Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-lj6df Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-08T08:41:03.525Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Selection principles and proofs from the Book

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  23 November 2023

Boaz Tsaban*
Affiliation:
Department of Mathematics, Bar-Ilan University, Ramat Gan, Israel
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

I provide simplified proofs for each of the following fundamental theorems regarding selection principles:

  1. (1) The Quasinormal Convergence Theorem, due to the author and Zdomskyy, asserting that a certain, important property of the space of continuous functions on a space is actually preserved by Borel images of that space.

  2. (2) The Scheepers Diagram Last Theorem, due to Peng, completing all provable implications in the diagram.

  3. (3) The Menger Game Theorem, due to Telgársky, determining when Bob has a winning strategy in the game version of Menger’s covering property.

  4. (4) A lower bound on the additivity of Rothberger’s covering property, due to Carlson.

The simplified proofs lead to several new results.

MSC classification

Type
Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BYCreative Common License - SA
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons-Attribution-ShareAlike licence (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/4.0/), which permits re-use, distribution, reproduction, transformation, and adaptation in any medium and for any purpose, provided the original work is properly cited and any transformation/adaptation is distributed under the same Creative Commons licence.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of The Canadian Mathematical Society

1 Introduction

The study of selection principles unifies notions and studies originating from dimension theory (Menger and Hurewicz), measure theory (Borel), convergence properties (Császár–Laczkovicz), and function spaces (Gerlits–Nagy and Arhangel’skiıĭ), notions analyzed and developed in numerous studies of later mathematicians, especially since the 1996 paper of Just, Miller, Scheepers, and Szeptycki [Reference Just, Miller, Scheepers and Szeptycki8]. The unified notions include, among others, many classic types of special sets of real numbers, local properties in function spaces, and more recent types of convergence properties.

Selective topological covering properties form the kernel of selection principles. These covering properties are related via the Scheepers Diagram (Figure 1). This is a diagram of covering properties and implications among them. The properties in this diagram are obtained as follows:

Figure 1 The Scheepers Diagram.

For families $\mathrm {A}$ and $\mathrm {B}$ of sets, let $\mathsf {S}_1(\mathrm {A},\mathrm {B})$ be the statement: For each sequence of elements of the family $\mathrm {A}$ , we can pick one element from each sequence member, and obtain an element of the family $\mathrm {B}$ . When $\mathrm {A}=\mathrm {B}=\mathrm {O}(X)$ , the family of open covers of a topological space X, we obtain Rothberger’s property (1941), the topological version of Borel’s strong measure zero. We say that a space X satisfies $\mathsf {S}_1(\mathrm {O},\mathrm {O})$ if the assertion $\mathsf {S}_1(\mathrm {O}(X),\mathrm {O}(X))$ holds, and similarly for the other selective properties.

The hypothesis $\mathsf {S}_{\mathrm {fin}}(\mathrm {A},\mathrm {B})$ is obtained by replacing one by finitely many in the above definition. The property $\mathsf {S}_{\mathrm {fin}}(\mathrm {O},\mathrm {O})$ is, by an observation of Hurewicz, equivalent to Menger’s basis property, a dimension-type property. The property $\mathsf {U}_{\mathrm {fin}}(\mathrm {A},\mathrm {B})$ is obtained by further allowing us to take the unions of the selected finite subsets – this matters for some types of covers. For technical reasons, this property does not consider all covers of type $\mathrm {A}$ , but only those that have no finite subcover.

A cover of a space is an $\omega $ -cover if no member of the cover covers the entire space, but every finite subset of the space is covered by some member of the cover. For a space X, $\Omega (X)$ is the family of open $\omega $ -covers of the space. A point-cofinite cover is an infinite cover where every point of the space belongs to all but finitely many members of the cover. $\Gamma (X)$ is the family of open point-cofinite covers of the space X.

Applying the mentioned selection principles to the cover types $\mathrm {O}$ , $\Omega $ , and $\Gamma $ , we obtain additional important properties, such as Hurewicz’s property $\mathsf {U}_{\mathrm {fin}}(\mathrm {O},\Gamma )$ [Reference Hurewicz7]. We also obtain the Gerlits–Nagy $\gamma $ -property $\mathsf {S}_1(\Omega ,\Gamma )$ [Reference Gerlits and Nagy6], characterizing the Fréchet–Urysohn property of the function space $\operatorname {C}_{\mathrm {p}}(X)$ of continuous real-valued functions, with the topology of pointwise convergence: A topological space is Fréchet–Urysohn if every point in the closure of a set is actually a limit of a sequence in the set. This duality between the spaces X and $\operatorname {C}_{\mathrm {p}}(X)$ also translates various tightness and convergence properties of the space $\operatorname {C}_{\mathrm {p}}(X)$ – discovered earlier by Arhangel’skiıĭ, Bukovský, Sakai, and others – to the selective covering properties $\mathsf {S}_{\mathrm {fin}}(\Omega ,\Omega )$ , $\mathsf {S}_1(\Gamma ,\Gamma )$ , and $\mathsf {S}_1(\Omega ,\Omega )$ . In Section 2, we provide a surprisingly simple proof of one of the most important results of this type. While the result itself does not involve selective covering properties explicitly, its proof does that extensively.

A topological space is Lindelöf if every open cover has a countable subcover. For example, all sets of real numbers are Lindelöf. Since all selection principles concern countable sequences, the theory mainly deals with Lindelöf spaces. For Lindelöf spaces, the Scheepers Diagram is the result of a classification of all properties thus introduced; each property is equivalent to one in the diagram [Reference Just, Miller, Scheepers and Szeptycki8]. It was long open whether any additional implication could be established among the properties in the diagram. In Section 3, we deal with the recent, surprising solution of this problem.

Menger’s covering property $\mathsf {S}_{\mathrm {fin}}(\mathrm {O},\mathrm {O})$ is the oldest, most general, and most applied property in the Scheepers Diagram. Initially, Menger conjectured his property to coincide with $\sigma $ -compactness. While this turned out false [Reference Tsaban19], the game version of this property does provide a characterization of $\sigma $ -compactness. A very transparent proof of this deep result is presented in Section 4.

In Section 5, we consider a connection to combinatorial set theory. We show that a nontrivial lower bound on the additivity of Rothberger’s property follows easily from basic knowledge on selection principles.

The Book is a popular myth by Paul Erdős: A transfinite book containing the most simple proofs for all theorems. I would like to believe that the proofs presented here are similar to ones from the Book …or from some of its preliminary drafts, at any rate.

2 The Quasinormal Convergence Theorem

By set of real numbers, or real set in short, we mean a topological space where every open set is a countable union of clopen sets. Such are, for example, totally disconnected subsets of the real line and, in particular, subsets of the Cantor space ${\{0,1\}^{\mathbb {N}}}$ . In general, every perfectly normal space with any of the properties considered in this section is a real set.

Let X be a real set. A sequence of real-valued functions $f_1, f_2, \dotsc $ on X converges quasinormally to a real-valued function f if there are positive real numbers $\epsilon _1, \epsilon _2, \dotsc $ converging to $0$ such that for each point $x\in X$ , we have

$$\begin{align*}\left|f_n(x)-f(x)\right|\le \epsilon_n \end{align*}$$

for all but finitely many n. Quasinormal convergence generalizes uniform convergence.

A real set X is a QN space if every sequence of continuous real-valued functions on X that converges to $0$ pointwise, converges to $0$ quasinormally. Equivalently, convergence in the space $\operatorname {C}_{\mathrm {p}}(X)$ is quasinormal.

QN spaces were studied intensively, e.g., by Bukovský, Recław, Repický, Scheepers, Nowik, Sakai, and Haleš ([Reference Tsaban and Zdomskyy20] and the references therein). This and other properties of similar type are preserved by continuous images, and all experience prior to the paper of the author and Zdomskyy [Reference Tsaban and Zdomskyy20] suggested that they are not preserved by Borel images. Thus, the following theorem [Reference Tsaban and Zdomskyy20, Theorem 9] came as a surprise.

The Baire space ${\mathbb {N}^{\mathbb {N}}}$ is quasiordered by the relation $\le ^*$ of eventual dominance: $f\le ^* g$ if $f(n)\le g(n)$ for all but finitely many n. A subset Y of the Baire space ${\mathbb {N}^{\mathbb {N}}}$ is bounded if it is bounded with respect to eventual dominance.

Theorem 2.1 (Quasinormal Convergence Theorem)

The following assertions are equivalent for real sets X:

  1. (1) The set X is a QN space.

  2. (2) Every Borel image of the set X in the Baire space ${\mathbb {N}^{\mathbb {N}}}$ is bounded.

The second property in the theorem is well known and straightforward to apply: The most natural transformations needed in proofs regarding these notions are always easily seen to be Borel. Consequently, the theorem had a dramatic impact on the study of QN spaces: First, many of the previous sophisticated arguments could be replaced by straightforward ones. Second, many properties that were hitherto considered separately turned out provably equivalent. Consequently, this theorem settled all problems concerning these properties [Reference Tsaban and Zdomskyy20].

The original proof of the Quasinormal Convergence Theorem is long and involved, and some of its parts are difficult to follow. A more natural proof was later published by Bukovský and Šupina [Reference Bukovský and Šupina4, Section 4]. Inspired by a paper of Gerlits and Nagy [Reference Gerlits and Nagy6], I have discovered the following surprisingly simple proof. All needed proof ingredients were already available at the time the Quasinormal Convergence Theorem was established. The following lemma provides the key to the proof.

For a space X, let $\mathrm {PF}(X)$ be the collection of countably infinite point-finite families of open sets in X.

Lemma 2.2 Let X be a topological space. The following assertions are equivalent:

  1. (1) Every Borel image of the space X in the Baire space ${\mathbb {N}^{\mathbb {N}}}$ is bounded.

  2. (2) The space X satisfies $\mathsf {S}_1(\mathrm {PF},\mathrm {PF})$ .

Proof. Let $\mathrm {F}(X)$ (respectively, $\mathrm {B}(X)$ ) be the family of countable closed (respectively, Borel) covers of the set X, and let $\mathrm {F}_{\Gamma} (X)$ (respectively, $\mathrm {B}_{\Gamma} (X)$ ) be the family of infinite closed (respectively, Borel) point-cofinite covers of the set X. The properties (1), $\mathsf {U}_{\mathrm {fin}}(\mathrm {B},\mathrm {B}_{\Gamma} )$ , and $\mathsf {S}_1(\mathrm {B}_{\Gamma} ,\mathrm {B}_{\Gamma} )$ are equivalent [Reference Scheepers and Tsaban16, Theorem 1]. For a family $\mathcal {U}$ of open sets, we have $\mathcal {U}\in \mathrm {PF}(X)$ if and only if

$$\begin{align*}\{\,U^{\mathtt{c}} : U\in\mathcal{U}\,\}\in\mathrm{F}_{\Gamma}(X). \end{align*}$$

It follows that $\mathsf {S}_1(\mathrm {PF},\mathrm {PF})=\mathsf {S}_1(\mathrm {F}_{\Gamma} ,\mathrm {F}_{\Gamma} )$ .

$(1)\Rightarrow (2)$ : Clearly, $\mathsf {S}_1(\mathrm {B}_{\Gamma} ,\mathrm {B}_{\Gamma} )$ implies $\mathsf {S}_1(\mathrm {F}_{\Gamma} ,\mathrm {F}_{\Gamma} )$ .

$(2)\Rightarrow (1)$ : A theorem of Bukovský–Recław–Repický [Reference Bukovský, Recław and Repický3, Corollary 5.3] asserts that

$$\begin{align*}\mathsf{U}_{\mathrm{fin}}(\mathrm{F},\mathrm{F}_{\Gamma})=\mathsf{U}_{\mathrm{fin}}(\mathrm{B},\mathrm{B}_{\Gamma}). \end{align*}$$

The usual argument [Reference Scheepers15, Proposition 11] shows that $\mathsf {S}_1(\mathrm {F}_{\Gamma} ,\mathrm {F}_{\Gamma} )$ implies $\mathsf {U}_{\mathrm {fin}}(\mathrm {F},\mathrm {F}_{\Gamma} )$ : If $\{\, C_n : n\in \mathbb {N}\}\in \mathrm {F}(X)$ and there is no finite subcover, then $\{\, \bigcup _{k=1}^n C_k : n\in \mathbb {N}\}\in \mathrm {F}_{\Gamma} (X)$ .

A topological space Y has Arhangel’skiıĭ’s property $\alpha _1$ if for every sequence $s_1, s_2, \dotsc $ of sequences converging to the same point, there is a sequence s such that the sets $\operatorname {im}(s_n)\setminus \operatorname {im}(s)$ are finite for all natural numbers n. This property is defined by properties of sets (images of sequences) rather than sequences. Fix a bijection $\varphi \colon \mathbb {N}\to \mathbb {N}\times \mathbb {N}$ . For sequences $s_1, s_2, \dotsc $ , with $s_n=(s_{(n,1)},s_{(n,2)},\dotsc )$ for each n, define

$$\begin{align*}\bigsqcup_{n=1}^\infty s_n:=(s_{\varphi(1)},s_{\varphi(2)},\dotsc). \end{align*}$$

Since convergence of a sequence does not depend on the order of its elements, it does not matter, for our purposes, which bijection $\varphi $ is used. A sequence $\bigsqcup _{n=1}^\infty s_n$ converges to a point p if and only if each sequence $s_n$ converges to p, and for each neighborhood U of p, we have $\operatorname {im}(s_n)\subseteq U$ for all but finitely many n.

Lemma 2.3 Let Y be an $\alpha _1$ space. For every sequence $s_1, s_2, \dotsc $ of sequences in the space Y converging to the same point p, there are tails $t_n$ of $s_n$ , for $n\in \mathbb {N}$ , such that the sequence $\bigsqcup _{n=1}^\infty t_n$ converges to p.

Proof. There is a sequence s such that the sets $\operatorname {im}(s_n)\setminus \operatorname {im}(s)$ are finite for all natural numbers n. By moving to a subsequence, we may assume that $\operatorname {im}(s)\subseteq \bigcup _{n=1}^\infty \operatorname {im}(s_n)$ . Suppose that $s=(a_1, a_2, \dotsc )$ . For each natural number n, since the sequence $s_n$ converges to the point p, every element other than p may appear in the sequence $s_n$ only finitely often. Thus, there is a tail $t_n$ of the sequence $s_n$ such that

$$\begin{align*}\operatorname{im}(t_n)\subseteq\{\,a_k : k\geq n\,\}\cup\{p\}. \end{align*}$$

Let U be a neighborhood of p. There is a natural number N such that

$$\begin{align*}\operatorname{im}(t_n)\subseteq\{\,a_k : k\geq n\,\}\cup\{p\}\subseteq U \end{align*}$$

for all natural numbers $n\ge N$ . Thus, the direct sum $t:=\bigsqcup _{n=1}^\infty t_n$ converges to the point p.

Sakai [Reference Sakai12, Theorem 3.7] and Bukovský–Haleš [Reference Bukovský and Haleš2, Theorem 11] proved that a real set X is a QN space if, and only if, the space $\operatorname {C}_{\mathrm {p}}(X)$ is an $\alpha _1$ space. Thus, the Quasinormal Convergence Theorem can be stated, and proved, as follows.

Theorem 2.4 The following assertions are equivalent for real sets X:

  1. (1) The space $C_p(X)$ is an $\alpha _1$ space.

  2. (2) Every Borel image of the set X in the Baire space ${\mathbb {N}^{\mathbb {N}}}$ is bounded.

Proof. $(2)\Rightarrow (1)$ : This is the straightforward implication. For completeness, we reproduce its proof [Reference Tsaban and Zdomskyy20, Theorem 9].

Let $s_1, s_2, \dotsc $ be sequences in the space $\operatorname {C}_{\mathrm {p}}(X)$ that converge to a function $f\in \operatorname {C}_{\mathrm {p}}(X)$ . For each natural number n, suppose that

$$\begin{align*}s_n = (f^n_1,f^n_2,f^n_3,\dotsc). \end{align*}$$

Define a Borel function $\Psi \colon X\to {\mathbb {N}^{\mathbb {N}}}$ by

$$\begin{align*}\Psi(x)(n) := \min{\biggl\{\,k : (\forall m\ge k)\ |f^n_m(x)-f(x)|\le \frac{1}{n}\,\biggr\}}. \end{align*}$$

Let $g\in {\mathbb {N}^{\mathbb {N}}}$ be a $\le ^*$ -bound for the image $\Psi [X]$ . Then the sequence

$$\begin{align*}\bigsqcup_{n=1}^\infty(f^n_{g(n)},f^n_{g(n)+1},f^n_{g(n)+2},\dotsc) \end{align*}$$

converges to the function f.

$(1)\Rightarrow (2)$ : This is the main implication. By Lemma 2.2, it suffices to prove that the set X satisfies $\mathsf {S}_1(\mathrm {PF},\mathrm {PF})$ . Let $\mathcal {U}_1, \mathcal {U}_2, \dotsc \in \mathrm {PF}(X)$ . By thinning out the point-finite covers, we may assume that they are pairwise disjoint [Reference Scheepers15, Lemma 4]. For each set $U\in \bigcup _{n=1}^\infty \mathcal {U}_n$ , let $\mathcal {C}_U$ be a countable family of clopen sets with $\bigcup \mathcal {C}_U=U$ . For each natural number n, let

$$\begin{align*}\mathcal{V}_n := \bigcup_{U\in\mathcal{U}_n}\mathcal{C}_U. \end{align*}$$

Every set $C\in \mathcal {V}_n$ is contained in at most finitely many sets $U\in \mathcal {U}_n$ . Thus, the family $\mathcal {V}_n$ is infinite and point-finite. Let $s_n$ be a bijective enumeration of the family

$$\begin{align*}\{\,\chi_V : V\in\mathcal{V}_n\,\}. \end{align*}$$

The sequence $s_n$ is in $\operatorname {C}_{\mathrm {p}}(X)$ , and it converges to the constant function $0$ .

As the space $\operatorname {C}_{\mathrm {p}}(X)$ is $\alpha _1$ , there is for each n a tail $t_n$ of the sequence $s_n$ such that the sequence $s:=\bigsqcup _{n=1}^\infty t_n$ converges to $0$ . For each natural number n, pick a set $U_n\in \mathcal {U}_n$ with $\mathcal {C}_{U_n}\subseteq \operatorname {im}(t_n)$ . Then the family $\{\, U_n : n\in \mathbb {N}\}$ is infinite and point-finite.

For a set $X\subseteq {\{0,1\}^{\mathbb {N}}}$ , Gerlits and Nagy (and, independently, Nyikoš) define a space $\mathrm {T}(X)$ as follows: Let $\{0,1\}^*$ denote the set of finite sequences of elements of the set $\{0,1\}$ . Let $X\subseteq {\{0,1\}^{\mathbb {N}}}$ . For each point $x\in X$ , let $A_x\subseteq \{0,1\}^*$ be the set of initial segments of the point x. Let $X\cup \{0,1\}^*$ be the topological space where the points of the set $\{0,1\}^*$ are isolated, and for each point $x\in X$ , a neighborhood base of x is given by the sets $\{x\}\cup B$ , where B is a cofinite subset of the set $A_x$ . Let $\mathrm {T}(X)$ be the one-point compactification of this space, and let $\infty $ be the compactifying point.

Gerlits and Nagy prove that if a set $X\subseteq {\{0,1\}^{\mathbb {N}}}$ is a Siepiński set, then the space $\mathrm {T}(X)$ is $\alpha _1$ , and that if the space $\mathrm {T}(X)$ is $\alpha _1$ , then the set X is a $\sigma $ -set [Reference Gerlits and Nagy6, Theorem 4]. The following theorem unifies these results and improves upon them. Indeed, every Borel image of a Siepiński set in the Baire space is bounded, and every set with bounded Borel images in the Baire space is a $\sigma $ -set ([Reference Scheepers and Tsaban16] and the references therein).

Theorem 2.5 Let $X\subseteq {\{0,1\}^{\mathbb {N}}}$ . The following assertions are equivalent:

  1. (1) The space $\mathrm {T}(X)$ is an $\alpha _1$ space.

  2. (2) Every Borel image of the set X in the Baire space ${\mathbb {N}^{\mathbb {N}}}$ is bounded.

Proof. For a finite sequence $s\in \{0,1\}^*$ , let $[s]$ be the basic clopen subset of the Cantor space ${\{0,1\}^{\mathbb {N}}}$ consisting of all functions extending s. Every open set in the space ${\{0,1\}^{\mathbb {N}}}$ is a disjoint union of basic clopen sets. A sequence $a_1, a_2, \dotsc $ in the set $\{0,1\}^*$ converges to $\infty $ in the space $\mathrm {T}(X)$ if, and only if, the set $\{\, [a_n] : n\in \mathbb {N}\}$ is point-finite in the space X [Reference Gerlits and Nagy6]. The argument in the proof of Theorem 2.4 applies.

3 The Scheepers Diagram Last Theorem

The implications in the Scheepers Diagram 1 were all rather straightforward to establish, and almost all other potential implications were ruled out by counterexamples [Reference Just, Miller, Scheepers and Szeptycki8]. Only two problems remained open: Does $\mathsf {U}_{\mathrm {fin}}(\mathrm {O},\Omega )$ imply $\mathsf {S}_{\mathrm {fin}}({\Gamma} ,\Omega )$ ? And if not, does $\mathsf {U}_{\mathrm {fin}}(\mathrm {O},{\Gamma} )$ imply $\mathsf {S}_{\mathrm {fin}}({\Gamma} ,\Omega )$ ? [Reference Just, Miller, Scheepers and Szeptycki8, Problems 1 and 2]. For nearly three decades, it was expected that the remaining two potential implications were refutable. Only when Peng came up with an entirely new method for refuting implications among selective covering properties [Reference Peng11], these problems were resolved. But not in the expected way: Having proved that $\mathsf {U}_{\mathrm {fin}}(\mathrm {O},\Omega )$ does not imply $\mathsf {S}_{\mathrm {fin}}({\Gamma} ,\Omega )$ , Peng tried to refute the last remaining potential implication. And, he failed. His close examination of the failure suggested a path for proving the last potential implication [Reference Peng11, Theorem 23]. Peng’s results establish the final form of the Scheepers Diagram (Figure 2).

Figure 2 The Final Scheepers Diagram.

Peng’s proof of the last implication is somewhat involved. The proof given below identifies the heart of Peng’s argument, and replaces the other parts with simple, quotable observations about selective covering properties.

Let k be a natural number. A cover of a space is a k-cover if no member of the cover covers the entire space, but every k-element subset of the space is covered by some member of the cover. Thus, a cover is an $\omega $ -cover if and only if it is a k-cover for all natural numbers k. For a space X and a natural number k, let $\mathrm {O}_k(X)$ be the family of open k-covers of the space.

Lemma 3.1 Let $\Pi $ be a selection principle, and let $\mathrm {A}$ be a type of open covers. The following assertions are equivalent:

  1. (1) $\Pi (\mathrm {A},\Omega )$ .

  2. (2) For each natural number k, we have $\Pi (\mathrm {A},\mathrm {O}_k)$ .

Proof. $(1)\Rightarrow (2)$ : Obvious.

$(2)\Rightarrow (1)$ : Let $\mathcal {U}_1, \mathcal {U}_2, \dotsc $ be a sequence in $\mathrm {A}$ . Split the sequence into infinitely many disjoint sequences. For each natural number k, apply $\Pi (\mathrm {A},\mathrm {O}_k)$ to the kth sequence, to obtain a k-cover $\mathcal {V}_k$ . Then $\bigcup _{k=1}^\infty \mathcal {V}_k$ is an $\omega $ -cover, in accordance with the required property $\Pi (\mathrm {A},\Omega )$ .

Theorem 3.2 (Peng [Reference Peng11, Theorem 23])

The Hurewicz property $\mathsf {U}_{\mathrm {fin}}(\mathrm {O},{\Gamma} )$ implies $\mathsf {S}_{\mathrm {fin}}({\Gamma} ,\Omega )$ .

Proof. Let X be a Hurewicz space. By Lemma 3.1, it suffices to prove that $\mathsf {S}_{\mathrm {fin}}({\Gamma} ,\mathrm {O}_k)$ holds for all natural numbers k. Fix a natural number k.

Let $\mathcal {U}_1, \mathcal {U}_2, \dotsc $ be a sequence in ${\Gamma} (X)$ . By moving to countably infinite subcovers, we may enumerate

$$\begin{align*}\mathcal{U}_n = \{\,U^n_m : m\in\mathbb{N}\,\} \end{align*}$$

for each n. For each n and m, we may replace the set $U^n_m$ with the smaller set

$$\begin{align*}U^1_m\cap U^2_m\cap\dotsb\cap U^n_m, \end{align*}$$

so that we may assume that

$$\begin{align*}U^1_m\supseteq U^2_m\supseteq U^3_m\supseteq\dotsb \end{align*}$$

for all natural numbers m. The refined covers $\mathcal {U}_n$ remain in ${\Gamma} (X)$ .

Let $g_0(m):=m$ for all m. We define, by induction, increasing functions $g_1,\dots ,g_k\in {\mathbb {N}^{\mathbb {N}}}$ . Let $l<k$ and assume that the function $g_l$ is defined. For natural numbers n, m, and i, let

$$ \begin{align*} V^{l,n}_i &:= \bigcap_{m=i}^{g_l(i)}U^n_m,\\ W^{l,n}_m &:= \bigcup\{\,V^{l,n}_i : n\le i, g_l(i)\le m\,\}. \end{align*} $$

For each l and n, the sets $W^{l,n}_m$ are increasing with m, and cover the space X. By the Hurewicz property, there is an increasing function $g_{l+1}\in {\mathbb {N}^{\mathbb {N}}}$ such that

$$\begin{align*}\{\, W^{l,n}_{g_{l+1}(n)} : n\in\mathbb{N}\}\in{\Gamma}(X). \end{align*}$$

This completes the inductive construction.

We will show that

$$\begin{align*}\{\,U^n_m : n\in\mathbb{N}, m\le g_k(n)\,\}\in\mathrm{O}_k(X). \end{align*}$$

Let $x_1,\dotsc ,x_k\in X$ . Since $\{\, W^{l,n}_{g_{l+1}(n)} : n\in \mathbb {N}\}\in {\Gamma} (X)$ for all $l=0,\dotsc ,k-1$ , there is a natural number N with

$$\begin{align*}x_1,\dots,x_k\in W^{l,n}_{g_{l+1}(n)} \end{align*}$$

for all $l=0,\dotsc ,k-1$ and all $n\ge N$ . Fix a number $n_0\ge N$ .

Since $x_1\in W^{k-1,n_0}_{g_{k}(n_0)}$ , there is $n_1$ with $n_0\le n_1,g_{k-1}(n_1)\le g_{k}(n_0)$ and

$$\begin{align*}x_1\in V^{k-1,n_0}_{n_1}=\bigcap_{m=n_1}^{g_{k-1}(n_1)}U^{n_0}_m. \end{align*}$$

Since $x_3\in W^{k-3,n_2}_{g_{k-2}(n_2)}$ , there is $n_3$ with $n_2\le n_3,g_{k-3}(n_3)\le g_{k-2}(n_2)$ and

$$\begin{align*}x_3\in V^{k-3,n_2}_{n_3}=\bigcap_{m=n_3}^{g_{k-3}(n_3)}U^{n_2}_m\subseteq \bigcap_{m=n_3}^{g_{k-3}(n_3)}U^{n_0}_m. \end{align*}$$

Since $x_k\in W^{0,n_{k-1}}_{g_{1}(n_{k-1})}$ , there is $n_k$ with $n_{k-1}\le n_k=g_{0}(n_k)\le g_{1}(n_{k-1})$ and

$$\begin{align*}x_k\in V^{0,n_{k-1}}_{n_k}=U^{n_{k-1}}_{n_k}\subseteq U^{n_0}_{n_k}. \end{align*}$$

It follows that $x_1,\dots ,x_k\in U^{n_0}_{n_k}$ , and $n_k\le g_k(n_0)$ .

The proof of Theorem 3.2 establishes a stronger result. To this end, we need the following definitions and lemma. An infinite cover of a space X is $\omega $ -groupable [Reference Kočinac and Scheepers9] (respectively, k-groupable, for a natural number k) if there is a partition of the cover into finite parts such that for each finite (respectively, k-element) set $F\subseteq X$ and all but finitely many parts $\mathcal {P}$ of the partition, there is a set $U\in \mathcal {P}$ with $F\subseteq U$ . Let $\Omega ^{\mathrm {\tiny gp}}(X)$ (respectively, $\mathrm {O}_k^{\mathrm {\tiny gp}}(X)$ ) be the family of open $\omega $ -groupable (respectively, k-groupable) covers of the space X.

Lemma 3.3 Let $\Pi $ be a selection principle, and let $\mathrm {A}$ be a type of open covers. The following assertions are equivalent:

  1. (1) $\Pi (\mathrm {A},\Omega ^{\mathrm {\tiny gp}})$ ;

  2. (2) For each natural number k, we have $\Pi (\mathrm {A},\mathrm {O}_k^{\mathrm {\tiny gp}})$ .

Proof. The proof is similar to that of Lemma 3.1, once we observe that if $\{\, U_n : n\in \mathbb {N}\}$ is a k-groupable cover for all k, then it is $\omega $ -groupable. This follows easily from the fact that for each countable family $\{\,\mathcal {P}_k : k\in \mathbb {N}\,\}$ of partitions of $\mathbb {N}$ into finite sets, there is a partition $\mathcal {P}$ of $\mathbb {N}$ into finite sets that is eventually coarser than all of the given partitions, that is, such that for each k, all but finitely many members of the partition $\mathcal {P}$ contain a member of the partition $\mathcal {P}_k$ .

Kočinac and Scheepers proved that if all finite powers of a space X are Hurewicz, then every open $\omega $ -cover of the space is $\omega $ -groupable. Together with Peng’s Theorem 3.2, if all finite powers of a space X are Hurewicz, then the space satisfies $\mathsf {S}_{\mathrm {fin}}({\Gamma} ,\Omega ^{\mathrm {\tiny gp}})$ . The following theorem shows that the assumption on the finite powers is not needed.

In the proof, we also mention the property $\mathsf {S}_{\mathrm {fin}}({\Gamma} ,\Lambda ^{\mathrm {\tiny gp}})$ . An open cover is large if each point is in infinitely many members of the cover. Let $\Lambda (X)$ be the family of large open covers of the space X. An open cover $\mathcal {U}$ is in $\Lambda ^{\mathrm {\tiny gp}}(X)$ [Reference Kočinac and Scheepers9] (also denoted $\gimel ({\Gamma} )$ , depending on the context [Reference Samet, Scheepers and Tsaban13]) if there is a partition of the cover into finite parts such that for each point $x\in X$ and all but finitely many parts $\mathcal {P}$ of the partition, we have $x\in \bigcup \mathcal {P}$ .

Theorem 3.4 The following assertions are equivalent:

  1. (1) $\mathsf {U}_{\mathrm {fin}}(\mathrm {O},{\Gamma} )$ .

  2. (2) $\mathsf {S}_{\mathrm {fin}}({\Gamma} ,\Omega ^{\mathrm {\tiny gp}})$ .

Proof. $(1)\Rightarrow (2)$ : The proof of Peng’s Theorem 3.2, as written above, shows, for a prescribed number k, that for each k-element set F, there is a natural number N such that for each $n\ge N$ , there is a member of the finite set $\mathcal {F}_{n}=\{\,U^{n}_m : m\le g_k(n)\,\}$ that contains the set F. By thinning out the point-cofinite covers, we may assume that they are pairwise disjoint [Reference Scheepers15, Lemma 4], and consequently so are the finite sets $\mathcal {F}_{n}$ . Thus, $\bigcup _{n=1}^\infty \mathcal {F}_n\in \mathrm {O}_k^{\mathrm {\tiny gp}}$ . This proves $\mathsf {S}_{\mathrm {fin}}({\Gamma} ,\mathrm {O}_k^{\mathrm {\tiny gp}})$ for all k. Apply Lemma 3.3.

$(2)\Rightarrow (1)$ : $\Omega ^{\mathrm {\tiny gp}}\subseteq \Lambda ^{\mathrm {\tiny gp}}$ . It is known that $\mathsf {S}_{\mathrm {fin}}({\Gamma} ,\Lambda ^{\mathrm {\tiny gp}})=\mathsf {U}_{\mathrm {fin}}(\mathrm {O},{\Gamma} )$ [Reference Samet, Scheepers and Tsaban13, Theorem 6]. For completeness, we provide a proof that $\mathsf {S}_{\mathrm {fin}}({\Gamma} ,\Lambda ^{\mathrm {\tiny gp}})$ implies $\mathsf {U}_{\mathrm {fin}}(\mathrm {O},{\Gamma} )$ .

Assume that the space X satisfies $\mathsf {S}_{\mathrm {fin}}({\Gamma} ,\Lambda ^{\mathrm {\tiny gp}})$ . It suffices to prove that it satisfies $\mathsf {U}_{\mathrm {fin}}({\Gamma} ,{\Gamma} )$ . Given a sequence $\mathcal {U}_1, \mathcal {U}_2, \dotsc $ in ${\Gamma} (X)$ , we may (as in the proof of Theorem 3.2) assume that the covers get finer with n. Apply $\mathsf {S}_{\mathrm {fin}}({\Gamma} ,\Lambda ^{\mathrm {\tiny gp}})$ to obtain a cover $\mathcal {U}\in \Lambda ^{\mathrm {\tiny gp}}$ , with parts $\mathcal {P}_n$ (for $n\in \mathbb {N}$ ) witnessing that.

Let $\mathcal {F}_1\subseteq \mathcal {U}_1$ be a finite set refined by $\mathcal {P}_1$ , that is, such that for each set $U\in \mathcal {P}_1$ , there is a set $V\in \mathcal {F}_1$ with $U\subseteq V$ . The set $\mathcal {F}_1$ exists since the covers $\mathcal {U}_n$ get finer as n increases. Let $n_2$ be minimal with $\mathcal {P}_{n_2}\subseteq \bigcup _{n=2}^\infty \mathcal {U}_n$ , and let $\mathcal {F}_2\subseteq \mathcal {U}_2$ be a finite set refined by $\mathcal {P}_{n_2}$ . Let $n_3$ be minimal with $\mathcal {P}_{n_3}\subseteq \bigcup _{n=3}^\infty \mathcal {U}_n$ , and let $\mathcal {F}_3\subseteq \mathcal {U}_3$ be a finite set refined by $\mathcal {P}_{n_3}$ . Continuing in this manner, we obtain finite sets $\mathcal {F}_n\subseteq \mathcal {U}_n$ for $n\in \mathbb {N}$ , with $\{\, \bigcup \mathcal {F}_n : n\in \mathbb {N}\}\in {\Gamma} (X)$ .

As mentioned in the proof, we have $\mathsf {U}_{\mathrm {fin}}(\mathrm {O},\Gamma )=\mathsf {S}_{\mathrm {fin}}(\Gamma ,\Lambda ^{\mathrm {\tiny gp}})$ . Kočinac and Scheepers proved that $\mathsf {U}_{\mathrm {fin}}(\mathrm {O},\Gamma )=\mathsf {S}_{\mathrm {fin}}(\Omega ,\Lambda ^{\mathrm {\tiny gp}})=\mathsf {S}_{\mathrm {fin}}(\Lambda ,\Lambda ^{\mathrm {\tiny gp}})$ [Reference Kočinac and Scheepers9, Theorem 14]. However, $\mathsf {U}_{\mathrm {fin}}(\mathrm {O},\Gamma )\neq \mathsf {S}_{\mathrm {fin}}(\Omega ,\Omega ^{\mathrm {\tiny gp}})$ : The latter property is equivalent to satisfying $\mathsf {U}_{\mathrm {fin}}(\mathrm {O},\Gamma )$ in all finite powers [Reference Kočinac and Scheepers9, Theorem 16], a property strictly stronger than $\mathsf {U}_{\mathrm {fin}}(\mathrm {O},\Gamma )$ [Reference Just, Miller, Scheepers and Szeptycki8, Theorem 2.12].

4 When Bob has a winning strategy in the Menger game

Menger [Reference Menger10] conjectured that his property $\mathsf {S}_{\mathrm {fin}}(\mathrm {O},\mathrm {O})$ implies $\sigma $ -compactness. While his conjecture turned out false ([Reference Tsaban19] and the references therein), a closely related assertion is true. The Menger game [Reference Hurewicz7], $\mathsf {G}_{\mathrm {fin}}(\mathrm {O},\mathrm {O})$ , is the game associated with Menger’s property $\mathsf {S}_{\mathrm {fin}}(\mathrm {O},\mathrm {O})$ . It is played on a topological space X, and has an inning per each natural number n. In each inning, Alice picks an open cover $\mathcal {U}_n$ of the space, and Bob chooses a finite set $\mathcal {F}_n\subseteq \mathcal {U}_n$ . Bob wins if $\bigcup _{n=1}^\infty \mathcal {F}_n$ is a cover of the space, and otherwise Alice wins. Telgársky [Reference Telgársky17] proved that if Bob has a winning strategy in the Menger game played on a metric space, then the space is $\sigma $ -compact.

Scheepers [Reference Scheepers14, Theorem 1] provided a direct proof of Telgársky’s theorem, using the notion of H-closed sets. We will eliminate the notion of H-closed sets and the closure operations from Scheepers’s proof, and obtain a more transparent proof.

A subset K of a topological space X is relatively compact if every open cover $\mathcal {U}$ of the entire space X has a finite subcover of the set K. A subset K of a regular space is relatively compact if and only if its closure is compact.

Lemma 4.1 Let $\kappa $ be a cardinal number. If a regular space X is a union of at most $\kappa $ relatively compact sets, then it is the union of at most $\kappa $ compact sets.

Proof. If $X=\bigcup _{\alpha <\kappa } K_\alpha $ , then $X=\bigcup _{\alpha <\kappa } \overline {K_\alpha }$ .

For a basis $\mathcal {B}$ for the topology of a space X, let $\mathrm {O}_{\mathcal {B}}(X)$ be the family of subsets of $\mathcal {B}$ that cover the space X.

Lemma 4.2 Let X be a topological space with a basis $\mathcal {B}$ , and let $\sigma $ be a function on the family $\mathrm {O}_{\mathcal {B}}(X)$ such that for each cover $\mathcal {U}\in \mathrm {O}_{\mathcal {B}}(X)$ , $\sigma (\mathcal {U})$ is a finite subset of $\mathcal {U}$ . Then the set

$$\begin{align*}K:=\bigcap_{\mathcal{U}\in\mathrm{O}_{\mathcal{B}}(X)}\bigcup\sigma(\mathcal{U}) \end{align*}$$

is relatively compact.

Proof. Every open cover is refined by a cover $\mathcal {U}\in \mathrm {O}_{\mathcal {B}}(X)$ which, in turn, has the finite subcover $\sigma (\mathcal {U})$ .

If Bob has a winning strategy in the Menger game played on X, then the space X is Menger and, in particular, Lindelöf. If X is, in addition, metric, then the space is regular and second countable. On the other hand, Urysohn’s Metrization Theorem asserts that every second countable regular space is metrizable.

Theorem 4.3 (Telgársky)

Let X be a metric space. If Bob has a winning strategy in the Menger game $\mathsf {G}_{\mathrm {fin}}(\mathrm {O},\mathrm {O})$ played on X, then the space X is $\sigma $ -compact.

Proof. We follow the steps of Scheepers’s proof [Reference Scheepers14, Theorem 1], removing what is not necessary.

The space X is regular and second countable. Let $\sigma $ be a winning strategy for Bob. Fix a countable base $\mathcal {B}$ for the topology of the space X. Let $\mathbb {N}^*$ be the set of finite sequences of natural numbers. We consider all possible games where Alice chooses her covers from the family $\mathrm {O}_{\mathcal {B}}(X)$ .

Since the base $\mathcal {B}$ is countable, the family $\{\,\sigma (\mathcal {U}) : \mathcal {U}\in \mathrm {O}_{\mathcal {B}}\,\}$ (the possible first responds of Bob) is countable, too. Choose elements $\mathcal {U}_1, \mathcal {U}_2, \dotsc \in \mathrm {O}_{\mathcal {B}}$ with

$$\begin{align*}\{\, \sigma(\mathcal{U}_n) : n\in\mathbb{N}\}=\{\,\sigma(\mathcal{U}) : \mathcal{U}\in\mathrm{O}_{\mathcal{B}}\,\}. \end{align*}$$

By induction, for a given natural number n and each sequence $s=(s_1,\dotsc ,s_n)\in \mathbb {N}^n$ , the family

$$\begin{align*}\{\,\sigma(\mathcal{U}_{s_1},\mathcal{U}_{s_1,s_2},\dotsc,\mathcal{U}_{s_1,\dotsc,s_n},\mathcal{U}) : \mathcal{U}\in\mathrm{O}_{\mathcal{B}}\,\} \end{align*}$$

is countable. Choose elements $\mathcal {U}_{{s_1,\dotsc ,s_n},1},\mathcal {U}_{{s_1,\dotsc ,s_n},2},\dotsc \in \mathrm {O}_{\mathcal {B}}$ with

$$\begin{align*}\{\,\sigma(\mathcal{U}_{s_1},\dotsc,\mathcal{U}_{s_1,\dotsc,s_n},\mathcal{U}_{{s_1,\dotsc,s_n},m}) : m\in\mathbb{N}\,\} = \{\,\sigma(\mathcal{U}_{s_1},\dotsc,\mathcal{U}_{s_1,\dotsc,s_n},\mathcal{U}) : \mathcal{U}\in\mathrm{O}_{\mathcal{B}}\,\}. \end{align*}$$

This completes our inductive construction.

By Lemma 4.2, for each sequence $s=({s_1,\dotsc ,s_n})\in \mathbb {N}^*$ , the set

$$\begin{align*}K_s := \bigcap_{m=1}^\infty \bigcup\sigma(\mathcal{U}_{s_1},\dotsc,\mathcal{U}_{{s_1,\dotsc,s_n}},\mathcal{U}_{{s_1,\dotsc,s_n},m}) \end{align*}$$

is relatively compact. By Lemma 4.1, it remains to see that $X=\bigcup _{s\in \mathbb {N}^*}K_s$ .

Assume that some element $x\in X$ is not in $\bigcup _{s\in \mathbb {N}^*}K_s$ .

  1. (1) Since $x\notin K_{()}$ , there is $m_1$ with $x\notin \bigcup \sigma (\mathcal {U}_{m_1})$ .

  2. (2) Since $x\notin K_{m_1}$ , there is $m_2$ with $x\notin \bigcup \sigma (\mathcal {U}_{m_1},\mathcal {U}_{m_1,m_2})$ .

  3. (3) Since $x\notin K_{m_1,m_2}$ , there is $m_3$ with $x\notin \bigcup \sigma (\mathcal {U}_{m_1},\mathcal {U}_{m_1,m_2},\mathcal {U}_{m_1,m_2,m_3})$ .

  4. (4) Etc.

Then the play

$$\begin{align*}\mathcal{U}_{m_1},\sigma(\mathcal{U}_{m_1}), \mathcal{U}_{m_1,m_2}, \sigma(\mathcal{U}_{m_1},\mathcal{U}_{m_1,m_2}), \mathcal{U}_{m_1,m_2,m_3}, \sigma(\mathcal{U}_{m_1},\mathcal{U}_{m_1,m_2},\mathcal{U}_{m_1,m_2,m_3}), \dotsc \end{align*}$$

is lost by Bob; a contradiction.

Let $\alpha $ be an ordinal number. The transfinite Menger game $\mathsf {G}_{\mathrm {fin}}^\alpha (\mathrm {O},\mathrm {O})$ is defined as the ordinary Menger game, with the only difference that now there is an inning per each ordinal number $\beta <\alpha $ . Clearly, if $\alpha _1<\alpha _2$ and Bob has a winning strategy in the $\alpha _1$ -Menger game, then Bob has a winning strategy in the $\alpha _2$ -Menger game: He can use a winning strategy in the first $\alpha _1$ innings, and then play arbitrarily. Thus, the following theorems are more general than Theorem 4.3.

The weight of a topological space is the minimal cardinality of a base for its topology.

Theorem 4.4 Suppose that X is a regular topological space of weight $\kappa $ , and $\lambda \le \kappa $ . If Bob has a winning strategy in the game $\mathsf {G}_{\mathrm {fin}}^\lambda (\mathrm {O},\mathrm {O})$ played on X, then the space X is a union of at most $\kappa ^{<\lambda }$ compact sets.

Proof. The proof is identical to that of Theorem 4.3, only that here we begin with a base of cardinality $\kappa $ . Here, the sequences s range over the set of sequences in $\kappa $ of length smaller than $\lambda $ .

Corollary 4.5 Let X be a regular topological space of weight $\kappa $ . If Bob has a winning strategy in the Menger game $\mathsf {G}_{\mathrm {fin}}(\mathrm {O},\mathrm {O})$ , then the space X is a union of at most $\kappa $ compact sets.

For spaces of uncountable weight $\kappa $ , the converse of Corollary 4.5 is false: The discrete space of cardinality $\kappa $ has weight $\kappa $ , and it is a union of $\kappa $ compact sets (singletons). This space is not Lindelöf, and thus not Menger, so Bob has no winning strategy in the Menger game played on this space.

5 The additivity of Rothberger’s property

Let $\operatorname {add}(\mathcal {N})$ be the minimal cardinality of a family $F \subseteq {\mathbb {N}^{\mathbb {N}}}$ such that there is no function $S\colon \mathbb {N}\to [\mathbb {N}]^{<\!\!\infty }$ with $\left |S(n)\right | \leq n$ for all n, such that for each function $f \in F$ , we have $f(n) \in S(n)$ for all but finitely many n.

The notation $\operatorname {add}(\mathcal {N})$ is explained by a result of Bartoszyński and Judah [Reference Bartoszyński and Judah1, Theorem 2.11]: The cardinal number $\operatorname {add}(\mathcal {N})$ is the minimal cardinality of a family of Lebesgue null sets of real numbers whose union is not Lebesgue null. In general, the additivity of a property is the minimum cardinality of a family of sets satisfying the property, whose union does not. The following theorem is attributed to Carlson by Bartoszyński and Judah [Reference Bartoszyński and Judah1, Theorem 2.9].

Theorem 5.1 (Carlson)

Let $\kappa <\operatorname {add}(\mathcal {N})$ . If a Lindelöf space is a union of at most $\kappa $ spaces satisfying $\mathsf {S}_1(\mathrm {O},\mathrm {O})$ , then the space X satisfies $\mathsf {S}_1(\mathrm {O},\mathrm {O})$ . That is, for Lindelöf spaces, $\operatorname {add}(\mathcal {N})\le \operatorname {add}(\mathsf {S}_1(\mathrm {O},\mathrm {O}))$ .

This theorem is an easy consequence of a simple, basic fact concerning selection principles. We need the following lemmata.

Let $\mathrm {A}$ and $\mathrm {B}$ be types of open covers. A topological space X satisfies $\mathsf {S}_{n}(\mathrm {A},\mathrm {B})$ if for all $\mathcal {U}_1,\mathcal {U}_2,\ldots \in \mathrm {A}(X)$ , there are finite sets $\mathcal {F}_1\subseteq \mathcal {U}_1,\mathcal {F}_2\subseteq \mathcal {U}_2,\dotsc $ such that $\left |\mathcal {F}_n\right |\le n$ for all n, and $\bigcup _{n=1}^\infty \mathcal {F}_n\in \mathrm {B}(X)$ .

Garcia-Ferreira and Tamariz-Mascarua [Reference Garcia-Ferreira and Tamariz-Mascarua5, Lemma 3.12] established the following observation in the case $\mathrm {A}=\mathrm {O}$ .

Lemma 5.2 [Reference Tsaban19, Theorem A.1]

Let $\mathrm {A}$ be a type of countable covers such that every pair of covers of type $\mathrm {A}$ has a joint refinement of type $\mathrm {A}$ . Then $\mathsf {S}_{n}(\mathrm {A},\mathrm {O})=\mathsf {S}_1(\mathrm {A},\mathrm {O})$ .

Lemma 5.3 (Folklore)

If a space X satisfies $\mathsf {S}_1(\mathrm {A},\mathrm {O})$ , then for each sequence $\mathcal {U}_1, \mathcal {U}_2, \dotsc $ in $\mathrm {O}(X)$ , there are elements $U_1\in \mathcal {U}_1,U_2\in \mathcal {U}_2,\dotsc $ such that for each point $x\in X$ , we have $x\in U_n$ for infinitely many n.

Proof. As usual, we split the sequence of open covers to infinitely many disjoint sequences, and apply the property $\mathsf {S}_1(\mathrm {A},\mathrm {O})$ to each subsequence separately.

Theorem 5.4 Let $\mathrm {A}$ be a type of countable covers such that every pair of covers of type $\mathrm {A}$ has a joint refinement of type $\mathrm {A}$ . Then $\operatorname {add}(\mathcal {N})\le \operatorname {add}(\mathsf {S}_1(\mathrm {A},\mathrm {O}))$ .

Proof. Let $\kappa <\operatorname {add}(\mathcal {N})$ and $X = \bigcup _{\alpha < \kappa }X_\alpha $ , where each space $X_\alpha $ satisfies $\mathsf {S}_1(\mathrm {A},\mathrm {O})$ . By Lemma 5.2, it suffices to show that the space X satisfies $\mathsf {S}_{n}(\mathrm {A},\mathrm {O})$ .

Let $\mathcal {U}_n=\{U^n_m : m\in \mathbb {N}\}\in \mathrm {A}(X)$ , for $n\in \mathbb {N}$ . For each ordinal number $\alpha <\kappa $ , as the space $X_\alpha $ satisfies $\mathsf {S}_1(\mathrm {A},\mathrm {O})$ , there is a function $f_\alpha \in {\mathbb {N}^{\mathbb {N}}}$ such that for each point $x\in X_\alpha $ , we have

$$\begin{align*}x\in U^n_{f_\alpha(n)} \end{align*}$$

for infinitely many n.

There is a function $S\colon \mathbb {N}\to [\mathbb {N}]^{<\!\!\infty }$ with $\left |S(n)\right | \leq n$ for all n, such that for each $\alpha <\kappa $ , we have

$$\begin{align*}\ f_\alpha(n) \in S(n) \end{align*}$$

for all but finitely many n. Then $\bigcup _{n=1}^\infty \{\,U^n_{m} : m\in S(n)\,\}\in \mathrm {O}(X)$ .

Judging by an extensive survey on the topic [Reference Tsaban and Kočinac18], the result in the second item below seems to be new.

Corollary 5.5

  1. (1) For Lindelöf spaces, $\operatorname {add}(\mathcal {N})\le \operatorname {add}(\mathsf {S}_1(\mathrm {O},\mathrm {O}))$ .

  2. (2) $\operatorname {add}(\mathcal {N})\le \operatorname {add}(\mathsf {S}_1(\Gamma ,\mathrm {O}))$ .

Proof. (1) Since the spaces are Lindelöf, we may restrict attention to countable covers, and the assumptions of Theorem 5.4 hold.

(2) A countably infinite subset of a point-cofinite cover is also a point-cofinite cover. Thus, we may restrict attention to countable point-cofinite covers. It is well known that every pair of point-cofinite covers has a joint refinement that is a point-cofinite cover. Indeed, let $\mathcal {U}$ and $\mathcal {V}$ be countable point-cofinite covers. Enumerate them $\mathcal {U}=\{\, U_n : n\in \mathbb {N}\}$ and $\mathcal {V}=\{\, V_n : n\in \mathbb {N}\}$ . Then $\{\, U_n\cap V_n : n\in \mathbb {N}\}\in \Gamma (X)$ . Theorem 5.4 applies.

We can extract additional information from this proof method. A topological space X satisfies $\mathsf {U}_n(\Gamma ,\Gamma )$ [Reference Tsaban19] if for all $\mathcal {U}_1,\mathcal {U}_2,\ldots \in \Gamma (X)$ , there are finite sets $\mathcal {F}_1\subseteq \mathcal {U}_1,\mathcal {F}_2\subseteq \mathcal {U}_2,\dotsc $ such that $\left |\mathcal {F}_n\right |\le n$ for all n, and $\{\, \bigcup \mathcal {F}_n : n\in \mathbb {N}\}\in \Gamma (X)$ . This property is strictly inbetween $\mathsf {S}_1(\Gamma ,\Gamma )$ and $\mathsf {U}_{\mathrm {fin}}(\mathrm {O},\Gamma )$ [Reference Tsaban19, Theorems 3.3 and 3.8].

Theorem 5.6 $\operatorname {add}(\mathcal {N})\le \operatorname {add}(\mathsf {U}_n(\Gamma ,\Gamma ))$ .

Proof. Let $\kappa <\operatorname {add}(\mathcal {N})$ and $X = \bigcup _{\alpha < \kappa }X_\alpha $ , where each space $X_\alpha $ satisfies $\mathsf {U}_n(\Gamma ,\Gamma )$ . It suffices to show that the space X satisfies $\mathsf {U}_{n^2}(\Gamma ,\Gamma )$ , where the cardinality of the nth selected finite set is at most $n^2$ [Reference Tsaban19, Lemma 3.2].

Let $\mathcal {U}_n=\{U^n_m : m\in \mathbb {N}\}\in \Gamma (X)$ , for $n\in \mathbb {N}$ . For each $\alpha <\kappa $ , as the space $X_\alpha $ satisfies $\mathsf {U}_n(\Gamma ,\Gamma )$ , there is a function $S_\alpha \colon \mathbb {N}\to \prod _n[\mathbb {N}]^{\le n}$ such that for each point $x\in X_\alpha $ , we have

$$\begin{align*}x\in \bigcup_{m\in S_\alpha(n)}U^n_m \end{align*}$$

for infinitely many n.

There is a function $S\colon \mathbb {N}\to \prod _n[\mathbb {N}]^{\le n}$ with $\left |S(n)\right | \leq n$ for all n, such that for each $\alpha <\kappa $ , we have

$$\begin{align*}\ S_\alpha(n) \in S(n) \end{align*}$$

for all but finitely many n. For each natural number n, let $F_n:=\bigcup S(n)$ . Then $\left |F_n\right |\le n^2$ for all n, and $\{\, \bigcup _{m\in F_n}U^n_m : n\in \mathbb {N}\}\in \Gamma (X)$ .

Acknowledgment

I write this paper after a personally challenging period. I thank all those who helped and encouraged me throughout, and supported my return to normal track afterward. Above all, I thank my wife, Adina, for her faith, support, and patience.

I thank Lyubomyr Zdomskyy for reading the paper carefully and making important comments. Finally, I thank the referee for their work on refereeing this paper.

Footnotes

To Adina

References

Bartoszyński, T. and Judah, H., On cofinality of the smallest covering of the real line by meager sets II . Proc. Amer. Math. Soc. 123(1995), 18791885.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bukovský, L. and Haleš, J., QN-space, wQN-space and covering properties . Topology Appl. 154(2007), 848858.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bukovský, L., Recław, I., and Repický, M., Spaces not distinguishing pointwise and quasinormal convergence of real functions . Topology Appl. 41(1991), 2541.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bukovský, L. and Šupina, J., Sequence selection principles for quasi-normal convergence . Topology Appl. 159(2012), 283289.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Garcia-Ferreira, S. and Tamariz-Mascarua, A., Some generalizations of rapid ultrafilters and Id-fan tightness . Tsubuka J. Math. 19(1995), 173185.Google Scholar
Gerlits, J. and Nagy, Z., On Fréchet spaces . Rend. Circ. Mat. i Palermo (2) 18(1988), 5171.Google Scholar
Hurewicz, W., Über eine Verallgemeinerung des Borelschen theorems . Math. Z. 24(1925), 401421.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Just, W., Miller, A., Scheepers, M., and Szeptycki, P., The combinatorics of open covers II . Topology Appl. 73(1996), 241266.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kočinac, L. and Scheepers, M., Combinatorics of open covers (VII): groupability . Fundam. Math. 179(2003), 131155.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Menger, K., Einige Überdeckungssätze der Punktmengenlehre . Sitzungsber. Wien. Akad. 133(1924), 421444.Google Scholar
Peng, Y., Scheepers’ conjecture and the Scheepers diagram . Trans. Amer. Math. Soc. 376(2023), 11991229.Google Scholar
Sakai, M., The sequence selection properties of ${C}_p(X)$ . Topology Appl. 154(2007), 552560.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Samet, N., Scheepers, M., and Tsaban, B., Partition relations for Hurewicz-type selection hypotheses . Topology Appl. 156(2009), 616623.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Scheepers, M., A direct proof of a theorem of Telgársky . Proc. Amer. Math. Soc. 123(1995), 34833485.Google Scholar
Scheepers, M., Combinatorics of open covers I: Ramsey theory . Topology Appl. 69(1996), 3162.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Scheepers, M. and Tsaban, B., The combinatorics of Borel covers . Topology Appl. 121(2002), 357382.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Telgársky, R., On games of Topsoe . Math. Scand. 54(1984), 170176.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tsaban, B., Additivity numbers of covering properties . In: Kočinac, L. (ed.), Selection principles and covering properties in topology, Quaderni di Matematica 18, Seconda Universita di Napoli, Caserta, 2006, pp. 245282.Google Scholar
Tsaban, B., Menger’s and Hurewicz’s problems: solutions from “the Book” and refinements . Contemp. Math. 533(2011), 211226.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tsaban, B. and Zdomskyy, L., Hereditarily Hurewicz spaces and Arhangel’skiĭ sheaf amalgamations . J. Eur. Math. Soc. 12(2012), 353372.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Figure 0

Figure 1 The Scheepers Diagram.

Figure 1

Figure 2 The Final Scheepers Diagram.