Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-6bf8c574d5-h6jzd Total loading time: 0.001 Render date: 2025-02-22T19:20:12.279Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

5 - Moral Dilemmas

from Part I - Building Blocks

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  20 February 2025

Bertram Malle
Affiliation:
Brown University, Rhode Island
Philip Robbins
Affiliation:
University of Missouri
Get access

Summary

This chapter of the handbook tackles a frequently discussed topic in moral psychology: moral dilemmas. The authors offer a normative characterization of moral dilemmas as a situation in which every available course of action involves a difficult moral trade-off and it is morally appropriate for the agent to feel conflicted about the choices available. The authors then explore different empirical accounts of why some moral trade-offs are experienced as difficult or impossible to resolve. Among the most influential of these accounts is dual-process theory, which traces the experience of moral dilemmas to a conflict between a value backed by automatic emotional processes and a value backed by reflection. The authors argue against the dual-process account, and review empirical research bearing on the psychological mechanisms underpinning a person’s experience and resolution of moral dilemmas, as well as the phenomenon of “moral residue.” They argue that further empirical work is needed to understand how people weigh competing values against one another and that such understanding requires expanding the range of moral dilemmas to include cases beyond those targeted in recent research.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2025

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Bago, B., & De Neys, W. (2019). The intuitive greater good: Testing the corrective dual process model of moral cognition. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 148(10), 17821801.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Barcan Marcus, R. (1980). Moral dilemmas and consistency. Journal of Philosophy, 77(3), 121136.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baron, J., & Gürcay, B. (2017). A meta-analysis of response-time tests of the sequential two-systems model of moral judgment. Memory & Cognition, 45, 566575.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Baron, J., & Spranca, M. (1997). Protected values. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 70, 116.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Bartels, D. M., Bauman, C. W., Cushman, F. A., Pizarro, D. A., & McGraw, A. P. (2015). Moral judgment and decision making. In Keren, G. & Wu, G. (Eds.), The Wiley Blackwell handbook of judgment and decision making (Vol. 1; pp. 478515). Wiley Blackwell.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Berman, J. Z., & Kupor, D. (2020). Moral choice when harming is unavoidable. Psychological Science, 31(10), 12941301.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Bialek, M., & De Neys, W. (2016). Conflict detection during moral decision-making: Evidence for deontic reasoners’ utilitarian sensitivity. Journal of Cognitive Psychology, 2(5), 631639.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Borges, L. M., Barnes, S. M., Farnsworth, J. K., Frescher, K. D., & Walser, R. D. (2020). A contextual behavioral approach for responding to moral dilemmas in the age of COVID-19. Journal of Contextual Behavioral Science, 17, 95101.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Bostyn, D. H., Sevenhant, H., & Roets, A. (2018). Of mice, men, and trolleys: Hypothetical judgment versus real-life behavior in trolley-style moral dilemmas. Psychological Science, 29(7), 10841093.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Capraro, V., Everett, J. A. C., & Earp, B. D. (2019). Priming intuition disfavors instrumental harm but not impartial beneficence. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 83, 142149.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chang, R. (Ed.). (1997). Incommensurability, incomparability, and practical reason. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Conee, E. (1982). Against moral dilemmas. Philosophical Review, 91(1), 8797.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Critcher, C. R., Helzer, E. G., & Tannenbaum, D. (2020). Character evaluation: Testing another’s moral-cognitive machinery. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 87, Article 103906.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Crockett, M. (2013). Models of morality. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 17, 363366.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Cushman, F. (2013). Action, outcome, and value: A dual-system framework for morality. Personality and Social Psychology Review, 17(3), 273292.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Cushman, F. A., Gray, K., Gaffey, A., & Mendes, W. (2012). Simulating murder: The aversion to harmful action. Emotion, 12, 27.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Cushman, F. A., & Greene, J. D. (2012). Finding faults: How moral dilemmas illuminate cognitive structure. Social Neuroscience, 7(3), 269279.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Cushman, F., Young, L., & Hauser, M. (2006). The role of conscious reasoning and intuition in moral judgment: Testing three principles of harm. Psychological Science, 17(12), 10821089.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Everett, J. A., Pizarro, D.A., & Crockett, M. J. (2016). Inference of trustworthiness from intuitive moral judgments. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 145, 772787.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Gamez-Djokic, M., & Molden, D. (2016). Beyond affective influences on deontological moral judgment: The role of motivations for prevention in the moral condemnation of harm. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 42(11), 15221537.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Goldstein-Greenwood, J., Conway, P., Summerville, A., & Johnson, B. N. (2020). (How) do you regret killing one to save five? Affective and cognitive regret differ after utilitarian and deontological decisions. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 46(9), 13031317.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Graham, J., Haidt, J., Koleva, S., Motyl, M., Iyer, R., Wojcik, S. P., & Ditto, P. H. (2013). Moral foundations theory: The pragmatic validity of moral pluralism. Advances in Experimental Social Psychology, 47, 55130.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Greene, J. D. (2008). The secret joke of Kant’s soul. In Sinnott-Armstrong, W. & Miller, C. B. (Eds.), Moral psychology: The neuroscience of morality: Emotion, brain disorders, and development (pp. 3579). MIT Press.Google Scholar
Greene, J. D. (2014). Beyond point-and-shoot morality: Why cognitive (neuro)science matters for ethics. Ethics, 124(4), 695726.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Griffin, B. J., Purcell, N., Burkman, K., Litz, B. T., Bryan, C. J., Schmitz, M., Villierme, C., Walsh, J., & Maguen, S. (2019). Moral injury: An integrative review. Journal of Traumatic Stress, 32, 350362.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Gürcay, B., & Baron, J. (2017). Challenges for the sequential two-system model of moral judgement. Thinking & Reasoning, 23(1), 4980.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hanselmann, M., & Tanner, C. (2008). Taboos and conflicts in decision making: Sacred values, decision difficulty, and emotions. Judgment and Decision Making, 3(1), 5163.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Holyoak, K. J., & Powell, D. (2016). Deontological coherence: A framework for commonsense moral reasoning. Psychological Bulletin, 142(11), 11791203.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Horne, Z., & Powell, D. (2016). How large is the role of emotion in judgments of moral dilemmas? PLOS ONE, 11(7), Article e0154780.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hursthouse, R. (2001). On virtue ethics. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jack, A. I., Robbins, P., Friedman, J., & Meyers, C. (2014). More than a feeling: Counterintuitive effects of compassion on moral judgment. In Sytsma, J. (Ed.), Advances in experimental philosophy of mind (pp. 125179). Bloomsbury.Google Scholar
Kahane, G. (2012). On the wrong track: Process and content in moral psychology. Mind & Language, 27(5), 519545.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kahane, G. (2014). Intuitive and counterintuitive morality. In D’Arms, J. and Jacobson, D. (Eds.), Moral psychology and human agency: Philosophical essays on the science of ethics (pp. 939). Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kahane, G. (2015). Sidetracked by trolleys: Why sacrificial moral dilemmas tell us little (or nothing) about utilitarian judgment. Social Neuroscience, 10(5), 551560.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kahane, G., Wiech, K., Shackel, N., Farias, M., Savulescu, J., & Tracey, I. (2012). The neural basis of intuitive and counterintuitive moral judgment. Social Cognitive and Affective Neuroscience, 7(4), 393402.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Knoch, D., Pascual-Leone, A., Meyer, K., Treyer, V., & Fehr, E. (2006). Diminishing reciprocal fairness by disrupting the right prefrontal cortex. Science, 314(5800), 829832.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Körner, A., & Volk, S. (2014). Concrete and abstract ways to deontology: Cognitive capacity moderates construal level effects on moral judgments. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 55, 139145.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Krosch, A., Figner, B., & Weber, E. U. (2012). Choice processes and their post-decisional consequences in morally conflicting decisions. Judgment and Decision Making, 7(3), 224234.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kurzban, R., DeScioli, P., & Fein, D. (2012). Hamilton vs. Kant: Pitting adaptations for altruism against adaptations for moral judgment. Evolution and Human Behavior, 33, 323333.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Landy, J. F., & Royzman, E. B. (2018). The moral myopia model: Why and how reasoning matters in moral judgment. In Pennycook, G. (Ed.), The new reflectionism in cognitive psychology (pp. 7092). Routledge.Google Scholar
Lee, J., & Holyoak, K. J. (2020). “But he’s my brother”: The impact of family obligation on moral judgments and decisions. Memory & Cognition, 48, 158170.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Lee, M., Sul, S., & Kim, H. (2018). Social observation increases deontological judgments in moral dilemmas. Evolution and Human Behavior, 39(6), 611621.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mandel, D. R., & Vartanian, O. (2008). Taboo or tragic: Effect of tradeoff type on moral choice, conflict, and confidence. Mind & Society, 7, 215226.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mata, A. (2019). Social metacognition in moral judgment: Decisional conflict promotes perspective taking. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology: Attitudes and Social Cognition, 117(6), 10611082.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
McPhetres, J., Conway, P., Hughes, J. S., & Zuckerman, M. (2018). Reflecting on God’s will: Reflective processing contributes to religious peoples’ deontological dilemma responses, Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 79, 301314.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Miller, R., & Cushman, F. (2013). Aversive for me, wrong for you: First-person behavioral aversions underlie the moral condemnation of harm. Social and Personality Psychology Compass, 7(10), 707718.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Molendijk, T. (2018). Toward an interdisciplinary conceptualization of moral injury: From unequivocal guilt and anger to moral conflict and disorientation. New Ideas in Psychology, 51, 18.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moore, A. B., Clark, B. A., & Kane, M. J. (2008). Who shalt not kill? Individual differences in working memory capacity, executive control, and moral judgment. Psychological Science, 19(6), 549557.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nichols, S. (2021). Rational rules: Towards a theory of moral learning. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nichols, S., & Mallon, R. (2006). Moral dilemmas and moral rules. Cognition, 100(3), 530542.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Nussbaum, M. C. (2000). The costs of tragedy: Some moral limits of cost-benefit analysis. Journal of Legal Studies, 29, 10051036.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Parker, S., & Finkbeiner, M. (2020). Examining the unfolding of moral decisions across time using the reach-to-touch paradigm. Thinking & Reasoning, 26(2), 218253.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Patil, I., Zucchelli, M. M., Kool, W., Campbell, S., Fornasier, F., Calò, M., Silani, G., Cikara, M., & Cushman, F. (2021). Reasoning supports utilitarian resolutions to moral dilemmas across diverse measures. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 120(2), 443460.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Paxton, J. M., Bruni, T., & Greene, J. D. (2014). Are “counter-intuitive” deontological judgments really counter-intuitive? An empirical reply to Kahane et al. (2012). Social Cognitive and Affective Neuroscience, 9, 13681371.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Paxton, J. M., & Greene, J. D. (2010). Moral reasoning: Hints and allegations. Topics in Cognitive Science, 2(3), 511527.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Paxton, J. M., Ungar, L., & Greene, J. D. (2012). Reflection and reasoning in moral judgment. Cognitive Science, 36(1), 163177.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Piazza, J., & Landy, J. (2013). “Lean not on your own understanding”: Belief that morality is founded on divine authority and non-utilitarian moral thinking. Judgment and Decision Making, 8(6), 639661.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rand, D. G., Greene, J. D., & Nowak, M. A. (2012). Spontaneous giving and calculated greed. Nature, 489(7416), 427430.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Reynolds, C. J., & Conway, P. (2018). Not just bad actions: Affective concern for bad outcomes contributes to moral condemnation of harm in moral dilemmas. Emotion, 18(7), 10091023.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Reynolds, C. J., Knighten, K. R., & Conway, P. (2019). Mirror, mirror, on the wall, who is deontological? Completing moral dilemmas in front of mirrors increases deontological but not utilitarian response tendencies. Cognition, 192, Article 103993.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rom, S. C., & Conway, P. (2018). The strategic moral self: Self-presentation shapes moral dilemma judgments. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 74, 2437.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ross, W. D. (1930). The right and the good. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Royzman, E. B., Goodwin, G. P., & Leeman, R. F. (2011). When sentimental rules collide: “Norms with feelings” in the dilemmatic context. Cognition, 121, 101114.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Royzman, E. B., Landy, J. F., & Leeman, R. F. (2015). Are thoughtful people more utilitarian? CRT as a unique predictor of moral minimalism in the dilemmatic context. Cognitive Science, 39(2), 325352.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Sauer, H. (2012). Morally irrelevant factors: What’s left of the dual process-model of moral cognition? Philosophical Psychology, 25(6), 783811.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shortland, N., & Alison, L. (2020). Colliding sacred values: A psychological theory of least-worst option selection. Thinking & Reasoning, 26(1), 118139.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Strohminger, N., & Nichols, S. (2014). The essential moral self. Cognition, 131(1), 159171.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Tetlock, P. E., Kristel, O. V., Elson, B., Green, M. C., & Lerner, J. S. (2000). The psychology of the unthinkable: Taboo trade-offs, forbidden base rates, and heretical counterfactuals. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 78(5), 853870.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Trémolière, B., & Bonnefon, J.-F. (2014). Efficient kill–save ratios ease up the cognitive demands on counterintuitive moral utilitarianism. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 40(7), 923930.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Uhlmann, E. L., Zhu, L., & Tannenbaum, D. (2013). When it takes a bad person to do the right thing. Cognition, 126(2), 326334.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williams, B. (1965). Ethical consistency. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society (Supplement), 39, 103124.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×