Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-dh8gc Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-05T05:27:31.992Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Explaining microvariation using the Tolerance Principle: plugging the amn’t gap

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  14 October 2024

Gary Thoms*
Affiliation:
New York University, 10 Washington Place, New York, 10003, USA
David Adger
Affiliation:
Queen Mary University of London, Mile End Road, London, E1, 4NS, United Kingdom
Caroline Heycock
Affiliation:
University of Edinburgh, 3 Charles Street, Edinburgh, EH8 9AD, United Kingdom
E. Jamieson
Affiliation:
University of York, Heslington, York, YO10 5DD, United Kingdom
Jennifer Smith
Affiliation:
University of Glasgow, 12 University Gardens, Glasgow, G12, 8QH, United Kingdom
*
Corresponding author: Gary Thoms; Email: [email protected]
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

In this article, we describe and explain patterns of variation in acceptance of amn’t in varieties of Scots, drawing upon data from the Scots Syntax Atlas. Partly in line with findings from Bresnan (2001), we show that amn’t is much more widely accepted in inversion environments (amn’t I?) than in declaratives (I amn’t), but nevertheless, amn’t in declaratives is still accepted in certain regions of Scotland. We combine the productivity-based explanation of the amn’t gap in Yang (2016, 2017) with new insights into the syntax of Scots negation from Thoms et al. (2023) to provide a predictive account of the attested variation.

Type
Research Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution and reproduction, provided the original article is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2024. Published by Cambridge University Press

1. Introduction

A well-known puzzle with English negation is that, in most varieties, it is not possible to attach the reduced form of negation -n’t to am (Langendoen Reference Langendoen1970, Zwicky & Pullum Reference Zwicky and Pullum1983). Examples such as (2b) with the form amn’t are judged as unacceptable, and speakers typically report that there is no other appropriate form for attaching negation to the auxiliary. Only the uncontracted negation can be used, as in (2a). For some speakers, however, the form aren’t is available in inversion contexts, as in (2d). This is unexpected, given that (2e) is consistently unavailable.

This absence of an am+n’t form has come to be known as ‘the amn’t gap’, in recognition of the fact that it represents a gap in what is generally thought of as a fairly consistent pattern of attachment of -n’t to finite auxiliaries (Francis Reference Francis and Viereck1985, Bresnan Reference Bresnan, Baltin and Collins2001, Anderwald Reference Anderwald2002, Broadbent Reference Broadbent2009).

Although the judgments in (2) hold for most varieties spoken in North America and England, there is some degree of dialectal variation in the acceptance of (2b) and (2c). Hudson (Reference Hudson2000) and Bresnan (Reference Bresnan, Baltin and Collins2001) report that Irish English speakers accept amn’t both in declarative, like (2b), and inverted orders, like (2c). In the varieties spoken in Scotland (herein, Scots), however, there is a curious asymmetry: amn’t is acceptable in inverted orders like (2c), but not in declaratives like (2b). We will call this the ‘inversion asymmetry’.

Bresnan (Reference Bresnan, Baltin and Collins2001) proposes an account of the inversion asymmetry in terms of morphosyntactic competition, connecting it to the fact that Scots varieties have an additional form for contracted negation, -nae. This negative form can combine with all the auxiliaries that -n’t can and, according to Bresnan (and, for example, Brown Reference Brown, Trudgill and Chambers1991), also with am to produce amnae; see (3).

However, no combination of -nae and an auxiliary can invert with the subject; see (4). No such constraint obtains with -n’t; see (5).

Bresnan’s (Reference Bresnan, Baltin and Collins2001) proposal is that in Scots varieties, amnae outcompetes amn’t in declaratives, but since amnae is not available in inversions, amn’t becomes possible. In Irish English, however, since there is no -nae negation, amn’t is used in both declaratives and inversions. Bresnan (Reference Bresnan, Baltin and Collins2001) takes this account of the dialectal variation with amn’t in inversions, and the accompanying account of the appearance of spurious aren’t, to provide an empirical argument for optimality-driven morphosyntactic competition more generally (but see Embick & Marantz Reference Embick and Marantz2008).

However, the absence of amn’t from varieties of English other than Irish English and Scots is ultimately taken by Bresnan (Reference Bresnan, Baltin and Collins2001) to be an accidental lexical gap, and so although her account gives us a handle on the inversion asymmetry, it leaves the source of the amn’t gap and its dialectal variability rather mysterious. More recently, Yang (Reference Yang, Bowern, Horn and Zanuttini2017) offers an analysis of the distribution of the amn’t gap across varieties of English in terms of differences in the productivity of the rule for the contracted negative form -n’t. He proposes that in American English, for example, there are, in fact, so many exceptions to the regularity of this ‘rule’ that children do not treat it as productive but learn each combination of auxiliary and negation separately, thus leaving open the possibility of a learned ‘gap’. For Scots and Irish English, however, he argues that there are fewer exceptions (mainly due to the absence of ain’t in these varieties); hence, learners conclude that there is a productive rule of -n’t suffixation, which will automatically result in the occurrence of amn’t. Yang argues for a principle – his ‘Tolerance Principle’ – that determines the threshold at which a productive rule kicks in and shows how this principle predicts the empirical outcomes. In contrast to Bresnan’s (Reference Bresnan, Baltin and Collins2001) proposal, then, the Tolerance Principle offers an explanation of the presence or absence of the amn’t gap across varieties.

Although the Tolerance Principle provides a new approach to the issue, it does not yet provide a satisfactory account of all the facts that Bresnan (Reference Bresnan, Baltin and Collins2001) brought into the discussion. First, it offers no explanation for the inversion asymmetry in Scots and its absence from Irish English. Connected to this, as it stands, it has nothing to say about the potential role for the Scots-specific negation -nae in the conditioning of the behaviour of amn’t, a possibility that was raised by Bresnan (Reference Bresnan, Baltin and Collins2001). It is also unclear how the two negative attachment rules would be expected to interact in a system that adopts the Tolerance Principle, especially in the absence of an analysis of the morphosyntax of negation in the relevant varieties.

In this article, we build on Yang’s productivity approach to the data but extend the theory, bringing in novel empirical data from microcomparative research into the syntax of negation, particularly in Scots varieties. We first describe the Scots empirical picture in detail, using fine-grained dialectal data from the Scots Syntax Atlas (Smith et al. Reference Smith, Adger, Aitken, Caroline Heycock and Thoms2019). We show that although the asymmetry Bresnan (Reference Bresnan, Baltin and Collins2001) describes holds for some speakers, there are also many speakers who accept amn’t in both declaratives and inversions, and that the variation observed is not tracked by acceptance/rejection of amnae forms in the way that Bresnan’s (Reference Bresnan, Baltin and Collins2001) account predicts. The atlas data allow us to see that there is a geographical coherence to where amn’t is accepted in both syntactic contexts (inverted and uninverted). With this established, we argue that, given a fuller understanding of the syntax of Scots arising from previous microcomparative work on other aspects of its negation system, it is possible to build on Yang’s productivity-based analysis in a way that can account for the richer pattern of data that the atlas has uncovered. In doing so, we stake out certain commitments to how the Tolerance Principle works in situations of morphosyntactic variability, extending the application of this set of ideas in a richer microcomparative domain.

2. Redrawing the Empirical Picture

This section introduces the Scots Syntax Atlas and shows how it provides a new perspective on the distribution of the amn’t gap in Scots. With that in place, we show that the geographical distribution of inversion with negation across Scotland broadly follows Bresnan’s (Reference Bresnan, Baltin and Collins2001) description, but that the geographical distribution of two distinct negated forms of first person present be (amn’t and amnae) does not.

2.1. The atlas

The Scots Syntax Atlas (SCOSYA, Smith et al. Reference Smith, Adger, Aitken, Caroline Heycock and Thoms2019) is a fully searchable online atlas, mapping morphosyntactic variation across Scots varieties. The atlas contains data gathered from over 140 locations across Scotland (Figure 1), with four speakers – two aged 18–25 and two aged 65+ – per location. Participants were recruited following standard sociolinguistic criteria for identifying speakers local to the community under study (e.g. Feagin Reference Feagin, Chambers and Schilling2013), and data collection was conducted by field-workers who were also members of the community in order to mitigate effects of the Observer’s Paradox (Labov Reference Labov1972).

Figure 1. Locations around Scotland where data have been collected in the Scots Syntax Atlas. Each dot represents one community.

Data were collected from each pair of participants in two ways. First, data were collected from sociolinguistic interviews (Labov Reference Labov, Baugh and Sherzer1984: 32), totalling ca. 275 hours of conversation. The interview recordings are text-to-sound transcribed using the open source software TranscriberAG (https://transag.sourceforge.net), creating a rich corpus of searchable spoken data from Scots varieties. Second, participants completed an acceptability judgment task on 200+ examples of morphosyntactic phenomena, administered following the ‘interview method’ for syntactic data collection (Barbiers & Bennis Reference Barbiers and Bennis2007). Participants judged each example on a Likert scale from 1 to 5 (e.g. Schütze Reference Schütze2016). Each point on the scale was labelled, with 5 described as ‘I would definitely say that’. At the other end of the scale, 1 was described as ‘I would never say that’. Each participant was asked to provide around 200 judgments, with a total of over 110,000 judgments overall. These data were fed into the online atlas and allowed us to visualise patterns of acceptability across geographic space (the different locations) and time (the different age groups). The full dataset and more details about the project are available through the online atlas at https://scotssyntaxatlas.ac.uk.

In what follows, we will focus on the judgment data for the following sentences in the questionnaire: one testing amn’t in an inversion environment (specifically a tag questionFootnote 1), one testing amn’t in a declarative, and one testing amnae in a declarative.Footnote 2

We use these data to investigate three empirical issues. In Section 2.2, we consider whether the inversion asymmetry with respect to amn’t holds more broadly across our larger dataset. In Section 2.3, we examine the relationship between amn’t and amnae in declaratives, assessing the predictions of the proposal in Bresnan (Reference Bresnan, Baltin and Collins2001) regarding the inversion asymmetry. In Section 2.4, we take a closer look at declarative amn’t and identify some major regional differences in its acceptance.

Before moving onto the results, we should establish some methodological caveats regarding the data that we have gathered using these examples. One potential issue with the examples in (7)–(8) is that they both involve the use of negative contraction (I amn’t/amnae) rather than auxiliary contraction (I’m not/no) in a context which strongly favours the use of the auxiliary contraction – namely, present tense be and a pronominal subject. The usage preference for auxiliary contraction in these contexts is well-documented for a number of British varieties, including varieties of Scots (Tagliamonte & Smith Reference Tagliamonte and Smith2002), and this effect is visible in the SCOSYA corpus, which contains not a single example of amn’t and only one example of amnae, given in (9); this is out of 1,800 potential contexts where negation and am occurred together, in the whole 3,000,000-word corpus.

We should stress that low frequency in use does not necessarily entail low acceptance or ungrammaticality; for example, you aren’t is also vanishingly rare in our spoken corpus (there are only a handful of examples in the SCOSYA corpus), due to a preference for you’re not, yet it seems unlikely to us that it is ungrammatical in any varieties in the United Kingdom. Nevertheless, it is possible that when naive informants are asked to rate I amn’t/amnae (or indeed, you aren’t) for acceptability, they may occasionally give it a low rating because of this preference, despite the best efforts of field-workers to explain the task – even if the relevant form is grammatical for the speaker and may show up (albeit rarely) in their usage. This might, in turn, lead to depression of the rate of acceptance of examples such as (7)–(8) – in particular, relative to examples like (6). We will return to this caveat at a few points below. Also, we note that there is a general role for age in the acceptability of amn’t/amnae in the SCOSYA data, with younger speakers accepting both inverted and declarative amn’t and declarative amnae at a higher rate than older speakers. A small benchmarking study investigating differences in acceptability between the age groups for seven known Scots-wide features showed an average acceptance rate of 72.2% for the older speakers and 90.2% for the younger speakers. It may be that this difference between the age groups is due to younger speakers having greater perceptual linguistic awareness than older speakers, evidenced in their accuracy in metalinguistic tasks (Drager Reference Drager2011, Carrera-Sabaté Reference Carrera-Sabaté2014, Lawrence Reference Lawrence2017, though see Jamieson Reference Jamieson2020 for the opposite). It may also be the case that there is change in progress with amn’t, moving towards greater acceptability. As instances of amn’t and amnae are so rare in the SCOSYA corpus, we cannot use any additional existing data to test this hypothesis further. We therefore acknowledge that change may be a possibility, but we set it aside for future sociolinguistic investigation.

We will now present the geographical distribution of the amn’t and amnae data from SCOSYA and highlight where it supports or provides counterarguments to Bresnan and Yang’s proposals. Throughout, we report the acceptance rate: how many participants rated the example 4 or 5 in the judgment task. We use this as an operationalisation of acceptability, following, for example, Zanuttini et al. (Reference Zanuttini, Wood, Zentz and Horn2018), who use the same cut-off for similar types of acceptability judgment results in the Yale Grammatical Diversity Project, and Thoms et al. (Reference Thoms, Adger, Heycock and Smith2019), Jamieson et al. (Reference Jamieson, Adger, Heycock, Smith and Thomsto appear), who used these cutoffs when investigating other aspects of the SCOSYA data. We also report the mode throughout as a quick and clear way to establish how the majority of participants responded to a particular example or in a particular area.

2.2. Geographical distribution of amn’t and the inversion asymmetry

To begin with, we show that there is indeed a strong asymmetry between declaratives and inversions with respect to the acceptability of amn’t across Scots dialects. This broadly confirms one of the key empirical claims in Bresnan (Reference Bresnan, Baltin and Collins2001). We can see this with maps representing the scores for the examples in 6 and 7. Figures 2 and 3 show acceptability maps, in which dark spots represent locations where the example was given a score of 4 or 5 by two or more speakers.

Figure 2. I’m coming with you, amn’t I?, accepted by $ \ge $ 2 speakers.

Figure 3. I amn’t ready yet, accepted by $ \ge $ 2 speakers.

We can see from simply looking at the maps that amn’t is accepted much more widely, and indeed much more uniformly, in inversions than in declaratives.Footnote 3 This can also be seen in the descriptive statistics: the inversion example in (6) had a mode of 5, with the individual-level acceptance rate at 60%. The numbers for declarative amn’t are much lower: Example (7) had a mode of 1 and an acceptance rate of 34%.

Clearly, then, the example testing amn’t in a declarative was less well accepted in the SCOSYA data than the example testing amn’t in inversions, potentially indicating a difference in terms of the grammatical status of amn’t in these two environments, in line with what was proposed by Bresnan Reference Bresnan, Baltin and Collins2001. While it is possible that some portion of the difference in acceptability between the two examples could be attributable to the preference for auxiliary contraction over negative contraction in declarative contexts, it seems unlikely that this would account for the full extent of the difference in scores. An additional consideration, which we expand on more in Section 2.4, is that whereas the scores for (6) in the map in Figure 2 are high more or less uniformly across the country, the scores for (7) in Figure 3 vary much more by region. This would be unexpected if the difference between inversions and declarative was due solely to methodological issues.

2.3. Geographical correlation between amn’t and amnae

We have seen that Bresnan’s (Reference Bresnan, Baltin and Collins2001) proposed inversion asymmetry holds in the SCOSYA data. Now let us consider the second major claim of her argument: that the amn’t asymmetry is due to the fact that declarative amnae effectively blocks declarative amn’t. In her account, then, the two forms should be in complementary distribution, at least in regions where -nae forms are used productively.

To assess this claim, we provide map data for declarative amnae in Figure 4, which can be compared with declarative amn’t in Figure 3. In addition, to contextualise the results for amnae, we provide map data from another example of -nae negation: havenae, as tested in the sentence in (10).Footnote 4

Figure 4. I amnae ready, accepted by $ \ge $ 2 speakers.

Figure 5. I havenae been there before, accepted by $ \ge $ 2 speakers.

It is easy to see from Figure 5 that havenae is generally accepted across Scotland, with the exception of the Highlands and the Western Isles, which exhibit standard English forms (e.g. Shuken Reference Shuken and Trudgill1984).

Figure 6. Labelled dialect regions of Scotland, corresponding to the regions in Table 1.

We can see in Figure 4 that amnae is also, unsurprisingly, rejected in these areas. However, what is surprising (in light of Bresnan Reference Bresnan, Baltin and Collins2001’s claim) is that acceptance of amnae is generally low outside of the Highlands, too, especially when compared to other -nae forms, like havenae. This can also be seen in the descriptive statistics: the example in (10) with havenae has a mode of 5 and an acceptance rate of 65%, whereas (8) (I amnae ready!) has a mode of 1 and an acceptance rate of 32% – very similar to what we saw for declarative amn’t. In fact, the maps for amnae and declarative amn’t are quite similar once the Highlands and Western Isles are ignored, with patches of lower acceptance in the Northeast and various places in the central part of the country.

Looking at the data at the individual level,Footnote 5 it is remarkable that scores for amnae and declarative amn’t are, in fact, moderately positively correlated (R = 0.52)– more so than amnae with other -nae forms such as havenae (R = 0.34). This is the opposite of what is expected on Bresnan (Reference Bresnan, Baltin and Collins2001)’s account, and we believe it tells us that that account cannot be right. We suggest that any account of the amn’t gap will have to also explain the fact that it tends to pattern together with amnae across Scots varieties, while still allowing them to come apart in some situations.

2.4. Geographical distribution of acceptability of declarative amn’t

We have seen that the SCOSYA data do not support Bresnan’s (Reference Bresnan, Baltin and Collins2001) claim that declarative amn’t is blocked by declarative amnae; instead, the presence of the two features is moderately positively correlated. We also saw in Figure 3 that there is regional variation in the patterns of acceptability of declarative amn’t. We explore that further below, showing that although it is not predicted by Bresnan’s (Reference Bresnan, Baltin and Collins2001) account, Yang’s (Reference Yang2016, Reference Yang, Bowern, Horn and Zanuttini2017) approach opens up the possibility of a different explanation for the distribution of the forms. As noted in Section 2, the SCOSYA data come from over 140 research sites across Scotland. In the atlas, these are grouped into broader geographic regions based on areas demarcated in traditional dialectological work (e.g. Grant Reference Grant1931, Aitken Reference Aitken and Trudgill1984, Johnston Reference Johnston and Jones1997, Millar Reference Millar2007), resulting in 15 broad regions. Table 1 provides an overview of the descriptive statistics for declarative amn’t for 11 of these dialect regions in the SCOSYA dataset.Footnote 6 The regions are labelled in Figure 6, which can be cross-referenced with Table 1.

Table 1. Declarative amn’t across Scotland

The descriptive statistics clearly show regional variation in the scores for declarative amn’t. Scores are particularly high in Lothian, the Western Isles and Tayside & Angus and particularly low in Ayrshire, Glasgow, the Northeast and Stirling & Falkirk. For the remaining regions (Borders, Dumfries, Fife and the Highlands), the picture is more mixed: in most of these regions, the mode was 1, indicating high levels of rejection. However, the number of participants accepting it was between 30%–50%, suggesting a more complex picture.Footnote 7

There are two striking observations we can make from this data. The first is the high scores for declarative amn’t in the Western Isles. The second is the regional variation on the east coast of Scotland. Acceptance is high in Lothian in the south but lower to the immediate north in Fife. Then it rises again as we go yet farther north to Tayside and Angus before plunging in the Northeast.

We can summarise the generalisations about the amn’t gap and the inversion asymmetry that we have extracted from SCOSYA as follows:

In what follows, we account for these generalisations by leveraging a view of the syntax of negation, proposed in Thoms et al. (Reference Thoms, Adger, Caroline Heycock and Smith2023), which takes negation in inversion constructions to be distinct from negation in declaratives. We combine this with a slight extension to Yang’s Tolerance Principle to deal with cases of variation in exponence, and we show how the two together provide a way of understanding why amn’t distributes the way it does in Scots (and potentially in varieties of English more generally).

3. On The Morphosyntax of Scots Negation

Speakers of Scots use two main forms of contracted negation: -n’t and -nae. The use of -nae is illustrated in the following examples from the SCOSYA corpus.Footnote 8

Varieties in the Western Isles and Highlands use only standard contracted negation -n’t (Thoms et al. Reference Thoms, Adger, Caroline Heycock and Smith2023). The rest of Scotland is characterised by use of both -n’t and -nae across communities and within individual speakers, with this variability subject to a number of sociolinguistic factors (e.g. Smith Reference Smith2000a). This alternation between the forms can be seen in the following sentences from the SCOSYA corpus, where speakers switch from one form to the other within a single utterance.

As noted in Thoms et al. (Reference Thoms, Adger, Caroline Heycock and Smith2023), -n’t and -nae show almost identical syntactic distributions. The examples in (12) and (13) all demonstrate cases of -nae attaching to finite auxiliaries in T, and all are contexts where -n’t-based forms may occur as well. The examples in (14) (from Thoms et al. Reference Thoms, Adger, Caroline Heycock and Smith2023) show that there are many other contexts that block contracted negation: note that both -n’t and -nae are prohibited from occurring.

The judgments reported in (14) hold across Scots varieties (modulo the absence of -nae forms in some dialects, as already mentioned), and as far as we know, the -n’t judgments hold across all varieties of English.

However, there are differences, both between -n’t and -nae, and between variants of -nae across different varieties of Scots.Footnote 9 A major difference between -n’t and -nae, which we already discussed in the Introduction, and which is further demonstrated in (15) and (16), is the asymmetry with inversion: auxiliaries negated with -n’t but not -nae can invert with the subject in questions.

To account for this, Thoms et al. (Reference Thoms, Adger, Caroline Heycock and Smith2023) proposed an analysis of -n’t and -nae as two distinct realisations of a single element, which they call NegOp. In declaratives, this occurs in the specifier of a NegP projection directly below finite T. NegOp attaches leftwards onto the adjacent finite auxiliary in T.

(17) provides a tree diagram for a simple example with the perfect auxiliary, and the associated spell-out rule is given in (18).Footnote 10 Leftward attachment of NegOp onto the finite auxiliary would produce the context for a variable rule in (18), which realises NegOp.

This analysis captures the highly selective nature of -n’t/-nae by stating a realisation rule that is specific to contexts where the NegOp has attached to the finite auxiliary. By positing the disjunctive realisation rule in (18), Thoms et al. (Reference Thoms, Adger, Caroline Heycock and Smith2023) analysed the variation between -n’t and -nae as an instance of sociolinguistically conditioned allomorphy – of a kind that is familiar from a long tradition of work in variationist sociolinguistics (see Smith Reference Smith2000b on Scots negation, in particular).

Thoms et al. (Reference Thoms, Adger, Caroline Heycock and Smith2023) treated the ‘inverted’ negation as an instance of NegOp appearing in the specifier of a distinct projection immediately below the C projection in the clause. They called this projection HighNegP. NegOp attaches onto the preceding raised auxiliary in C, much as its lower instantiation does. (19) illustrates a case like (15b), haven’t you read it?: the auxiliary raises through T and other heads on the verbal spine to C (which bears an interrogative feature [int]), and then NegOp cliticises to C post-syntactically.

The differences in the form of negation in the different contexts – -n’t or -nae in declaratives, only -n’t in inversions – is then captured in terms of different spell-out rules that are sensitive to the features of their local contexts. The absence of -nae in most inversion contexts is captured by stating a spell-out rule for NegOp in the context of CINT, which only realises NegOp as -n’t. We extend our realisation rules then to the following:

We then have two realization rules for NegOp, each dependent on syntactic context.Footnote 11 The differences between -nae and -n’t, on this account, ultimately rest in the inventory of spell-out rules rather than in syntactic parameters or features.

A prediction of this way of analysing contracted negation is that we should expect to see cases where the morphological paradigm for negated auxiliaries may differ depending on the syntactic context in which the negative occurs, since the distinct spell-out rules need not have the same inventories of forms. And, indeed, this is what we see. One case, mentioned in the Introduction, is the use of aren’t to ‘plug’ the gap left by amn’t, but only in inversion contexts.

This approach seems preferable to Bresnan’s (Reference Bresnan, Baltin and Collins2001) idea that the emergence of aren’t in inversion contexts is the result of an optimality-driven retreat to the unmarked form. Bresnan’s (Reference Bresnan, Baltin and Collins2001) account predicts that speakers who accept amn’t in inversion contexts will not accept (21a), but this is not the case, as at least some Scots speakers who accept amn’t also accept and produce (21a) (see Embick & Marantz Reference Embick and Marantz2008 and Frampton Reference Frampton, Andronis, Ball, Elston and Neuvel2001 for further problems with Bresnan’s Reference Bresnan, Baltin and Collins2001 analysis).

In addition, Thoms et al. (Reference Thoms, Adger, Caroline Heycock and Smith2023) described a number of cases in varieties of Scots where the form of negation in certain inversion contexts is distinct from that of negation in T in declaratives. (22) and (23) illustrate two cases from Shetland Scots and Glasgow Scots, respectively (for more details, see Thoms et al. Reference Thoms, Adger, Caroline Heycock and Smith2023 and Jamieson Reference Jamieson2020).

Such facts are a challenge for the standard analysis where -n’t in inversions is always just a pied-piped form which attaches to the auxiliary in T prior to auxiliary raising; however, if the forms of negation are allomorphs conditioned by adjacent syntactic features, the patterns fall into place.

4. The Limits of Productivity: The Tolerance Principle

Although the analysis of Scots negation just outlined provides a foundation for understanding how -nae could influence amn’t and how an asymmetry between inversion and noninversion contexts could come about, we are still in need of some explanation for why we see the variation we see in the acceptability of amn’t. The second ingredient of our analysis of the amn’t gap is the theory of productivity in Yang (Reference Yang2016) and its extension to the amn’t gap in Yang (Reference Yang, Bowern, Horn and Zanuttini2017). In this section, we briefly outline the core components of Yang’s approach to paradigm gaps and its application to amn’t. Footnote 12

The Tolerance Principle of Yang (Reference Yang2016) is a theory of what patterns in observed linguistic data will result in learners developing productive – generalising – rules. The underlying intuition, which is, as Yang remarks, a quite widely held one, is that rules only become (or remain) productive if they are applicable to a sufficiently large proportion of the candidates they could apply to. That is, there is a limit to the number of exceptions a rule can tolerate.

The Tolerance Principle gives a specific quantification of the number of exceptions – the threshold $ {\theta}_N $ – that a rule potentially applying to N items can ‘tolerate’ while being retained as a productive rule (for a detailed explanation of how this formula is arrived at, see Yang Reference Yang2016, Chapter 3, especially pp. 60–66):

This principle thus predicts whether or not a potential rule will be productive, on the basis of two numbers: N (the number of items in the learner’s lexicon to which the rule is applicable) and e (the number of items in the learner’s lexicon that are exceptions). In Yang (Reference Yang, Bowern, Horn and Zanuttini2017), it is argued that this approach to productivity can give an account of the dialectal distribution of the amn’t gap, in the following way.

First, Yang proposes a general realisation rule for contracted negation in English that would plausibly be posited by learners, according to which a syllabic [n̩t] is attached to the finite auxiliary. (25) is an adjusted version of this rule (see footnote 10):

This rule will produce forms such as hasn’t, couldn’t – and also amn’t. If an acquirer has (25) as a productive rule, they will produce amn’t, even if they have never heard this form in their input: a productive rule will simply ‘fill in’ the gap. Although children who have learned such a rule might at some stage overuse it, producing forms such as willn’t, eventually they will learn the full range of irregular forms, and the irregulars will block these regularisations; that is, won’t will block willn’t, via the Elsewhere Principle.

Whether the rule in (25) actually does become productive will, by hypothesis, depend on the Tolerance calculation, and so the second step for Yang’s account is to determine N: the number of items that the rule is applicable to. In this case, that is the number of finite auxiliaries that have a negative form sufficiently robustly attested in child-directed speech to plausibly be acquired. Surveying CHILDES and BNC data, and taking the minimum frequency for counting a form to be once per 1,000,000 words, Yang concludes that 18 finite auxiliaries have negated forms that are sufficiently frequent in the input. Table 2 lists the positive auxiliaries and the negative forms of these auxiliaries that are robustly attested in Yang’s corpora, with his IPA transcriptions for the American English pronunciations of the negative forms. Given that N = 18, the formula in (24) tells us that the threshold for exceptions is six ( $ {\theta}_{18}=\frac{18}{\mathit{\ln}(18)}=6 $ ). That is, for this rule to be productive, there can be at most six exceptions (auxiliaries with irregular contracted negative forms).

Table 2. Auxiliaries and their negative forms in American English (adapted from Yang Reference Yang, Bowern, Horn and Zanuttini2017: 7)

Note: Irregular forms in bold.

The third step, then, is to count the number of auxiliaries that actually do have irregular negated forms – that is, to calculate e. Based on the data in Table 2, Yang arrives at a count of 10 such forms in American English (bolded in the table).Footnote 13 Some of the irregulars are straightforwardly characterised as such (see the discussion in Zwicky & Pullum Reference Zwicky and Pullum1983): won’t is suppletive, don’t involves an unpredictable vowel change, mustn’t involves an unpredictable [t] deletion, and can’t is monosyllabic (whereas applying (25) would return a bisyllabic form). By similar reasoning, we would also count weren’t and aren’t as irregulars because they are also transcribed as monosyllabic in Yang’s table, and nothing about the phonotactics of American English forces them to be monosyllabic.Footnote 14 The table also includes five entries for ain’t, since it represents a robustly attested negated form of all of the finite forms of present tense have and be in Yang’s corpora. Given that the number of exceptions to the putative rule in (25) is above six – the threshold derived from the Tolerance Principle – the prediction is that (25) will not be acquired as a rule.

Irregular forms – those that are not the output of a productive rule – have to be learned individually. Such forms can be thought of as generated by a morpholexical rule (Yang Reference Yang2002, Reference Yang, Bowern, Horn and Zanuttini2017) keyed to the item or set of items. For this to happen, sufficient positive evidence is required (that is, frequent enough presence of the output form in the input to the learner). In the case at hand, this is how the attested negated forms must be acquired: both obviously irregular forms like won’t and don’t, but also forms like didn’t and couldn’t. However, in the absence of a productive rule, if there is not enough positive evidence in the input for an irregular form (and all attested forms are irregular by definition), we have the conditions for a paradigm gap. This is precisely what Yang argues is the explanation for the absence of amn’t in American varieties: there is no productive rule to generate it, and it cannot be acquired from the input directly since it is not attested in the speech of American adults.Footnote 15

5. The amn’t Gap in Scots

The situation in Scots is different. As we saw in the atlas data in Section 2 above, there are many areas in Scotland where amn’t is accepted. Thus, we might expect that even if there were no productive rule for contracted negation in Scots, this form could be acquired simply by learning it as an irregular form directly from the input, on a par with don’t. It is possible that this is the case for some Scots speakers. However, recall from the discussion at the end of Section 2.1 that amn’t is very rare in speech, even in Scotland. There was not a single example of amn’t in the entire SCOSYA corpus of 3,000,000 words, and there was only one example of amnae, even though there were more than 1,800 contexts where one of them could have been used.Footnote 16 In consequence, we think that it is unlikely that direct acquisition of the amn’t form could account for the whole range of data, given how rare it is in speech, and it would certainly leave unexplained the dialectal variation that we have documented.

Yang’s account of the amn’t gap makes strong, fine-grained predictions about dialectal variation: dialects are predicted to differ as to whether a gap may occur depending on the number of irregular forms that they include. For this reason alone, if these predictions are borne out empirically, it represents an advance on all existing accounts of the amn’t gap, which typically have little to nothing to say about why dialects differ on this matter.Footnote 17

Our account is based on the three ingredients that we have established in the previous sections. The following is a summary:

  • Ingredient 1: negation in inversion contexts does not have exactly the same syntactic components as negation in declaratives, and therefore, the two heads may be realised via distinct spell-out rules.

  • Ingredient 2: the realisation rule for negation in declaratives in Scots is a variable rule that generates both -n’t and -nae forms.

  • Ingredient 3: for a given negative morpheme’s realisation rule, the Tolerance Principle calculation will determine whether it is productive and therefore automatically generates amn’t.

These ingredients conspire to derive the main results in the following manner. First, in Section 5.1, we show that, because negation in inversions can be the result of a distinct spell-out rule, the Tolerance calculation for negation in inversions can be different for the Tolerance calculation for negation in declaratives. In particular, this will be true when the inventories of negated auxiliaries in the two environments are distinct. Second, the use of a variable rule to realise negation in declaratives as either -n’t or -nae will ensure that the two negatives are tied together when it comes to the Tolerance calculation. In particular, an increase in irregularity in one of the disjuncts of the rule will impact upon the rule’s Tolerance calculation as a whole, with the consequence that irregularity in -nae will also impact upon the productivity of -n’t. In Section 5.2, we will spell this out in more detail and show that it predicts both the correlation between amn’t and amnae and the lower acceptability of declarative amn’t in certain areas of Scotland.

5.1. Accounting for amn’t in inversion contexts

In Section 3, we analysed negation in inversion versus declarative contexts as realisations of distinct morphosyntactic elements. That is, negation in declaratives is the realisation of a NegOP in Spec,NegP, which is just below T, and which cliticises to the finite auxiliary in T. Negation in inversion contexts, however, is the realisation of a NegOP in Spec,HighNegP, just below C in the left periphery. The realisation rules we posited above are repeated in (26):

Given that these are distinct realisation rules, it should be possible for each rule to be assessed separately with respect to Tolerance calculations. This provides the route to an account of the inversion asymmetry: if the inventories of negative auxiliary forms attested in declaratives and inversions are substantially different, then the outcome of the Tolerance calculations for (26a) and (26b) may differ, and with that come differences with respect to amn’t.

Let us consider in detail how the Tolerance calculation would work out for (26b), the spell-out rule for -n’t in inversion environments. Recall that the N for a given rule is the number of finite auxiliaries with reliably attested forms that correspond to an output of (26b), which would mean negated auxiliaries in the pre-subject position. Yang proposed the N for his general -n’t attachment rule to be 18, since there were 18 finite auxiliaries that had reliably attested forms in his COCA survey. We will assume that a similar N would apply for the rule in (26b).Footnote 18 This gives a threshold of six, as before.

What about the list of exceptions? In Scots, there are no ain’t forms, and the reduced form of don’t, [dɔ̃], does not occur in inversion contexts at all (Kaisse Reference Kaisse1985). Unlike in American English, aren’t and weren’t are not stored as exceptions since they are realised as bisyllabic forms in Scots, as predicted by the rule. Ultimately, then, the list of exceptions only includes can’t, won’t and don’t,Footnote 19 and, for some speakers, the use of aren’t for am in aren’t I? (See Section 3 above). This would amount to a minimum of four (maximally five) exceptions, below the threshold of six. In consequence, the theory predicts that (26b) will be productive, thus generating amn’t in inversions. This is summarised below:

The calculation above will work out similarly for most varieties of Scots since the inventories of negated auxiliaries in inversion contexts are largely uniform.Footnote 20 The account, therefore, correctly predicts the fairly widespread acceptance of amn’t in inversions in Scotland.

5.2. Amn’t in declaratives: the impact of the variable rule analysis

What of amn’t in declaratives? For this, we must consider the variable realisation rule in (26a). At first blush, one might expect that this rule is doomed to fail to become productive because any rule that realises negation as -n’t would have the -nae forms as exceptions to contend with, and vice versa. However, it is essential to note that we are proposing that the different negative forms are generated by two distinct disjuncts of a single spell-out rule – a Labovian variable rule.

How can Yang’s Tolerance calculations apply to such Labovian rules? There is no reason to expect a difference in how we should calculate N (the number of items to which the rule is applicable). The question is how we should calculate e (the number of exceptions). We propose that all that has to be done to make sure that the Tolerance calculation generalises to this case is to take seriously the idea that a variable rule is just that – a single rule. Hence, any realisation that cannot be generated by the rule counts as an exception.

That is, if the rule is not a variable rule, exceptions will be counted just as before. If there are multiple disjunctive parts (i.e. if the rule is variable), the exception list for the rule is the union of the exceptions to all the disjuncts. Thus, following the principle proposed in (28), don’t and can’t would constitute exceptions to (26a), and so would daa and caa. By contrast, cannae, havenae and other regular forms would not constitute an exception to this particular rule since they are generated by one of the disjuncts.

It follows that in Scots varieties where -nae ‘contributes’ more irregular forms, the entire rule in (26a) would become less likely to be productive because the irregular -nae forms would increase the number of exceptions. Crucially for the case at hand, this variable rule is the one that, if productive, generates amn’t. That is, in a dialect where there are many irregular -nae forms, learners are less likely to retain a productive rule like (26a), and so they would be less likely to produce and accept amn’t.

Let us demonstrate by considering two varieties: Lothian Scots and Northeastern Scots. First, consider the Lothian Scots forms in Tables 3 and 4, where again the irregular forms are in boldface. Following the principle in (28), the range of exceptions to (26a) in this variety is the union of the the irregular forms listed in these two tables. As shown in Table 3, the irregular -n’t forms are can’t, don’t, mustn’t, won’t and the reduced don’t form [dɔ̃]; recall that aren’t and weren’t are regular as pronounced in Scots, and ain’t is absent altogether. In Table 4, we can see that there is only one irregular -nae form in Lothian Scots – dae for don’t (and this only for a subset of speakersFootnote 21). With this mix of forms, the rule in (26a) is below or at the Tolerance threshold, and so learners in that area ought to be likely to acquire (26a) as a productive rule.

Table 3. Auxiliaries and their negated -n’t forms in Lothian Scots

Note: Irregular forms in bold.

Table 4. Auxiliaries and their -nae-negated forms in Lothian Scots

Note: Irregular forms in bold.

As a result, the analysis predicts that amn’t would commonly be accepted by speakers of this variety. This prediction is borne in our data: amn’t was rated particularly highly in the Lothian region.

The calculation is quite different for Northeastern Scots, not because there are any differences in its -n’t inventory compared to what we have just seen for Lothian Scots, but because there are more irregular -nae forms – namely, caa ‘can’t’, winna ‘won’t’. This variety also has zero auxiliary forms for have and do when they are followed by negation (see Thoms et al. Reference Thoms, Adger, Caroline Heycock and Smith2023), in addition to daa (the local variant of dae) ‘don’t’. This inventory puts the exception list for this variety well above the threshold, and so (26a) is predicted to typically fail to become productive here.

Our analyses, therefore, predict that amn’t should be widely rejected in the Northeastern Scots varieties – again, the right result.

Let us now consider how this account extends to other varieties of Scots. Recall that one of the major results that we sought to account for was the variation up the east coast, whereby declarative amn’t is accepted very widely in Lothian, Tayside and Angus, very little in the Northeast, and to some degree in Fife. We have already shown that the account explains the substantial difference in scores between the Northeast and Lothian. The analysis extends readily to Tayside and Angus, which have the same inventory of negated auxiliary forms as Lothian (modulo some predictable vowel quality differences). Irregulars such as the winna(e) ‘won’t’ and caa ’can’t’ that are present in the Northeast seem not to be a feature of these varieties, and the zero auxiliary forms are not used there at all. The Tolerance calculation is thus the same as for Lothian, and amn’t is predicted to be productive in declaratives.

As for Fife, which occupies the peninsula between Lothian and Tayside & Angus, there are more irregular negative forms in the varieties spoken there, as caa and winnae are attested conservative features of the area, and dae is also widely used by young and old speakers. As a result, the number of irregulars in Fife is generally higher than in Lothian, Tayside and Angus, and almost as high among older or conservative varieties as in the Northeastern varieties. The picture with amn’t in Fife, however, is quite mixed; in particular, there is an especially strong difference between the generations, as the acceptance rate among the old participants was particularly low, just 4.5% (mode and median 1), whereas the acceptance rate among younger participants was 50%. This can be compared with the situation in the other areas with generally low scores (Northeast, Glasgow and Ayrshire), where the rates of acceptance were much closer between the age groups (10% and 24%, 12% and 25%, and 19% and 19%, respectively). We suggest, then, that there is a true generational difference in the use of amn’t in Fife, and we speculate that this could be related to change in the use of the irregular forms in this region. Although we cannot use corpus data to probe this analysis of the Fife data further, additional judgment data gathering in future work may be able to test it more rigorously. As it stands, we take this analysis to give us a plausible account of the Fife data, and thus a fairly complete understanding of the variation with amn’t on the east coast.

Finally, let us comment on how the analysis handles the data from the rest of the country. Putting the varieties without -nae to one side, the account predicts two broad kinds of varieties: those with a larger number of exceptions to (26a), which should pattern with Northeastern Scots in disfavouring amn’t, and those with fewer exceptions, which should pattern with Lothian Scots. Concerning the latter group, the analysis makes broadly the right predictions for varieties in Dumfries and the Borders, both of which have higher rates of acceptance of amn’t (see Table 1 above). These varieties typically have the same inventory of irregulars as Lothian Scots: although some speakers in these regions accept daa/dae (examples were attested in all areas), caa is largely unattested (except for in some varieties in the Borders), winna(e) is unattested, and the zero auxiliaries are completely unattested.

As for the remaining regions, the proposal’s predictions are unclear in the cases of Stirling and Falkirk, and the Highlands (which encompasses Inverness and the area around it). In the case of Stirling and Falkirk, this is a somewhat unusual region: there are only seven locations in this grouping, and it is in a transitional area in central Scotland between several other, better-defined dialect regions. We generally have lower information about the dialects of this region compared to others (for instance, concerning the use of irregular auxiliariesFootnote 22). We therefore tentatively put this region to one side, pending further empirical data collection.

Similar remarks apply to the Highlands region, which contains just seven locations (23 ratings in total for (7), I amn’t ready yet!). Speakers in that region also gave amn’t in inversions relatively low ratings. This suggests there is more to understand about the status of the data from there, and again, we put this region aside.

What about Glasgow and Ayrshire? The proposal seems to make the wrong prediction for Glasgow and Ayrshire, where there is little to no irregularity in the -nae paradigm, but amn’t is rated quite low. However, the varieties of this region have at their disposal an additional form for the realisation of negated first-person singular present tense be – namely, amurnae:

Given the Elsewhere Principle, our account predicts that the availability of another, more specific form will result in blocking of the application of the general rule, and so amurnae will block application of (26a) to generate amn’t for the relevant speakers, just like won’t blocks generation of willn’t for all other English speakers. Thus, even if (26a) is productive for speakers of these varieties, they are not expected to produce and accept amn’t in declaratives if they have acquired amurnae. This accounts for the low acceptability of declarative amn’t in this region. It is possible that amurnae is used beyond these regions – for instance, in parts of Stirling and Falkirk – in which case, this might explain some of the uncertainties surrounding what is going on in this region, but information on this feature is very sparse. We also leave this for future investigation.

The results of our analysis are summarised in Table 5, which shows that the predictions of our account are largely confirmed.

Table 5. Our predictions regarding declarative amn’t across Scotland

A final comment to make on the data from declarative amn’t is the extent of interspeaker variation: in no single area was declarative amn’t uniformly rejected or uniformly accepted, and in most areas there was a mix of responses. Thus, there was a degree of what we might call overacceptance, with some speakers accepting declarative amn’t in some areas where our analysis predicts it should be absent (e.g. the Northeast). Similarly, there was a degree of what we might call underacceptance, where a number of speakers reject declarative amn’t in areas where we would expect it to be accepted more uniformly (e.g. the Western Isles).

There may well be methodological reasons for this. It is, of course, reasonable to assume that some proportion of overacceptance and underacceptance can be attributed to the noisy nature of large-scale acceptability judgment data gathering. However, previous work has shown (Jamieson et al. Reference Jamieson, Adger, Heycock, Smith and Thoms2023) that the judgment data from the SCOSYA project largely lines up with patterns of production in the SCOSYA corpus – in particular, in the case of features that are not strongly stigmatisedFootnote 23 and which are used commonly enough in the corpus for usage statistics to be observed.

We noted at the end of Section 2 that there might be some methodological issues with respect to gathering data on negative contraction examples specifically – speakers might rate negative contraction lower because of a preference for using auxiliary contraction I’m no/not – which would account for some amount of underacceptance of declarative amn’t. This could potentially be a factor in explaining the fact that declarative amn’t is rated lower than inversion amn’t in general, even in regions where the two are predicted by our analysis to be more or less the same. For instance, in the Western Isles, where there are no -nae forms in the mix, declarative amn’t is accepted 53% of the time, and inversion amn’t 72% of the time.

In addition to methodological issues, our analysis makes room for a certain degree of individual-level variation, in particular, with respect to overacceptance of amn’t in areas where the general -n’t-attachment rules fail to become productive. Recall from the discussion in Section 4 that forms that may be the output of a productive rule in one variety may be learned as irregular forms in another where there are more exceptions and hence no productive rule. Indeed, on our account – following Yang – this is the situation for North American speakers learning the form isn’t or hasn’t. Amn’t is likely to be extremely rare in the input to North American learners, so we would not expect it to be learned as an irregular in this way, but things could potentially be different in some Scots varieties. It is clear that amn’t is rare in production – recall there was not a single clear example in the 3,000,000-word SCOSYA corpus – and so usage of amn’t is unlikely to be driving the whole set of dialect differences we have seen above, but it is possible that there will be individuals who have learned amn’t on the basis of (scant) production data in neighbouring varieties, even in communities where the makeup of the negative auxiliary inventory is such that it would typically rule out a productive negative attachment rule.

Taken together, these factors give us a way to understand the variability in the amn’t data. However, it is highly unlikely that these factors combine to explain the extensive and systematic regional differences that we have laid out above.

6. Conclusion

In this article, we have provided new data from SCOSYA that repaints the empirical picture of the distribution of the amn’t gap, yielding a much richer landscape of microvariation, and one that challenges extant accounts. We have argued that these data can be accounted for on the basis of the analysis of Scots negation in Thoms et al. (Reference Thoms, Adger, Caroline Heycock and Smith2023), together with a new proposal for how the Tolerance Principle should be updated to apply also to Labovian variable rules. Thus, we hope to have both provided a new and much more adequate description of microvariation in Scots contracted negation and to have improved our theoretical understanding of the nature of productivity in linguistic rules.

Acknowledgments

We gratefully acknowledge the support of the Arts and Humanities Research Council for award No. AH/M005550/1. Material from this paper has been presented to audiences at Cambridge, Edinburgh, Konstanz, Yale, MIT, NYU and Stanford, and at Comparative Germanic Syntax Workshop (CGSW) 32 (Trondheim) and Generative Linguistics in the Old World (GLOW) 43 (Berlin/online). We thank those audiences for their feedback and input, as well as the anonymous reviewers for the Journal of Linguistics who gave us valuable feedback and advice. We also thank Brian Aitken, Derek Henderson, Laurel MacKenzie, Warren Maguire, Andrew Nevins, Craig Sailor, Devyani Sharma, Andrew Weir and Charles Yang.

Footnotes

1 We do not have data on whether there are any differences in judgments for different inversion environments. However, see Thoms et al. (Reference Thoms, Adger, Caroline Heycock and Smith2023) on differences between negative morphemes in different classes of inversion environments.

2 There were some differences in the orthographic representations used for the example sentences for different areas; for example, -nae is represented as -na in questionnaires used in Dundee and the Northeast, in line with previously established orthographic representations of how these are pronounced. We will flag these differences up where relevant, but as far as we know, they do not impact the analyses we develop.

3 This pattern of wide acceptance for tags across the whole of Scotland is mirrored in a much larger number of crowdsourced judgments collected in the Speak for Yersel project, which can be viewed at http://www.speakforyersel.ac.uk.

4 We present data for havenae here; the same pattern holds across the SCOSYA data for other -nae examples, such as isnae, wasnae and didnae.

5 In calculating these statistics, we excluded all locations from the Western Isles and the Highlands, as demarcated in Figure 6, since -nae is not used there in general (as noted above).

6 We have removed data from any dialect area where there are $ \le $ 20 observations to generalise over. This means we do not analyse or discuss data from Caithness, Kinross, Orkney or Shetland.

7 It is these regions in which a change in progress with the acceptability of amn’t seems more likely. However, as noted in Section 2.1, we do not have appropriate data to address the question of change in apparent time, and so we set this aside for future work.

8 The phonetic realisation of -nae differs across Scotland. In general, it is pronounced as [nə] in the Northeast, Tayside and the northern Isles, and it is often represented as -na orthographically. It is realised as [ne] elsewhere, including Glasgow and Edinburgh, and is usually written -nae. Despite these different phonetic realisations, the morphosyntax of these forms is the same across these varieties. We use the -nae orthographic form by default in the rest of the paper since it reflects more transparently the pronunciation of the most commonly used form.

9 There are few (if any) differences between varieties (in Scotland and elsewhere) with respect to the syntactic properties of -n’t, as far as we know, although there are differences in the inventories of -n’t forms, the variation with amn’t being one prominent case.

10 The rule in (18) is an adjusted version of the one in Thoms et al. (Reference Thoms, Adger, Caroline Heycock and Smith2023), which is given in (i).

The rule in (i) excludes the auxiliary from both the left and the right context, and so such a rule would have nothing to say about cases of stem allomorphy such as mustn’t, where the form of -n’t is the same as it usually is, but the stem of the auxiliary undergoes some change (the [t] is dropped; see Zwicky & Pullum Reference Zwicky and Pullum1983 and below). This distinction is important for the Tolerance calculation which is to follow, since cases of stem allomorphy must be counted as irregularities of the -n’t attachment rule, so we adopt the adjusted rule in (18) in what follows. Thanks to Craig Sailor (personal communication) for pointing out this issue for us.

11 Thoms et al. (Reference Thoms, Adger, Caroline Heycock and Smith2023) showed how the form of negation in negative imperatives is captured by a third realisation rule, while the form of negation in uncontracted contexts is the elsewhere case.

12 See Belth et al. (Reference Belth, Payne, Beser, Kodner and Yang2021), Liang et al. (Reference Liang, Marsala, Yang, Gong and Kpogo2022) and Kodner (Reference Kodner2023) for recent work that has put the Tolerance Principle to use in explaining acquisitional and diachronic linguistic data. For criticisms, see Goldberg (Reference Goldberg2019).

13 The number would be higher if relic forms such as shan’t were included (as they are in the discussion in Zwicky & Pullum Reference Zwicky and Pullum1983, who also make the point that the proportion of irregulars is quite high). But, as Yang notes, this form has fallen out of use and can scarcely be taken to be an influence on the acquisition of negation in any contemporary varieties. Yang’s count does not include the use of ain’t for didn’t, which is attested in contemporary African American language varieties. We suspect it is underrepresented in these corpora because it is a fairly recent innovation, as observed by Fisher (Reference Fisher2018). Adding this use of ain’t to the count does not change any of the predictions discussed here.

14 For some reason, Yang only counts weren’t as an irregular in his final calculation. We assume this is an error of presentation.

15 In fact, we are simplifying Yang’s proposal here. Having suggested the possible rule in (25), he then goes on to propose that learners retreat from this rule by entertaining a narrower version that applies only to obstruent-final auxiliaries (Yang Reference Yang, Bowern, Horn and Zanuttini2017: p. 222).

We adopt the simpler formulation here.

16 Recall that this usage fact is arguably part of a broader tendency in more northern varieties of English, and particularly Scots (noted in the discussion in Section 2.1 above) for preference for the use of auxiliary contraction over negative contraction with present tense forms of be and a pronominal subject (she’s not, as opposed to she isn’t), as discussed by Tagliamonte & Smith (Reference Tagliamonte and Smith2002).

17 For example, as mentioned briefly in the Introduction, Bresnan (Reference Bresnan, Baltin and Collins2001) simply stipulates that United States varieties and Scots varieties differ with respect to whether they have stored an amn’t form in their lexicons, in effect, an instance of lexical variation; the same is true for Hudson (Reference Hudson2000).

18 We acknowledge that the N might be lower than this for (20b), as it may be that certain negated auxiliaries (e.g. needn’t, possibly also mustn’t) are so infrequent in inversion contexts that they might not occur enough to impact upon the acquisition process. An N as low as 15 would still get the same threshold and thus the same results, so we do not dwell on the matter here.

19 We might include mustn’t, but mustn’t is very high-register for most speakers of Scots, and it is rarely (if ever) used in questions.

20 We did note in Section 2.4 that there are further forms of the negation in imperatives and in tags (and for non-information-seeking questions in general, see Thoms et al. Reference Thoms, Adger, Caroline Heycock and Smith2023). However, each of these requires a separate realisation rule and hence a separate Tolerance Principle calculation.

21 Here and throughout, we base our claims about the distribution of irregular negative auxiliaries – in particular, the Scots-specific forms – on a combination of judgment data and corpus data. The judgment data are from informal follow-up consultations with speakers from the regions in question, as the SCOSYA questionnaire did not test for these forms systematically. The corpus data are from the SCOSYA corpus, broken up into subcorpora for the different regions. In the case of dae for don’t, it is clear from the production data that this is a productive feature of some Lothian varieties, but by no means all of them.

22 We should note that for every region except Stirling and Falkirk and the Borders, we managed to consult with researchers or field-workers who grew up in that region (or had extensive research knowledge of it) and who had extensive training in linguistics.

23 This seems to be the case with amn’t. The lack of stigma with amn’t in Scotland is perhaps in part due to the fact that it involves the use of the more standard form of negation rather than the more non-standard -nae.

References

Aitken, Jack. 1984. Scottish accents and dialects. In Trudgill, Peter (ed.), Language in the British Isles, 94–114. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Anderwald, Lieselotte. 2002. Negation in non-standard British English: Gaps, regularizations and asymmetries. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Barbiers, Sjef & Bennis, Hans. 2007. The syntactic atlas of the Dutch dialects. A discussion of choices in the SAND project. Nordlyd. 34. 5372.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Belth, Caleb, Payne, Sarah, Beser, Deniz, Kodner, Jordan & Yang, Charles. 2021. The greedy and recursive search for morphological productivity. In Proceedings of CogSci 2021, https://arxiv.org/abs/2105.05790.Google Scholar
Bresnan, Joan. 2001. Explaining morphosyntactic competition. In Baltin, Mark & Collins, Chris (eds.), Handbook of contemporary syntactic theory, 144. Malden, MA: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Broadbent, Judith. 2009. The *amn’t gap: The view from West Yorkshire. Journal of Linguistics. 45(2). 251284.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brown, Keith. 1991. Double modals in Hawick Scots. In Trudgill, Peter & Chambers, J. K. (eds.), Dialects of English: Studies in grammatical variation, 74103. London: Longman.Google Scholar
Carrera-Sabaté, Josefina. 2014. Does meta-linguistic awareness play any role at the beginning of an ongoing sound change? The case of some vowel-ended verbs in Catalan. Sociolinguistic Studies. 8(2). 193221.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Drager, Katie. 2011. Speaker age and vowel perception. Language and Speech. 54(1). 99121.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Embick, David & Marantz, Alec. 2008. Architecture and blocking. Linguistic Inquiry. 39(1). 153.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Feagin, Crawford. 2013. Entering the community: Fieldwork. In Chambers, J. K. & Schilling, Natalie (eds.), The handbook of language variation and change, 1737 (2nd edn). London: Wiley Blackwell.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fisher, Sabriya. 2018. Variation and change in past tense negation in African American English, 113. Philadelphia, PA: University of Pennsylvania dissertation.Google Scholar
Frampton, John. 2001. The amn’t gap, ineffability, and anomalous aren’t: Against morphosyntactic competition. In Andronis, Mary, Ball, Christoper, Elston, Heidi & Neuvel, Sylvain (eds.), Proceedings of Chicago Linguistics Society 37, 113. Chicago, IL: Chicago Linguistics Society.Google Scholar
Francis, Nelson. 1985. Amn’t I, or the hole in the pattern. In Viereck, Wolfgang (ed.), Focus on: England and Wales varieties of English around the world, 141152. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.Google Scholar
Goldberg, Adele E. 2019. Explain me this: Creativity, competition, and the partial productivity of constructions. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Grant, William. 1931. The Scottish national dictionary. Edinburgh: Scottish National Dictionary Association.Google Scholar
Hudson, Richard. 2000. *I amn’t. Language. 76(2). 297323.Google Scholar
Jamieson, E. 2020. Viewing dialect change through acceptability judgments: A case study in Shetland dialect. Glossa: A journal of general linguistics. 5(1): 19. 1–28.Google Scholar
Jamieson, E., Adger, David, Heycock, Caroline, Smith, Jennifer & Thoms, Gary. To appear. When intuitions (don’t) fail: Combining syntax and sociolinguistics in the analysis of Scots. English Language and Linguistics.Google Scholar
Johnston, Paul. 1997. Regional variation. In Jones, Charles (ed.), The Edinburgh history of the Scots language, 433513. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kaisse, Ellen M. 1985. Connected speech: The interaction of syntax and phonology. London: Academic Press.Google Scholar
Kodner, Jordan. 2023. What learning Latin verbal morphology tells us about morphological theory. Natural Language and Linguistic Theory. 41. 733792.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Labov, William. 1972. Negative attraction and negative concord in English grammar. Language. 48(4). 773818.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Labov, William. 1984. Field methods of the project on linguistic change and variation. In Baugh, John & Sherzer, Joel (eds.), Language in use: Readings in sociolinguistics, 2866. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall.Google Scholar
Langendoen, D. Terence. 1970. Essentials of English grammar. New York: Rinehart and Winston.Google Scholar
Lawrence, Daniel. 2017. The social perception of a sound change. Penn Working Papers in Linguistics. 23(1). 111120.Google Scholar
Liang, Kevin, Marsala, Diana & Yang, Charles. 2022. Distributional learning of syntactic categories. In Gong, Ying & Kpogo, Felix (eds.), Proceedings of the 46th annual Boston University Conference on Language Development, 442455. Somerville, MA: Cascadilla Press.Google Scholar
Millar, Robert McColl. 2007. Northern and Insular Scots. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schütze, Carson T. 2016. The empirical base of linguistics: Grammaticality judgments and linguistic methodology. Berlin: Language Sciences Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shuken, Cynthia. 1984. Highland and Island English. In Trudgill, Peter (ed.), Language in the British Isles, 152166. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Smith, Jennifer. 2000a. Synchrony and diachrony in the evolution of English: Evidence from Scotland. York: University of York dissertation.Google Scholar
Smith, Jennifer. 2000b. ‘you 0 na hear o’ that kind o’ things’: Negative do in Buckie Scots. English World-Wide. 21(2). 231259.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smith, Jennifer, Adger, David, Aitken, Brian, Caroline Heycock, E. Jamieson & Thoms, Gary. 2019. The Scots syntax atlas. University of Glasgow. https://scotssyntaxatlas.ac.uk.Google Scholar
Tagliamonte, Sali & Smith, Jennifer. 2002. ‘Either it isn’t or it’s not’: neg/aux contraction in British dialects. English World-Wide. 23(2). 251281.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thoms, Gary, Adger, David, Heycock, Caroline & Smith, Jennifer. 2019. Syntactic variation and auxiliary contraction: The surprising case of Scots. Language. 95(3). 421455.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thoms, Gary, Adger, David, Caroline Heycock, E. Jamieson & Smith, Jennifer. 2023. English contracted negation revisited: Evidence from varieties of Scots. Language. 99(4). 726759.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Yang, Charles D. 2002. Knowledge and learning in natural language. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Yang, Charles. 2016. The price of productivity. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Yang, Charles. 2017. How to wake up irregular (and speechless). In Bowern, Claire, Horn, Laurence & Zanuttini, Rafaella (eds.), On looking into words (and beyond), 211233. Berlin: Language Sciences Press.Google Scholar
Zanuttini, Rafaella, Wood, Jim, Zentz, Jason & Horn, Laurence. 2018. The Yale grammatical diversity project: Morphosyntactic variation in North American English. Linguistic Vanguard. 4(1). 115.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zwicky, Arnold & Pullum, Geoffrey K.. 1983. Cliticization vs inflection: English n’t. Language. 59(3). 502513.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Figure 0

Figure 1. Locations around Scotland where data have been collected in the Scots Syntax Atlas. Each dot represents one community.

Figure 1

Figure 2. I’m coming with you, amn’t I?, accepted by $ \ge $2 speakers.

Figure 2

Figure 3. I amn’t ready yet, accepted by $ \ge $2 speakers.

Figure 3

Figure 4. I amnae ready, accepted by $ \ge $2 speakers.

Figure 4

Figure 5. I havenae been there before, accepted by $ \ge $2 speakers.

Figure 5

Figure 6. Labelled dialect regions of Scotland, corresponding to the regions in Table 1.

Figure 6

Table 1. Declarative amn’t across Scotland

Figure 7

Table 2. Auxiliaries and their negative forms in American English (adapted from Yang 2017: 7)

Figure 8

Table 3. Auxiliaries and their negated -n’t forms in Lothian Scots

Figure 9

Table 4. Auxiliaries and their -nae-negated forms in Lothian Scots

Figure 10

Table 5. Our predictions regarding declarative amn’t across Scotland