Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-tf8b9 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-27T16:47:01.247Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Direct Democracy and the Courts. By Kenneth P. Miller. New York: Cambridge University Press, 2009. 278 pp. $24.99 paper.

Review products

Direct Democracy and the Courts. By Kenneth P. Miller. New York: Cambridge University Press, 2009. 278 pp. $24.99 paper.

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2024

Jason Pierceson*
Affiliation:
University of Illinois, Springfield
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Type
Book Reviews
Copyright
© 2011 Law and Society Association.

Direct Democracy and the Courts comes at a time when the conflict between courts and direct democracy is particularly visible, as evidenced by the passage of California's Proposition 8 banning same-sex marriage and its subsequent challenge in federal court. This lucidly written, rich, and important book effectively explores the politics that result from a political system that blends strong judicial review with strong direct democracy. The author, Kenneth P. Miller, evaluates this hybrid system from a Madisonian perspective of appreciation for deliberative, representative democracy, and neither the courts nor the initiative process are immune from criticism. In the end, however, Miller posits that “direct citizen lawmaking has been largely contained by the constitutional system in which it operates,” largely through judicial counterbalancing (p. 216).

The book's greatest strength is the extensive research on the history of initiatives. Because of Miller's thorough research, the book will serve as a resource for scholars of both direct democracy and judicial politics. Miller's framing of the Progressive Era's push for voter initiatives as being driven by a very different view of democratic politics than that of the Founders is particularly useful. Elite deliberation with passive publics was replaced, or partially replaced, by a system that values active citizen engagement and control. This, of course, creates a tension in the U.S. polity, particularly over majoritarian power and the rights of the minority. Indeed, this concern for minority rights that are, and have been, threatened by the initiative process is, appropriately, one of the central themes of the book. As Miller notes, “A fair reading of the record suggests that direct democracy's consequential impact on rights has been to limit the expansion of rights in a numbers of areas, including affirmative action, bilingual education, marriage, and certain areas of the criminal law” (pp. 154–5; emphasis in original). Miller is careful to point out that the normative implications of this depend on one's view of what rights are, or should be, but he clearly notes that rights expansion is complicated by the presence of direct democracy.

The role of the courts in constraining the initiative process complicates this process even further, and in a way unintended by the Progressives, according to Miller. Indeed, the several chapters that Miller devotes to the exploration of judicial attempts to limit direct democracy will be of great interest to law and society scholars. He chronicles the process of unfavorable judicial response to the constraining of rights or initiative interference with the constitutional allocation of governmental powers, as reflected in the U.S. Supreme Court's invalidation of term limits at the federal level. This discussion will contribute to an ongoing debate among scholars of the courts regarding the extent to which courts are willing, or have the power, to challenge political majorities. Contrary to scholars who make the argument for generally passive and constrained courts, Miller demonstrates that judges can, and often do, effectively challenge majorities, especially in the states. In other words, law and legal norms matter for judicial policymaking. If judges feel that majorities have made a mistake in constricting rights or by unduly interfering with constitutional mechanisms or principles, then they often act on these sentiments.

One weakness of the book is that, because of the breadth of policy areas covered, Miller's analysis is sometimes underdeveloped. For example, as evidence of his central point about the shift of so much politics to initiatives and the courts, away from legislatures, Miller criticizes both the California Supreme Court for legalizing same-sex marriage in 2008 and the voters for enacting Proposition 8. As he states, “in this hybrid constitutional system, the initiative system and the judicial power have fed off each other as they have competed in a high-stakes fight for the last word” (p. 221). Consequently, he calls upon judges to refrain from judicial activism as a way to defuse this situation. (Miller also calls for supermajority requirements for state constitutional amendments and multiphase processes for their enactment.) This characterization of the situation in California might have been less critical of the courts had Miller seen the decision not as an activist forcing of same-sex marriage on the California polity but the culmination of a decade-long attempt to provide rights for same-sex couples, largely driven by the legislature. In fact, by the time of the high court decision, the legislature had already enacted a domestic partnership framework that mirrored the state's marriage law and had twice passed same-sex marriage legislation, only to be thwarted by Governor Arnold Schwarzenegger's veto pen. In other words, Madisonian deliberation very nearly accomplished the policy that the court mandated. Arguably, then, the courts and the initiative are not equal culprits. Proposition 8 more directly undermined Madisonianism.

Overall, this is an important book that will be of great interest to scholars of the courts, direct democracy, democratic theory, and state politics, and more generally to anyone interested in this unique aspect of the U.S. political system.