Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-jkksz Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-18T23:50:56.990Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Chapter 14 - A neo-Aristotelian substance ontology: neither relational nor constituent

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 December 2011

Tuomas E. Tahko
Affiliation:
University of Helsinki
Get access

Summary

Following the lead of Gustav Bergmann (1967), if not his precise terminology, ontologies are sometimes divided into those that are ‘relational’ and those that are ‘constituent’ (Wolterstorff 1970). Substance ontologies in the Aristotelian tradition are commonly thought of as being constituent ontologies, because they typically espouse the hylemorphic dualism of Aristotle’s Metaphysics – a doctrine according to which an individual substance is always a combination of matter and form. But an alternative approach drawing more on the fourfold ontological scheme of Aristotle’s Categories is not committed to this doctrine and may regard individual (or ‘primary’) substances as having no constituent structure, their only possible complexity residing in their possession, in some cases, of a multiplicity of substantial parts. However, as we shall see, this does not imply that such an ontology falls instead into the relational camp: for although it invokes, in addition to the category of individual substance, also those of substantial kind (‘secondary’ substance), attribute, and mode (or ‘individual accident’), it need not and arguably should not take there to be external relations between entities in the different categories. On this view, truths of exemplification and instantiation, such as ‘Dobbin is white’ and ‘Dobbin is a horse’, do not need relational truthmakers. Hence, it can be maintained that there are no such relations as ‘exemplification’ and ‘instantiation’, at most only certain relational truths of exemplification and instantiation – truths whose logical form is relational. This being so, I shall argue, such an ontology cannot fairly be classified as a ‘relational’ one.

Constituent versus relational ontologies

There is a common presumption that ontologies inspired by Aristotle are ‘constituent’ ontologies, whereas ones inspired by Plato are ‘relational’ – a presumption founded on the notion that Aristotle’s metaphysics is distinctively ‘immanent’ whereas Plato’s is distinctively ‘transcendent’. This way of putting matters is obviously rather crude and simplistic, but may still seem to capture an important difference. The immanent/transcendent distinction appears to come down to this: that the immanentist sees the properties of concrete objects as being ingredients of those very objects, whereas the transcendentist sees them as being separate entities to which the objects stand in some special relation of exemplification. By ‘properties’ in this context I mean to speak very broadly, to include not only features, such as redness or squareness, but also forms, such as humanity or equinity. Of course, some may hold that forms are merely combinations of features but others, including myself, certainly deny this. I am also assuming that, at this point at least, both features and forms are to be understood as being universals, rather than particulars, and in this respect unlike the concrete objects – or ‘individual substances’ – which ‘possess’ them. However, it is certainly open to a metaphysician to hold that features and forms are themselves particulars, or indeed to hold that features and forms come in two different varieties – the universal and the particular – so that, for example, as well as redness the universal feature we have a plurality of particular rednesses, a different one belonging to each individual substance that is red.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2011

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×