Book contents
- Frontmatter
- Contents
- Preface
- 1 Reading Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics
- 2 The goal of human life (Nicomachean Ethics, book 1)
- 3 Character-related virtue (Nicomachean Ethics 1.13 and book 2)
- 4 Actions as signs of character (Nicomachean Ethics 3.1–5)
- 5 Some particular character-related virtues (Nicomachean Ethics 3.6–4.9)
- 6 Justice as a character-related virtue (Nicomachean Ethics, book 5)
- 7 Thinking-related virtue (Nicomachean Ethics, book 6)
- 8 Akrasia, or failure of self-control (Nicomachean Ethics 7.1–10)
- 9 Friendship (Nicomachean Ethics, books 8 and 9)
- 10 Pleasure (Nicomachean Ethics 7.11–14 and 10.1–5)
- 11 Happiness (Nicomachean Ethics 10.6–9)
- References
- Index
6 - Justice as a character-related virtue (Nicomachean Ethics, book 5)
Published online by Cambridge University Press: 05 June 2012
- Frontmatter
- Contents
- Preface
- 1 Reading Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics
- 2 The goal of human life (Nicomachean Ethics, book 1)
- 3 Character-related virtue (Nicomachean Ethics 1.13 and book 2)
- 4 Actions as signs of character (Nicomachean Ethics 3.1–5)
- 5 Some particular character-related virtues (Nicomachean Ethics 3.6–4.9)
- 6 Justice as a character-related virtue (Nicomachean Ethics, book 5)
- 7 Thinking-related virtue (Nicomachean Ethics, book 6)
- 8 Akrasia, or failure of self-control (Nicomachean Ethics 7.1–10)
- 9 Friendship (Nicomachean Ethics, books 8 and 9)
- 10 Pleasure (Nicomachean Ethics 7.11–14 and 10.1–5)
- 11 Happiness (Nicomachean Ethics 10.6–9)
- References
- Index
Summary
THE PLATONIC CONTEXT
Aristotle's discussion of justice, which he regards as one among other character-related virtues, is quite different from a treatment of justice which one might find in John Stuart Mill or John Rawls. Aristotle devotes much labor, for instance, to defining justice as a “particular” rather than a “general” virtue. In order to appreciate why, we need (once again) to understand the Platonic context in which he is evidently writing.
Aristotle begins book 5 by remarking,
We observe, then, that everyone intends, in referring to “justice,” to mean that condition of character which makes someone the sort of person who does just actions, and responds justly, and who likes to see justice done. In the same way, by “injustice” they mean that which makes someone the sort of person who acts unjustly and likes to see injustice done. Very well, then, for a start, let us adopt these as schematic definitions.
(1129a6–11)By the end of chapter 5 he has filled in those schemata, and he gives the following as his finished definitions:
Justice is that with respect to which a just person is said to be the sort of person who, of his own choice, does what is just, and who distributes goods, both to himself in his dealings with others, and to others in their relations to one another, not in such a way that he gets more of what is desirable, and his neighbor gets less (and contrariwise for harmful things), but rather in such a way that he gets an equal amount (that is, a proportionately equal amount), and, likewise, when he distributes goods to others, and he's not himself involved, he does so in such a way that the others each get an equal amount (again, a proportionately equal amount).[…]
- Type
- Chapter
- Information
- Aristotle's Nicomachean EthicsAn Introduction, pp. 181 - 205Publisher: Cambridge University PressPrint publication year: 2005
- 1
- Cited by