (perceived) instincts, talents, and expertise.

For the court engaged with Adjudicated Law, the demands of coherence will point first and foremost to what might be called ‘courtroom coherence’. Courts working within an Adjudicated Law model need to worry that like cases be treated alike and that litigants be able to predict the rules that will apply to them. These are core factors legitimating a court’s authority to explicate and develop legal rules, which only become heightened in international criminal cases where they may merge with human rights and due process. Courtroom coherence grows out of the model’s emphasis on legitimacy of reasoning and expertise. Both of those would be undercut if rules were interpreted differently in each case: if the court’s legal reasoning is so solid, why can it not convince itself? If the court is so expert in the law, why does it have so much trouble finding the right rule? But courtroom coherence also draws from Adjudicated Law’s emphasis on justice and binary choices of right and wrong, winner and loser. It becomes much harder to argue that one answer is the just one in any given case if that answer’s justice seems so unclear over time.Footnote 80

In sum, Adjudicated Law’s emphasis on courtroom coherence and the expectations of litigants before them should lead courts to favour interpretations concordant with their own prior rulings, to follow a form of precedent, even at the expense of developments elsewhere in international law or renegotiation or clarification by states. When investment tribunals do just this, rightly or wrongly, Adjudicated Law seems to be the model they have in mind.

Legislated Law, drawing on a story of ratification, common understanding, and the demands of cooperation and planning, also favour the coherence that comes from predictable rules. Focused, though, on the quasi-legislative nature of international agreement, Legislated Law will favour transsubstantive, transforum predictability – the coherence of systemic integration. Legislated Law is meant to avoid the uncertainty of Negotiated Law and the ex-post justice of Adjudicated Law by creating clear frameworks for action that can be interpreted in common ways with as little friction between them as possible. Legislated Law values coordination over conflict, settled rules over settlement. Fragmentation undercuts these goals and may even seem illegitimate. A court placing its own precedent ahead of the will of the international community becomes a judicial despot. Legislated Law will thus favour common rules for all, accepted by all, which can integrate rules across courts and regimes into a single doctrine of international law.

In a vacuum then, courts applying Legislated Law would still be expected to hew to prior rulings. But that expectation would be based on the assumption that the court was correct in its prior interpretation, not on notions of litigant fairness. A single court’s interpretation should remain revisable in the face of evidence of other courts having arrived at a different interpretation or in light of developments elsewhere in international law. Legislated Law argues in favour of transjudicial dialogue and drawing from one set of rules to another, whether environmental law into trade or human rights into humanitarian law.

Negotiated Law presents the most difficult problems for courts. As noted in Sections 2.3 and 2.4, the logics of Negotiated Law and of courts are in some opposition.Footnote 81 Courts are asked to decide in favour of one party or another, to decide that one actor was right and the other was wrong; Negotiated Law prefers negotiated settlements that leave room for future negotiation and wrangling. Courts are asked to provide justice; Negotiated Law is looked to provide a modicum of peace. Courts lean on delegated responsibility to the law; Negotiated Law leans on the autonomy of parties to order their affairs. To some extent, courts are faced with a problem like Heisenberg’s: deciding a case based on Negotiated Law risks transforming it, giving its rules a level of certainty that wrangling within that model would not have produced.

If courts are to be attentive to Negotiated Law, if they believe that Negotiated Law is the true source of the rules before them, then they must be very careful not to overstep their role. Courts should be minimalist in their decision-making and treat their decisions as ad hoc and revisable. They should revisit state practice in each new case regarding the rule at issue to see whether their prior interpretation has been vindicated or rejected.Footnote 82 Here, the coherence sought is negotiating-table coherence. The goal for courts interpreting Negotiated Law is to maintain states’ expectations about the shape of the negotiating space, about what has been negotiated and what has not. A court should not be able, like an interloper, to stick its nose in ongoing negotiations (which in this model are all the time and endemic) and throw things in favour of one side or another.

An analog to these problematic, divergent choices can be seen in the WTO Dispute Settlement Understanding (DSU). While largely a matter of treaty interpretation, the problem is the same. DSU 3.2 provides that:

The dispute settlement system of the WTO is a central element in providing security and predictability to the multilateral trading system. The Members recognize that it serves to preserve the rights and obligations of Members under the covered agreements, and to clarify the existing provisions of those agreements in accordance with customary rules of interpretation of public international law. Recommendations and rulings of the DSB [Dispute Settlement Body] cannot add to or diminish the rights and obligations provided in the covered agreements.Footnote 83

In other words, WTO panels and the Appellate Body should stick to negotiated agreements, and only those agreements, but provide security and predictability (a justification for precedent), all while taking account of customary rules of interpretation of public international law, which of course might require looking at other, external agreements and general international law.Footnote 84 The impossibility and incompatibility of doing all of those at the same time is evident in the Appellate Body’s attempts to interpret rules regarding antidumping duties and zeroing, where the Appellate Body, seeking courtroom predictability, adopted a doctrine of precedent, policed by a cogent reasons standard.Footnote 85 Simple, the Appellate Body thought, we will apply the same zeroing rule regardless of plaintiff and regardless of defendant. But to the United States, this position regarding both the rule and the Appellate Body’s authority was simply wrong. In response, the United States declared war on the body, drawing on a Negotiated Law model to argue that zeroing was a gap in the agreements purposely left for future negotiation and explicitly questioning the Appellate Body’s authority to fill it.Footnote 86

Fair and equitable treatment in investment law provides another example. Faced with a question about the scope and meaning of the concept,Footnote 87 an arbitral panel is left with a series of choices:Footnote 88 if it wants to be true to the Negotiated Law model, it will adopt a minimalist view of role and precedent, see its interpretations as mere proffers, and be extraordinarily attentive to state responses to these decisions, including attempts to renegotiate bilateral investment treaties. This, though, would come at the cost of doctrinal coherence or courtroom coherence. If the panel instead worries most about its authority as court-like tribunal and about courtroom coherence, it will strive to treat like cases alike and stick to its own precedent, potentially at the cost of both systemic integration and negotiating space. If, though, the panel is concerned about systemic or doctrinal coherence, it might eschew the consistency of its own opinions in favour of looking to jurisprudence constante or acquis, or even beyond to foster systemic integration by looking to rules about the environment, human rights, and sovereignty. In this case, the panel could rely neither on Negotiated Law bases of legitimacy nor on its delegated authority. Instead, it would have to rely on the authority of the international community. Systemic integration might be achieved, but only at the cost of treating like cases alike, respecting specific negotiated deals, and respecting space for future deals (see Table 2).

Table 2 Justification-based sources of international law: summary

Negotiated LawLegislated LawAdjudicated Law
Underlying logicProduct of settlements hashed out over timeBroad (precisely how much unclear) acquiescence to some stated propositionProduct of reasoned elaboration and application by experts
JustificationSpecific consent, autonomy, pragmatic experience, flexibilityCommon consent, certainty, predictable planningDelegation, expertise, neutrality, finality, justice
ExamplesTraditional custom, bilateral treaties such as BITSArticles on State Responsibility, VCLT, Genocide ConventionRegime-specific precedents, general PIL precedents
Coherence?Negotiating table coherence, predictability of negotiating spaceDoctrinal coherence, transsubstantive and transforum predictability, common rules for allCourtroom coherence, treating like cases alike

Coherence, ironically, thus represents a fragmented choice. Different courts will take different views on these issues, but these decisions are always contested and contestable. What is often only recognized by critics, though, is that these choices are foundationally not about coherence or methods of interpretation, but about justifications of authority. Even if only implicit, the legitimating source of a rule must be identified before the proper interpretative tools can be deployed.

5 Conclusion

Debates over the proper interpretation of customary international law reveal the limits of doctrinal consensus. Methods of interpretation draw on the authority of the particular interpreter and the authority of the rules being interpreted. As such, the choice of methods must be sensitive to our accounts of each. But surfacing those accounts by teasing out the stories we tell to justify customary international law rules reveals the deep theoretical disagreements buried beneath our doctrine of sources. Multiple, competing, perhaps even contradictory concepts of customary international law are in common use; what we call ‘custom’ might emanate from any of those sources of authority. It is no wonder that we disagree on how to interpret it. Interpretive debates reflect the varied sources we have agreed to group under the label of ‘custom’ and the deep normative pluralism undergirding the agreed formal sources of international law. Competing justificatory accounts of customary international law that formal doctrine seeks to ignore resurface in these debates. Interpretation becomes the battleground on which our justificatory accounts of custom are forced into combat.

4 Interpretation Dynamics in CIL An Entropic Approach

Eleni Micha

A throw of the dice never, even when truly cast in the eternal circumstance of a shipwreck’s depth, will abolish chance.

Stéphane Mallarmé, French poet, 1842–98

The tossing of a dice – the symbol of chance, uncertainty and unpredictability. Jiří Kylián, Czech former dancer and choreographer, b. 1947

1 Uncertainty and Change: The Dynamic Character of CIL

The uncertain character of CIL has been discussed time and time again among academics and practitioners. To most of them, the uncertain character of CIL entails a twofold defect: first, uncertainty is perceived with respect to the identification of the rule, since we may not know whether there is a valid legal rule,Footnote 1 and second, uncertainty is perceived with respect to the content of the rule, since we may not know the precise meaning of the rule.Footnote 2

Thus, uncertainty is viewed as the basic reason for the lack of coherence and consistency attributed to CIL rules. In turn, it is argued that uncertainty is a doctrinal issue discussed among scholars but not among judges. However, judges will inevitably deal with uncertainty, even indirectly, when they have to assess the meaning of the rule to apply in the case at hand. Uncertainty will in this respect lead to unpredictability (and, consequently, even greater uncertainty) when different legal meanings taken from a range of probabilities are assigned to a CIL rule. But if uncertainty is taken to mean ambiguity – i.e. different interpretive approaches to an applicable rule – then, by induction, there can be no evolution of CIL, which leads to rigidity and denial of change. Yet, not only is such an inference irrational but it does not even correspond to existing judicial practice.Footnote 3 Therefore – and to hark back to H. L. A. Hart once againFootnote 4 – the quest for certainty is of vital importance in attempting to soften the shadows of uncertainty.

At the same time, uncertainty in terms of unpredictability, although seen as a ‘necessary evil’ by its discussants, ought to be avoided in order to strengthen state compliance with judicial rulings.Footnote 5 Understandably, therefore, both practitioners and scholars, albeit through different paths, have tried and are still struggling to manage uncertainty in international law in order to better apprehend the nature of CIL and how it functions.Footnote 6 To this end and inasmuch as uncertainty cannot be eliminated, it can be argued that ‘reduced’ uncertainty is preferable as the ‘lesser of two evils’.Footnote 7

Vital questions also arise regarding the way CIL develops. One such question is, how does interpretation of CIL rules functions in a complex environment with a multiplicity of actors generating ‘polycentric disputes’,Footnote 8 if indeed the interpretation process applies to CIL at all? And where international courts interpret CIL, what kind of change can be expected with respect to the application of CIL? Is there a ‘spontaneous’ change like a Grotian moment,Footnote 9 or a slow-developing process that rarely leads to change in CIL rules? And is it likely to contribute to the progressive development of CIL or to its decline?

Providing answers to these questions is of crucial importance to understanding the proper function of CIL, given that uncertainty is a fact of life, and as such characteristic of the international legal system, too. Yet, what seems to be missing from the entire discourse on uncertainty is a focus on how CIL functions. Although a number of theories have been formulated, extensively discussed, and even strongly debated,Footnote 10 there are no persuasive answers that would explain when and how changes in CIL occur, the significance of CIL inertia in resisting these changes, and the effects these changes may produce with respect to a certain time and place. In other words, the dynamics of CIL, as the driving force behind its evolution, remain essentially unexplored.Footnote 11

Providing answers to these questions requires in-depth understanding not only of the structure of CIL but also of the processes that occur in and out of CIL during its operation as a social system. In this respect, the discussion on uncertainty is closely connected to the complexity of the law. When lawyers refer to the complex nature of legal problems, they are pointing out not only the density of the legislation and its lack of simplicity but also the difficulty of understanding the meaning of the law. Thus, issues of indeterminacy, uncertainty and, often, unpredictability arise when multiple meanings become available through interpretation of the law.

The present chapter is divided into four parts. Section 2 focuses on the dynamic character of CIL and what dynamic complexity entails for the system of CIL. In Section 3 we discuss how complexity science may throw light on the functioning of CIL and explore CIL’s construction as a social system. In Section 4 we demonstrate the force that sets the CIL system in motion and gives it its dynamic character: this section attempts to construct a physically based representation of the interpretation process in the CIL system. Since the present analysis regards interpretation of CIL as a process, we introduce the concept of entropy, a fundamental concept of nature, to explain the functioning of CIL as a complex social system. In Section 5, focussing on the interpretative authority of international criminal courts, we will uncover the various phases of the interpretation process followed by those courts in their case law. The analysis will, thus, adopt an entropic approach to interpretation in order to explain the progressive development of CIL.

2 The Theoretical Foundations of CIL’s Dynamic Character: A Study in Physics

It has been rightly maintained that complex laws are the inevitable price of human society that is itself complex.Footnote 12 But what exactly is complexity in relation to CIL, and why is it something we only acknowledge ‘when we see it’?Footnote 13

To begin with, complexity concerns the dynamic expression of a whole – that is, a system comprising a hierarchy of multiple interacting components. As described in the natural sciences, complexity usually implies the existence of a hierarchical, multi-component system in which each component is networked and interacts with a multiplicity of other components at all hierarchical levels. Accordingly, complexity includes a process that distributes/re-distributes energy throughout the system; owing to the multiplicity of local and remote connections at all levels, this causes the system to evolve in an apparently simple but formally unpredictable manner.Footnote 14 In other words, the multiplicity of actors and the large number of issues generated between them are the main characteristics of a complex system. The prime example of such a ‘polycentric situation’ is a human society,: it involves a great number of interacting social forces that create various network structures, which in turn interact with their environment. Such a scheme is prone to change in order to adapt to new realities, especially when the existing law cannot address them.

The present analysis looks at CIL as the outcome of social processing within a constantly evolving international milieu, as originally perceived by G. Scelle.Footnote 15 It will show that this dynamic character of CIL is inherent to its social identity, since complexity serves as a frame of reference for CIL. Thus, CIL is not considered as a self-referential system, but a communicative, flexible and adaptive network analogous to physical systems.Footnote 16 In turn, interpretation, as the main function of the judiciary, will be treated as an internal property of the CIL system that initiates changes according to the particular circumstances of each individual case. In this context, interpretation plays a cardinal role in ensuring legal security.Footnote 17 Such an approach cannot of course confer on CIL the consistency and coherence it is alleged to lack, but it can explain how legal interpretation works in a complex social environment like that of CIL.

Such an approach to CIL may raise objections. Pre-emptively addressing these provides an opportunity to make a number of clarifications and further delimit the scope of the present analysis. To begin with, there is no doubt that the transfer of concepts and definitions from one discipline to another is subject to many risks. One example is the possible misinterpretation of the phenomenological basis and semantics of concepts deriving from different scientific areas. This would undermine a common effort to ask the right questions and seek the proper answers: the interpretative tools of different disciplines are by nature distinct and those of one may not fully apply, or be transposable, to the conceptual constructs of another. By way of illustration, a deterministic approach to the law does not fully correspond to how determinism functions in physics. Determinism in the natural sciences implies exact knowledge, a mathematical description of natural processes. Complicated, multiparametric physical systems involving interdependent physical processes subject to different random effects may evolve in totally unpredictable ways depending on the initial conditions.Footnote 18 Prime examples of such chaotic systems are the weather, the geomagnetic field and celestial dynamics. By contrast, the law associates determinism with strict predictability through causation; in other words, an event is causally determined if, and only if, a set of prior events has taken place. Accordingly, the law ‘argues’ that future events can be predicted with reference to prior events. The assessment of CIL is a mirror image of this construction.

If, on the other hand, we oversimplify the way things work, we tend to underestimate the complexity of both nature and society and risk producing unwarranted assumptions that do not correspond to reality – an outcome that often occurs to the detriment of both disciplines.Footnote 19 Trying to find all the answers to the questions presented is a most ambitious undertaking that cannot be realized within the restricted limits of the present chapter. Instead, our analysis will merely try to define a basis for elaborating a functional model to explain how judicial interpretation of CIL works as the main force for the motion and, accordingly, the development of CIL. The ensuing analysis will further explore the mechanics of CIL by placing a special focus on international criminal justice.

The findings of international criminal courts and tribunals are of interest mainly due to the strong ties that international criminal law maintains with CIL. As one of the sources of international criminal law, CIL has been applied not only to fill gaps in the characterization of ‘criminal conduct’ as a war crime or a crime against humanity, but also to introduce new crimes for future mass atrocities that allegedly contravene the principle of legality. In this regard, much attention has been given to the case law of the ICTY – in contrast to the ICC, whose statutory foundations in the Rome Statute has had the effect of reducing the role of CIL, since the latter constitutes a secondary source of law for the ICC.Footnote 20 This is not to say that CIL has lost its importance; instead, it functions as both a source of international criminal law (ICL) and an interpretative instrument for the purpose of clarifying or filling gaps in the text of the Rome Statute, which ‘is not in all aspects an authoritative account of the current state of the law’.Footnote 21 For there is persistent debate over possible breaches of the legality principle,Footnote 22 which creates even more uncertainty than that which interpretation of the relevant CIL rules seeks to remove.

3 CIL as a Complex Social System: The Shared Understanding of CIL

As the outcome of ‘social constraint’,Footnote 23 CIL is distinguished by its diversity and adaptability to a constantly changing societal environment, thus reflecting the maxim ubi societas, ibi jus. It is this dynamic character of CIL that makes it a complex system and, in particular, a complex social system.

The idea of explaining societal functions and interconnections in terms of complexity has its roots in systems theory as proposed by Talcott Parsons in the 1950s and much later by Niklas Luhmann at the beginning of the 1990s. Concurrently, system dynamics was introduced by Jay Forrester in the mid1950s as an aspect of systems theory, though in a different setting. Whereas Luhmann held that social systems, including the law, are closed ones tending to (re)produce themselves, Forrester, an engineer, introduced a methodology and a mathematical model for understanding and solving complex problems, initially in the corporate domain but later also in non-corporate areas where the focus was on the world’s socioeconomic system.Footnote 24 Notwithstanding the influence of Luhmann’s theory on the law, the author of the present study argues that CIL is an open system whose interacting elements also interact with its environment.Footnote 25

In short, complexity theory as developed to explain social behaviour rests upon the findings of sociology, which viewed societal institutions as autopoietic, dynamic and chaotic. However, the concept of complexity originated in the physical sciences is not defined, as sociologists or lawyers would expect, according to their normative background. As a result, the concept of complexity is often confused with the concept of complicatedness. A complicated system is one made of an intricate arrangement of many individual components and can be understood by explaining the function of each of its constituent parts. On the other hand, complexity concerns the dynamic, evolutionary behaviour of a system and is manifested by dynamically emergent properties that arise from interactions between its constituent parts; complex systems can be understood only by interpreting the multiple interactions between their multiple components.Footnote 26 Besides, the exchange of energy within and through a system’s boundaries is of critical importance in comprehending the functioning of open complex systems. Accordingly, ‘complexity’ refers to the capacity of a ‘living’, dynamic system to change, adapt and evolve and should not be confused with complicatedness, which refers to a collection of discrete elements that can be de-assembled and re-assembled. Thus, a complicated problem is usually difficult to solve, although it may be simple in its structure, whereas a complex problem may be understood by studying how the whole system operates.Footnote 27

Therefore, to consider CIL a complex system is to acknowledge that human society is part of nature and functions in compliance with its fundamental laws. As pointed out in Section 2, the construction of an adequate model of CIL is essential to understanding how complexity works in this area of international law. To be functional, such a model must be representative of the society it simulates or, in mathematical terms, be isomorphic to the physical setting of CIL. To clarify, isomorphic models are not identical to the entities they represent; instead, they are structured in such a way as to preserve the arrangements and binary relationships between the elements of those entities. Let us give an illustration from elementary algebra: adding together two numbers and then multiplying the sum by a third number gives the same result as multiplying each natural number by the same third number and then adding together the products (distributive property); so these sets of numbers are isomorphic, since one set can be mapped onto the other set of numbers.Footnote 28 In the present analysis, isomorphism can aptly represent the two-way relationships developed between the elements of the ‘complex CIL system’. Accordingly, and for the purposes of this study, the CIL model will comprise a network of multiple, connected (interacting) states, each engaged in two-way, one-to-one interaction with international criminal tribunals.Footnote 29

At this point, it is necessary to clarify that the current CIL social order is shaped by various actors, both state and non-state, operating at the international or transnational level. International and regional organizations, general or specialized, play a significant role in building the ‘practice’ endorsed by states; armed groups originating from various environments contribute to building ‘practice’, often through their involvement in conducting military operations; judicial institutions even forge state practice through compliance mechanisms.Footnote 30

An illustration of the diversity of actors who join other actors in the field of CIL can be found in the recent Ongwen case before the ICC.Footnote 31 The ICC stressed that human communities shape their own concept of property according to their customary rules and principles. For the ICC, the content of such ‘communal property’ must be taken into account when considering the material element (actus reus) of ownership in relation to the war crime of pillaging within the context of a non-international armed conflict.Footnote 32

Such a kaleidoscope of actors renders the system of CIL even more complex, adding components and interactions that call for further study in respect of their input and output. The diversity of actors may also lead to the emergence of multiple clusters;Footnote 33 new relationships will arise between the agents of the system, and the feedback the agents receive from one another but also from their environment will probably lead to new processes and patterns of behaviour. This two-way feedback will reflect shared or opposing views of the law.Footnote 34 Such movement entails exchange of energy between the various components of the system and may influence its evolution. Yet, one thing is certain: a complex CIL system is dynamic, since it can change in response to changing circumstances over time.

The United Kingdom’s position on air strikes in Syria in 2013 and 2018 is illustrative of the interactions between the diverse actors within the complex CIL system and between CIL and its environment, since it reveals how CIL is assessed and functions. In deciding to join with the United States and France in their efforts to reduce Syria’s chemical weapons capability, the UK Department of Defence argued in favour of a right to humanitarian intervention as the legal basis for its actions.Footnote 35 It is significant to note that in 2013 the UK did not take part in the air strikes since the British parliament rejected the government’s motion for intervention. In both 2013 and 2018, however, the UK tried to establish a general doctrine of intervention applicable in situations of humanitarian necessity and to give the doctrine the force of customary law.

What is significant here is the reaction of several states to the UK’s position on the right of humanitarian intervention. Those actors and the various interactions between them and the UK form a cluster (often ephemeral) within the CIL system. Systems do not function in a vacuum, but operate within a specific environment which affects them through the exchange and redistribution of energy. In a complex legal system, like that of CIL, the flow of information regarding the meaning of the law is defined to be the energy source of the system (see Section 4).

The UK’s complex system lies within the environment of the United Nations; that environment affects the UK through the UN Security Council’s decision on air strikes against Syria.Footnote 36 Although the air strikes were not qualified as an act of aggression, it seems that there was no agreement with the UK as to the customary law status of humanitarian intervention, since no state referred directly to a right of humanitarian intervention in accord with the UK’s reasoning.Footnote 37 It is interesting to note that the states which rejected the proposal by the Russian Federation to condemn the air strikes – eight out of fifteen – did not openly disagree with the UK on the need to alleviate humanitarian suffering nor on the need to ensure compliance with the prohibition on the manufacture and use of chemical weapons. The absence of such feedback could signify that a shared understanding on the content of humanitarian intervention by the states was wanting.

The principal characteristic of the complex environment of CIL is the diversity of the components’ internal activity, explained by the fact that they possess a considerable degree of freedom:Footnote 38 it is the discretionary power of the judiciary that confers such diversity on the agents of the system. Under the influence of Hersch Lauterpacht, the International Criminal Court underlined that the ‘constant presence of judicial discretion in matters of customary international law [entails] the “constant necessity of making a choice … between conflicting and equally legitimate principles of interpretation”’.Footnote 39 In the context of an international organization (the UN in the UK example), the multiple interactions between states and other actors even accelerate the process of international standard-setting. In this respect, the UK example mirrors the model of an open system that can adapt to changing circumstances thanks to the degrees of freedom that its agents possess. In turn, when making choices, international courts cannot ignore the statements made by state leaders – nor their silence – within an international organization; thus, the courts can adapt to the developing needs of the international community.Footnote 40

Accordingly, there may be a two-level complexity in the structure of a CIL system, with a number of complex CIL sub-systems operating within the main system (see Figures 1 and 2).

Figure 1 A one-to-one, binary relationship

Figure 2 Security Council draft resolution proposed by the Russian Federation

The result is a network, in which a broad array of interactions link the system’s various actors, the nodes of the system.Footnote 41 Therefore, understanding the binary relationships between states and international courts as a one-to-one correspondence constitutes the first crucial step in explaining the function of CIL as a complex system, and in turn its dynamic character.

4 The Mechanics of CIL: A Manifestation of Entropy

Having designed our CIL complex system with its basic units and interacting constituent parts (states, international courts, international organizations and other non-state actors as agents), we shall now proceed to explore the forces that cause it to react and stimulate its evolution. We will refer to these dynamic processes as the ‘mechanics’ of CIL and its ‘laws of motion’.Footnote 42 It is the relationship between the force that excites a system and the motion it causes that defines the dynamic response of the system, causing it to change, if necessary adapt and subsequently evolve.Footnote 43 This is true of the CIL system, which is prone to change, to adapt whenever required and, therefore, to evolve. In this respect, the CIL is not a deterministic system. This fundamental characteristic of CIL constitutes both its strength and its weakness, since unpredictability is the offspring of change, whereas predictability – or, better, foreseeability – is an essential requirement of our legal universe.Footnote 44

In order to account for these conflicting characteristics, we will have recourse to the concept of entropy as applied by information theory. Rooted in the field of thermodynamics and statistical mechanics, information entropy is the measure of the number of possible ways in which information is distributed in a system. A neologism derived from Greek, the term and concept of entropy was introduced by Rudolf Clausius in the mid nineteenth centuryFootnote 45 to describe a thermodynamic property of all physical systems. To the German physicist, entropy was related to transformation and change, since thermodynamics deals with the exchange of energy between different physical systems and the work done during this process.Footnote 46

The melting of an ice cube is the classic illustration of what entropy is, given that heat is a form of energy corresponding to a definite amount of mechanical work: when heated, ice turns into water, leading to higher internal energy (entropy) as the molecules have more freedom to move around in the liquid than in the ice cube’s solid state. For the liquid to revert back to a solid state, thermal energy must be removed and the new ice cube will not be the same as the old one. Thus changes are irreversible.

In turn, this led to the ‘second law of thermodynamics’, which is one of the most fundamental axioms of nature and essentially states that entropy cannot decrease. Later, Ludwig Boltzmann linked entropy with probability in relation to the thermal motion of particles in systems with large numbers of agents (like gases composed of large numbers of molecules), thus introducing the discipline of statistical mechanics.Footnote 47 In other words, the second law of thermodynamics is explained as the system’s tendency towards more probable states. Consequently, entropy tends to maximize when the internal thermal energy is evenly distributed among the agents of a system – that is, when all probabilities (expectations) tend to be the same and no energy can be extracted from the system.

Information entropy offers an analogous definition: here, entropy is the measure of the amount of uncertainty represented by the probability distribution of unavailable information in a system.Footnote 48 The entropic state of a physical or informational system cannot be reversed unless an outside force removes internal energy from the system, but that will always be at the expense of increasing entropy elsewhere and in the Universe at large. Consequently, entropy is the sum of the probabilities of all possible microstates (configurations) of a physical or informational system.Footnote 49

As already explained, entropy defines the thermodynamic state of a physical system, which may be reversible or irreversible depending on the ability of the system to exchange energy with its environment (i.e. with other systems).Footnote 50 In closed/isolated systems that cannot exchange energy with their environment, entropy is irreversible; although it cannot decrease, entropy can remain constant, in which case the system is said to rest in thermodynamic equilibrium.Footnote 51 In short, isolated systems are incapable of changing and, thus, evolving. If a system is not isolated and can exchange energy with its environment, then it cannot remain in equilibrium and must evolve. Human societal constructs are by nature open systems, as they are embedded in, and continuously interact with, other human societal constructs: their internal energy is subject to continuous redistribution, putting them in a state of perpetual non-equilibrium resulting in continuous change and evolution.

The definition of entropy in statistical mechanics is, to all intents and purposes, identical to that introduced by Claude Shannon in information theory/communication science in 1948.Footnote 52 It applies to social systems, and most certainly to legal network systems such as CIL. There, the exchange of information assumes the role of the exchange of energy in inducing excitation and response of the system. In non-technical parlance, Shannon entropy quantifies the expected value of information in a message:Footnote 53 the more information is transmitted/received, the less uncertainty results and the less information entropy in the system, causing the possible outcomes of the exchange of information to be highly predictable. Flipping coins or rolling dice provide characteristic examples of measurable Shannon entropy – namely, the difference between the information contained in the message and the part of information provided by the message (i.e. the coin or the dice). Before we flip a coin, we are uncertain about what will happen when it is flipped. After the coin is flipped, the uncertainty immediately drops to zero since we now know the response (i.e. heads or tails). This, in turn, means that we have gained information on the content of the message. As a measure of uncertainty of a random variable, this definition of entropy is probabilistic in nature; accordingly, the information exchanged is a measure of that entropy’s reduction.Footnote 54

Transposing this fundamental physical process to CIL allows us to make some very interesting observations. The CIL system’s elements – namely, states and courts – exchange information regarding the meaning of CIL; states respond through their practice and courts by interpreting rules. The greater the number of probable meanings assigned to the rules in question, the greater the entropy of the CIL system; conversely, when there are fewer probable meanings, there is less uncertainty as to the content of the rule and thus minimal entropy. To this end, legal interpretation plays a fundamental role in reducing the entropy of the CIL system by providing the information that was originally not available (i.e. the concrete meaning of the CIL rule). In particular, the exchange of information about the most probable, or even precise, content of a CIL rule creates a network of binary relations between the courts that transmit the message contained in the information and the states that receive it. When international courts like the ICC form binary relations with states, this creates a one-to-one connection between them, since they are the sole components of the complex CIL system concerned.Footnote 55 The transmission of the precise content of a CIL rule to states by international courts through the interpretation process shapes the connections between the courts and the states, for courts receive feedback from the states, regardless of whether the states comply with the court’s judgment.

Having said this, the analysis will now focus in Section 5 on what we call an entropic approach to the interpretation of CIL and how it is reflected in the jurisprudence of the ICC and other international criminal tribunals.

5 Modelling the Interpretation of CIL: What Do International (Criminal) Courts Say?

Traditionally, the function of the judicial power – that is, courts and tribunals stricto sensu – is to state the law (i.e. not only to decide which legal rules are applicable but also to determine their content in a concrete case).Footnote 56 The legal reasoning that unfolds during the process of interpreting a CIL rule has a concretizing function (i.e. to give a concrete meaning to a CIL rule, the content of which is by definition general).Footnote 57 Legal interpretation is an exercise akin to the solving of a mathematical problem; when judges seek to determine the content of a rule in a particular case, they apply their skills to solve the problem by either settling the dispute or establishing the guilt of an accused individual.

In the case of CIL interpretation, courts determine the content of a rule by searching for states’ shared understanding of the rule. Such was the approach taken by the International Criminal Court when its Appeals Chamber dealt with the thorny issue of immunity for heads of state having committed international crimes under the Rome Statute in Sudan. As Judges Eboe-Osuji, Morrison, Hofmanski and Bossa in their concurring opinion openly stated, ‘the consistent and repeated rejection of immunity (even for Heads of State) in sundry instruments of international law since World War II … has resulted in a general understanding of customary international law in that way’.Footnote 58

Yet, interpreting CIL rules in a criminal law context runs the grave risk of overstepping the principle of legality, which is one of the basic pillars of international criminal justice. Since international criminal courts are not permitted to ‘expand uncritically the scope of [international] crimes’,Footnote 59 they are confronted with a challenge when called upon to determine the content of a CIL rule with a view to characterizing it as a core international crime.

In the Kupreskic case, the ICTY adopted an interpretation with interesting reasoning when, following extensive analysis, it defined the content of the residual category of ‘inhumane acts’ as crimes against humanity.Footnote 60 Based on the notion of ‘humane treatment’ included in Common Article 3 of the Geneva Conventions 1949 and international human rights standards, the ICTY ruled that it is possible to ‘identify a set of basic human rights’ whose violation could amount to a crime against humanity. Bearing in mind that Common Article 3 had already been recognized as having erga omnes effect and that basic rules protecting human rights have the force of customary law, the ICTY defined the notion of inhumane act as a rule having ‘less broad’ customary law content.Footnote 61 The flexibility with which the ICTY handled the issue of CIL interpretation is particularly revealing, albeit not always plain to see. The case of Krstic is also indicative, since the ICTY recognized the concretizing function of CIL, which had delimited the actus reus of the crime of genocide so as to include only acts of physical destruction, a limitation accepted both by the ICTY and the ICTR in their respective statutes.Footnote 62

Most significantly, the Appeals Chamber of the International Criminal Court followed the same path in one of its most recent judgments in the Ntaganda case,Footnote 63 although not in order to directly downsize the CIL rule; instead, the its aim was to ensure consistency with international humanitarian law (IHL), in both its customary and its treaty forms. Such an outcome can be achieved either by interpretation of its terms or by identifying additional elements to the crime in question. In particular, the Appeals Chamber came to an ‘unprecedented’ conclusion when it accepted that additional elements originating from CIL can be included as an element of the war crimes listed in Article 8(2)(b) or (e) of the Rome Statute as part of examining the ‘established framework of international law’.Footnote 64 Although not openly stated, it is clear from the Court’s analysis that if an element external to the Rome Statute is added to the war crimes enumerated as other serious violations of the law of war, such an element can and will be interpreted, irrespective of whether it derives from customary or treaty IHL. Besides, the Court explicitly ruled that ‘the “established framework of international law” within article 8 (2) (b) and (e) of the Statute permits recourse to customary and conventional international law regardless of whether any lacuna exists.’Footnote 65 In short, the ICC recognized the interpretability of CIL and rejected allegations of possible violation of the legality principle.Footnote 66 This is a novel approach, not only for ICL but for the function of the judiciary in general. As successfully argued by Scelle back in 1948, jurisprudence ‘assouplit et adapte’ (softens and adjusts) legal rules in accordance with evolving social needs. Since the judicial function grows out of the social environment through natural evolution, its technique has a dynamic character. In this respect, jurisprudence, fulfilling the law, is part of the judicial order.Footnote 67 The interpretation process as just described allows CIL, thanks to its equally dynamic character, to adjust to changes in its social environment. The reactions of the acting agents in the CIL system (i.e. states, non-state actors and international criminal courts) provide feedback into the system, driving it to change and evolve. Entropy is thus at a low level, since uncertainty over the content of the CIL rule has been reduced.

This dynamic process was analysed by Judge Antonio Cassese when, as president of the Special Tribunal for Lebanon (STL), he delivered an interlocutory decision on the applicable law in the Ayyash case.Footnote 68 In explaining the role of the interpreting judge, Cassese recalled the constructive function of interpretation as being ‘to give consistency, homogeneity and due weighting to the different elements of a diverging or heterogeneous set of provisions’.Footnote 69 This approach to interpretation is founded upon the context of the rule, both internal and external. In particular, it was stressed that ‘the rules of interpretation that evolved in international custom and were codified or developed in the 1969 Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties … must … be held to be applicable to any internationally binding instrument, whatever its normative source’.Footnote 70

As CIL is unwritten law, it falls upon the courts to elucidate relevant rules in their context – in other words, to contextualize the CIL rules.Footnote 71 Thereby, CIL can be interpreted according to the general principles of judicial interpretation with a view to ‘apply[ing] legal norms consistently’.Footnote 72 The constructive approach, adopted by the STL, is inextricably linked to teleological interpretation. Taking the form of the effectiveness principle, contextual interpretation aims to ‘harmonise the various provisions in light of the goal pursued by the legislature’.Footnote 73 In giving concrete meaning to a CIL rule, it reconciles the various meanings of the CIL rule. Subsequently, entropy is reduced, as harmonization counteracts uncertainty by revealing the most probable meaning of a CIL rule. In this respect, a CIL rule will consequently reflect the shared understanding of international actors regarding the content of the rule.

For the STL, such an interpretive approach corresponds to the reality of a dynamic society that changes over time, thus leading to the progressive development of the law. Recalling Jeremy Bentham, the presiding judge, the late Antonio Cassese, clarified that CIL also develops through a ‘continuing and prospective evolution’ in order ‘to adjust [the Court’s] decision to the special circumstances [of a particular case]’.Footnote 74 Progressive development does not preclude the application of the legality principle, ‘as long as this application was foreseeable’.Footnote 75 To the extent that international actors – state and non-state – are affected by that interpretation, they will react by providing feedback to the Court’s interpretative approach.Footnote 76

At this point, some clarification is needed: obtaining feedback from states in ICL cases is not of the same nature as in other international law interstate cases such as those before the ICJ. Feedback from states in ICL cases involving CIL interpretation can assume different shapes and forms. Take, for example, Articles 86–87 and 97 of the Rome State on the obligation of state parties to cooperate and consult with the ICC during the investigation, prosecution and enforcement stages. Here, the triggering of a mechanism of non-compliance with the Court’s judgments constitutes proof of feedback by a member state. Let us elaborate on the facts and the Court’s reasoning to comprehend how entropy changes in this case.

The judgments against South Africa and Jordan, parties to the Rome Statute, concerning non-execution of the arrest warrant against Omar al-Bashir, are examples of such a complex case. The ICC ruled that both states had violated their obligations deriving from the Rome Statute, since they had not arrested and surrendered Sudan’s head of state al-Bashir to the Court for having committed war crimes, crimes against humanity and genocide.Footnote 77 Pursuant to a UN Security Council referral of the situation in Darfur to the ICC, the latter issued two arrest warrants for al-Bashir in 2009 and 2010 calling upon all state parties to cooperate with the Court in accordance with their obligations under the Rome Statute.Footnote 78 After rejecting the objections of South Africa and Jordan invoking the immunity rule for heads of state, the Court explained that there was no CIL norm on immunity that shielded active heads of state accused of having committed core international crimes.Footnote 79 The most interesting conclusion of the ICC Pre-Trial Chamber was its decision to refer the non-compliance issue to the Assembly of States Parties and the UN Security Council. However, it did so only for Jordan, not for South Africa, reasoning that the former was aware of its obligations but ‘chose not to execute [them]’,Footnote 80 whereas the latter was not. The second Pre-Trial Chamber (PTC II) maintained a different approach towards South Africa based on two main reasons: firstly, there was genuine interaction with South African authorities regarding the state’s obligation to co-operate with the Court and, secondly, South Africa’s violation of its obligations had also been recognized by the country’s domestic courts.Footnote 81 The Appeals Chamber overturned the decision for Jordan and decided not to refer the situation to the Assembly of States Parties and the UN Security Council. It held that Jordan had not refused to consult with the court in defiance of its obligation deriving from Article 97 of the Rome Statute. On the contrary, its note verbale qualified as a request for consultations with the Court and was proof of good faith with regard to the problem of the execution of the arrest warrant.Footnote 82

We draw particular attention to the feedback of the Court based on the different legal reasoning of the PTC II and the Appeals Chamber. Although not directly connected to interpreting CIL, each legal reasoning is important insofar as it portrays how interpretation works as a means of keeping the entropy of the CIL system at a low level. Further evidence of that is the Appeal Chamber judgment concluding that the different treatment of Jordan and South Africa was due to abuse by PTC II of its discretionary power. When state parties rejected the Court’s interpretation regarding their obligations under the customary rule of immunity, the entropy of the system increased, as there were many possible interpretive (and conflicting) outcomes. When the Appeals Chamber overturned the PTC II’s judgment, the CIL entropy had been reduced to a minimum as there was only one possible interpretive outcome for the CIL rule on immunity. This shows that the process of ICC feedback to states proves to be particularly influential for complex systems, since it keeps the entropy at a low level.

International case law can also affect state behaviour by triggering a change in state practice.Footnote 83 The feedback process leads the CIL system to adapt through a learning process that relies on information from its own agents as well as its environment. In other words, the topology of the CIL system (i.e. the structure of the CIL network and the frequency and intensity of interactions between its agents) is indicative of its inherently dynamic character and its ability to evolve as a real social phenomenon.

6 Concluding Remarks: A ‘Low Entropy’ Mode of Interpretation for CIL

The present chapter has attempted to show how the interpretation of CIL operates in accordance with the fundamental rules of nature. Since human systems are affected by various kinds of complexity, we turned to the findings of complexity science to describe CIL as a complex adaptive system forming societal bonds between the various state and non-state agents involved in international criminal justice.

In modelling CIL as an epistemic tool, we have sought to explain the mechanical behaviour of CIL when international criminal tribunals and, in particular, the ICC interpret its rules. To this end, we introduced entropy, as the internal property of a complex system that stimulates changes according to the flow of information transmitted both between its component elements and between the latter and the system’s environment.

For the CIL complex system, legal interpretation is the source of information provided by the international courts when they concretize abstract CIL rules by attributing the most probable meaning to those rules. Such an entropic mode of interpretation reduces uncertainties over the content of the rules, triggers changes in the CIL system and, thus, encourages the system to develop further and thereby evolve. The extent of the changes that will occur depends on the feedback such interpretation draws from the agents of the CIL system.

Adopting such an approach to the interpretation of CIL helps us redefine our perceptions as lawyers regarding the quest for certainty and predictability in international law. Thus, we have argued that chance does not correspond to the unknown and the uncertain that Czech choreographer J. Kylian considered to be epitomized in the tossing of the dice; rather, throwing a dice is all about probabilities.

In the field of international criminal justice, reducing uncertainties is especially vital to the unity and progressive development of international criminal law. Recent interpretation by the ICC has displayed low entropy. Were the Court to follow such an entropic interpretation in the future, this could lead to the transformation of CIL and in turn to a unified approach in ICL. It remains to be seen whether the international judiciary will seize the opportunity to ‘activate’ entropic interpretation to stimulate changes in the complex CIL system.

Footnotes

1 The Illusion of Gold-Digging: Interpretation of State Practice

The author thanks Andreas Follesdal and Kostiantyn Gorobets for their helpful comments on an earlier draft

1 DH Joyner, ‘Why I Stopped Believing in Customary International Law’ (2019) 9 Asian JIL 31.

2 For good – but not uncritical – expositions of the two-element doctrine, see P Haggenmacher, ‘La doctrine des deux éléments du droit coutumier dans la pratique de la Cour internationale’ (1986) 1 RGDIP 1; K Wolfke, ‘Some Persistent Controversies Regarding Customary International Law’ (1993) 24 NYIL 1; M Akehurst, ‘Custom as a Source of International Law’ (1975) 47 BYBIL 1, 37.

3 See P Westerman, ‘Opinio Juris: Test, Filter, Ideal or Map?’ in K Gorobets, A Hadjigeorgiou and P Westerman (eds), Conceptual (Re)Constructions of International Law (Edward Elgar 2022) 127.

4 Wolfke (Footnote n 2) 4.

5 HWA Thirlway, International Customary Law and Codification (AW Sijthoff 1972) 47, quoted in ILA Committee on Formation of Customary (General) International Law, ‘Final Report of the Committee: Statement of Principles Applicable to the Formation of General Customary International Law’ (London Conference, 2000) 30.

6 AE Roberts, ‘Traditional and Modern Approaches to Customary International Law: A Reconciliation’ (2001) 95 AJIL 757, 757, 781, 788. Even Hakimi, despite her rich conception of practice, describes claims and counterclaims as ‘raw data’; M Hakimi, ‘Making Sense of Customary International Law’ (2020) 118 Mich L Rev 1487, 1493.

7 Roberts (Footnote n 6).

8 S Talmon, ‘Determining Customary International Law: The ICJ’s Methodology between Induction, Deduction and Assertion’ (2015) 26 EJIL 417.

9 P Merkouris, ‘Interpreting the Customary Rules on Interpretation’ (2017) 19 ICLR 126.

10 I will refrain from discussing the problem of induction as the logical problem that general statements can never exhaustibly be verified by sense-data and that induction can therefore not be justified without having to rely on sense-data, which leads to infinite regress and circularity. See K Popper, The Logic of Scientific Discovery (Hutchinson 1972).

11 We owe to Mendelson the important distinction between the various points of view from which we address CIL. M Mendelson, ‘Formation of International Law and the Observational Standpoint’ in ILA Committee on Formation of Customary (General) International Law, ‘Report of 63rd Conference: Annex to the 1st Interim Report of the Committee’ (Warsaw 1988) 935–72. This paper starts from the question of what courts (as ‘third party decision-makers’) do if they examine state practice.

12 See KN Llewellyn, The Bramble Bush: The Classic Lectures on the Law and Law School; with a New Introduction and Notes by Steve Sheppard (Oxford University Press 2008); F Schauer, ‘Pitfalls in the Interpretation of Customary Law’ in A Perreau-Saussine and JB Murphy (eds), The Nature of Customary Law: Legal, Historical and Philosophical Perspectives (Cambridge University Press 2007) 13–34.

13 As Bradley remarked: ‘Merely looking out into the world to see what nations have done and said does not itself reveal rules of international law.’ CA Bradley, ‘Customary International Law Adjudication as Common Law Adjudication’ in CA Bradley (ed), Custom’s Future: International Law in a Changing World (Cambridge University Press 2016) 34–61.

14 NR Hanson, Perception and Discovery: An Introduction to Scientific Inquiry (MD Lund ed, Springer 2018).

15 ‘Nur wer schon versteht, kann zuhören.’ M Heidegger, Sein und Zeit (Max Niemeyer Verlag 1979) 164.

16 P Westerman, ‘Open or Autonomous? The Debate on Legal Methodology as a Reflection of the Debate on Law’ in M van Hoecke (ed), Methodologies of Legal Research: Which Kind of Method for What Kind of Discipline? (Hart 2011) 87.

17 In the Rome Statute, for instance, concepts such as ‘crimes against humanity’ are defined in part by enumerating instances and examples. See Rome Statute of the International Criminal Court (adopted 17 July 1998, entered into force 1 July 2002) 2187 UNTS 3.

18 H Kelsen, General Theory of Law and State (A Wedberg tr, Harvard University Press 1945) 48.

19 See GJ Postema, ‘Custom, Normative Practice, and the Law’ (2012) 62 DLJ 707, 707–38; K Gorobets, ‘Practical Reasoning and Interpretation of Customary International Law’ in P Merkouris, J Kammerhofer and N Arajärvi (eds), The Theory, Practice, and Interpretation of Customary International Law (Cambridge University Press 2022).

20 Mendelson (Footnote n 11) 249. See also Bradley (Footnote n 13). A similar distinction is elaborated by Eugen Ehrlich, who distinguished between rules of conduct and norms for (juridical) decision. See E Ehrlich, Fundamental Principles of the Sociology of Law, with an Introduction by Roscoe Pound (Walter L Moll tr, first published 1936, Routledge 2017) esp ch XIX.

21 Hakimi (Footnote n 6) 1511.

22 Footnote ibid 1521.

23 Heidegger (Footnote n 15) 153.

24 HG Gadamer, Wahrheit und Methode (4th edn, JCB Mohr 1975) 255.

25 Bradley (Footnote n 13); Schauer (Footnote n 12).

26 North Sea Continental Shelf Cases (Germany/Netherlands; Germany/Denmark) (Judgment) [1969] ICJ Rep 3, 75 (emphasis added).

27 Asylum (Colombia v Peru) (Judgment) [1950] ICJ Rep 266, 276–77.

28 Military and Paramilitary Activities in and against Nicaragua (Nicaragua v USA) (Merits) [1986] ICJ Rep 16 [207].

30 To make matters worse, the argument in paragraph 77 of the North Sea Continental Shelf judgment runs that not only for CIL but also for opinio juris both elements are required. Probably this is a mistake. In paragraph 77 it is stated: ‘The essential point in this connection – and it seems necessary to stress it – is that even if these instances of action by non-parties to the Convention were much more numerous than they in fact are, they would not, even in the aggregate, suffice in themselves to constitute the opinio juris; for, in order to achieve this result, two conditions must be fulfilled. Not only must the acts concerned amount to a settled practice, but they must also be such, or be carried out in such a way, as to be evidence of a belief that this practice is rendered obligatory by the existence of a rule of law requiring it. The need for such a belief, i.e., the existence of a subjective element, is implicit in the very notion of the opinio juris sive necessitatis. The States concerned must therefore feel that they are conforming to what amounts to a legal obligation. The frequency, or even habitual character of the acts is not in itself enough.’ (emphasis added).

31 See Haggenmacher (Footnote n 2).

32 See Westerman (Footnote n 3).

33 That is why Anthony d’Amato has a point in emphasising articulation. See A d’Amato, The Concept of Custom in International Law (Cornell University Press 1971).

34 In a similar vein, see M Mendelson, ‘The Formation of Customary International Law’ (1998) 272 RdC 155, 176. For an analysis of such declarative propositions, see JR Searle, Expression and Meaning: Studies in the Theory of Speech Acts (Cambridge University Press 1979) 17.

35 See Westerman (Footnote n 3).

36 External conduct of States with each other as well as ‘diplomatic acts and correspondence; conduct in connection with resolutions adopted by an international organization or at an intergovernmental conference; conduct in connection with treaties; executive conduct, including operational conduct ‘on the ground’; legislative and administrative acts; and decisions of national courts’. see ILC, ‘Identification of Customary International Law: Text of the Draft Conclusions Provisionally Adopted by the Drafting Committee’ (30 May 2016) UN Doc A/CN.4/L.872, art 6(2).

37 SJ Choi & M Gulati, ‘Customary International Law: How Do Courts Do It?’ in CA Bradley (ed), Custom’s Future: International Law in a Changing World (Cambridge University Press 2016) 117.

38 Mendelson (Footnote n 34) 381–82 (emphasis added).

39 M Koskenniemi, From Apology to Utopia (Cambridge University Press 2006) 437.

40 D Bodansky, ‘Customary (And Not So Customary) International Environmental Law’ (1995) 3(1) IJGLS 105, 105–19.

41 The unity of the two elements is also observed by R Müllerson, ‘The Interplay of Objective and Subjective Elements in Customary Law’ in K Wellens (ed), International Law, Theory and Practice (Kluwer 1998) 161–78; O Elias, ‘The Nature of the Subjective Element in Customary International Law’ (1995) 44 ICLQ 501, 501–20; and, of course, Haggenmacher (Footnote n 2).

42 Postema (Footnote n 19) 715.

43 Heidegger (Footnote n 15) 149.

44 R Dworkin, Law’s Empire (Harvard University Press 1986) 228–38.

45 JL Goldsmith and EA Posner, The Limits of International Law (Oxford University Press 2005).

46 P Ricœur, Hermeneutics and the Human Sciences: Essays on Language, Action, and Interpretation (JB Thompson ed, Cambridge University Press 2016) 104.

47 For a nice application of Ricœur’s insights, see the dissertation by P Phoa, EU Law as a Creative Process: A Hermeneutic Approach for the EU Internal Market and Fundamental Rights Protection (Europa Law 2021).

49 See Westerman (Footnote n 3).

50 See the empirical study by SA Lindquist and FB Cross, ‘Empirically Testing Dworkin’s Chain Novel Theory: Studying the Path of Precedent’ (2005) 80 NYUL Rev 1156.

2 Addressing the Chronological Paradox of CIL From Good Faith to Opinio Juris, and Opinio Juris to New Customary Rules

The author is grateful to Jaap Hage, Wagner Menezes, and Antonia Waltermann for discussing the initial ideas that inspired the research underlying this chapter; to Eloá Figaro, Sarah McGibbon, Paula Miranda da Cruz, Nevitton Vieira Souza, and the participants at the second TRICI-Law conference for their comments on an earlier version of the chapter; and especially to Pauline Westerman, Kostiantyn Gorobets, and Marina Fortuna for their valuable comments on this final version. The content remains the sole responsibility of the author. The research underlying this chapter was partially funded by the CAPES Foundation (Brazil).

1 This chapter follows Wittgenstein’s broad understanding of ‘rule’ as covering not only rules sensu stricto but also principles and other kinds of legal and non-legal rules such as norms, postulates, and standards. L Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations (GEM Anscombe tr, 3rd edn, Blackwell 1986) paras 207–32; H-J Glock, A Wittgenstein Dictionary (Blackwell 1996) 324–25.

2 R Mangabeira Unger, Law in Modern Society: Toward a Criticism of Social Theory (Free Press 1976) 49; T Treves, ‘Customary International Law’ (MPEPIL 2006) <https://opil.ouplaw.com/display/10.1093/law:epil/9780199231690/law-9780199231690-e1393> accessed 27 March 2024; HLA Hart, The Concept of Law (3rd edn, Oxford University Press 2012) ch III.

3 MH Mendelson, ‘The Formation of Customary International Law’ (1998) 272 RdC 155.

4 United Nations Convention on the Law of the Sea (adopted 10 December 1982, entered into force 16 November 1994) 1833 UNTS 3.

5 M Lee, ‘The Interrelation between the Law of the Sea Convention and Customary International Law’ (2006) 7 SDILJ 405.

6 J d’Aspremont, The Discourse on Customary International Law (Oxford University Press 2021) ch 1.

7 DH Levine, ‘The Chronological Paradox in Customary International Law (Or, the Virtue of Sloppy Timing in a Messy World)’ (PhD thesis, Georgetown University 2005); D Lefkowitz, ‘(Dis)Solving the Chronological Paradox in Customary International Law: A Hartian Approach’ (2008) 21 CJLJ 129; V Jeutner and F Paddeu, ‘Three Paradoxes of Customary Law’ (Logic of International Law conference, Maastricht University 2022).

8 For this chapter, coherence means the possibility of intelligible argument. See S Haack, ‘Coherence, Consistency, Cogency, Congruity, Cohesiveness, &c.: Remain Calm! Don’t Go Overboard!’ (2004) 35 NLH 167. See also Y Radi, ‘Coherence’ in J d’Aspremont and S Singh (eds), Concepts for International Law: Contributions to Disciplinary Thought (Edward Elgar 2019).

9 J Tasioulas, ‘Customary International Law and the Quest for Global Justice’ in A Perreau-Saussine and JB Murphy (eds), The Nature of Customary Law (Cambridge University Press 2007) 307, 321–22.

10 ILC, ‘Draft Conclusions on Identification of Customary International Law, with Commentaries’ (30 April–1 June and 2 July–10 August 2018) UN Doc A/73/10.

11 P Merkouris, ‘Interpreting the Customary Rules on Interpretation’ (2017) 19 ICLR 126. See also L Blutman, ‘Conceptual Confusion and Methodological Deficiencies: Some Ways that Theories on Customary International Law Fail’ (2014) 25 EJIL 529.

12 Statute of the International Court of Justice (adopted 26 June 1945, entered into force 24 October 1945) 33 UNTS 993.

13 S Droubi and J d’Aspremont (eds), International Organisations, Non-State Actors, and the Formation of Customary International Law (Manchester University Press 2020).

14 ILC (Footnote n 10) 130 (Conclusion 4.2).

15 Duties being here treated as a kind of obligation; see J Hage, Foundations and Building Blocks of Law (Eleven International Publishing 2018) ch VI.

16 SO Hansson, ‘The Varieties of Permission’ in DM Gabbay and others (eds), Handbook of Deontic Logic and Normative Systems (College Publications 2013) 204–06.

17 E Schwitzgebel, ‘Belief’, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter edn, 2021) <https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/belief/> accessed 1 April 2022.

18 A Cassese, International Law (2nd edn, Oxford University Press 2005) 4. See also A Waltermann, ‘Why Non-Human Agency?’ in A Waltermann and others (eds), Law, Science, Rationality (Eleven International Publishing 2020) 51. Also, the cognitive sciences teach us that human brains do not have a single, top-level decision-maker. So, when we assign a belief held by a group of humans to a state, we are simply going a step further than when we assign mental acts to humans rather than parts of their brains. See DC Dennett, Consciousness Explained (Little Brown 1991) 102–03; J Hage, ‘Are the Cognitive Sciences Relevant for Law?’ in B Brożek, J Hage, and N Vincent (eds), Law and Mind: A Survey of Law and the Cognitive Sciences (Cambridge University Press 2021) 17, 40–41.

19 Hart (Footnote n 2) ch I. See also GJ Postema, ‘Custom in International Law: A Normative Practice Account’ in A Perreau-Saussine and JB Murphy (eds), The Nature of Customary Law (Cambridge University Press 2007).

20 Levine (Footnote n 7); Lefkowitz (Footnote n 7); Jeutner and Paddeu (Footnote n 7).

21 CA Bradley, ‘Customary International Law Adjudication as Common Law Adjudication’ in CA Bradley (ed), Custom’s Future: International Law in a Changing World (Cambridge University Press 2016) 34.

22 PE Benson, ‘François Gény’s Doctrine of Customary Law’ (1983) 20 CYIL 267, 276.

23 Tasioulas (Footnote n 9) 321.

24 P Westerman, ‘Test, Filter, Ideal or Map?’ in K Gorobets, A Hadjigeorgiou and P Westerman (eds), Conceptual (Re)Constructions of International Law (Edward Elgar 2022) 127. See also O Elias, ‘The Nature of the Subjective Element in Customary International Law’ (1995) 44 ICLQ 501.

25 J Searle, The Construction of Social Reality (Free Press 1995) 31; J Searle, Mind, Language, and Society: Philosophy in the Real World (Basic Books 1999) 85; J Searle, Making the Social World: The Structure of Human Civilization (Oxford University Press 2010) 25.

26 ILC (Footnote n 10) 138.

27 R Tuomela, ‘Collective Acceptance, Social Institutions, and Social Reality’ (2003) 62 AJES 123.

28 Searle (Footnote n 25) 57.

29 See Chapter 1.

30 On the (widely rejected) idea that experience gives points of certainty that can be used as absolute bases for knowledge, see JR O’Shea, ‘What Is the Myth of the Given?’ (2021) 199 Synthese 10543.

31 NR Hanson, Patterns of Discovery (Cambridge University Press 1965) 4; PK Feyerabend, ‘Science Without Experience’ (1969) 66 Journal of Philosophy 791; TS Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions (2nd edn, University of Chicago Press 1970) 35. See also RW Proctor and EJ Capaldi, Psychology of Science: Implicit and Explicit Processes (Oxford University Press 2012) 1–10.

32 HLA Hart, ‘Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morals’ in Hart, Essays in Jurisprudence and Philosophy (Oxford University Press 1983) 63.

33 HG Gadamer, Truth and Method (J Weinsheimer and DG Marshall trs, 2nd edn, Continuum 2004) 383.

34 This chapter uses the term ‘realism’ not in the sense of legal realism but to express the idea that true statements are true because they reflect the content of an independently existing reality. See M Devitt, Realism and Truth (2nd edn, Princeton University Press 1997) ch 2.

35 P Lorenzen, Constructive Philosophy (University of Massachusetts Press 1987) ix.

36 For a comprehensive argument against the descriptivist view, see J Hage, ‘Construction or Reconstruction? On the Function of Argumentation in the Law’ in C Dahlman and E Feteris (eds), Legal Argumentation Theory: Cross-Disciplinary Perspectives (Springer 2012) 125; J Hage, ‘Legal Reasoning and the Construction of Law’ (2012) i-Lex 81.

37 R Dworkin, Taking Rights Seriously (Harvard University Press 1978) 81. See also G Dorota, ‘Hard Cases’ (2013) 2 UMSLR 240.

38 J Vidmar, ‘The Use of Force as a Plea of Necessity’ (2017) 111 AJIL 302.

39 T Ruys, ‘The Meaning of “Force” and the Boundaries of the Jus ad Bellum: Are “Minimal” Uses of Force Excluded from UN Charter Article 2(4)?’ (2014) 108 AJIL 159; O Corten, The Law Against War: The Prohibition on the Use of Force in Contemporary International Law (2nd ed, Hart 2021) ch 2.

40 S Yee, ‘Sketching the Debate on Military Activities in the EEZ: An Editorial Comment’ (2010) 9 Chinese JIL 1.

41 R Dworkin, Law’s Empire (Harvard University Press 1986) 52. See also DO Brink, ‘Originalism and Constructive Interpretation’ in W Waluchow and S Sciaraffa (eds), The Legacy of Ronald Dworkin (Oxford University Press 2016) 273.

42 GJ Postema, Legal Philosophy in the Twentieth Century: The Common Law World (Springer 2011) 425; R Porto Macedo Júnior, Do Xadrez à Cortesia: Dworkin e a Teoria do Direito Contemporânea (Saraiva 2013) 219.

43 A Peczenik, Scientia Juris: Legal Doctrine as Knowledge of Law and as a Source of Law (Springer 2005) 6.

44 Rome Statute of the International Criminal Court (adopted 17 July 1998, entered into force 1 July 2002) 2187 UNTS 3.

45 On interpretation (or classification) of rules in relation to cases, see J Hage, Reasoning with Rules: An Essay on Legal Reasoning and Its Underlying Logic (Springer 1997) 95–97. See also J Raz, ‘Why Interpret?’ (1996) 9 Ratio Juris 349; F Perin Shecaira, ‘Sources of Law Are Not Legal Norms’ (2015) 28 Ratio Juris 15.

46 Military and Paramilitary Activities in and against Nicaragua (Nicaragua v United States of America) (Merits) [1986] ICJ Rep 14 [178].

47 North Sea Continental Shelf (Judgment, Dissenting Opinion of Judge Tanaka) [1969] ICJ Rep 172 [182].

48 ILC (Footnote n 10) 142.

50 Merkouris (Footnote n 11); O Chasapis Tassinis, ‘Customary International Law: Interpretation from Beginning to End’ (2020) 31 EJIL 235; K Gorobets, ‘Practical Reasoning and Interpretation of Customary International Law’ in P Merkouris, J Kammerhofer and N Arajärvi (eds), The Theory, Practice, and Interpretation of Customary International Law (Cambridge University Press 2022) 370.

51 Colombian-Peruvian Asylum Case (Judgment) [1950] ICJ Rep 266 [276].

52 D’Aspremont (Footnote n 6) ch 2. See also Military and Paramilitary Activities in and against Nicaragua (Nicaragua v United States of America) (Merits) [1986] ICJ Rep 14; Delimitation of the Maritime Boundary in the Gulf of Maine Area (Judgment) [1984] ICJ Rep 246.

53 ILC (Footnote n 10) 133, 140–41.

54 The ILC’s formulations on state responsibility reflect CIL. See ILC, ‘Draft Articles on Responsibility of States for Internationally Wrongful Acts, with Commentaries’ (23 April–1 June and 2 July–10 August 2001) UN Doc A/56/10; F Lusa Bordin, ‘Reflections of Customary International Law: The Authority of Codification Conventions and ILC Draft Articles in International Law’ (2014) 63 ICLQ 535.

55 Armed Activities on the Territory of the Congo (Democratic Republic of the Congo v Uganda) (Judgment) [2022] ICJ Rep 1.

56 Hage (Footnote n 45); J Hage and A Waltermann, ‘Logical Techniques for International Law’ in D Krimphove and G Lentner (eds), Law and Logic: Contemporary Issues (Duncker und Humblot 2017) 125; H Marcos, A Waltermann and J Hage, ‘From Sovereignty to International Cooperation: Lessons from Legal Logic and Social Ontology’ (2021) Maastricht Faculty of Law Working Paper Series 2021/01 <www.maastrichtuniversity.nl/maastricht-faculty-law-working-paper-series-2021> accessed 15 April 2024.

57 On the different kinds of rule application, see L Duarte d’Almeida, ‘What Is It to Apply the Law?’ (2021) 40 Law Philos 361.

58 ILC (Footnote n 54).

59 While it is possible to formulate a rule as a statement, we should not conclude that rules are statements. See J Hage, ‘Consistency of Rules and Norms’ (2000) 9 ICTL 219; H Marcos, ‘A Study on Defeasibility and Defeaters in International Law: Process or Procedure Distinction against the Non-discrimination Rule’ in W Menezes, A Nunes Filho and PH Reis de Oliveira (eds), Tribunais Internacionais e a Garantia dos Direitos Sociais (Academia Brasileira de Direito Internacional 2021) 199, 208.

60 B Smith, ‘John Searle: From Speech Acts to Social Reality’ in B Smith (ed), John Searle (Cambridge University Press 2003) 19.

61 Some authors prefer to use ‘object’, ‘being’, or ‘existent’ instead of ‘entity.’ See B Rettler and AM Bailey, ‘Object’, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter edn, 2017) <https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/object/> accessed 2 April 2022.

62 The terminology ‘basic social entities’ and ‘rule-based entities’ used in this chapter reflects the influence of Hage’s work on legal logic and social ontology. See J Hage and B Verheij, ‘Reason‐Based Logic: A Logic for Reasoning with Rules and Reasons’ (1994) 3 ICTL 171; Hage, Foundations and Building Blocks of Law (Footnote n 15); J Hage, ‘Constructivist Facts as the Bridge between Is and Ought’ (2022) 1 IJSL 1. Following Anscombe, basic entities and rule-based entities may also be called ‘conventional’ and ‘institutional’ entities, respectively. See GEM Anscombe, ‘On Brute Facts’ (1958) 18 Analysis 69; N MacCormick and O Weinberger (eds), Institutional Theory of Law: New Approaches to Legal Positivism (Springer 1986).

63 F Schauer, Playing by the Rules: A Philosophical Examination of Rule-Based Decision-Making in Law and in Life (Oxford University Press 1991) 10.

64 Wittgenstein (Footnote n 1) para 219; R Brandom, Making It Explicit: Reasoning, Representing, and Discursive Commitment (Harvard University Press 1994) 649–50.

65 Wittgenstein (Footnote n 1) paras 207–32; Glock (Footnote n 1) 324–25.

66 Searle (Footnote n 25) 97. See also J Hage, ‘Two Concepts of Constitutive Rules’ (2018) 4 Argumenta 21; C Roversi, ‘In Defence of Constitutive Rules’ (2021) 199 Synthese 14349; Hage, ‘Constructivist Facts as the Bridge between Is and Ought’ (Footnote n 62).

67 Smith (Footnote n 60).

68 Hage calls them ‘rule-based rules’. See Hage, Foundations and Building Blocks of Law (Footnote n 15) 87; Hage, ‘Constructivist Facts as the Bridge between Is and Ought’ (Footnote n 62).

69 See Section 3.

70 See Section 4.2.

71 Wittgenstein (Footnote n 1) para 201; Glock (Footnote n 1) 327.

72 Advisory Committee of Jurists, ‘Procès-Verbaux of the Proceedings of the Committee’ (Permanent Court of International Justice 1920) 322.

73 B Russell, Our Knowledge of the External World: As a Field for Scientific Method in Philosophy (Routledge 2009) 49.

74 North Sea Continental Shelf (Judgment) [1969] ICJ Rep 3 [72].

75 D’Aspremont (Footnote n 6) ch 3.

76 See Section 4.2.

77 We will discuss persistent objectors later in Section 4.3.2.

78 As first explained by Hume, the is/ought problem arises when we derive an ‘ought judgement’ from premises based on ‘is’ and vice versa. D Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature (Floating Press 2009) 715–16.

79 See Hage, Foundations and Building Blocks of Law (Footnote n 15) ch IX; Hage, ‘Two Concepts of Constitutive Rules’ (Footnote n 66). See also J Searle, ‘How to Derive “Ought” From “Is”’ (1964) 73 Philosophical Review 43.

80 Advisory Committee of Jurists (Footnote n 72) 322.

81 Statute of the International Court of Justice (Footnote n 12). On good faith as a general principle of law, see R Kolb, Good Faith in International Law (Hart 2017); S Reinhold, ‘Good Faith in International Law’ (2013) 2 UCLJLJ 40.

82 H Grotius, The Rights of War and Peace (Richard Tuck ed, Liberty Fund 2005) bk III, ch XXV, s I.1.

83 Nuclear Tests (Australia v France) (Judgment) [1974] ICJ Rep 253 [46].

84 K Schmalenbach, ‘Article 26’ in O Dörr and K Schmalenbach (eds), Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties: A Commentary (2nd edn, Springer 2018) 473.

85 B Cheng, General Principles of Law as Applied by International Courts and Tribunals (Cambridge University Press 1994) s 5.C; Reinhold (Footnote n 81) 54. As explained in Section 2, a prohibition on acting is equivalent to an obligation not to act. We might wonder if the general principle of good faith is not itself this rule on legitimate expectations. As pointed out above, good faith leads to many legal by-products. Some of them are tied to prohibiting states from acting inconsistently, but others are focused on legal interpretation and rule application. We can also think of pacta sunt servanda, rebus sic stantibus, and the prohibition of abus de droit, which are also derivatives of good faith. In any case, it is theoretically possible to perceive good faith as a rule protecting legitimate expectations. But in this chapter we formulate it as a general principle which has as a corollary the rule that protects legitimate expectations by prohibiting acts inconsistent with such expectations. This theoretical choice allows for a simple conditions⇒conclusion formulation, as will become clear.

86 Case Concerning Certain German Interests in Polish Upper Silesia (Merits) [1926] PCIJ Rep 5 Series A No 7.

87 ‘A. A. Megalidis v Turkey’ [1932] 4 ADPILC 395.

88 Case Concerning the Temple of Preah Vihear (Cambodia v Thailand) (Merits, Separate Opinion of Vice-President Alfaro) [1962] ICJ Rep 39; North Sea Continental Shelf (Judgment, Separate Opinion of Judge Fouad Ammoun) [1969] ICJ Rep 101.

89 Obligation to Negotiate Access to the Pacific Ocean (Bolivia v Chile) (Merits) [2018] ICJ Rep 507 [162].

90 Obligation to Negotiate Access to the Pacific Ocean (Bolivia v Chile) (Merits, Dissenting Opinion of Judge ad hoc Daudet) [2018] ICJ Rep 607 [45].

91 See G Fitzmaurice, ‘The Law and Procedure of the International Court of Justice, 1954–9: General Principles and Sources of International Law’ (1959) 35 BYIL 183, 195.

92 G Priest, ‘The Structure of the Paradoxes of Self-Reference’ (1994) 103 Mind 25.

93 On Tarski’s escape from the self-reference antinomy, see M Gruber, Alfred Tarski and the ‘Concept of Truth in Formalized Languages’ (Springer 2016).

94 This ensures that L and M are a part of the same activity or ‘language game’. Wittgenstein (Footnote n 1) para 23. On international law and language games, see A Carty, ‘Language Games of International Law’ (2012) 13 Melb JIL 1.

95 On exceptions see J Hage, A Waltermann and G Arosemena Solorzano, ‘Exceptions in International Law’ in L Bartels and F Paddeu (eds), Exceptions and Defences in International Law (Oxford University Press 2018) 11.

96 ILC (Footnote n 10) 152.

98 Dworkin (Footnote n 41) 13. See also Brandom (Footnote n 64) 649–50.

3 Interpreting the Plural Sources of CIL

The author is indebted to Marina Fortuna and the organizers of the December 2021 TRICI-Law conference, where an earlier version of this chapter was first presented. Thanks also go to Dan Bodansky, Evan Criddle, Andreas Follesdal, Kostia Gorobets, Fleur Johns, David Lefkowitz, Nahuel Maisley, Steve Ratner, Nicole Roughan, and Oisin Suttle for helping to work through the ideas expressed in this chapter and to Sarah Burns for helping to round it into shape.

1 See M Fortuna, ‘Different Strings of the Same Harp: Interpretation of Customary International Rules, Their Identification and Treaty Interpretation’ in P Merkouris, J Kammerhofer, and N Arajärvi (eds), The Theory, Practice and Interpretation of Customary International Law (Cambridge University Press 2021) (observing that ‘hardly any theoretical account of customary international law can coherently explain what it is, how it emerges and how it develops’).

2 Statute of the International Court of Justice (adopted 26 June 1945, entered into force 24 October 1945) 33 UNTS 993, art 38(1)(b).

3 See ILC, ‘Draft Conclusions on Identification of Customary International Law, with Commentaries’ (30 April–1 June and 2 July–10 August 2018) UN Doc A/73/10, 121, 124.

4 Footnote ibid 124 (‘[T]he draft conclusions do not address, directly, the processes by which customary international law develops over time … They do not … deal systematically with how such rules emerge, change, or terminate.’).

5 See generally M Hakimi, ‘Making Sense of Customary International Law’ (2020) 118 Mich L Rev 1487 (rejecting the rulebook approach to CIL).

6 I am not the first to suggest that what we call ‘customary international law’ may, in fact, reflect more than one source or type of international law rules. See generally D Bodansky, ‘Prologue to a Theory of Non-Treaty Norms’ in MH Arsanjani and others (eds), Looking to the Future: Essays on International Law in Honor of W. Michael Reisman (Brill 2010); D Bodansky, ‘Does Custom Have a Source?’ (2014) 108 AJIL Unbound 179. In fact, the three sources of custom identified here bear some resemblance to Bodansky’s categories of common law, declarative law, and the behaviour of states (Bodansky, ‘Does Custom Have a Source’ 180). The list is also not exclusive. A more exhaustive account would need to include a variety of potential natural law sources as well.

7 While built on somewhat different explanations, these sources also very roughly coincide with notions of traditional custom, modern custom, and international common law proffered by others. See generally AE Roberts, ‘Traditional and Modern Approaches to Customary International Law: A Reconciliation’ (2001) 95 AJIL 757. One advantage of this account of international law’s sources is that it may help explain the divergence between those categories.

8 As will be explained in Section 2, these sources of justification cut across our formal sources. For our purposes here, though, we will focus primarily on custom.

9 See Bodansky, ‘Does Custom Have a Source?’ (Footnote n 6) 180–81 (‘Should we follow the example of Ptolemaic astronomers, who added epicycle upon epicycle to their descriptions of planetary motion, in their efforts to save the geocentric system? Or should we seek a paradigm shift, a new way of understanding the sources of international law?’). No one will be surprised if, like Bodansky, I favour the latter.

10 To be clear, what I am exploring here is why people think certain rules have normative authority – the justifications they articulate. I leave to the side both whether these reasons are good and worthy of authority and whether they actually explain the operative authority of these rules.

11 See Bodansky, ‘Prologue to a Theory of Non-Treaty Norms’ (Footnote n 6).

12 See Hakimi (Footnote n 5) 1493; see also MH Mendelson, ‘The Formation of Customary International Law’ (1998) 272 RdC 155, 189–91 (‘Out of this constant process of claim and response rules emerge, are strengthened, or are superseded.’). For more on this model and other places where we might find it, see HG Cohen, ‘International Law’s Erie Moment’ (2013) 34 MJIL 249, 257–70.

13 GJ Postema, ‘Custom, Normative Practice, and the Law’ (2012) 62 DLJ 707, 726 (‘Customs are relatively stable points or nodes in the network of expectations.’).

14 See Hakimi (Footnote n 5) 1495 (‘[B]ecause the CIL process is continuous, a position’s status or content within CIL can be transitory and elusive.’); Postema (Footnote n 13) 710 (‘As such it is flexible, open to reformulation and reformation, and inviting rather than silencing scrutiny.’).

15 MS McDougal, ‘The Hydrogen Bomb Tests and the International Law of Sea’ (1955) 49 AJIL 356, 357. Negotiation here may thus be more implicit than explicit. Rules emerge from a constant give-and-take (‘negotiation’), but the results need not take the form of an explicit agreement.

16 For a rich account that seeks to move beyond this ‘separation thesis’, see C Turner, ‘Interconstituted Legal Agents’ (2022) University of Georgia School of Law Research Paper 2022-07, <https://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=4049942> accessed 27 May 2022.

17 See generally J Brunnée and SJ Toope, Legitimacy and Legality in International Law: An Interactional Account (Cambridge University Press 2010).

18 Postema (Footnote n 13) 709 and passim.

19 See Hakimi (Footnote n 5) 1493–96.

20 See Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties (adopted 23 May 1969, entered into force 27 January 1980) 1155 UNTS 331, art 31(3)(a) and (b). See also K Gorobets, ‘Peaks and Valleys: Contemplating the Authority of International Law’ in K Gorobets, A Hadjigeorgiou, and P Westerman (eds), Conceptual (Re)Constructions of International Law (Edward Elgar 2022) 171 (noting the commonality between CIL and bilateral treaties). General principles, the third sources mentioned in Article 38, generally are not described this way. Their legitimacy is instead usually described either as a concomitant of rule of law principles or as derivative of their acceptance at the national law level.

21 Hakimi (Footnote n 5) 1525 (‘CIL derives what legitimacy it has not from any secondary rules but from the process through which it is developed and used.’).

22 Footnote ibid 1524–26.

23 As Stefan Talmon observes: ‘In none of the cases where the Court has found a (draft) article of the ILC to reflect customary international law did it enquire whether the Commission was actually codifying international law or whether it was not perhaps progressively developing international law. In all cases, the ILC has served as a kind of pseudo-witness for a rule having acquired the status of customary international law.’ S Talmon, ‘Determining Customary International Law: The ICJ’s Methodology between Induction, Deduction and Assertion’ (2015) 26 EJIL 417, 437.

24 One might compare here the more critical reception of the Draft Articles on the Responsibility of International Organizations to that of the much more successful Articles on the Responsibility of States for Internationally Wrongful Acts. See K Daugirdas, ‘Reputation and the Responsibility of International Organizations’ (2014) 25 EJIL 991, 992; ILC, ‘Draft Articles on the Responsibility of International Organizations’ (2011) UN Doc A/66/10; ILC, ‘Draft Articles on Responsibility of States for Internationally Wrongful Acts, with Commentaries’ (23 April–1 June and 2 July–10 August 2001) UN Doc A/56/10.

25 Declaration on Principles of International Law Concerning Friendly Relations and Co-operation among States in Accordance with the Charter of the United Nations, UNGA Res 2625 (XXV) (24 October 1970).

26 Military and Paramilitary Activities in and against Nicaragua (Nicaragua v United States of America) (Merits) [1986] ICJ Rep 14, eg [264].

27 Stockholm Declaration on the Human Environment in ‘Report of the United Nations Conference on the Human Environment’ (Stockholm 5–16 June 1972) (16 June 1972) UN Doc. A/CONF. 48/14, at 2 and Corr. 1.

28 See J Vessey, ‘The Principle of Prevention in International Law’ (1998) 3 ARIEL 181, 182 (observing that ‘the Stockholm Declaration contains the most widely cited version of the principle’); Legality of the Threat or Use of Nuclear Weapons (Advisory Opinion) [1996], ICJ Rep 226 [27], [29].

29 See R Mohamad, ‘Some Reflections on the International Law Commission Topic “Identification of Customary International Law”’ (2016) 15 Chinese JIL 41; ILA, Committee on the Formation of Customary (General) International Law, ‘Statement of Principles Applicable to the Formation of General Customary International Law’ (2000) 24–25.

30 As has been oft noted, the traditional model of Negotiated Law favours action over inaction and the powerful, better-resourced states more able to monitor activity and defend their interests. The vast majority of states are rendered (or kept) voiceless – rule-takers rather than rule-makers. Legislated Law, with its emphasis on formal processes of articulation and a more democratic notion of ratification, shifts that power more towards the majority.

31 See Roberts (Footnote n 7). See also Talmon (Footnote n 23) 429.

32 Choi and Gulati note, for example, that international courts seem more likely to look to treaties and international organization declarations when assessing customs related to human rights and international humanitarian law. See SJ Choi and M Gulati, ‘Customary International Law: How Do Courts Do It?’ in CA Bradley (ed), Custom’s Future: International Law in a Changing World (Cambridge University Press 2016) 117, 145.

33 See eg I Ehrlich and RA Posner, ‘An Economic Analysis of Legal Rulemaking’ (1974) 3 JLS 257, 258, 261.

34 See EA Posner and JC Yoo, ‘Judicial Independence in International Tribunals’ (2005) 93 CLR 1.

35 See N Grossman, ‘Solomonic Judgments and the Legitimacy of the International Court of Justice’ in N Grossman and others (eds), Legitimacy and International Courts (Cambridge University Press 2018) 43; see also LR Helfer and AM Slaughter, ‘Why States Create International Tribunals: A Response to Professors Posner and Yoo’ (2005) 93 CLR 901, 942.

36 To be clear, courts and court-like bodies are not the only ones who can or might articulate this view of the law. Based on reasoned articulation, many legal ‘experts’ may claim this authority, whether they are self-designated (scholars?) or given a specific formal role (UN special rapporteurs).

37 For more on the role of uniformity in Adjudicated Law, see Footnote n 80 and accompanying text.

38 See Cohen, ‘International Law’s Erie Moment’ (Footnote n 12) 259–66.

39 Some may also take categorical approaches, believing that all customary international law rules, for example, can and should be associated with only one of these sources. Such a categorical approach to the justificatory source should and likely will result in an equally categorical approach to interpretation.

40 See eg SA Yeini, ‘The Specially-Affecting States Doctrine’ (2018) 112 AJIL 244. See also generally AS Deeks, ‘Unwilling or Unable: Toward a Normative Framework for Extraterritorial Self-Defense’ (2012) 52 VJIL 483.

41 See KJ Heller, ‘Specially-Affected States and the Formation of Custom’ (2018) 112 AJIL 191 (developing such an account).

42 See eg KJ Heller, ‘The Law of Neutrality Does Not Apply to the Conflict with Al-Qaeda, and It’s a Good Thing, Too: A Response to Chang’ (2011) 47 TILJ 115, 140; ME O’Connell, ‘Remarks: The Resort to Drones under International Law’ (2011) 39 Denv J Intl L & Pol’y 585, 594–95.

43 See Jurisdictional Immunities of the State (Germany v Italy; Greece intervening) (Merits) [2012] ICJ Rep 99; Arrest Warrant (Democratic Republic of the Congo v Belgium) (Jurisdiction and Admissibility) [2002] ICJ Rep 3.

44 See The Prosecutor v Omar Hassan Ahmad Al Bashir (Judgment in the Jordan Referral re Al-Bashir Appeal) ICC-02/05-01/09-397-Corr (6 May 2019) [103].

45 See Jurisdictional Immunities (Footnote n 43) Dissenting Opinion of Judge Cançado Trindade 331.

46 Particularly intriguing here is the ILC’s citation in the final Draft Articles on State Responsibility to the ICJ’s decision in Gabčíkovo Nagymaros, Gabčíkovo-Nagymaros Project (Hungary v Slovakia) (Merits) [1997] ICJ Rep 7, a decision which favourably cited the ILC’s first draft report on the subject, a draft which was itself a distillation of state practice. See J d’Aspremont, ‘Canonical Cross-Referencing in the Making of the Law of International Responsibility’ in S Forlati, M Mbengue, and B McGarry (eds), The Gabčíkovo-Nagymaros Judgment and Its Contribution to the Development of International Law (2020) 22.

47 Think here, for example, of how, regularly repeated, Daniel Webster’s particular formulation of the customary international law of anticipatory self-defense – ‘a necessity of self-defense, instant, overwhelming, leaving no choice of means, and no moment for deliberation’ – is now interpreted almost as text, with each word parsed as if deliberately chosen.

48 See, for example, Ezgi Yildiz and Umut Yüksel’s investigation of the role of ICJ judgments in maritime boundary negotiations. E Yildiz and U Yüksel, ‘Limits of Behavioral Approaches: Lessons from the Field of Maritime Boundary Making’ (2022) 23 GLJ 413–30.

49 See eg T Treves, ‘Customary International Law’ para 2 (2006) MPEPIL <https://opil.ouplaw.com/display/10.1093/law:epil/9780199231690/law-9780199231690-e1393> accessed 27 March 2024; M Bos, A Methodology of International Law (Elsevier 1984).

50 ‘Claims are advanced and interpretations and defenses of actions are offered; exchanges of interpretations are made with other parties; counterclaims or challenges are advanced; arguments are offered, reviewed, assessed, and answered.’ Postema (Footnote n 13) 728.

51 Footnote ibid 726 (‘custom following is never a matter of rote repetition’). Başak Etkin beautifully evokes the image of the river to describe this reality, in which flux is the constant and defining state of customary international law. B Etkin, ‘The Changing Rivers of Customary International Law: The Interpretative Process as Flux’ (2022) 11(5) ESIL Reflections <https://esil-sedi.eu/esil-reflection-the-changing-rivers-of-customary-international-law-the-interpretative-process-as-flux/> accessed 16 December 2022.

52 Postema (Footnote n 13) 728. See also Hakimi (Footnote n 5) 1494 (‘No one entity is entitled to assess the various claims on an issue, weed out the outliers, and finally settle CIL’s normative content.’); MJ Durkee, ‘Interpretive Entrepreneurs’ (2021) 107 VLR 431, 442 (describing interpretation of international law as ‘decentralized’).

53 Etkin (Footnote n 51) (‘While interpretation is done in an active sense by an actor invested with the authority to interpret the rule, be it for instance a court or a state, change (as an umbrella term for modification, evolution and beyond as used in this paper) is the result of that process, and all of these phenomena contribute to the rule’s flux.’)

54 OC Tassinis, ‘Customary International Law: Interpretation from Beginning to End’ (2020) 31 EJIL 235, 243 (‘Observation is then itself theory-laden.’).

55 A Marmor, Interpretation and Legal Theory (2nd edn, Hart 2005) 25.

56 See Chapter 1.

57 See Etkin (Footnote n 51) (‘[T]he direction of fit is doubled, as the interpreting authority, while trying to fit world to word, also fits word to world.’).

58 K Gorobets, ‘Practical Reasoning and Interpretation of Customary International Law’ in P Merkouris, J Kammerhofer, and N Arajärvi (eds), The Theory, Practice and Interpretation of Customary International Law (Cambridge University Press 2021) 382 (‘This is precisely why, even when states do not explicate their position regarding actions of other states, this may still contribute to formation of a new, or sustaining an existing, practice.’), also 375 (observing that ‘state practices are not only the containers but also the content of rules one wants to interpret’).

59 This is precisely why, even when states do not explicate their position regarding actions of other states, this may still contribute to the formation of a new, or sustaining of an existing, practice. Even an absence of reaction may, under certain circumstances, be deciphered by other participants in a practice meaningfully either as endorsement or at least as acquiescence. Gorobets, ‘Practical Reasoning’ (Footnote n 58) 382.

60 Footnote ibid (‘From this perspective, customary rules do not and cannot exist separately or detached from practices that sustain them.’). See also J d’Aspremont, ‘The Multidimensional Process of Interpretation: Content-Determination and Law-Ascertainment Distinguished’ in A Bianchi, D Peat, and M Windsor (eds), Interpretation in International Law (Oxford University Press 2015) 111, 114 (‘all practices and discourses about international law having an interpretive dimension’).

61 Postema (Footnote n 13) 728.

62 See Chapter 1 (where Westerman describes a ‘practice of claims’ in which opinio juris is understood best ‘not as a conviction or belief’ but ‘as an articulated and publicly accessible claim’). See also d’Aspremont (Footnote n 60) 113.

63 Cohen, ‘International Law’s Erie Moment’ (Footnote n 12); HG Cohen, ‘Methodology and Misdirection: Custom and the ICJ’ (EJIL:Talk!, 1 December 2015) <www.ejiltalk.org/methodology-and-misdirection-a-response-to-stefan-talmon-on-custom-and-the-icj/> accessed 27 May 2022.

64 FV Kratochwil, Rules, Norms, and Decisions: On the Conditions of Practical and Legal Reasoning in International Relations and Domestic Affairs (Cambridge University Press 1989) 102.

66 ‘In the international system, which does not have the benefit of much judicial assistance, the norms are interpreted, elaborated, shaped, reformulated, and applied in large part in the course of debate about the justification for contested action.’ A Chayes and AH Chayes, The New Sovereignty: Compliance with International Regulatory Agreements (Harvard University Press 1995) 122.

67 See eg B Clark, ‘The Vienna Convention Reservations Regime and the Convention on Discrimination Against Women’ (1991) 85 AJIL 281, 361.

68 See P Merkouris, ‘Interpreting the Customary Rules on Interpretation’ (2017) 19 ICLR 126.

69 Footnote ibid 128, 136.

70 See Tassinis (Footnote n 54) 244–46.

71 Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties (Footnote n 20) art 31(3)(c).

72 Cohen, ‘International Law’s Erie Moment’ (Footnote n 12).

73 Legality of the Threat or Use of Nuclear Weapons, Dissenting Opinion, in Talmon (Footnote n 23) 423.

74 Talmon (Footnote n 23) 423.

77 Footnote ibid 434–40.

78 HG Cohen, ‘Theorizing Precedent in International Law’ in A Bianchi, D Peat, and M Windsor (eds), Interpretation in International Law (Oxford University Press 2015) 268, 282–83.

79 Coherence is arguably a factor in the legitimacy of their judgments. See TM Franck, ‘Legitimacy in the International System’ (1988) 82 AJIL 705, 712.

80 One can arguably see the results of the opposite in perceptions of the International Criminal Court, where regular disagreements between its judges have undercut its legitimacy. For some discussion, see D Guilfoyle, ‘Lacking Conviction: Is the International Criminal Court Broken? An Organisational Failure Analysis’ (2019) 20 Melb JIL 401.

81 For more, see Cohen, ‘International Law’s Erie Moment’ (Footnote n 12); Cohen, ‘Methodology and Misdirection’ (Footnote n 63).

82 See Etkin (Footnote n 51) (‘One cannot adjudicate the same custom twice.’). Recognizing that decisions of international courts are only ‘subsidiary means for the determination of such rules’, the ILC nods in this direction as well. ILC (Footnote n 3) 149 (‘It needs to be borne in mind, moreover, that judicial pronouncements on customary international law do not freeze the law: rules of customary international law may have evolved since the date of a particular decision.’). Whether courts pay any attention is a different matter.

83 Understanding on the Rules and Procedures Governing the Settlement of Disputes, Annex 2 to the 1994 Agreement Establishing the World Trade Organization (1947) 1869 UNTS 401, art 3.2.

84 See Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties (Footnote n 20) art 31(3)(c). See also Merkouris (Footnote n 68).

85 See HG Cohen, ‘Culture Clash: The Sociology of WTO Precedent’ in A Frese and J Schumann (eds), Precedent as Rules and Practice: New Approaches and Methodologies in Studies of Legal Precedents (Nomos 2021) 112; N Ridi, ‘United States: Anti-dumping Measures Applying Differential Pricing Methodology to Softwood Lumber from Canada’ (2020) 114 AJIL 735.

86 See Cohen, ‘Culture Clash’ (Footnote n 85) 114–22.

87 The question is usually complicated by its entanglement of treaty and customary international law, though, as noted in Section 2, from the perspective of interpretation those may not be as different as is usually thought.

88 See similar discussion in A Roberts, ‘Power and Persuasion in Investment Treaty Interpretation: The Dual Role of States’ (2010) 104 AJIL 179.

4 Interpretation Dynamics in CIL An Entropic Approach

1 See eg M Jovanovic, The Nature of International Law (Cambridge University Press 2019) 228–33; J Kammerhofer, Uncertainty in International Law: A Kelsenian Perspective (Routledge 2010) 3–4, 59.

2 Such cognitive questions lie at the heart of the epistemological debate concerning CIL’s uncertainty. See J Kammerhofer (Footnote n 1) 3–4. Yet there is not necessarily a strong connection between certainty and knowledge. AP Martinich and A Stroll, ‘epistemology’, Encyclopedia Britannica (26 August 2022) <www.britannica.com/topic/epistemology> accessed 10 January 2023.

3 P Merkouris, ‘Interpreting Customary International Law: You’ll Never Walk Alone’ in P Merkouris, J Kammerhofer and N Arajarvi (eds), The Theory, Practice, and Interpretation of Customary International Law (Cambridge University Press 2022) 4.

4 HLA Hart, The Concept of the Law (1st edn, Cambridge University Press 1961) esp 12–13.

5 A Guzman, ‘A Compliance-Based Theory of International Law’ (2002) 90 CLR 1823; A D’Amato, ‘Legal Uncertainty’ (2010) Faculty Working Papers 108 <http://scholarlycommons.law.northwestern.edu/facultyworkingpapers/108> accessed 10 January 2023.

6 Jovanovich (Footnote n 1) 232 n.

7 Use of probabilistic reasoning to frame and manage risk, and thus uncertainty, by predicting a number of possible outcomes and adopting preventive measures seems to offer a way out of the uncertainty gap. S Townley, ‘The Rise of Risk in International Law’ (2018) 18 CJIL 593; M Ambrus, R Reyfuse and W Werner (eds), Risk and the Regulation of Uncertainty in International Law (Oxford University Press 2017) 3–10. Yet such an approach is based upon a fragmented view of international law, as the various legal regimes function according to their own rules and procedures, hence the need for a ‘different modelling for framing and regulating their inherent uncertainties’. See Jovanovich (Footnote n 1) 3.

8 The concept of a polycentric policy dispute was introduced by LL Fuller, who described a situation of interacting points of influence among a large number of parties that generates a polycentric problem, which, he argued, is beyond the limits of adjudication. LL Fuller and KI Winston, ‘The Forms and Limits of Adjudication’ (1978) 92 Harv L Rev 353.

9 A Grotian moment occurs when a fundamental change within the international system, acting as an accelerating agent, enables CIL to form rapidly and with less state practice instead of the ordinary long-term process. See M Scharf, ‘Hugo Grotius and the Concept of Grotian Moments in International Law’ (2022) 54 CWR J Int Law 17. See also T Sparks and M Somos, ‘Grotian Moments: An Introduction’ (2021) 42 Grotiana 179.

10 PH Verdier and E Voeten, ‘Precedent, Compliance, and Change in Customary International Law: An Explanatory Theory’ (2014) 108 AJIL 389.

11 The word dynamics comes from the Greek denames, meaning force. Authors who have dealt with the dynamic character of CIL have mostly treated the subject through the lens of political science. See the insightful work of P Diehl and C Ku, The Dynamics of International Law (Cambridge University Press 2010) esp 1–27, in which, through the lens of international relations, the authors offer an explanation of how and why international law evolves with a view to closing the gap between international law and international relations.

12 E Kades, ‘The Laws of Complexity and the Complexity of Laws: The Implications of Computational Complexity Theory for the Law’ (1997) Faculty Publications 646 <https://scholarship.law.wm.edu/facpubs/646> accessed 25 January 2023.

13 The expression ‘I know … when I see it’ was famously used by US Supreme Court judge Potter Stewart in 1964 when referring to hard-core pornography, which lay outside the Constitution’s protection of obscenity. Jacobellis v Ohio (378 U.S. 184).

14 To a layman, a complex problem might seem equivalent to a complicated problem; however, this is far from the truth since the two concepts are qualitatively different. See Section 3.

15 G Scelle, Manuel de droit international public (Domat-Montchrestien 1948) 9–10 and esp 577–78.

16 On interpretation as a self-referential construction that ‘invents [its] own origin and regulates [its] own functioning’, see J d’Aspremont, ‘Bypassing the Authority of International Law: The Virtue of Modern Self-Referentiality’ (21 September 2017; forthcoming in G Hernandez and G Jokubauskaite (eds), Constructing Authority in International Law) <https://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=3040975> accessed 1 February 2023. On the basic characteristics of complex adaptive systems, see B Parsons, ‘Using Complexity Science Concepts When Designing System Interventions and Evaluations’ (InSites, April 2010, revised March 2012) <https://insites.org/wp-content/uploads/559c709812d66-InS.10.CASConcpts.pdf> accessed 1 February 2023.

17 According to Scelle, legal security is achieved through the judicial function. See Scelle (Footnote n 15) 662–64. See also Section 4, where it will be argued that these conclusions are mirrored in the process of CIL interpretation by international criminal tribunals.

18 This deterministic view of nature is chaotic (deterministic chaos). Chaos, as perceived in natural sciences, is not to be confused with disorder and decay. On the contrary, it describes dynamic systems that evolve over time depending on their initial conditions and the precision with which these conditions can be measured. Thus, determinism is related to a probabilistic view of things but not to strict predictability. See M Cattani and others, ‘Deterministic Chaos Theory: Some Basic Concepts’ (2017) 39(1) RBEF e1309-1.

19 RP Crease, ‘Comment: The Quantum Moment’ (2013) 26(3) Physics World 25.

20 Y Tan, The Rome Statute as Evidence of Customary International Law (Brill 2021) 1–27; WA Schabas, The International Criminal Court: A Commentary on the Rome Statute (2nd edn, Oxford University Press 2016) 519–23; L van den Herik, ‘The Decline of Customary International Law as a Source of International Criminal Law’ in C Bradley (ed), Custom’s Future: International Law in a Changing World (Cambridge University Press 2016) 230–52.

21 C Stahn, A Critical Introduction to International Criminal Law (Cambridge University Press 2019) 95.

22 A Bufalini, ‘The Principle of Legality and the Role of CIL in the Interpretation of the ICC Statute’ (2015) 14 LPICT 233.

23 The term, from the French contrainte sociale, belongs to Scelle, who argued that sociability (sociabilité) describes the true nature of contemporary international society. Scelle (Footnote n 15) 577–78.

24 JW Forrester, World Dynamics (2nd edn, Wright-Allen 1973).

25 C Mesjasz, ‘Complexity of Social Systems’ (2010) 117 Acta Phys Pol A 706, 707–08; S Wheatley, The Idea of International Human Rights Law (Oxford University Press 2019) 45–48; A Siegenfeld and Y Bar-Yam, ‘An Introduction to Complex Systems Science and Its Applications’ [2020] Complexity <https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1155/2020/6105872> accessed 1 March 2023.

26 Although complex systems may be complicated, this is not their inherent characteristic. A car and an aircraft are examples of complicated systems, since they can be dismantled and their parts put back together again. As far as legal systems are concerned, the large number of laws and the ambiguity of their content does not necessarily mean that there are many interactions between the system’s components. See D Bourcier and P Mazzega, ‘Toward Measures of Complexity in Legal Systems’, ICAIL ’07: Proceedings of the11th International Conference on Artificial Intelligence and Law (June 2007) <https://dl.acm.org/doi/10.1145/1276318.1276359> accessed 27 May 2024.

27 For a digest of the distinctions between the two concepts, see JM Kamensky, ‘Managing the Complicated vs. the Complex’ (IBM Center for the Business of Government, Fall/Winter 2011) <www.businessofgovernment.org/sites/default/files/JohnKamensky.pdf> accessed 1 March 2023.

28 WL Hosch, ‘isomorphism’, Encyclopedia Britannica (15 July 2009) <www.britannica.com/science/isomorphism-mathematics> accessed 1 March 2023.

29 Modelling a complex social system, like CIL, will inevitably entail a simplified representation of reality, since, especially at this early stage of research, it is not possible to depict all possible interactions, direct and indirect, between the agents of the system (see Figure 1). See C Castellano, S Fortunato and V Loretto, ‘Statistical Physics on Social Dynamics’ (2009) 81 RMP 591; M Boon and T Knuuttila, ‘Models as Epistemic Tools in Engineering Sciences’ in AWM Meijers (ed), Philosophy of Technology and Engineering Sciences (Elsevier 2009) 695–703.

30 It is important to note that these developments are also recognized by the ILC in ‘Draft Conclusions on Identification of Customary International Law, with Commentaries’ (30 April–1 June and 2 July–10 August 2018) UN Doc A/73/10. Yet the ILC emphatically states that, as a constituent element of customary international law, general practice refers primarily to the practice of states and only secondarily to the practice of international organizations. As far as other non-state actors are concerned, their practice can play only an indirect role ‘to the extent that States have endorsed or reacted [to these practices]’ (Conclusion 4, emphasis added). For text accompanying Footnote n. 35 for a characteristic example of states’ reactions. On the behaviour of non-state actors regarding CIL and how they affect transnational behaviour, see also RB Baker, ‘Customary International Law: A Reconceptualization’ (2016) 41 BJIL 458.

31 Prosecutor v Dominic Ongwen, ICC-02/04-01/15 (4 February 2021).

32 Footnote ibid [2766]. Customary practices regarding land ownership adopted by indigenous peoples have been taken into account not only by the ICC but also by human rights judicial bodies. As a result, possession of land by indigenous communities should suffice for official recognition of ownership even if a title of ownership is missing. Mayagna (Sumo) Awas Tingni Community v Nicaragua (Merits, Reparations and Costs) IACHR Series C No 79 (2001) [151].

33 A cluster is defined as a group of states that, on occasion, operate coherently towards a specific objective.

34 The concept of shared understanding of the law draws upon the theory of interactional law as conceived and developed by J Brunnée and S Toope, ‘International Law and the Practice of Legality: Stability and Change’ (2018) 49 VUWLR, 429, 433–37. The present author similarly considers that ‘the law is grounded in a society’s shared understanding’ and further argues in favour of a dynamic CIL system, capable of change and subsequent evolution, while acknowledging the need to safeguard its predictable character. See also van Aaken’s view on the role of states and international courts in the interpretation process from the perspective of veto player theory. A van Aaken ‘Interests, Strategies and Veto Players: The Political Economy of Interpreting Customary International Law’ (2022) ESIL Reflections 11(2) <https://esil-sedi.eu/wp-content/uploads/2022/09/ESIL-Reflection-Anne-van-Aaken_final-version.pdf> accessed 2 April 2022.

35 UK Government, ‘Chemical Weapon Use by Syrian Regime: UK Government Legal Position’ (Policy paper, 29 August 2013) <www.gov.uk/government/publications/chemical-weapon-use-by-syrian-regime-uk-government-legal-position/chemical-weapon-use-by-syrian-regime-uk-government-legal-position-html-version> accessed 7 March 2023. Yet, like its allies, the UK relied on the customary law status of the prohibition on the use of chemical weapons that most states accepted. For present purposes, we do not consider whether the UK’s position was valid according to the interpretation of CIL current at the time.

36 A system’s environment encompasses factors beyond its natural boundaries that affect it through the exchange of energy/information. See K Bailey, Social Entropy (State University of New York Press 1990) 51.

37 None of the four states that abstained referred to this issue. UNSC 8233rd meeting (14 April 2018) UN Doc S/PV.8233 (Provisional) <https://documents-dds-ny.un.org/doc/UNDOC/PRO/N18/108/91/PDF/N1810891.pdf?OpenElement> accessed 30 April 2022. See M Milanovic, ‘The Syria Strikes: Still Clearly Illegal’ (EJIL:Talk!, 15 April 2018) <www.ejiltalk.org/the-syria-strikes-still-clearly-illegal/> accessed 30 April 2020; C Henderson, ‘The UK Government’s Legal Opinion on Forcible Measures in Response to the Use of Chemical Weapons by the Syrian Government’ (2015) 64 ICLQ 179.

38 PH Schuck, ‘Legal Complexity: Some Causes, Consequences and Cures’ (1992) 42 DLJ 9.

39 Prosecutor v Uhuru Muigai Kenyatta, ICC-01/09-02/11 (18 October 2013) [102]–[103], citing Hersch Lauterpacht, The Development of International Law by the International Court (Cambridge University Press 1996) 395–96.

40 Prosecutor v Uhuru Muigai Kenyatta, ICC-01/09-02/11 (18 October 2013), separate further opinion of Judge Eboe-Osuji [12].

41 These may be ‘short path lengths’ and/or ‘high clustering coefficients’ (i.e. the links between two or three neighbouring nodes). F Schweitzer, ‘Sociophysics’ (2018) 71 Physics Today 2, 40. With regard to a CIL complex system, see also Figure 2 (public domain map available at <www.freeworldmaps.net> accessed 20 March 2022)

42 D Goodstein, ‘mechanics’, Encyclopedia Britannica (21 August 2020) <www.britannica.com/science/mechanics> accessed 2 April 2022.

43 The German mathematician and philosopher Leibniz (1646–1716) conceived the word dynamics from the Greek word δύναμις (denames), meaning ‘force’, ‘strength’ or ‘power’, which in turn comes from the Greek word δύναμαι (denamai), meaning ‘I can’ or ‘I am able’.

44 On the ‘paradox of custom as a source both dynamic and stabilizing’, see O Corten and others, A Critical Introduction to International Law (Éditions de l’Université de Bruxelles 2019) 311–14; P Staubach, The Rule of Written International Law (Routledge 2018) 56–63.

45 The German physicist and mathematician Clausius (1822–88) synthesized ‘entropy’ (entrepein in Greek) from the terms ‘energy’ and ‘trope’ (i.e. direction of motion); it literally means to turn about, to change.

46 Thus, entropy was defined as the thermodynamic state of a physical system according to the distribution of its internal thermal energy. See GWF Drake, ‘thermodynamics’, Encyclopedia Britannica (15 May 2023) <www.britannica.com/science/thermodynamics> accessed 10 April 2022.

47 It was thus clear that the second thermodynamics law was essentially statistical; thus, entropy can be measured to give us the total number of possible states of particles distributed within a given system. See J Sethna, ‘What Is Statistical Mechanics?’ in Statistical Mechanics: Entropy, Order Parameters and Complexity (2nd edn, Oxford University Press 2021) 6.

48 ET Jaynes, ‘Information Theory and Statistical Mechanics’ (1957) 106 Phys Rev 620, 622. As successfully argued, ‘the purpose of probability theory is to help us in forming plausible conclusions in cases where there is not enough information available to lead to certain conclusions; thus detailed verification is not expected.’ (Footnote ibid 622).

49 It is crucial to note that entropy is always a property of the whole (i.e. a system) but not of the microstates that form the system. As a probabilistic concept, entropy ‘does not focus on individuals or small sub-sets, [but] presupposes a macroscopic view of the [physical] phenomena’. D Koutsoyiannis and GF Sargentis, ‘Entropy and Wealth’ (2021) 23 Entropy 1356.

50 In a social context, entropy has been applied to indicate disorder, social disintegration and possibly the decay of society, largely due to its ability to increase. As a natural property, however, entropy is an objective concept and not a subjective one with negative implications for the future of humanity. E Michaelides, ‘Entropy, Order and Disorder’ (2008) 2 Open Thermodyn J 7. In this respect, entropy constitutes the driving force of evolution, since in a state of uncertainty there is a plurality of options, which in turn entails freedom to choose among the most probable outcomes. See Koutsoyiannis and Sargentis (Footnote n 49) 1364.

51 Although the concept of equilibrium is crucial in structuring a system, it has been misinterpreted as the self-maintenance of order in a system and the non-randomness of the system’s variables. However, drawing an analogy between equilibrium and regularity has been correctly characterized as arbitrary, since in a state of equilibrium there can be no change in a closed or isolated system except where an external force acts upon parts of the system. See Britannica, The Editors of Encyclopedia, ‘equilibrium’, Encyclopedia Britannica (21 July 2022) <www.britannica.com/science/equilibrium-physics> accessed 12 May 2022.

52 C Shannon, ‘A Mathematical Theory of Communication’ (1948) 27 BSTJ 379 and 623.

53 O Rioul, ‘This Is IT: A Primer on Shannon’s Entropy and Information’ in B Duplantier and V Rivasseau (eds), Information Theory (Progress in Mathematical Physics vol 78, Springer 2021).

54 JP Sethna (Footnote n 47) 99.

55 Based on mathematics and computer science, a binary relation is represented by a line connecting the two entities. There are three types of binary relations: one-to-one, where one entity is related to another entity; one-to-many, where one entity is related to many other entities; and many-to-many, where each entity is related to many other entities. A characteristic example of a many-to-many binary relation is a university student enrolled in many courses with each course having many students enrolled in it. For present purposes we are referring to a one-to-one binary relation between international criminal courts and individual states in a simplified form (see Figure 1).

56 The judicial function is the main feature of the judicial authority. Literally, juris dictio means to state what the law is. Scelle (Footnote n 15) 694–95. Notwithstanding the debate over the susceptibility of CIL rules to the same form of interpretation as treaty law, the arbitration tribunal in the Lake Lanoux case of 1957 clarified that ‘international law does not sanction any absolute and rigid method of interpretation’. See Lake Lanoux (France v Spain) (1957) 12 RIAA 281. See also M Herdegen, ‘Interpretation in International Law’ (MPEPIL 2020) <https://opil.ouplaw.com/display/10.1093/law:epil/9780199231690/law-9780199231690-e723> accessed 26 April 2024. Accordingly, the present author argues that interpretation has an entropic character since it gives meaning to CIL rules by transmitting information about their content. On the discussion regarding the role of the international judiciary, see also GI Hernández, ‘Interpretative Authority and the International Judiciary’ in A Bianchi, D Peat and M Windsor (eds), Interpretation in International Law (Oxford University Press 2015) 166–85.

57 Merkouris and Mileva have argued that interpretation of a CIL rule performs an evolutive function in addition to the concretizing one. See P Merkouris and N Mileva, ‘Introduction to the Series: Customary Law Interpretation as a Tool’ (2022) 11(2) ESIL Reflections <https://esil-sedi.eu/esil-reflection-introduction-to-the-series-customary-law-interpretation-as-a-tool/> accessed 20 May 2022. The present author believes that there is no clear-cut distinction between these two functions of legal reasoning; in practice, they are intertwined with each other, like ivy on an oak tree, and shape the content of a CIL rule through evolutive interpretation. The content-determination process of interpretation is an inherent part of adjudication. On the content-determination process and its distinction from the law-ascertainment process of interpretation, see J d’Aspremont, ‘The Multidimensional Process of Interpretation: Content-Determination and Law-Ascertainment Distinguished’ in A Bianchi, D Peat and M Windsor (eds), Interpretation in International Law (Oxford University Press 2015) 111, 117–18.

58 Prosecutor v Al-Bashir, ICC-02/05-01/09-397-Anx1 (6 May 2019) [66] (emphasis added). It has been said that this judgment ‘has added another important layer of jurisprudence, [although] it will not silence the raging academic and political debate’. See A Mudukuti, ‘Prosecutor v. Omar Hassan Ahmad Al-Bashir, Judgment in the Jordan Referral re Al-Bashir Appeal’ (2020) 114 AJIL 103. See also Prosecutor v Uhuru Muigai Kenyatta (Footnote n 40) [7], [12].

59 Prosecutor v Ongwen (Footnote n 31) [2741].

60 Prosecutor v Kupreskic (Judgment) ICTY-95-16-T (14 January 2000) [562]–[566].

61 Footnote ibid [566]. See also Prosecutor v Kordic and Cerkez (Judgment) ICTY-95-14/2-T (26 February 2001) [269]–[270]; Prosecutor v Kordic and Cerkez (Judgment) ICTY-95-14/2-A (17 December 2004). In the Ongwen case, the ICC followed the same interpretive approach when it had to decide if the act of forced marriage could be qualified as another inhumane act, and subsequently as a crime against humanity, according to Article 7(1)(k) of the Rome Statute (Statute of the International Criminal Court (adopted 17 July 1998, entered into force 1 July 2002) 2187 UNTS 3). See Prosecutor v Ongwen (Footnote n 31) [2741], [2747].

62 Prosecutor v Krstic (Judgment) ICTY-98-33-T (2 August 2001) [580].

63 Prosecutor v Ntaganda, ICC-01/04-02/06 OA5 (15 June 2017).

64 Footnote ibid [52]–[55]. See also F Pocar, ‘Symposium on the Rome Statute at Twenty: Transformation of Customary Law through ICC Practice’ (2018) 112 AJIL Unbound 182.

65 Prosecutor v Ntaganda (Footnote n 63) [53].

66 Footnote ibid [54]. On the interpretability of CIL, see P Merkouris, ‘Interpreting the Customary Rules on Interpretation’ (2017) 19 ICLR 139. For an early, yet meaningful, discussion regarding the contribution of international case law to the interpretation of CIL, see KS Gallant, ‘International Criminal Courts and the Making of Public International Law: New Roles for International Organizations and Individuals’ (2010) 43 J Marshall L Rev. 607.

67 Scelle (Footnote n 15) 16–17, 662–64, 676–78. According to the French jurist, the judicial function aims towards establishing a legal order (‘ordonnancement juridique’) that describes the legal relations/connections between public and private persons. Scelle’s systemic approach to international law dates back to 1948.

68 Interlocutory Decision on the Applicable Law: Terrorism, Conspiracy, Homicide, Perpetration, Cumulative Charging STL-11-01/I (16 February 2011).

69 Footnote ibid [23]–[24]. On Judge Cassese’s contribution regarding the construction of international criminal law through custom, see M Fan, ‘Custom, General Principles and the Great Architect Cassese’ (2012) 10 JICJ 1063.

70 Interlocutory Decision (Footnote n 68) [26] (emphasis added).

71 Footnote ibid [19]–[20]. For present purposes, ‘contextualize’ means ‘to provide information about the situation in which something happens’. See ‘contextualize’ (The Britannica Dictionary) <www.britannica.com/dictionary/contextualize> accessed 30 May 2022.

72 Interlocutory Decision (Footnote n 68) [26].

73 Footnote ibid [30].

74 Footnote ibid [106], [135].

75 Footnote ibid. The ICC has equally ruled in the Ongwen case and in relation to Article 7(1)(k) of the Rome Statute that judicial interpretation ‘must be consistent with the essence of the offence and in a manner which could have been reasonably foreseen’. Prosecutor v Ongwen (Footnote n 31) [2741] (emphasis added). Yet debate over the strict application of the legality principle remains intense, with those opposed arguing in favour of flexibility of the rules in order to fight impunity. See JL Corsi, ‘An Argument for Strict Legality in International Criminal Law’ (2018) 49(4) GJIL 1321.

76 According to Sur, the subjects of international law provide feedback when they accept a judicial interpretation; in so doing, they lend authenticity to this interpretation. S Sur, ‘La créativité du droit international’ (2012) 363 RdC 9. Such was the interpretative stance of the ICC in the Ntaganda case when the Court rejected the defence submissions on introducing status requirements as additional elements to the war crimes of Article 8(2)(b)(xxii) and (e)(vi) of the Rome Statute. The Court thereby transmitted information on the customary law context of war crimes based on the intention of the drafters of the Rome Statute; such intention demonstrated the drafters’ shared understanding of the provisions. Prosecutor v Ntaganda (Footnote n 63) [47]–[48].

77 Prosecutor v Al-Bashir, Decision under Article 87(7) of the Rome Statute on the Non-compliance by South Africa with the Request by the Court for the Arrest and Surrender of Omar Al-Bashir, ICC-02/05-01/09-302 (6 July 2017); Prosecutor v al-Bashir, Decision under Article 87(7) of the Rome Statute on the Con-compliance by Jordan with the Request by the Court for the Arrest and Surrender or Omar Al-Bashir, ICC-02/05-01/09-309 (11 December 2017).

78 Rome Statute (Footnote n 61) arts 86ff.

79 Although strongly criticized for these judgments by part of academia, the ICJ had already been receptive to the idea that the immunity rule cannot justify impunity when the accused is a head of state. Case Concerning the Arrest Warrant of 11 April 2000 (Democratic Republic of Congo v Belgium) [2002] ICJ Rep 3.

80 Prosecutor v Al-Bashir (Footnote n 77) (11 December 2017) [53].

81 Prosecutor v Al-Bashir (Footnote n 77) (6 July 2017) [136].

82 Prosecutor v Al-Bashir, ICC-02/05-01/09 OA2 (6 May 2019) [204].

83 A characteristic example is the European Court of Human Rights and the profound influence of its judgments upon the shaping of state policies, through the adoption of national legislation and/or administrative practice. See Verdier, and Voeten (Footnote n 10) 420; L Helfer and E Voeten, ‘International Courts as Agents of Legal Change: Evidence from LGBT Rights in Europe’ (2014) 68 IO 77. In the area of international criminal law, the notion of positive complementarity as a state policy to address core crimes through the adoption of domestic measures and the initiation of national proceedings, is of particular importance with respect to the feedback provided by member states to the Rome Statute. See Annual Report of the Office of the Prosecutor (2022) <www.icc-cpi.int/sites/default/files/2022-12/2022-12-05-annual-report-of-the-office-of-the-prosecutor.pdf> accessed 1 June 2022; Final Report of the ILA Committee on positive complementarity in international criminal law (2022) <www.ila-hq.org/en/committees/complementarity-in-international-criminal-law> accessed 1 June 2022.

Figure 0

Table 1 Justification-based sources of international law

Figure 1

Table 2 Justification-based sources of international law: summary

Figure 2

Figure 1 A one-to-one, binary relationship

Figure 3

Figure 2 Security Council draft resolution proposed by the Russian Federation

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×