Published online by Cambridge University Press: 05 June 2014
Although today we tend to invoke supermajority rules as an alternative to majority rule, the classical medieval justification for supermajority rules emerged as a substitute for unanimity. As the preceding chapter suggested, the unanimity requirement for the election of the pope broke down early in the second millennium, and was replaced with the doctrine of the sanior et maior pars, by which those electors possessing sounder judgment prevailed. But conflict over the criteria for sound judgment led again to breakdown. Further, following innovations designed to improve the learning and moral quality of the cardinals who served as electors, a strictly aggregative procedure could be introduced: each elector had a judgment worthy of being counted. In choosing a decision rule, the aim was to reflect the epistemic dignity of the electors through a strictly aggregative mechanism.
Supermajority rule from the twelfth century reflected commitments that made it in many ways more attractive than the unanimity it replaced. The most important of these commitments was the acceptance of fallibility, both moral and epistemic. Because people can err both in conduct and judgment, a unanimity rule came to be seen as excessively demanding. A unanimous election required perfect concord: no member could veto a candidate for his own private purposes, or fail to correctly identify the pope. In contrast, a supermajority rule accommodated the possibility that members of an assembly would fail to recognize the truth or would not agree, but wide support of the electors signified both that the outcome reflected the divine will and would command the cardinals’ allegiance.
To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.
Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.
Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.
To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.
To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.