Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-6bf8c574d5-2jptb Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-02-22T19:24:47.124Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

9 - Moral Categorization and Mind Perception

from Part II - Thinking and Feeling

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  20 February 2025

Bertram Malle
Affiliation:
Brown University, Rhode Island
Philip Robbins
Affiliation:
University of Missouri
Get access

Summary

This chapter of the handbook discusses the role of mind perception in the categorization of individuals as moral agents and moral patients. Moral agents are defined as individuals that can commit morally wrong actions; moral patients are defined as individuals that can be morally wronged. It is generally agreed that the attribution of moral agency and moral patiency is linked to the attribution of mental capacities and traits. The chapter surveys a variety of models of mind perception, some of which focus on the representation of mental capacities, some of which focus on the representation of mental traits. The dominant model of mind perception in moral psychology is the experience-agency model, which divides the space of mindedness into experiential capacities like sentience and self-awareness, and agentic capacities like deliberative reasoning and self-control. Reviewing the empirical literature on moral categorization, the author argues that neither the experience-agency model nor any of the major alternatives to it captures all the factors to which everyday attributions of moral agency and moral patiency are sensitive.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2025

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Abele, A. E., & Wojciszke, B. (2007). Agency and communion from the perspective of self versus others. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 93(5), 751763.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Akechi, H., & Hietanen, J. K. (2021). Considering victims’ minds in the evaluation of harmful agents’ moral standing. Social Cognition, 39(4), 489503.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Alicke, M. D. (2000). Culpable control and the psychology of blame. Psychological Bulletin, 126(4), 556574.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Anderson, R. A., Crockett, M. J., & Pizarro, D. A. (2020). A theory of moral praise. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 24(9), 694703.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Arico, A. (2010). Folk psychology, consciousness, and context effects. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 1(3), 371393.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Arico, A. (2012). Breaking out of moral typecasting. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 3(3), 425438.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Arico, A., Fiala, B., Goldberg, R. F., & Nichols, S. (2011). The folk psychology of consciousness. Mind & Language, 26(3), 327352.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Arpaly, N. (2003). Unprincipled virtue. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Barrett, J. L., & Keil, F. C. (1996). Conceptualizing a nonnatural entity: Anthropomorphism in God concepts. Cognitive Psychology, 31(3), 219247.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Bastian, B., Costello, K., Loughnan, S., & Hodson, G. (2012). When closing the human–animal divide expands moral concern: The importance of framing. Social Psychological and Personality Science, 3(4), 421429.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bastian, B., Crimston, C. R., Klebl, C., & van Lange, P. A. M. (2023). The moral significance of protecting environmental and cultural objects. PLoS ONE, 18(2), Article e0280393.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Bastian, B., Denson, T. F., & Haslam, N. (2013). The roles of dehumanization and moral outrage in distributive justice. PLoS ONE, 8(4), Article e61842.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bastian, B., Laham, S. M., Wilson, S., Haslam, N., & Koval, P. (2011). Blaming, praising, and protecting our humanity: The implications of everyday dehumanization for judgments of moral status. British Journal of Social Psychology, 50(3), 469483.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Bastian, B., Loughnan, S., Haslam, N., & Radke, H. R. M. (2012). Don’t mind meat? The denial of mind to animals used for human consumption. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 38(2), 247256.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Bentham, J. (1970). Introduction to the principles of morals and legislation. Clarendon Press. (Original work published 1789)Google Scholar
Bernstein, M. H. (1998). On moral considerability: An essay on who morally matters. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bigman, Y. E., Waytz, A., Alterovitz, R., & Gray, K. (2019). Holding robots responsible: The elements of machine morality. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 23(5), 365368.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Block, N. (1995). On a confusion about a function of consciousness. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 18(2), 227247.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bonnefon, J.-F., Rahwan, I., & Shariff, A. (2024). The moral psychology of artificial intelligence. Annual Review of Psychology, 75, 653675.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Brambilla, M, & Leach, C. W. (2014). On the importance of being moral: The distinctive role of morality in social judgment. Social Cognition, 32(4), 397408.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bratanova, B., Loughnan, S., & Bastian, B. (2011). The effect of categorization as food on the perceived moral standing of animals. Appetite, 57(1), 193196.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Buckwalter, W., & Phelan, M. (2013). Function and feeling machines: A defense of the philosophical conception of subjective experience. Philosophical Studies, 166(2), 349361.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Callicott, J. B. (1980). Animal liberation. Environmental Ethics, 2(4), 311338.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Capezza, N. M., & Arriaga, X. B. (2008). Why do people blame victims of abuse? The role of stereotypes of women on perceptions of blame. Sex Roles, 59(11), 839850.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carruthers, P. (1992). The animals issue: Moral theory in practice. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chalmers, D. (1995). Facing up to the problem of consciousness. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 2(3), 200219.Google Scholar
Cushman, F. (2008). Crime and punishment: Distinguishing the roles of causal and intentional analyses in moral judgment. Cognition, 108(2), 353380.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
DeGrazia, D. (2008). Moral status as a matter of degree? Southern Journal of Philosophy, 46(2), 181198.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
de Vel-Palumbo, M., Schein, C., Ferguson, R., Chang, M. X-L., & Bastian, B. (2021). Morally excused but socially excluded: Denying agency through the defense of mental impairment. PLoS ONE, 16(6), Article e0252586.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Epley, N., & Waytz, A. (2010). Mind perception. In Fiske, S. T., Gilbert, D. T., & Lindzey, G. (Eds.), Handbook of social psychology (pp. 498541). Wiley.Google Scholar
Fischer, J. M., & Ravizza, M. (1998). Responsibility and control: A theory of moral responsibility. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fiske, S. T., Cuddy, A. J. C., & Glick, P. (2006). Universal dimensions of social cognition: Warmth and competence. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 11(2), 7783.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Fiske, S. T., Cuddy, A. J. C., Glick, P., & Xu, J. (2002). A model of (often mixed) stereotype content: Competence and warmth respectively follow from perceived status and competition. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 82(6), 878902.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fragale, A. R., Rosen, B., Xu, C., & Merideth, I. (2009). The higher they are, the harder they fall: The effects of wrongdoer status on observer punishment recommendations and intentionality attributions. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 108(1), 5365.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Friedman, M. (2013). How to blame people responsibly. Journal of Value Inquiry, 47(3), 271284.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goodpaster, K. E. (1978). On being morally considerable. Journal of Philosophy, 75(6), 308325.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goodwin, G. P. (2015). Experimental approaches to moral standing. Philosophy Compass, 10(12), 914926.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goodwin, G. P., Piazza, J., & Rozin, P. (2014). Moral character predominates in person perception and evaluation. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 106(1), 148168.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gray, H. M., Gray, K., & Wegner, D. (2007). Dimensions of mind perception. Science, 315(5812), 619.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Gray, K., Young, L., & Waytz, A. (2012). Mind perception is the essence of morality. Psychological Inquiry, 23(2), 101124.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gray, K., & Wegner, D. (2009). Moral typecasting: Divergent perceptions of moral agents and moral patients. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 96(3), 503520.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Gray, K., & Wegner, D. (2011). To escape blame, don’t be a hero – Be a victim. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 47(2), 516519.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Greene, J. (2008). The secret joke of Kant’s soul. In Sinnott-Armstrong, W. (Ed.), Moral psychology: Vol. 3. The neuroscience of morality: Emotion, brain disorders, and development (pp. 3580). MIT Press.Google Scholar
Greene, J., & Cohen, J. (2004). For the law, neuroscience changes nothing and everything. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London B, 359(1451), 17751785.Google ScholarPubMed
Guglielmo, S., Monroe, A. E., and Malle, B. F. (2009). At the heart of morality lies folk psychology. Inquiry, 52(5), 449466.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gunnthorsdottir, A. (2001). Physical attractiveness of an animal species as a decision factor for its preservation. Anthrozoös, 14(4), 204215.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Haslam, N. (2006). Dehumanization: An integrative review. Personality and Social Psychology Review, 10(3), 252264.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Haslam, N., & Loughnan, S. (2014). Dehumanization and infrahumanization. Annual Review of Psychology, 65, 399423.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Huebner, B. (2010). Commonsense concepts of phenomenal consciousness: Does anyone care about functional zombies? Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 9(1), 133155.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jack, A. I., & Robbins, P. (2012). The phenomenal stance revisited. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 3(3), 383403.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kant, I. (1998). Groundwork of the metaphysics of morals (M. Gregor, Ed. and Trans.). Cambridge University Press. (Original work published 1785)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kant, I. (1996). The metaphysics of morals (M. Gregor, Ed. and Trans.). Cambridge University Press. (Original work published 1797)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Khamitov, M., Rotman, J. D., & Piazza, J. (2016). Perceiving the agency of harmful agents: A test of the dehumanization versus moral typecasting accounts. Cognition, 146(1), 3347.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Klebl, C., Luo, Y., & Bastian, B. (2022). Beyond aesthetic judgment: Beauty increases moral standing through perceptions of purity. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 48(6), 954967.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Klebl, C., Luo, Y., Tan, N. P, Ping Ern, J. T., & Bastian, B. (2021). Beauty of the Beast: Beauty as an important dimension in the moral standing of animals. Journal of Environmental Psychology, 75, Article 101624.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Knobe, J., & Prinz, J. (2008). Intuitions about consciousness: Experimental studies. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 7(1), 6783.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kozachenko, H. H., & Piazza, J. (2021). How children and adults value different animal lives. Journal of Experimental Child Psychology, 210, Article 105204.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ladak, A., Loughnan, S., & Wilks, M. (2023). The moral psychology of artificial intelligence. Current Directions in Psychological Science, 33(1), 2734.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Loughnan, S., Haslam, N., & Bastian, B. (2010). The role of meat consumption in the denial of moral status and mind to meat animals. Appetite, 55(1), 156159.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Malle, B. F. (2019). How many dimensions of mind perception really are there? In Goel, A. K., Seifert, C. M., & Freska, C. (Eds.), Proceedings of the 41st Annual Meeting of the Cognitive Science Society (pp. 22682274). Cognitive Science Society.Google Scholar
Monroe, A. E., Dillon, K. D., & Malle, B. F. (2014). Bringing free will down to earth: People’s psychological concept of free will and its role in moral judgment. Consciousness and Cognition, 27, 100108.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Nadler, J. (2012). Blaming as a social process: The influence of character and moral emotion on blame. Law and Contemporary Problems, 75(2), 131.Google Scholar
Nadler, J., & McDonnell, M.-H. (2012). Moral character, motive, and the psychology of blame. Cornell Law Review, 97(2), 255304.Google Scholar
Nagel, T. (1974). What is it like to be a bat? Philosophical Review, 83(4), 435450.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nijssen, S. R. R., Müller, B. C. N., Bosse, T., & Paulus, M. (2023). Can you count on a calculator? The role of agency and affect in judgments of robots as moral agents. Human-Computer Interaction, 38(5–6), 400416.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Opotow, S. (1993). Animals and the scope of justice. Journal of Social Issues, 49(1), 7185.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Phelan, M., Arico, A., & Nichols, S. (2013). Thinking things and feeling things: On an alleged discontinuity in folk metaphysics of mind. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 12(4), 703725.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Piazza, J., Landy, J. F., & Goodwin, G. P. (2014). Cruel nature: Harmfulness as an important, overlooked dimension in judgments of moral standing. Cognition, 131(1), 108124.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Piazza, J., & Loughnan, S. (2016). When meat gets personal, animals’ minds matter less: Motivated use of intelligence information in judgments of moral standing. Social Psychological and Personality Science, 7(8), 867874.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pizarro, D., & Tannenbaum, D. (2012). Bringing character back: How the motivation to evaluate character influences judgments of moral blame. In Mikulincer, M. & Shaver, P. R. (Eds.), The social psychology of morality: Exploring the causes of good and evil (pp. 91108). American Psychological Association.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Raz, J. (1984). On the nature of rights. Mind, 93(370), 194214.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Robbins, P., & Alvear, F. (2023). Deformative experience: Explaining the effects of adversity on moral evaluation. Social Cognition, 41(5), 415446.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Robbins, P., & Jack, A. I. (2006). The phenomenal stance. Philosophical Studies, 127(1), 5985.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Robbins, P., & Litton, P. (2018). Crime, punishment, and causation: The effect of etiological information on the perception of moral agency. Psychology, Public Policy, and Law, 24(1), 118127.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schein, C., & Gray, K. (2018). The Theory of Dyadic Morality: Reinventing moral judgments by redefining harm. Personality and Social Psychology Review, 22(1), 3270.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Schtulman, A., & Lindeman, M. (2016). Attributes of God: Conceptual foundations of a foundational belief. Cognitive Science, 40(3), 635670.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schwartz, F., Djeriouat, H., & Trémolière, B. (2022). Agents’ moral character shapes people’s moral evaluations of accidental harm transgressions. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 102, Article 104378.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Singer, P. (1989). All animals are equal. In Regan, T. and Singer, P. (Eds.), Animal rights and human obligations (pp. 215226). Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Strawson, P. F. (1962). Freedom and resentment. Proceedings of the British Academy, 48, 187211.Google Scholar
Sytsma, J., & Machery, E. (2009). How to study folk intuitions about phenomenal consciousness. Philosophical Psychology, 22(1), 2135.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sytsma, J., & Machery, E. (2010). Two conceptions of subjective experience. Philosophical Studies, 151(2), 299327.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sytsma, J., & Machery, E. (2012). The two sources of moral standing. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 3(3), 303324.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Todd, P. (2019). A unified account of the moral standing to blame. Noûs, 53(2), 347374.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vetter, B. (2013). ‘Can’ without possible worlds: Semantics for anti-Humeans. Philosophers’ Imprint, 13(16), 127.Google Scholar
Vollmer, F. (1993). A theory of traits. Philosophical Psychology, 6(1), 6779.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ward, A. F., Olsen, A. S., & Wegner, D. M. (2013). The harm-made mind: Observing victimization augments attributions of minds to vegetative patients, robots, and the dead. Psychological Science, 24(8), 14371445.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Waytz, A., Gray, K., Epley, N., & Wegner, D. M. (2010). Causes and consequences of mind perception. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 14(8), 383388.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Weisman, K., Dweck, C. S., & Markman, E. M. (2017). Rethinking people’s conceptions of mental life. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 114(43), 1137411379.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Weisman, K., Legare, C. H., Smith, R. E., Dzokoto, V. A., Aulino, F., Ng, E., Dulin, J. C., Ross-Zehnder, N., Brahinsky, J. D., & Luhrmann, T. M. (2021). Similarities and differences in concepts of mental life among adults and children in five cultures. Nature Human Behaviour, 5(10), 13581368.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×