Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-f554764f5-nt87m Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-04-14T10:08:40.368Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

1 - What Is Democratic Education and Why Should We Care?

from Introduction

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  20 April 2023

Julian Culp
Affiliation:
The American University of Paris, France
Johannes Drerup
Affiliation:
Universität Dortmund
Douglas Yacek
Affiliation:
Universität Dortmund

Summary

Democratic education is central to the functioning and flourishing of modern multicultural democracies, and yet it is subject to increasing public controversy and political pressure. Waning public trust in government institutions, sustained attacks on democratic values and customs from populist politicians and organizations, political sectarianism, and increasing trends toward privatization and chartering in the educational landscape have placed immense strain on the existing structures of public education and generally worked to undermine public confidence in democratic education. In light of these developments, it seems to us to be of central importance to return to the essential concepts, theories and values of democratic education, both as a social ideal and a political institution. This Handbook aims to offer an expansive view of the formation of individuals for democratic life and includes a diversity of theoretical traditions, topics, and thinkers that are relevant to the theory and practice of democratic education.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2023

Democratic education is central to the functioning and flourishing of modern multicultural democracies, and yet it is subject to increasing public controversy and political pressure. Waning public trust in government institutions (Miner, Reference Miner2020; Stitzlein, Reference Stitzlein2020; Wilson, Reference Wilson2020; cf. MacDonald, Reference Macdonald2019; Pew Research Center, 2022), sustained attacks on democratic values and customs from populist politicians and organizations (Brown, Reference Brown2019; Müller, Reference Müller2016, Reference Müller2021; Runciman, Reference Runciman2019), political polarization and “sectarianism” (Finkel et al., Reference Finkel, Bail, Cikara, Ditto, Iyengar, Klar and Skitka2020; Iyengar et al., Reference Iyengar, Lelkes, Levendusky, Malhotra and Westwood2019), and increasing trends toward privatization and chartering in the educational landscape (Abrams, Reference Abrams2016; Levin, Reference Levin2001; Verger et al., Reference Verger, Fontdevila and Zancajo2016) have placed immense strain on the existing structures of public education and generally worked to undermine public confidence in democratic education. Practically speaking, this has meant that educators have been thrust into hazardous pedagogical terrain, in which students and parents are increasingly empowered to opt out of course content and evaluations on political grounds (Wilson, Reference Wilson2020), while teachers are expected to maintain scrupulous neutrality on politically and morally controversial issues, regardless of the intellectual merit of the opinions involved, or else face charges of indoctrination (Hand, Reference Hand2008; Zimmermann & Robertson, Reference Zimmerman and Robertson2017). This contentious educational atmosphere has made it increasingly difficult to foster cooperation, rational discussion and a sense of political community in students beyond partisan political divisions (Hess & McAvoy, Reference Hess and McAvoy2015).

At the same time, several movements in educational and political theory have called some of the basic concepts, premises, and normative justifications of democratic education into question. According to the most critical of these perspectives, we should seriously reconsider the status of democratic education as an educational ideal and recognize its intrinsically hegemonic, bourgeois, or oppressive character. While in some cases these thoroughgoing critiques have led to important advancements in our understanding of democratic theory – for example, in our growing awareness of how power, racism, xenophobia, nationalism, and sexism have historically influenced political and educational theory-building – in other cases they have seemed to authorize anti-democratic or autocratic impulses under the auspices of academic scholarship.

In light of these developments, it seems to us to be of central importance to return to the basic concepts, theories, and values of democratic education, both as a social ideal and a political institution. Of course, “democratic education” has been defined in almost as many ways as its constitutive terms, “democracy” and “education,” and we do not want to enter this particular debate in this introductory chapter (see, for instance, Brighouse, Reference Brighouse1998; Brumlik, Reference Brumlik2018; Callan, Reference Callan1997; Gutmann, Reference Gutmann1999; Kitcher, Reference Kitcher2022; Merry, Reference Merry2018; Reichenbach, Reference Reichenbach2022). Rather, we would like to make a brief case for democratic education as a core focus of educational theory and practice – that is, for caring about democratic education in a profound way.

In the first place, democratic education, in its broadest sense, expresses what we hope will result from our efforts to educate the next generation. Caring about democratic education means that, whatever curricular materials or pedagogical methods may be used in the process, we hope that our educational institutions are contributing to producing a happier and more flourishing society. At the individual level, this means that we hope students come out the other end of their education prepared to see themselves as worthy and able to participate in democratic decision-making, to uphold democratic ideals in their social and vocational lives, and to be prepared to protect the integrity and stability of democratic processes if they are threatened. Democratic education is, in other words, education for democracy (cf. Sant, Reference Sant2019). It takes seriously the belief that human communities and individuals flourish most, or become the most just, when they commit to a basic principle of equality among all human beings and when they keep opportunities and social roles open to all those who strive to achieve them. To this end, education for democracy cultivates not only the will and ability to enact this basic principle in a comprehensive way, but also an active consciousness of historical injustices, so that the enduring effects of oppression, marginalization and demoralization can be counteracted and, ultimately, neutralized.

If caring about democratic education means enacting an education for democracy, then this implies something important about what democratic education looks like in practice. Democracy is not only a formal characteristic of political or educational institutions, but also an attitude toward our fellow human beings. Crucially, although this attitude may in some cases arise naturally in individuals, it is nonetheless in tension with other widespread and psychologically powerful human motivations and tendencies – for example, avarice, competitiveness, or the desire for power. Developing the ability to recognize our fundamental moral equality with other human beings, to make this recognition psychologically effective enough in our actions and decisions that it can overcome countervailing impulses, and to draw on this principle for strength when democratic ideals are challenged requires a rigorous and thoroughgoing educational program that creates democratically oriented habits, dispositions and virtues in students. In order to supply this comprehensive educational experience, democratic education will have to occur across the curriculum, in physical education, mathematics, and biology just as much as in social studies or civics. This insight prevents us from outsourcing the demands of citizen formation to one disciplinary location. It makes the concept of democratic education importantly different from terms like “civic education” or “political education,” which focus more exclusively on the particular knowledge and skills necessary for effective participation in contemporary political processes.

Democratic education not only implies an education for democracy, but also that this education is conducted in a certain kind of way. Imagine a program designed to instill democratic habits and virtues that was taught in an authoritarian manner, allowing little to no room for students’ own experiences and personalities and with harsh punishment schemes in place. Clearly, such an approach to “democratic education” would be a performative contradiction. However, the same goes for educational programs that too starkly individualize students, making education centrally a matter of individuals earning grades, accolades, credentials, and other forms of social recognition for their own personal advancement. John Dewey pointed out at the turn of the twentieth century that we seriously undermine the potential to cultivate and achieve democracy through our schools if we make education so individual an affair. The example he uses is the quintessential exam experience. What happens during exams? Students sit in individual desks, call up objective, impersonal knowledge to answer the standardized questions posed, remain quiet and still while they do so, and turn in their work at the end for an individual grade. If they decide – in the spirit of democracy – to communicate with each other and work together, perhaps even to help the weakest students improve their academic abilities, they are punished, sometimes with expulsion. Dewey urged us to ask ourselves, What could be more devastating for cultivating democratic sentiments and habits?

If we care about democracy and a truly democratic education, then this will not do. What counts as a characteristically democracy-promoting pedagogy, then? Dewey famously thought it was provided by the intrinsic “social control” of rich practical activities like cooking, sewing, woodwork, and gardening, and this is why these occupations made up the bulk of the school day at his laboratory school. In contrast, A. S. Neill thought it meant the almost complete forfeiture of curricular and educational decision-making power to students, particularly in an assembly-style structure composed of them and their teachers. Harold Rugg, a colleague of Dewey’s and a fellow progressive, thought that “parliamentary discussion” of controversial social issues should form the core of the democratic educational experience. Freire thought, too, that only a thoroughly dialogical pedagogy would suffice, though it should be one in which students’ home lives become the topic of instruction, particularly, the manifold ways in which oppression colors their experience. Countless further proposals have been made since these classic positions were staked out. Recently, programs that bring in important global issues and cosmopolitan perspectives have gained in popularity.

This is not the place to take a stand on this question, though it does seem to us that some combination of each of these elements would likely be necessary for providing a comprehensive democratic education. However, at a somewhat more general level, we can say that the two notions of democratic education – education for democracy and education as democracy (democratic pedagogy) – constitute two practical desiderata that limit and complement each other. For example, if we knew we could instill democratic qualities most efficiently by means of autonomy-denying methods, we would not want to do so because of our commitment to democratic pedagogy. On the other hand, if we allow democratic education to be too open-ended or student-centered in order to emulate the structures and procedures of democratic government in adulthood, then we fail to provide a compelling and effective education of sentiment and habit that furthers democratic flourishing (and personal flourishing, too). Indeed, not only would this prevent us from helping students develop democratic virtues; it inhibits us from counteracting anti-democratic influences in the larger culture – influences that shape students both outside and inside of schools every single day.

In light of this broad understanding of the importance and scope of democratic education, this handbook offers an expansive view of the formation of individuals for democratic life and includes theoretical traditions, topics, and thinkers that are not always immediately connected to this task when construed as civic, political, or citizenship education. More concretely, this volume provides readers with a comprehensive overview of the fundamental ideas, concepts, theories, aims and challenges of democratic education, both as a social ideal and as a contemporary institution. If educators are to provide students with a worthwhile and socially productive education within the current educational landscape, and if researchers are to understand the specific sociopolitical factors influencing the present educational moment, we believe that a broad engagement with the value and meaning of democratic education will be an indispensable resource to them. This volume will therefore not only introduce readers to the central contours of contemporary thinking about democratic education, but also function, we hope, as a clear signal of the practical and scholarly significance of democratic education. Given the current challenges to democratic education, we believe it to be an opportune time to send such a signal.

However, we believe that the reasons for compiling this Cambridge Handbook of Democratic Education go beyond the particularities of the present moment. Democratic education is a perennial concern of societies committed to the value of justice and the well-being of children. Debates about the meaning, purpose and aims of democratic education had already begun in Ancient Athens, in which the proper content of the encyclios paideia (general education) was vigorously disputed. On the one side, followers of Plato and Aristotle, though the two sages of Greek Antiquity expressed skepticism about democracy, defended the role of speculative and philosophically oriented studies for political formation, while followers of Isocrates and other sophists forcefully argued for public rhetoric and civic engagement as the prerequisite studies for democratic citizenship. This ancient debate has continued throughout Western history (Stasavage, Reference Stasavage2020; Sen, Reference Sen2005), with some educational thinkers taking the speculative, philosophical side and others the rhetorical side (Kimball, Reference Kimball1986). These issues became particularly poignant in the aftermath of the democratic revolutions in eighteenth-century Europe and America, in which it became apparent – to such figures as Thomas Jefferson and Horace Mann in the American context, for example – that access to a democracy-promoting education should be free and open to all citizens (though often excluding women, African-Americans and other groups). The discussion of what kinds of subjects and what kinds of pedagogy are appropriate for such an educational program are thus not only important in the present political situation. This discussion is a mainstay of open and free societies. The debates and deliberations over the content, methods, and aims of democratic education can be seen as so many indications of a healthy democratic community, so long as they are conducted in a humane and constructive manner.

In this way, this volume aims to be an enduring resource for those interested in advancing the discussion of democratic education well into the future. Not only does the volume encompass several chapters on the history of democratic education, including analyses of some of the major historical figures who have contributed to the discussion; it also engages with some of the central concepts, ideas, and ideals that have wielded influence over the programs and theories of democratic education in history. We hope to encourage readers to return to these issues and thinkers as a part of their study of democratic education, since they continue to provide fresh insight for the project of understanding and realizing democratic education.

There are four main themes that organize the handbook into four parts: (i) Historical Perspectives, (ii) Philosophical and Normative Foundations, (iii) Key Topics and Concepts, and (iv) Challenges. In Historical Perspectives, we include chapters on significant figures in the history of political and educational thought who have contributed significantly to our understanding of democratic education and whose ideas warrant perennial reconsideration. In Philosophical and Normative Foundations, we provide chapters connecting democratic education to important foundational ideas in ethics, moral philosophy, as well as social and political philosophy broadly construed. This part is essential to the handbook, for it shows that the discussion of democratic education is connected in myriad ways to some of the central issues in contemporary political and educational thought, such as the emerging field of educational ethics, moral education, political liberalism, and critical theory. The part dedicated to Key Topics and Concepts takes up some of the central issues in the research on democratic education today. This part provides the reader with a broad and systematic overview of some of the most pressing theoretical and practical questions in democratic education, including classroom debate and dialogue, controversial issues, global justice, punishment, patriotism, and free speech. The final part of the handbook addresses Challenges to the project of democratic education today. This part looks not only at intellectual movements that have contested the basic principles and aims of democratic education, but also movements in the public realm, such as the rise of populist political organizations, the changing media terrain and climate change.

With this thematic and conceptual orientation, we thus hope to have provided a distinctive and comprehensive treatment of democratic education, one that can serve as an enduring resource for researchers and practitioners who care about democratic education.

References

Abrams, S. E. (2016). Education and the commercial mindset. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Brighouse, H. (1998). Civic education and liberal legitimacy. Ethics, 108(4), 719–45.Google Scholar
Brumlik, M. (2018). Demokratie und Bildung. Berlin: Neofelis.Google Scholar
Brown, W. (2019). In the ruins of neoliberalism: The rise of antidemocratic politics in the West. New York: Columbia University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Callan, E. (1997). Creating citizens: Political education and liberal democracy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Finkel, E. J., Bail, C. A., Cikara, M., Ditto, P. H., Iyengar, S., Klar, S., … & Skitka, L. J. (2020). Political sectarianism in America. Science, 370(6516), 533–36.Google Scholar
Gutmann, A. (1999). Democratic education. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Hand, M. (2008). What should we teach as controversial? A defense of the epistemic criterion. Educational Theory, 58(2), 213–28.Google Scholar
Hess, D., & McAvoy, P. (2015). The political classroom: Evidence and ethics in democratic education. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Iyengar, S., Lelkes, Y., Levendusky, M., Malhotra, N., & Westwood, S. J. (2019). The origins and consequences of affective polarization in the United States. Annual Review of Political Science, 22, 129–46.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kimball, B. A. (1986). Orators & philosophers: A history of the idea of liberal education. New York: Teachers College Press.Google Scholar
Kitcher, P. (2022). The main enterprise of the world: Rethinking education. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Levin, H. (2001). Privatizing education: Can the school marketplace deliver freedom of choice, efficiency, equity, and social cohesion? Boulder, CO: Westview Press.Google Scholar
Macdonald, D. (2019). Trust in government and the American public’s responsiveness to rising inequality. Political Research Quarterly, 73(4), 790804.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Merry, M. (2018). Can schools teach citizenship? Discourse: Studies in the Cultural Politics of Education, 41(1), 124–38.Google Scholar
Miner, M. A. (2020). Unmet promises: Diminishing confidence in education among college‐educated adults from 1973 to 2018. Social Science Quarterly, 101(6), 2312–31.Google Scholar
Müller, J.-W. (2016). What is populism? Philadelphia, PA: University of Pennsylvania Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Müller, J.-W. (2021). Democracy rules. London: Allen Lane.Google Scholar
Pew Research Center (2022). Public trust in government: 1958–2022. Available at: https://www.pewresearch.org/politics/2022/06/06/public-trust-in-government-1958-2022.Google Scholar
Reichenbach, R. (2022). “Une plante sauvage” – Über das Politische und die Politische Bildung. Zeitschrift für Pädagogik, 68(4), 445–61.Google Scholar
Runciman, D. (2019). How democracy ends. London: Profile Books.Google Scholar
Sant, E. (2019). Democratic education: A theoretical review (2006–2017). Review of Educational Research, 89(5), 655–96.Google Scholar
Sen, A. (2005). The argumentative Indian. London: Penguin Books.Google Scholar
Stasavage, D. (2020). The cecline and rise of democracy: A global history from antiquity to today. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Stitzlein, S. M. (2020). The democratic potential of parental dissent: Keeping public schools public, legitimate, and educational. Educational Theory, 70(3), 355–72.Google Scholar
Verger, A., Fontdevila, C., & Zancajo, A. (2016). The privatization of education: A political economy of global education reform. New York: Teachers College Press.Google Scholar
Wilson, T. S. (2020). Contesting public education: Opting out, dissent, and activism. Educational Theory, 70(3), 247–54.Google Scholar
Zimmerman, J., & Robertson, E. (2017). The case for contention: Teaching controversial issues in American schools. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×