Hostname: page-component-745bb68f8f-grxwn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-01-23T09:44:49.816Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

American Political Violence (The Government and Opposition/Leonard Schapiro Lecture 2023)

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  14 January 2025

Desmond King*
Affiliation:
Department of Politics and IR, University of Oxford, Oxford, UK
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Amongst the ways in which American democracy is distinct, the Weberian anomaly stands out: the United States equates to a classical Weberian state with the routine trappings of bureaucratic power, national organization, stable territorial parameters, a legal code and military power. But it is at best a quasi-Weberian state in respect of state monopolization of legitimate violence. The scope of the Second Amendment means the federal government has control in many instances over the use of physical force but historically this authority coexists with the (explicit or implicit) delegation of political violence to societal actors. In this article I argue that the legitimation of political violence outside the state is endogenous to the American constitutional settlement, a feature which arises from the country's origins and the institutional arrangements adopted in key constitutional clauses and judicial decisions.

Type
Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution and reproduction, provided the original article is properly cited.
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2025. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of Government and Opposition Ltd

Our President will need us. ALL OF US …!! On January 6th. We the People owe him that debt. He Sacrificed for us and we must pay that debt. (Guy Wesley Reffitt on a private group chat of the Texas Three Percenters, 20 December 2020, quoted in Feuer et al. Reference Feuer, Schmidt and Broadwater2022)

Now, if I don't get elected [with tariffs], it's going to be a bloodbath … for the country. (President Elect Donald Trump,Footnote 1 16 March 2024, Ohio, quoted in Washington Post)

Amongst the ways in which American democracy is distinct, the Weberian anomaly stands out: the United States equates to a classical Weberian state with the conventional trappings of bureaucratic power, national organization, stable territorial parameters, a legal code and military power. But it is at best a quasi-Weberian state in respect of the state monopolization of legitimate violence (Francis Reference Francis2014; Gerstle Reference Gerstle2015; Johnson Reference Johnson2007; King and Lieberman Reference King and Lieberman2009).

Violence is not ring-fenced out of American society but accommodated and (mostly) controlled within it. The scope of the Second Amendment (Carlson Reference Carlson2015; Corley Reference Corley2020; Cornell Reference Cornell2006; Filindra Reference Filindra2023) means the federal government has control in many instances over the use of physical force – notably in the deployment of national guards domestically under the Insurrection Act and in foreign affairs – but historically this authority coexists with the (explicit or implicit) delegation of political violence to societal actors. Who these actors are varies over time but includes the enslavers and their cronies, white supremacists and militias, private police or detective forces and local police forces (Carlson Reference Carlson2019; Holman Reference Holman2024; Obert Reference Obert2022). This legitimation of political violence outside the state is a function of the American constitutional order (not a corruption of it), emanating from the country's origins and the institutional arrangements adopted in select constitutional clauses and subsequent court decisions about them. European states do not regard the use of force by non-state actors as legitimate, and neither do other settler states such as Canada, Australia or New Zealand (although they tended to do so with respect to the treatment of Indigenous persons during the period of violent settlement). The resultant constitutional toleration of political violence by non-state actors violates the expectation of a monopoly over the legitimate use of physical force commonly deemed requisite to the democratic state.

My account of this Weberian anomaly challenges standard views of political violence in the United States. There is a strong pro status quo leaning in much scholarship to view political violence as a routinized expression of a political system with built-in obstacles to change – such as the arduous process of enacting laws, the skewed representational basis of the Senate, the life tenure of Supreme Court justices, and corrosive effect of money-fuelled primaries in candidate selection. This view of conflict significantly underplays, for example, the racialized character of this ‘routinized’ conflict and lacks explanatory traction in the face of the rise in political violence in the 21st century (Jones and Miller Reference Jones and Miller2024). Common to all these scholars' work is the view of political violence as exogenous to the political system (even if endogenously prompted) and as an anomaly rather than as a constitutive element, accommodated institutionally and politically.

Of course, people complain that such behaviour falls beyond the bounds of decency, but the courts do not always agree. When 17-year-old Kyle Rittenhouse drove across state lines to Kenosha, Wisconsin with a loaded assault rifle to ‘protect’ local businesses from protesters involved in the Black Lives Matter (BLM) movement in 2020, the courts found that he was within his rights not only to join the counter-protest armed with a lethal weapon, but also to slay two BLM protesters who tried to disarm him. To justify the shooting, he relied on the generous Wisconsin self-defence law eviscerating the ‘duty of retreat’ doctrine (Lustbader Reference Lustbader2021; Weinstein Reference Weinstein2021).

In Part 1, I argue that the legitimation of political violence outside the state is endogenous to the American constitutional settlement. This feature arises from the country's origins in the 1770s and the institutional arrangements adopted in key constitutional clauses and judicial decisions (Ware Reference Ware2011). Endogeneity fundamentally constrains how the American polity manages political violence. Violence in society is policed but endemic and accepted. Comprehensive fieldwork-based studies of urban disorders, notably the Chicago Commission on Race Relations Report (1922) set up by Illinois Governor Frank Lowden after the ‘race riot’ of July–August 1919 left 38 people dead and the Kerner Commission (1968) set up after the widespread city strife in America during the 1960s are vital primary sources about how to define political violence.

In Part 2, I analyse the place of political violence in the non-Weberian American state by periodizing the polity's development across four eras, differentiated by how (a) extra-state violence was legitimated in particular ways to serve identifiable interests, and (b) how some initiatives to limit extra-state violence succeeded in widening the state's control over the use of physical force. Our era of heightened partisan polarization corresponds with a resurgence and spread of positive attitudes towards violence in democracy (Carter Jackson Reference Carter Jackson2022; Jardina and Mickey Reference Jardina and Mickey2022; Kalmoe and Mason Reference Kalmoe and Mason2022; Kleinfeld Reference Kleinfeld2021, Reference Kleinfeld2023; Nacos et al. Reference Nacos, Bloch-Elkon and Shapiro2024). The strength of the nation's gun culture, historically fanned by pro-gun rights advocacy groups, has contributed to this resurgence (Elinson Reference Elinson2021; Elinson and McWhirter Reference Elinson and McWhirter2024; Filindra Reference Filindra2023; Lacombe Reference Lacombe2021; McIntire and Kantor Reference McIntire and Kantor2024; Pew Research Center Reference Pew Research Center2017; Yamane Reference Yamane2023).

In Part 3, I analyse some of the main mechanisms through which American democracy has accommodated political violence as an endogenous characteristic and their consequences including the use of violence for reform and the legitimating role of presidential pardons.

Part 1. Weber's limited state: Violence with social order

Violence

Two key types of political violence stand out in the US case (Graham and Gurr Reference Graham and Gurr1969; Kalyvas Reference Kalyvas, Chenoweth, English, Gofas and Kaylvas2019). First, political violence involving the state either as a target – including armed insurrection, terrorist bombings, secession in 1861, mass protests and rebellions, and incivilities against and targeting of state officials – or by the state targeting groups such as organized labour in the 19th and early 20th centuries and civil rights activists in the 1960s and 1970s. Second, intergroup or intercommunal violence perpetuated to suppress a designated out-group by those who see themselves as the in-group. Both types illustrate the salience of political violence in American political development facilitated by the Constitution but in distinct ways.

Examples of intercommunal violence include the scorched-earth destruction in Tulsa, Oklahoma of the black Greenwood neighbourhood in 1921 by white citizens, when 36 African Americans were murdered and a district wiped out; the multiple unlawful attacks on African American towns in the post-Civil War decades by whites (who were rarely held accountable, and if charged, commonly acquitted) (Keith Reference Keith2008; Lane Reference Lane2008); or the attacks by white supremacist councils to prevent racially integrated housing in the 1950s and 1960s (Sugrue Reference Sugrue1995). The murder of 14-year-old Emmett Till in 1955 in Mississippi falls into this type too. Civil rights leader Medgar Evers's murder in Jackson, Mississippi in 1963 by a white supremacist-motivated attack on the Civil Rights Movement. Both the killings of Trayvon Martin (2012) and George Floyd (2020) are incomprehensible outside the racial hierarchy of the US. Floyd's murder regalvanized Movement for Black Lives protesters. Both Martin’s death and the self-defence actions of Rittenhouse fit a tradition of intercommunal violence. Intergroup violence is aided further by a tradition of militia formation and maintenance, and by federal disengagement in the long 19th century from protecting Black Americans' rights (Cowie Reference Cowie2022; Francis Reference Francis2014).

Mobilized to subvert a presidential election result, the insurrectionists of 6 January 2021 caused mayhem, deaths and political instability but failed to stop democracy. The plot to kidnap the governor of Michigan also failed. But failure and success are imprecise measures: consider the killing of eight people and wounding of six others, including some Holocaust survivors, at the Pittsburgh Tree of Life Synagogue during the Shabbat morning service in October 2017, infamously becoming the deadliest assault on Jews in American history. Rather, the compelling indicator is the recurrence of political violence in the United States in a much more pronounced way than in other democracies. Thus, other acts of political violence – including the racial murder of ten African Americans in a supermarket in Buffalo, New York in 2022 designed to spark a ‘race war’; anti-government gestures such as the murderous Oklahoma City bombing; and even abuse by some members of Congress of their colleagues – offer compelling evidence of an irresistible tendency amongst some Americans to behave violently for political motives (Arceneaux et al. Reference Arceneaux, Gravelle, Osmundsen, Petersen, Reifler and Scotto2020; Belew Reference Belew2018; Freeman Reference Freeman2018; Hinton Reference Hinton2015; Hinton and Cook Reference Hinton and Cook2021; Miller Reference Miller2015).

Social order

The ubiquity of violence distinguishes American democracy comparatively and challenges a core expectation of democratic order. Social scientists share an assumption that states hold a monopoly on legitimate violence and that achieving this monopoly is necessary to enable a functioning polity. This idea is based on the enduring definition advanced by Max Weber: ‘a state is that human community which (successfully) lays claim to the monopoly of the legitimate physical violence within a given territory’ (Weber Reference Weber1994: 310–311).

The centrality of violence to control or more broadly maintain public order is the great Hobbesian challenge of state control. The absence of predictable sources of authority expressed in part in some routinized version of the rule of law makes economic activity precarious and unrewarding. Wresting authority and order from social groups or organized militias has become a core preoccupation in how comparativists analyse the development of modern states, especially as forms of democracy spread despite evidence of democratic backsliding.

In the US the eradication of the ‘illegitimate use of violence’ (North et al. Reference North, Wallis and Weingeist2009: 22), deemed necessary to a Weberian monopoly of legitimate force, is incomplete. Violence is a legitimate part of American democracy. Constitutional protection permits members of society, as individuals or conditionally organized into militias, to access lethal weapons for political purposes, and the state's constitutional founding laws mean state power over violence has coexisted with violence in society.

The federal government of the United States lacks, and has always lacked, a monopoly over the legitimate use of violence. This absence comes from various reasons, including Second Amendment rights (as they have evolved); a political culture which includes a celebration of lawlessness and anti-government sentiment; and the original status accorded to militias in that Second Amendment, a status driven, in large part, by the presence of enslavement as a form of private property (Bogus Reference Bogus2023; Cornell Reference Cornell2006). This feature means at a minimum, in sociologist Jennifer Carlson's terms, that we need ‘to racialize the Weberian presumption’ (Reference Carter Jackson2019: 677). Not only did the establishment of the US signal a violence-led skewering to Native American communities (Blackhawk Reference Blackhawk2023), it also consolidated enslavement as a form of property that a majority of the Delegates to Philadelphia wanted to protect (King and Smith Reference King and Smith2005; Van Cleve Reference Van Cleve2010).

Historically the absence of a monopoly of legitimate violence by the American state created space for non-state actors to ‘take matters into their own hands’ in ways that range from lynchings and murders to riots to incivilities. This legacy persists, as a number of scholars underline, and in ways that could be argued – and are argued – to be legitimate by gun rights advocates. The last three presidential elections have featured death threats to election workers, members of Congress or ideological opponents (Sullivan Reference Sullivan2023). The threats have extended to judges, jury members and prosecutors presiding in cases in which the former Republican Party president Donald Trump appeared as the defendant before his re-election in 2024. The same GOP candidate in 2024 imprecated the dangers of a ‘bloodbath’ if his candidature failed. There is undoubtedly an ebb and flow to federal enforcement of its putative monopoly on political violence (King Reference King2017), with contests about the scope of that power, but it is not settled in a conventional state-formation sense, given the embrace of what Jonathan Obert (2024) terms ‘armed federalism’.

Acts of political violence are not confined historically to the actions of white supremacists, though these loom massively over American political development. Federal government policy towards Native Americans throughout the 19th century was murderous, contradicted the rulings of the Supreme Court and perpetrated tens of thousands of avoidable deaths. The virtual destruction of the Osage Nation depicted in the Martin Scorsese film Killers of the Flower Moon, where the perpetrators are largely sanctioned by the police and protected by the courts, is an egregious example. Federal force turned too on the efforts of workers to organize collectively to demand better working conditions and wages. National guards were routinely deployed under the Insurrection Act – which permits presidents to assist civilian authorities in law enforcement – to protect employers' interests and to uphold the constitutional principle that employers' plants, manufacturing and distribution networks were private property in which site-workers had no legal standing other than as hired labour (Taft and Ross Reference Taft, Ross, Graham and Gurr1969).

This political violence coexists within a functioning political system. The ambition to protect enslavement as property and property acquired through dispossession (Park Reference Park2024) motivated a localist-biased federalism (for example, in the Senate's representational disproportionality); a constitutional guaranteed access to arms; and an explicit role for deputizing local militias (Rao Reference Rao2008), as an alternative to a national army and potentially as a force deployable against national authority. Combined, the First and Second Amendments protecting free speech and the right to bear arms as part of a local defensive militia (Kirkpatrick Reference Kirkpatrick2024) – and instead of a professional standing army – buttress the partial Weberian constitutional settlement.

Contemporary examples of how this constitutional settlement functions abound. For example, the judicial doctrine of self-defence enacted in certain states (which helped acquit Trayvon Martin's killer in Florida in 2012) and the erosion of the ‘duty to retreat’ and its replacement with the ‘stand your ground’ doctrine expand property rights. The removal of the requirement of a licence to carry concealed weapons has spread rapidly across the states. Since 2013, the year in which Illinois made this switch, the right to carry a concealed weapon has been legal in every state. These examples reflect how America's origins imbue these rights, since early colonists fought with and killed Native Nations to seize land and ran a regime based on enslaving millions of African Americans. Early homesteaders were armed to self-defend their property dispossessed from Native Americans. The railway companies sponsoring white immigrants from Europe as homesteaders provided weapons to them for self-defence.

The Second Amendment is thus central to this Weberian anomaly and helped perpetuate America's lasting gun culture. In United States v. Cruikshank (1875) the Supreme Court exempted states from regulation under the First and Second Amendments and cemented the distinction between arms held as part of militia rights under the Second Amendment and individuals possessing firearms for self-defence, though states did have the power to regulate gun ownership if they wanted to.

Part 2. Political violence and the American state: A periodization

Political violence has been a constant of the American polity, since its pre-federal origins in the early 17th century, through the foundational constitutional agreements of the 1780s, the Civil War and into the 21st century's insurrectionist turn. As the historian Kellie Carter Jackson ruefully observes, American history is ‘benchmarked by violence’ (Reference Carter Jackson2022: 11).

This analysis is heuristic. Each historical era (Figure 1) is distinguishable in terms of the legal order for access to weapons, scale of intergroup violence, the use or non-use of federal power and the salience of anti-state political violence.

Figure 1. The Four Eras of Political Violence.

Period 1. Getting started: Localism and militias in charge

Most scholars recognize the 1770s and 1780s as a key stage in the arc of the American state. This first era was shaped and opened in the 16th century with European colonialism, and decisively shaped in 1619 with the arrival of kidnapped Africans, to be enslaved as part of the burgeoning economy of North America. The 13 colonies present by the last quarter of the 18th century were strong separate entities with constitutions and legal rules precariously bound together from the 1770s in opposition to the British Crown's fiscal and military policies towards them. They differed by levels of enslavement, though enslaved people were present in most colonies. The authors of the Declaration of Independence declaimed in the 27th grievance against King George III that ‘He has excited domestic insurrections amongst us, and has endeavoured to bring on the inhabitants of our frontiers, the merciless Indian savages, whose known rule of warfare is an undistinguished destruction of all ages, sexes and conditions.’ The reference to ‘domestic insurrections’ related not only to Shay's Rebellion (1786–1787) in Massachusetts – an anti-state action violently to repel government debt collectors – but also to a fear that enslaved African Americans would revolt.

Hostility to the British imperial monarch resulted not only in the Declaration and achievement of independence from the UK, but also in a localist sentiment opposed to strong national government amongst the colonials (if not all the Delegates). This anxiety fatally weakened the Articles of Confederation (1781–1789): they created a limp confederal government with limited authority (for instance, the Confederation Congress could only act if 9 of the 13 states agreed) and allocated most power to the states. The government of the Confederation ‘had no executive, no courts, and no way for the Congress directly to collect revenues to pay the nation's bills’ other than by requesting states' contributions (Robertson Reference Robertson, Tushnet, Graber and Levinson2015: 23).

Anti-national government sentiment is also a defining element of the Constitution ratified in 1789, enshrined in a powerful notion of the will of the people and a Montesquieu republicanism favouring separated powers. Former colonial leaders' hostility to federal authority meant inflated powers of the states. Strict limits constrained a US professional army. Community-based white militias gained a leading role in military defence (with any short-term military mobilization under civil control), with Delegates purposefully constraining the state's possession of Weberian-style legitimate control of the exercise of physical coercion in the territorial boundaries (Gerstle Reference Gerstle2015). Until abolition, some American citizens queried the ‘legitimacy of federal compulsion’ to join, for example, posses intended to round up escaped slaves (Rao Reference Rao2008: 6). The posse comitatus doctrine's expectation that white citizens had a duty to join such posses rendered the federal government an agent of enslavement which some Americans rejected, a role reconfigured in former slaveowners' advantage after Reconstruction. In federal actions against striking workers, posse comitatus legitimated employing private armed agencies.

The enslavement system rooted in the political economy of plantations and bond issuing on Wall Street was outside the nominal or formal legal system of the US. That is, enslaved men and women experienced only a violent system of authority maintained by enslavers. Accounts of militias before the American Revolution and in the post-Revolution decades make clear the extent to which plantation owners and enslavers throughout the US and states feared rebellions such as the slave rebellion in New York City in April 1712, Tacky's Rebellion at Fort Haldane in April 1760 and later the Haiti Revolution. In response, all able-bodied white males had to enrol in their local militia. And of course the right to bear arms was something included in state constitutions, and traced to the right to possess arms provision included in the English Declaration of Rights in 1689. This principle was entirely familiar to the Founders as British subjects, steeped in the notion that the British constitution defended liberty. In 1770, there were 470,000 enslaved persons in the US, doubling to 900,000 by 1800, heightening a problem of control and prompting Madison's militias (Bogus Reference Bogus2023). Violence in this enslavement regime and after the Civil War performed communicative and instrumental roles – to keep a forced-labour system going and maintain white privilege.

Local, state and federal jurisdictions impose regulations about both gun possession and gun use, but these regulations are racially calibrated. The sociologist Jennifer Carlson (Reference Carlson2019) underlines how race has set limits and opportunities on access to weapons, noting that:

in myriad ways, early gun laws and gun customs helped to first construct and then enforce a color line that equated freedom, citizenship, arms bearing, and whiteness. Thanks to custom, law (including the 1850 Fugitive Slave Act), and firearms access, whites had broad ability and authority to aggressively and violently stop, question, detain, and indefinitely confine those of African descent. (Reference Carlson2019: 641)

Carlson places the homesteading movement in this context, as ‘white posses’ that used legally acquired arms to ‘pillage and seize land’ for white settlement. The anodyne label ‘homesteading’ promoted the idea of magnanimously occupying empty land, whitewashing genocide violence and racial hierarchy (Carlson Reference Carlson2019: 641). In practice, the whole basis of homesteading rested on an earlier institutional system – registries – establishing what land was included in the jurisprudence of the US and who owned it. The legal scholar K-Sue Park (Reference Park2024) demonstrates how the registry system was a vital tool of the expanding colonial powers from the 17th century, giving deeds to white owners of land seized from Native Americans and of enslavement as property. The title registries' systems were soaked in political violence: ‘colonialists’ property innovations involved introducing ostensible ‘race neutral’ institutions like the registry. The registry arose in the context of colonial laws that openly provided for different treatment of racial groups and that sanctioned extreme violence against nonwhites and especially enslaved people’ (Park Reference Park2024: 1494). The development of property law in the United States (and its preceding colonies) is sown in ‘histories of racial violence in America’ (Park Reference Park2024: 1495). Dispossession in the 18th and 19th centuries led to property expansion through homesteading and strengthening of physical property defence rights. Armed homesteaders relied on the Castle doctrine law which stored the legal presumption of self-defence to homeowners if they harmed intruders. Property ownership and the right to armed self-defence were neatly sutured, and rendered endogenous to the polity as it expanded before and after the Civil War.

The accommodation of enslavement in the Constitution unravelled (exacerbated by the Court's Dred Scott v. Sandford decision), sparking abolition, the secession of Confederate southern states and a decisive victory for the Union championed by northern states. The defeat of the South vanquished any notion of the legitimacy of a state to mobilize its militias against the federal government, though a proposal in Congress to disband southern states' militias foundered – slain by reference to the Second Amendment.

A period of military presence in former Confederate states during Reconstruction demonstrated the potential force of federal authority and national power, to promote civil rights against the preferences and actions of states and local communities. Southern Republicans created new militias composed of African American and white citizens, a significant reform quickly targeted by the Ku Klux Klan militias reassembling former confederates (Behrend Reference Behrend2017: 117–178, 211–213).

The American state's legitimacy to use federal force to oppose southern states' insurrection marked a strengthening of the national state's capacity and legitimate exercise of force. The federal government had crushed Native American communities too, with the Bureau of Indian Affairs operative from 1824 to guide this forceful displacement policy, culminating in Wounded Knee in 1890 and the assimilationist 1887 Dawes Act (King Reference King2005). But federal authority was far from universally accepted: vicious anti-draft riots in New York City in July 1863 and the hapless collapse of posse comitatus as an obligation on citizens after 1865 permitted whites to overpower African Americans despite Reconstruction (Rao Reference Rao2008: 54).

Although southern states have not engaged in overt insurrection or violence since, the Civil War did not, however, end the role of militias, the power of local enforcement agents to enlist civilians into posses as needed (Obert Reference Obert2018; Rao Reference Rao2008), or the protections afforded under the First and Second Amendments. Most importantly, the post-enslavement racial order turned on white civilian violence against African Americans, again permitted by the state with complicity from local whites and state law-enforcement authorities. This combination became the essence of the second period.

Period 2. Recognizing spheres: The limits of federal force

The potency of national authority to challenge political violence waned after the Civil War when federal troops returned north, and the enslavement transmogrified into a de jure segregationist order enforced (after Plessy) with Jim Crow laws, an absent federal government and ruthless white violence and intimidation against African Americans. The Supreme Court stubbornly ruled a lack of federal legitimacy to intervene. And in its 1875 ruling, United States v. Cruikshank, the justices confirmed a distinction between the Second Amendment right to bear arms as part of a militia and a separate right to carry arms for self-defence. This latter conclusion weakened efforts by pro-Reconstruction Republicans and civil rights reformers to get weapons away from such groups as the Klan, busy terrorizing the formerly enslaved – especially if in militias – but a display of concentrated federal action led by President Ulysses S. Grant quelled the Klan in the 1870s (Bordewich Reference Bordewich2023), showing how formal authority could control violence when deployed. The Court did, however, underline individual states' authority to enact laws regulating possession and use of firearms in the interest of public safety (Cornell Reference Cornell2006).

The arrival of a new century left political violence undiminished. Federal force rained down on striking workers and immediately after World War I white supremacists set on Black Americans in dozens of cities in what the National Association for the Advancement of Colored People (NAACP) swiftly daubed the ‘Red Summer’ of 1919. In rural Elaine, Arkansas, hundreds of whites killed over two hundred African Americans. The disorder and deaths prompted the Illinois governor to form a Chicago Commission on Race Relations (1922) to investigate. The Commission rightly documented the consolidating racial segregation in Chicago's neighbourhoods and accompanying ingrained racism but lamely offered no proposals to weaken local violence.

Segregation and white supremacist violence were universal across the US but not brought under control in southern states. The deliberate weakness of federal government authority was essential to racist lawlessness; such enfeeblement confirmed the legitimacy of violence in society outside federal control. The racial order rested on violence, fear and intimidation, and immunity for white perpetrators (Aaronson Reference Aaronson2014) – with some rare exceptions (Francis Reference Francis2014). By default, federal inactivity in response to widespread societal violence thereby legitimated the constitutional order.

The ubiquity of unchecked political violence was disastrous. Intense lawlessness in the South ensued – race massacres from Colfax to Tulsa to Birmingham church bombs – with no accountability. Anti-lynching legislation faltered. Halting resolution came only with deployment of national guards in the 1950s and 1960s to suppress racist-based violence (King Reference King2017; King and Lieberman Reference King and Lieberman2021). Such deployment by Democrat presidents Kennedy and Johnson was resisted and challenged as illegitimate by southern leaders, a position epitomized in Alabama Governor George C. Wallace's inauguration declaration on 14 January 1963, ‘segregation now, segregation tomorrow, segregation forever’ (Cowie Reference Cowie2022: 2). In the long term, federal activism ended the Democrat Party's control of the South and allowed the Republican Party to begin its march to dominance there.

Workers organizing strikes in the 19th century and opening decades of the 20th century encountered aggressive responses from employers, supplemented by private police forces (Obert Reference Obert2018). Employers could also call upon the federal government, as successive presidents – citing the Insurrection Act – mobilized national guards to break strikes in a role upheld by the courts. The unequal balance shifted under President Franklin D. Roosevelt's New Deal. For labour, the passage of the Wagner (National Labor Relations) Act in 1935 transformed industrial relations from its peak of violence to legitimate strikes and a displacement of violence to inter-union conflicts. Wagner empowered employees in the private sector to organize into trades unions, engage in collective bargaining and take collective action (strikes) to advance their cause. The legitimacy of national troops deployed under the Insurrection Act against workers faded.

Before Roosevelt and the New Deal, not only was the limited role of the federal government as enforcer of civil rights locally confirmed – the last state to ratify a Jim Crow Constitution (Mississippi) did so in 1910, deepening the post-Reconstruction racial order – but the institutionalization of racism across the federal government animated the Woodrow Wilson administration elected in 1913 (King Reference King2007). This Wilsonian imperative formalized racial segregation between federal workers and hierarchically in all government departments, setting the stage for mortgage redlining and structural racism. The 1877 Dawes Act ended Native American autonomy. In 1919 the ‘Red Summer’ showed the federal government's capacity to assert national authority when a wave of anarchy and communist-inspired violence and protests – a Red Scare – was quashed by the Palmer Raids and the 1917 Espionage Act.

Period 3. False dawn: Political violence at bay?

The passage of civil and voting rights legislation and the diffusion of desegregation and broader rights of citizenship marked major changes in American political development. But concurrently the deep urban unrest of the 1960s signalled persistent discrimination by police forces as a source of political violence (a dynamic intensifying in the 21st century, including in Minneapolis in May 2020 when George Floyd was murdered). Urban disorder in the early 1960s prompted first the Great Society and subsequently the Kerner Commission (1968) and its recommendations to increase federal spending on cities, initiate police reforms and enforce anti-segregation laws. The assassination, in 1968, of Dr Marin Luther King Jr – one of numerous assassinations in this decade – provoked protests and underscored the depth of inequality. This came against a backdrop of political violence from right and left, including the Democrats' Convention of so-called hardhats in Chicago in 1968, George Wallace's 1968 presidential campaign and the assassination attempt on Wallace in 1970. The national guard deployed in Detroit, Newark, Washington, DC and Watts, in each case resulting in deaths of African American protesters. Overall, the 1960s was a decade of exceptional political violence in the United States, probably the country's most violent decade since the 1870s when Reconstruction collapsed in a hail of violence orchestrated by white supremacists. The chief of police in Los Angeles proposed a paramilitary response to protesters, the Weathermen set off bombs, the Black Panther Party movement was active and a rigorous counter-intelligence federal response emerged (CONTREL). Chicago hosted the hardhats convention in 1968 and the trial of the Chicago Eight in 1969, and in December 1969 the prominent Black Panther Party leader Fred Hampton was killed in his apartment by a tactical unit of the Cook County State Attorney's Office with assistance from the Chicago Police Department and the FBI under the illegal COINTELPRO programme. Over 100 gunshots hit the apartment, killing a drugged Hampton and another Panther member. An investigation by the Cook County coroner ruled the two deaths as justifiable homicides (though in the 1980s a civil lawsuit by Hampton's survivors successfully sued the federal government, Cook County and the City of Chicago, each of whom had to pay out a third of the settlement for what was in effect a state assassination).

Extreme political violence at the workplace ceased by the last quarter of the 20th century, and the regularity of white supremacist violence towards African Americans declined. Laws against prejudice and discrimination had some muscle in employment contracts and public life. The explicit use of racist tropes in election campaigns declined but the unsubtle implicit use – Reagan's welfare queens in 1980 and the Willie Horton ad used by George H.W. Bush in 1988 – was not far beneath the surface. Indeed retrospectively, an angry white ethnic identity was seething, ready to align with an invigorated white evangelical nationalism in the new century (Jardina Reference Jardina2019), a dynamic present in whites' vicious opposition to desegregation and busing across the country (Bobo Reference Bobo1983). Gun culture is undiminished. Gun ownership is revered amongst white Americans, Republican and Democrat, more than other groups according to Alexandra Filindra's survey, especially those who equate ‘true American identity’ with Christianity (Filindra Reference Filindra2023).

The Supreme Court had not yet begun its shift to liberalize gun ownership and gun use laws. Its Lewis v. United States decision in 1980 showed the Court upholding a congressional law limiting access to weapons for certain groups.

President George H.W. Bush's invocation of the Insurrection Act to help civilian authorities respond to widespread disorders in Los Angeles in 1992 (leaving 63 dead and over 2,000 injured) after the court acquitted four LA police officers of beating an African American man, Rodney King; and the right-wing terrorist bombing of federal government offices in Oklahoma in 1995 (killing 168 people) became searing reminders of the place of political violence in American political development, however. Because this was the pre-internet and social media era, access to materials with anti-government ideologies and pro-violence advocacy was harder to acquire. The Oklahoma City bomber was tutored into action through a group of right-wing militias and extremists. Twenty-three years later the racist killer who shot dead nine African American church attenders in Charleston, South Carolina learned his trade and ideology from widely available internet sources, long after the ‘fairness doctrine’ (requiring controversial issues be presented to audiences with differing views) had ended as a constraint on broadcasting content.

Period 4. Heller, militias and the ‘normalization of violence’

Our contemporary era is characterized by the jurisprudential liberalization of access to and public use of weapons, the uptick in political violence across the US – including protests about deaths in communities of colour resulting from police or stand-your-ground encounters – deepened and aligned partisan, racial and affective polarization among voters, and weakened federal force after the steady enhancement in states' rights since the 1990s. Localists are emboldened, reviving values and sentiments celebrated in the late 18th century, with some communities seeking secession from larger territorial units to establish racially segregated school and residential districts (Johnson and King Reference Johnson and King2019; Rocco Reference Rocco, Lieberman, Mettler and Roberts2021; Yancy Reference Yancy2022). Racially motivated massacres – such as the Charleston church and Buffalo supermarket killings in 2016 and 2022 respectively – ensure violence is at the forefront of American society.

The election of Barack Obama as America's first African American president and the Supreme Court's monumental decision in District of Columbia v. Heller, both in 2008, set the stage for the contemporary resurgence in gun ownership, political violence and heightened affective polarization. Obama endured an unprecedented number of death threats for a president. First and Second Amendment constitutional rights are hugely significant as they contribute to the barriers thwarting laws to regulate access to guns and their use (Carlson Reference Carlson2023; Filindra Reference Filindra2022; Winkler Reference Winkler2013). Protected in the Second Amendment, the right to bear arms has significantly expanded and deepened. Gun ownership is up, spurred, for example, by the Obama presidency: the election of Obama led many whites to acquire a gun or to augment their collection in anticipation of tighter ownership regulations (Berrigan et al. Reference Berrigan, Azrael and Miller2022; Yamane Reference Yamane2023). Lobbying by gunmakers and the National Rifle Association (NRA) helped drive this process (Carlson Reference Carlson2023; Lacombe Reference Lacombe2021; McIntire Reference McIntire2022; McWhirter and Elinson Reference McWhirter and Elinson2023). Lobbying also intensified to make gun ownership less about militias and more about individuals. Pro-gun lobbyists, including the NRA, play a key role in depoliticizing mass school and other shootings, defining their perpetrators as dangerous people with guns for whom no regulation would make a difference to their actions. Indeed, for gun owners mass shootings expose the need for more weapons – in the hands of teachers, for example – not fewer. After the kidnapping attempt on Michigan's governor, the governor's chief of staff recoiled at ‘the normalization of violence’ that it seemed to signal (quoted in Barrett Reference Barrett2022).

The Supreme Court steps in

Since 2008, the opportunities to own and to use firearms has changed under several important Supreme Court rulings. These decisions affirm that the right to gun ownership and to bear arms is an individual right (thereby demolishing long-standing jurisprudence) not one confined to membership of a volunteer militia (District of Columbic v. Heller 2008). The right to carry concealed weapons in public places has steadily widened (New York State Rifle and Pistol Association v. Bruen 2022). The right to modify a weapon into a more deadly form with a ‘bump stock’ adjustment has been rendered constitutional (Garland v. Cargill 2024). These constitutional rights are hugely significant as they contribute to the barriers thwarting laws to regulate access to guns and their use (Carlson Reference Carlson2023; Cornell Reference Cornell2006; Filindra 2022).

Heller decisively shifted the Court's view of the Second Amendment from a state militia power to an individual right to bear arms unrelated to military service and in the context of personal confrontations (notably in the home), in the majority's decision employing the conservative ‘originalism’ doctrine and even citing pre-American Revolution English law. If Heller affirmed the individual's right to bear arms unconnected to militia service, Bruen paved the way for exercising that right in places outside the home by rejecting a discretionary concealed carry licensing law from New York State. This expansion – previously limited in a gun regulation in 1968 prompted by Black Panthers carrying open arms as allowed then constitutionally – permits organized militias openly to display arms at rallies. One study of 700 armed demonstrations between January 2022 and November 2022 found ‘at about 77 percent of them, people openly carrying guns represented rightwing views, such as opposition to L.G.B.T.Q. rights and abortion access, hostility to racial justice rallies and support for former President Donald J. Trump's lie of winning the 2020 election’ (McIntire Reference McIntire2022).

The Court's majority opinion separated any relative assessment of the harm produced by gun ownership (measured in evidence-based gun regulation laws) from a judicial defence of the Second Amendment, urging lower-court justices to seek out historical analogies to justify contemporary gun policy. Right-wing militias such as the Boogaloo Boys and the Proud Boys meet at rallies around the country fully armed up to defend First and Second Amendment rights, and such assemblies are enjoying an uptick. The study cited above finds that armed protests occur across the United States, but in those states (Washington, Virginia, Texas, Pennsylvania, Oregon, North Carolina, Michigan, Kentucky, Georgia and Arizona) which have responded to Supreme Court rulings with enhanced open-carry laws, organized rallies and mass protests with militia-style protesters have grown (McIntire Reference McIntire2022).

The increased number of political violence incidents

The incidence of political violence appears heightened in 21st-century America. The racist-motivated massacre of nine African Americans at a church in Charleston, South Carolina in 2015 and the Unite the Right killing of Heather Heyer in Charlottesville in 2017 are a foreground to George Floyd's filmed death in Minneapolis. Floyd's murder, stirring a nationwide and international protest movement, gave way to the storming of Capitol Hill in January 2021 with at least four deaths, to the murder of ten African Americans at a supermarket in Buffalo, New York in 2022, and the attempted assassination of the Republican presidential candidate in Butler, Pennsylvania in 2024. These overt acts of political violence hark back to the origins and political development of the US. Perpetrators face punitive consequences. Both the Charleston and Buffalo racist perpetrators are in jail for life (one under a death penalty), the police officer convicted of Floyd's murder got a long sentence, the killer of Heather Heyer was jailed and over 1,000 Capitol Hill insurrectionists were convicted, many receiving lengthy periods of confinement.

The persistence of political violence despite this pattern of retribution reveals how strongly those Americans engaging in violent acts feel and maintain the legitimacy of such actions despite the authority of the federal government set out in the Constitution. Often the violent acts stem from affiliation with a group committed to violence, such as the Three Percenters militia members at 6 January (a group which takes its appellation from the size of the population in the 13 colonies fighting the British – three percent). Their symbol of a Roman numeral III circled by 13 stars adds to the political culture of non-peaceful interaction with government in America. The Confederate flag – unfurled in Congress by insurrectionists on 6 January – is another instance as is the anti-government Gadsden rattlesnake flag, and the American flag turned upside down (a symbol of support used by the 2020 election deniers), sported in the residence of US Supreme Court Justice Samuel A. Alito Jr (Kantor Reference Kantor2024). Alito garnered further controversy when a Revolutionary War–era ‘appeal to heaven’ flag was spotted at his vacation home, a symbol of Christian nationalism adopted also by election deniers (Kantor et al. Reference Kantor, Toler and Tale2024). These symbols assume heightened significance when the propensity for violence intensifies under partisan polarization (Vavreck Reference Vavreck2016) and racial spillover of policy issues (Tesler Reference Tesler2012), combined with such threats as those to kill the former vice-president, Mike Pence (ironically VP to former President Trump), and a serving Supreme Court justice.

Violence impinges on many elected politicians. The convicted assailant of the former Democrat Party Speaker Nancy Pelosi's husband was apparently on a mission to harm her. Entering the Pelosi home with a hammer, the intruder bludgeoned her husband while demanding, ‘where is Nancy?’, he plainly had an intent to attack a politician (quoted in Edmondson Reference Edmondson2022). In common with many other leading Democrat politicians, Pelosi featured in Republican ads and numerous social media conspiracy tropes demonizing her (Parker et al. Reference Parker, Allam and Sotomayor2022) and extending into violent threats against her person. The insurrectionists storming Congress on 6 January shouted her name and hunted down her office. Convicting one 24-year-old woman from Pennsylvania – she had encouraged others to enter the Speaker's office, advocated stealing and boasted on social media before removing material in an effort to evade capture – the justice singled out her casual lawlessness: ‘the defendant's conduct that day was utterly reprehensible’ (quoted in Wolfe Reference Wolfe2023). The defendant received a three-year term, joining hundreds of other insurrectionists hunted down by the FBI since January 2021.

But insurrectionists are embraced by the former Republican President Donald Trump as ‘hostages’: that is, they are American citizens, incarcerated unfairly by the federal government, who were simply exercising legitimate rights to protest and express their opposition to an election under First Amendment rights. Trump's characterization goes directly to the issue of state monopoly and the legitimacy of political violence exercised in society.

Affective polarization and political violence

The elevated polarization along partisan and racial lines in the American electorate since the 1990s impedes long-standing opposition to the legitimacy of violence in political life, and to the standard measures of democracy such as vacating an elected office after electoral defeat (Iyengar et al. Reference Iyengar, Sood and Lelkes2012). In other words, public attitudes towards the acceptability of using violence to defend or advance political beliefs has moderated from an overwhelming opposition to such actions to a softer belief that on occasion such extremes may be necessary and therefore legitimate.

Polarization is deeply about racism in the United States (Jardina Reference Jardina2019; Kleinfeld Reference Kleinfeld2021, Reference Kleinfeld2023; Mutz Reference Mutz2018; Rhodes and Nteta Reference Rhodes and Nteta2024; Tesler Reference Tesler2012). ‘Affective polarization’ describes levels of hostility by one group of partisan supporters towards those who support another party, a division not based on ideological differences, which is the standard approach to explaining party political cleavages. Democrat Party supporters hate Republican partisan supporters simply because they are Republicans; the reverse antipathy holds too as Republican partisan supporters hate Americans who are Democrat Party supporters. This atavism goes below mere partisan polarization to a deeper animosity rooted in personal values and hatreds (Druckman et al. Reference Druckman, Klar, Krupnikov, Levendusky and Ryan2021). The levels of bile associated with the affectively polarized is such that the step to act violently on these feelings is short. Nathan Kalmoe and Lilliana Mason (Reference Kalmoe and Mason2022) call this ‘radical American partisanship’.

The rise of positive attitudes to the use of political violence

The Public Religion Research Institute's (PRRI) annual survey of public opinion attitudes has reported an increase in the acceptability and perceived need for political violence in the early 2020s. The 2023 survey (with 2,535 respondents) reports an increase in positive views towards the need to use political violence in US politics from the 2021 survey: from 15% to 23% for all Americans, 7% to 13% for Democrat respondents, 13% to 22% amongst independents, and from 28% to 33% for Republican voters (PRRI 2023). One in three registered Republican Party supporters accept that ‘true American patriots’ are likely to have to employ violence to save the country they believe in, ‘because things have gotten so far off track, true American patriots may have to resort to violence in order to save our country’. Having run the question for several years, in eight surveys, the response in 2023 was the first time that the positive response rate towards political violence was above 20%. White evangelical Protestants also report a similar third believing that resorting to political violence may be necessary to save the country. None of the other religious groups surveyed had a similar level of support for political violence. Unsurprisingly, in the PRRI surveys, support for political violence amongst voters who believe the argument that the 2020 election was stolen and are ardent Trump supporters is marked – standing at 46% – and of those Americans who simply hold a positive view of the former president, 41% accept the need for political violence.

Support for the use of political violence in politics and an acceptance that it may be necessary to resort to its use has grown this century, whether by as much as some surveys report or not. The notion of legitimacy is again crucial to this analysis: the issue is not the extent of the state's monopoly on violence; rather it is about the state's monopoly of legitimate violence. Polarization, racism and the division between Trump-supporting Republicans and other American voters is piercing into political culture, attitudes and sentiments. For some commentators the danger of a civil war seems realistic, but a meaningful erosion of democratic beliefs is a more probable trajectory (Mettler and Lieberman Reference Mettler and Lieberman2020; Skocpol Reference Skocpol, Skocpol and Tervo2020; Walter Reference Walter2022). From their online experimental study, Matthew Graham and Milan Svolik report a turn against democracy amongst some American voters. They write, ‘when faced with the choice between a co-partisan candidate whose positions violate democratic principles and a candidate who complies with democratic principles but is otherwise unappealing, a significant fraction of voters may sacrifice democratic principles to elect a candidate who champions their party or interests’ (Reference Graham and Svolik2020: 392, emphasis added). In their results, Graham and Solvik do find that a majority of Americans favour democracy but this sentiment is not held strongly and a majority now favour partisan loyalty over commitment to democratic principles (and see Jardina and Mickey Reference Jardina and Mickey2022).

While such findings represent in part the exceptional era of polarization of 21st-century America, they are consistent with my argument about the endogenous place of political violence.

Part 3. American democracy and the accommodation of political violence

This article has demonstrated how intrinsic and ubiquitous political violence is to the history and politics of the United States, before and since the adoption of its Constitution in 1787–1789. This violence includes intergroup conflicts, often murderous, anti-government actions and mobilizing armed organized militias, activities which persist despite a shifting legal order and efforts to hem in lawlessness. The partiality of the federal government's authority to control the legitimate exercise of physical force – exposing the limits of America's version of the Weberian state – is a fundamental source enabling political violence to endure, I have argued. What role does this accommodation of violence play politically?

First, the deployment of violence for reform has been vital because of how violence is endogenous: it is an unavoidable backlash. The political scientist Ted Lowi's The Politics of Disorder – written in the early 1970s in response to the previous decade's protests – called, in opaque prose, for a celebration of ‘law and disorder’. He imputed a cathartic energy to challenge hierarchy and authority as tests of leadership. For others, however. the use of violence is less discretionary.

In Black Power (Reference Ture and Hamilton1967) Stokely Carmichael (Kwame Ture) and Charles Hamilton underlined the inevitability of a violent alternative trajectory to the non-violent civil rights movement: ‘a key phrase in our buffer-zone days was non-violence. For years it has been thought that black people would not literally fight for their lives. Why this has been so is not entirely clear; neither the larger society nor black people are noted for passivity … Black people should and must fight back.’ Or as the scholar Charles Cobb (Reference Cobb2014) phrases his pithy book title, ‘this nonviolent stuff'll get you killed’, to convey the key role of violence in the civil rights movement. Historian Kellie Carter Jackson's Force and Freedom (Reference Carter Jackson2019) examines how black abolitionists came to accept that a peaceful path would not get results (and see Taylor Reference Taylor2023). In We Refuse, Carter Jackson (Reference Carter Jackson2024) argues that the role of non-violent resistance as a part of the civil rights struggle overlooks significant acts of refusal and rebellion; she emphasizes the number of African American women who have owned firearms historically to protect their households from white supremacists – including, Carter Jackson notes, the iconic Rosa Parks. Several scholars challenge the accuracy and rigidity of the long-established dichotomy between armed self-defence and non-violence in the civil rights movement. The historian Akinyele Omowale Umoja (Reference Umoja2013) uses the case study of Mississippi to illustrate how non-violent civil rights activists there necessarily depended on armed colleagues to help resist the white violence heaped on them as they struggled for change. Umoja emphasizes the embrace of violence to defend communities and fellow activists as a reluctant but ineluctable option in the face of white repression and terrorism. Because the federal government declined to use its enforcement powers (King and Lieberman Reference King and Lieberman2021) or to deploy national guards under the Insurrection Act to protect civil rights activists in the 1964 Summer Freedom campaign, armed activists hung out at the fringes of the peaceful protests to provide self-defence, as the historian Charles Payne documents (Reference Payne1995).

Charles Cobb (Reference Cobb2014) elaborates on this point. He surveys acts of armed self-defence by African Americans across enslavement, Reconstruction, the early 20th century and particularly during the 1950s and 1960s – notably the Deacons for Defense in Jonesboro, Louisiana and the unnamed group active in Tuscaloosa Alabama under Joseph Mallisham's guidance – when the Freedom Movement peaked. He finds that beneath the surface of non-violent rhetoric and strategy armed self-defence was necessarily at work to protect non-violent civil rights activists from racist violence; he contends that the movement's success in practice required this element of armed self-defence. Veterans (of whom Medgar Evers was one) made up a striking number of activists providing this armed self-defence. Among them was the civil rights activist in Monroe, North Carolina, Robert F. Williams. Williams had no reservations about using violence, entitling his book Negroes with Guns (Reference Williams2013), and doubted whether any change could occur without resorting to violent resistance and protest: for Williams the depth of America's structural racism meant any transition to civil rights was improbable. Williams argued for retaliatory violence against white supremacist in addition to armed self-defence, both forms of political violence dictated by the embeddedness of America's racial order. He relished how the image of ‘Negroes with guns’ alarmed white Americans.

Frances Fox Piven, known for her work on protest movements, puts ‘disruptive’ challenging at the core of her account of change but argues that protest often needs violence: ‘Students of American social movements … tend to ignore episodes of violence that do occur, excluding them by fiat from their definition of social movements’ (Reference Piven2006: 47). She adds that ‘violence by protesters are often treated as a purely moral issue, a stance that ignores the violence inherent in the institutional routines, such as the starvation wages paid to the Lawrence MA 1912 strikers’ (Piven Reference Piven2006: 47).

Second, from its colonial origins, political violence has upheld America's racial order. Racialized violence in America is ubiquitous, particularly in respect of criminal justice and social protest (Banerjee et al. Reference Banerjee, Willison and Greer2024; Miller Reference Miller2015). Historically, the fears induced by the 18th-century pre-Independence race riots in New York City (and resulting laws setting up slave watches and banning Black Americans from owning firearms), the Haitian Revolution and the draft riots in the 1860s soaked up these features. The 20th-century mobilization of the American Indian Movement (AIM) for rights looked back to the legacy of 19th-century massacres such as Wounded Knee.

Occasionally and non-trivially some enslaved people would encounter the formal system and then discover that the laws there merely confirmed the system of enslavement – notoriously in Dred Scott, which ruptured the polity to its core and ushered in civil war. Formal legal rules and incarceration reinforced each other. The legacies of decisions taken in the 1770s and institutionalized in the Constitution, then rooted in the legal system and in the system of law enforcement, ‘inextricably … linked them to the history of slavery and settler colonialism’ (Hinton and Cook Reference Hinton and Cook2021: 265). The post-enslavement racial order moved violence to a new domain, enforcing racism with a combination of laws and the constant threat of violence, a spectre regularly animated (for example, through lynching and beatings; Brundage Reference Brundage1993; Pfeifer Reference Pfeifer2004). The federalization of racial hierarchy in the 1910s and 1920s ensured that segregationist violence persisted after the reforms of the 1960s.

The nominal de jure termination of segregation and discrimination in civil rights reforms has not ended racialized violence remotely. As Megan Francis remarks of the present era, ‘the way racial violence is embedded in the criminal punishment system is striking: Black people are disproportionately imprisoned, abused in custody, stopped and frisked by police, and sentenced to longer terms’ (Reference Francis2022: 188). Although the enduring influence of racial violence is a profound threat to democratization in America, Francis notes that ‘state-sanctioned killing of Black citizens’ is omitted in the recent scholarship about the dilution of democracy. For Francis, placing racial violence as ‘outside’ the polity precludes grasping its centrality: ‘despite the enduring influence of racial violence, scholars of American politics do not usually treat it as a durable threat to democracy’, but treat it as exogenous. Anti-Black violence is not partisan-based: ‘the absence of a more nuanced discussion of racial violence results from examining democracy through a single frame’ (Francis Reference Francis2022: 188, 189), a frame neglecting endogeneity.

Third, a mechanism aiding the endogenous status of political violence is the constitutional system of pardons releasing those who engaged in violence from their sentences. Civil War secessionists faced trials and imprisonment but then pardons (Dodds Reference Dodds2021), and many senior figures such as Jefferson Davis skirted prosecution (Lepore Reference Lepore2023). Assassinated President Lincoln's successor and unexpected White House incumbent, Andrew Johnson, proved an enthusiastic pardoner of ex-Confederates and a weak enforcer of Union conditions on the former rebel states (Dodds Reference Dodds2021). The record of convicting white Americans for racial violence is weak (Aaronson Reference Aaronson2014; Romano Reference Romano2014), though increasingly expanded as standards of civil rights gain federal enforcement and ballast (for example, through the application of federal hate crimes of the sort used against the killers of Ahmaud Arbery in Georgia; Nakamura Reference Nakamura2022).

This tradition of presidential pardon not only gives credibility to the legitimacy of violent actions but laces it with the expectation that this legitimate quality will be vindicated, resulting in perpetrators' release from incarceration. Of the nearly 1,500 people charged for rioting on 6 January, dozens faced sedition charges (more than at any time in US history), notably members of militias such as the Proud Boys and Oath Keepers (whose Yale-educated and veteran leader won 18 years’ imprisonment; Feuer Reference Feuer2023). Convictions or guilty pleas have been won for over 1,000, and by the election in 2024 560 had gone to prison. Former Republican President Donald Trump had, by August 2024, come to promise pardons not only for those convicted of misdemeanour charges but even for those prisoners who had assaulted police officers (Debusmann and Wendling Reference Debusmann and Wendling2024). Asked if he would pardon rioters who had assaulted police officers, Trump responded, ‘Oh absolutely … If they are innocent I would pardon them’ (quoted in Levien Reference Levien2024). This promise – aired during a combative interview with African American journalists in Chicago on the last day of July 2024 – confirmed what Trump had said in the previous months (‘full pardons with an apology to many’, quoted in Paybarah Reference Paybarah2024), and with his giddy elevation of insurrectionists as ‘hostages’.

Protests mobilized by partners and families of convicted felons from 6 January have sprung up. Justice for January 6thers (J4J6) holds nightly vigils outside the jail in Washington, DC in which many of the 6 January prisoners are incarcerated, anointing their spot as Freedom Corner, communicating each evening with some inmates on speaker phone to sing in solidarity with them (Rosin Reference Rosin2024). But Trump's use of the language of ‘hostage’ is under challenge. District of Columbia Judge Royce C. Lambeth rebuffed such a characterization to describe criminals charged with breaking into property, rioting and assault. He resisted the normalization of the insurrectionists' behaviour on 6 January. Justice Lambeth issued a memo ‘Notes for Sentencing’, with a forceful statement of why lawlessness and vigilantism is incompatible with a society ordered by the rule of law. The First Amendment, he reiterated, offered scope for peaceful assembly and protest.

Conclusion

Taking American political violence seriously challenges accounts of the formation of the American state and its purported monopoly on the use of legitimate violence and physical force. For example, the persistence of racialized violence means the institutions of state and government settled in the 1770s and revised in the 1860s rested more widely on violent presumptions and arrangements than commonly appreciated. Hobbling national authority had to be an essential aim of the Delegates in Philadelphia or they would each confront unsustainable futures. To make violence so embedded required extending it into the constitutional core through such vociferous causes as states' rights, free speech, the Second Amendment right to bear arms, and rejection of a standing army in favour of local militias mobilized as needed and under local or state authority and not the centre. Carrying arms was never a lost cause.

Political scientists commonly understand political violence as exogenous to the political system (even if endogenously prompted) and as an anomaly rather than as a constitutive element. Demise in violence is presumed. Since there is a constitutional accommodation, containing and facilitating a transition from routine violence has been an urgent political task since the 18th century. There is some success – for instance, in the erosion of violence at strikes.

Political violence features more in the US political system than in comparable democracies because the founders' constitutional arrangements legitimated political violence outside the state. Within society, the constitutional settlement placed limits on the power of the federal state despite nominally according it a monopoly on physical force. This renders political violence endogenous to American politics.

The enduring challenge for Americans is how to reconcile respect for a capacious exploitation of the First and Second Amendments with the imperatives of the rule of law. For Justice Lambeth (Reference Lambeth2024) in his District of Columbia courtroom, there is no question about the unconstitutionality of 6 January: ‘nor was the January 6 riot an act of civil disobedience, because it was violent, not peaceful; opportunistic, not principled; coercive, not persuasive; and selfish, not patriotic’. Those Americans advocating pardons adopt the obverse view. They cite the same constitutional rules in affirmation of insurrectionists' legitimate embrace of political violence. Weber would side with the judge but acknowledge also the vulnerabilities bequeathed by the Constitution to the federal government's exercise of legitimate coercion.

Acknowledgements

This article is based on the Government and Opposition / Leonard Schapiro Lecture, held at the Royal Society of the Arts, London, 18 May 2023.

Footnotes

1 This was his position at the time of writing.

References

Aaronson, E (2014) From Slave Abuse to Hate Crime. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Arceneaux, K, Gravelle, TB, Osmundsen, M, Petersen, MB, Reifler, J and Scotto, TJ (2020) Some People Just Want to Watch the World Burn: The Prevalence, Psychology and Politics of the ‘Need for Chaos’. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B 376, 20200147. https://doi.org/10.1098/rstb.2020.0147.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Banerjee, V, Willison, C and Greer, S (2024) Policing the Police. British Journal of Politics and International Relations 26, 122. https://doi.org/10.1177/13691481241267285.Google Scholar
Barrett, D (2022) Jury Acquits Two in Michigan Governor Kidnap Plot: Deadlocks on Two Others. Washington Post, 8 April.Google Scholar
Behrend, J (2017) Reconstructing Democracy. Athens: University of Georgia Press.Google Scholar
Belew, K (2018) Bring the War Home. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Berrigan, J, Azrael, D and Miller, M (2022) The Number of Type of Private Firearms in the United States. ANNALS of the American Academy of Political and Social Science 101(704), 7091. https://doi.org/10.1177/00027162231164855.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Blackhawk, N (2023) The Rediscovery of America. New Haven: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Bobo, L (1983) Whites’ Opposition to Busing: Symbolic Racism or Realistic Group Conflict? Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 45, 11961210. https://doi.org/10.1037/0022-3514.45.6.1196.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bogus, CT (2023) Madison's Militias. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bordewich, FM (2023) Klan War. New York: Knopf.Google Scholar
Brundage, WF (1993) Lynching in the New South. Urbana: University of Illinois Press.Google Scholar
Carlson, J (2015) Citizen-Protectors. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carlson, J (2019) Revisiting the Weberian Presumption: Gun Militarism, Gun Populism and the Racial Politics of Legitimate Violence in Policing. American Journal of Sociology 125, 633682. https://doi.org/10.1086/707609.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carlson, J (2023) Merchants of the Right. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Carter Jackson, K (2019) Force and Freedom. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press.Google Scholar
Carter Jackson, K (2022) The Story of Violence in America. Daedalus 151, 1123. https://doi.org/10.1162/daed_a_01884.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carter Jackson, K (2024) We Refuse. New York: Seal.Google Scholar
Chicago Commission on Race Relations (1922) The Negro in Chicago: A Study of a Race Riot. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Cobb, CE Jr. (2014) That Nonviolent Stuff'll Will Get You Killed. Durham, NC: Duke University Press.Google Scholar
Corley, C (2020) Nearly 700 People in the US Die from Gun Violence Each Week, NPR, 4 February.Google Scholar
Cornell, S (2006) A Well Regulated Militia. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cowie, J (2022) Freedom's Dominion. New York: Hachette.Google Scholar
Debusmann, B Jr. and Wendling, M (2024) Capitol rioters’ families draw hope from Trump's promise of pardons. BBC online. 5 April. https://www.bbc.co.uk/news/world-us-canada-68632188.Google Scholar
Dodds, G (2021) Mass Pardons in America. New York: Columbia University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Druckman, JN, Klar, S, Krupnikov, Y, Levendusky, M and Ryan, JB (2021) Affective Polarization, Local Contexts and Public Opinion in America. Nature Human Behavior 5, 2838. https://doi.org/10.1038/s41562-020-01012-5.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Edmondson, C (2022) Attack Highlights Fears of Political Violence. New York Times, 1 November.Google Scholar
Elinson, Z (2021) Women Are Nearly Half of New Gun Buyers, Study Finds. Wall Street Journal, 16 September.Google Scholar
Elinson, Z and McWhirter, C (2024) A Divisive Symbol Behind Trump’s Attempted Assassination: The AR-15. Wall Street Journal, 15 July.Google Scholar
Feuer, A (2023) Sedition Case Offers U.S. Some Accountability. New York Times, 29 May.Google Scholar
Feuer, A, Schmidt, MS and Broadwater, L (2022) The Trump Tweet that Galvanized Far-Right Supporters. New York Times, 28 March.Google Scholar
Filindra, A (2023) Race, Rights and Rifles. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Francis, MM (2014) Civil Rights and the Making of the Modern American State. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Francis, MM (2022) Can Black Lives Matter within U.S. Democracy? ANNALS of the American Academy of Political and Social Science 699, 186199. https://doi.org/10.1177/00027162221078340.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Freeman, JB (2018) The Field of Blood. New York: Picador.Google Scholar
Gerstle, G (2015) Liberty and Coercion. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Graham, HD and Gurr, TR (1969) Violence in America. New York: Praeger.Google Scholar
Graham, MH and Svolik, MW (2020) Democracy in America? Partisanship, Polarization, and the Robustness of Support for Democracy in the US. American Political Science Review 114, 392409. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0003055420000052.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hinton, E (2015) A War within Our Own Boundaries. Journal of American History 98, 98113. https://doi.org/10.1093/jahist/jav328.Google Scholar
Hinton, E and Cook, D (2021) The Mass Criminalization of Black Americans. Annual Review of Criminology 27, 261284. criminol.annualreviews.org. https://doi.org/10.1146/annurev-criminol-060520-033306.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Holman, MR (2024) The Power of the Badge. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Iyengar, S, Sood, G and Lelkes, Y (2012) Affect, Not Ideology. Public Opinion Quarterly 76(3), 405431. http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/poq/nfs038.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jardina, A (2019) White Identity Politics. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jardina, A and Mickey, R (2022) White Racial Solidarity and Opposition to American Democracy. ANNALS of the American Academy of Political and Social Science 699, 7989. https://doi.org/10.1177/00027162211069730.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Johnson, KS (2007) Governing the American State. Princeton: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Johnson, R and King, D (2019) ‘Race Was a Motivating Factor’: The Rise of Re-Segregated Schools. Journal of International and Comparative Social Policy 35, 7595. https://doi.org/10.1080/21699763.2018.1526701.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jones, R and Miller, LL (2024) Lethal Violence and the Racialized Failure of the American State. Perspectives on Politics 23(1), 4567.Google Scholar
Kalmoe, NP and Mason, L (2022) Radical American Partisanship. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kalyvas, S (2019) The Landscape of Political Violence. In Chenoweth, E, English, R, Gofas, A and Kaylvas, S (eds), Oxford Handbook of Terrorism. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 4258.Google Scholar
Kantor, J (2024) The Alitos, the Neighborhood Clash, and the Upside-Down Flag. New York Times, 28 May.Google Scholar
Kantor, J, Toler, A and Tale, J (2024) Another Provocative Flag Was Flown at Another Alito Home. New York Times, 22 May.Google Scholar
Keith, L (2008) The Colfax Massacre. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kerner Commission (1968) Report of the National Advisory Commission on Civil Disorders. New York: Bantam.Google Scholar
King, D (2005) The Liberty of Strangers. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
King, D (2007) Separate and Unequal. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
King, D (2017) Forceful Federalism against Racial Inequality. Government and Opposition: An International Journal of Comparative Politics 52, 356382. https://doi.org/10.1017/gov.2016.52.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
King, D and Lieberman, RC (2009) Ironies of the American State. World Politics 61, 547588. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0043887109000185.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
King, D and Lieberman, RC (2021) ‘The Latter Day General Grant’: Forceful Federal Power and Civil Rights. Journal of Race, Ethnicity & Politics 6, 529564. https://doi.org/10.1017/rep.2020.19.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
King, D and Smith, RM (2005) Racial Orders in American Political Development. American Political Science Review 99(1), 7592. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0003055405051506.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kirkpatrick, DD (2024) Infiltrating the Far Right. New Yorker, 18 August.Google Scholar
Kleinfeld, R (2021) The Rise of Political Violence in the United States. Journal of Democracy 32, 160176. https://doi.org/10.1353/jod.2021.0059.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kleinfeld, R (2023) Polarization, Democracy and Political Violence in the United States. New York: Carnegie Endowment for International Peace. https://carnegie-production-assets.s3.amazonaws.com/static/files/Kleinfeld_Polarization_final_3.pdf.Google Scholar
Lacombe, M (2021) Firepower. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Lambeth, DC Justice Royce C (2024) Notes for sentencing, in U.S.A. v. Taylor James Johnatakis Case No 1: 21-cr-91-RCL-3.Google Scholar
Lane, C (2008) The Day Freedom Died. New York: Holt.Google Scholar
Lepore, J (2023) The Mistrial: When the U.S. Prepared to Prosecute an Insurrectionist Ex-President. New Yorker, 8 December.Google Scholar
Levien, SJ (2024) Trump Says He Would Pardon Jan. 6 Rioters who Attacked Police. New York Times, 31 July.Google Scholar
Lustbader, S (2021) What the Arbery and Rittenhouse Verdicts Couldn't Tell Us. New York Times, 24 November.Google Scholar
McIntire, M (2022) At Protests, Guns Are Doing the Talking. New York Times, 26 November.Google Scholar
McIntire, M and Kantor, J (2024) The Gun Lobby's Hidden Hand in the 2nd Amendment Battle. New York Times, 18 June.
McWhirter, C and Elinson, Z (2023) American Gun: The Story of the AR-15. New York: Farrar, Straus.Google Scholar
Mettler, S and Lieberman, RC (2020) Four Threats. New York: St Martin's Press.Google Scholar
Miller, LL (2015) What's Violence Got to Do with It? Punishment and Society 17, 184210. https://doi.org/10.1177/1462474515577153.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mutz, DC (2018) Status Threat, Not Economic Hardship, Explains the 2016 Presidential Vote. Proceedings of the National Academy of Science 115, E4330E4339. https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.1718155115.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Nacos, BL, Bloch-Elkon, Y and Shapiro, RY (2024) Hate Speech and Political Violence. New York: Columbia University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nakamura, D (2022) Arbery Hate-Crimes Trail Highlights Everyday Racism – and Casual Gun Culture. Washington Post, 20 February.Google Scholar
North, D, Wallis, J and Weingeist, B (2009) Violence and Social Orders. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Obert, J (2018) The Six-Shooter State. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Obert, J (2022) Armed Federalism, Gun Markets and the Right to Bear Arms in the United States. Publius 54, 534572. https://doi.org/10.1093/publius/pjae020.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Park, K-S (2024) Property and Sovereignty in America: A History of Title Registries & Jurisdictional Power. Yale Law Review 133, 14871590.Google Scholar
Parker, A, Allam, H and Sotomayor, M (2022) Attack on Nancy Pelosi's Husband Follows Years of GOP Demonizing Her. Washington Post, 29 October.Google Scholar
Paybarah, A (2024) Trump Embraces Woman Convicted for Jan. 6 Crimes, Helps Raise Money for Legal Costs. Washington Post, 5 April.Google Scholar
Payne, C (1995) I've Got the Light of Freedom. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Pew Research Center, (2017) America's Complex Relationship with Guns. Washington, DC: Pew Research Center.Google Scholar
Pfeifer, MJ (2004) Rough Justice. Urbana: University of Illinois Press.Google Scholar
Piven, FF (2006) Challenging Authority. New York: Rowman and Littlefield.Google Scholar
Public Religion Research Institute (PRRI) (2023) Threats to American Democracy ahead of an Unprecedented Presidential Election: The 2023 American Values Survey. Washington, DC: PRRI. https://www.prri.org/wp-content/uploads/2023/10/2023-AVS-Presentation.pdf.Google Scholar
Rao, G (2008) The Federal Posse Comitatus Doctrine. Law and History Review 26, 156. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0738248000003552.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rhodes, JH and Nteta, TM (2024) The New Racial Spillover. Political Science Quarterly 139, 159176. https://doi.org/10.1093/psquar/qqae010.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Robertson, DB (2015) The Constitution from 1620 to the Early Republic. In Tushnet, M, Graber, MA and Levinson, S (eds), The Oxford Handbook of the U.S. Constitution. New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 2542.Google Scholar
Rocco, P (2021) Laboratories of What? American Federalism and the Politics of Democratic Subversion. In Lieberman, R, Mettler, S and Roberts, KM (eds), Democratic Resilience. New York: Cambridge University Press, pp. 154175.Google Scholar
Romano, RC (2014) Racial Reckoning. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rosin, H (2024) The Insurrectionist Next Door. The Atlantic, October.Google Scholar
Skocpol, T (2020) The Elite and Popular Roots of Contemporary Republican Extremism. In Skocpol, T and Tervo, C (eds), Upending American Politics. New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 2447.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sugrue, TJ (1995) Crabgrass-Roots Politics: Race, Rights and the Reaction against Liberalism in the Urban North, 1940–1964. Journal of American History 82, 551578. https://doi.org/10.2307/2082186.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sullivan, E (2023) Election Worker Tells Jury: ‘Giuliani Just Messed Me Up’. New York Times, 13 December.Google Scholar
Taft, P and Ross, P (1969) American Labor Violence: Its Causes, Consequences and Outcomes. In Graham, H and Gurr, TR (eds), Violence in America. New York: Praeger, pp. 5575.Google Scholar
Taylor, NM (2023) Brooding over Bloody Revenge. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tesler, M (2012) The Spillover of Racialization into Health Care: How President Obama Polarized Public Opinion by Race and Racial Attitudes. American Journal of Political Science 56, 690704. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1540-5907.2011.00577.x.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ture, K (formerly Stokely Carmichael) and Hamilton, CV (1967) Black Power. New York: Doubleday.Google Scholar
Umoja, AO (2013) We Will Shoot Back. New York: New York University Press.Google Scholar
Van Cleve, GW (2010) A Slaverholders’ Union. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vavreck, L (2016) American Anger: It's Not the Economy. It's the Other Party. New York Times, 2 April.Google Scholar
Walter, BF (2022) How Civil Wars Star. New York: Crown.Google Scholar
Ware, AJ (2011) Political Conflict in America. New York: Palgrave.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Weber, M (1994) Weber: Political Writings. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Weinstein, TF (2021) Kyle Rittenhouse, Travis McMichael and the Problem of ‘Self-Defense’. New York Times, 29 November.Google Scholar
Williams, RF (2013) (Orig. 1962). Negroes with Guns. Mansfield Centre, CT: Martino Books.Google Scholar
Winkler, A (2013) Gunfight. New York: Norton.Google Scholar
Wolfe, J (2023) Jan. 6 Rioter Gets Three-Year Sentence for Storming Nancy Pelosi's Office. New York Times, 23 March.Google Scholar
Yamane, D (2023) Gun Culture 2.0: The Evolution and Contours of Defensive Gun Ownership in America. ANNALS of the American Academy of Political and Social Science 704, 2044. https://doi.org/10.1177/00027162231156292.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Yancy, NM (2022) How the Color Line Bends. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Figure 0

Figure 1. The Four Eras of Political Violence.