Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-mlc7c Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-14T09:30:03.342Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The critique of psychiatry as we enter the third decade of the 21st century

Commentary on… Critical psychiatry

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  27 February 2020

Mohammed Abouelleil Rashed*
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, School of Social Sciences, History and Philosophy, Birkbeck College, University of London, UK
*
Correspondence to Dr Mohammed Abouelleil Rashed ([email protected])
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Summary

Critical psychiatry takes the position that ‘mental illness’ should not be reduced to ‘brain disease’. Here I consider whether this particular stance is outdated in light of more recent exchanges on reductionism, which consider questions raised by new mental health sciences that seek truly integrative and specific biopsychosocial models of illness.

Type
Commentary
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2020

The anti-reductionist position of critical psychiatry

According to Duncan Double, the essential position of critical psychiatry is that ‘functional mental illness should not be reduced to brain disease’.Reference Double1 As it stands, this claim is ambiguous with regard to the basis of the normative (ethical) prescription contained within it: why does critical psychiatry maintain that we should not reduce ‘mental illness’ to ‘brain disease’? We are provided with a clue as to Double's view when he writes that ‘most psychopathology is functional, in the sense that there are no structural abnormalities in the brain’.Reference Double1 Accordingly, we should not engage in such a reduction because we do not possess the evidence that it can be done. To insist on this reduction, and on the treatments and practices it entails, can therefore be construed as ethically problematic. Now this sort of justification for critical psychiatry's essential position lands us in indeterminate territory: it relies on establishing the presence of ‘structural abnormalities’, which depends on how we define this term, on the state of the science and on the nature of evidence and its interpretation. There will always be claims and counterclaims as to the evidence for the biological basis of ‘mental illness’.

There is another more substantial argument that can be provided in support of critical psychiatry's position: we should not engage in the offending reduction because even if there were ‘structural abnormalities in the brain’, the subject matter – ‘mental illness’ – requires an altogether different approach for its classification, understanding and management. Double seems to intend something like this when he argues, along with von Feuchtersleben, Meyer and Engels, for a holistic, non-reductionist and integrative conception of ‘psychopathology’. This is a valuable analysis, and it is hard to disagree with the general direction of Double's argument in this regard: mental health conditions cannot be understood, treated or managed through radically reductionist concepts and approaches. And radical reductionism is the villain that critical psychiatry, on Double's account, is engaged in a fight with. It is a reductionism that is so obtuse, it has no place for meaning, human relationships or social context. And it was certainly evident in the early days of psychiatry, through the wild goose chase prompted, in part, by the discovery of the celebrated causal connection between general paresis of the insane and the syphilis spirochaete. How far does this view exist today?

We can quarrel endlessly about critical psychiatry's representation of the views of its opponents, and it is unlikely that we can ever resolve this to everyone's satisfaction. Instead, I shall introduce a more recent exchange on reductionism, and from there we can discern where things are at and what critical psychiatry has to say to us today.

Towards a truly integrated understanding of health

In a paper published in the BMJ in 2012, White and colleagues argue for an end to the distinction between mental disorders and brain disorders in favour of a single overarching category: disorders of the nervous system.Reference White, Rickards and Zeman2 One of the arguments they make in support of this proposal is that psychosocial factors ‘interact strongly’ with neurological disorders, whereas ‘disorders of the mind are rooted in dysfunction of the brain’.Reference White, Rickards and Zeman2, Reference Fitzgerald3 Psychological, social and biological causal and risk factors run across all medical conditions, whether mental or physical.Reference White, Rickards and Zeman2 If so, there might not be much sense insisting on the distinction between mental disorders and brain disorders, especially, they argue, considering recent advances in the neurological and genetic bases of mental disorders. Standing in contrast to White and colleagues’ proposal is a position paper by Bracken and colleagues that rejects the suggested equivalence between psychiatry and neurology: ‘Psychiatry is not neurology; it is not a medicine of the brain. Although mental health problems undoubtedly have a biological dimension, in their very nature they reach beyond the brain to involve social, cultural and psychological dimensions’.Reference Bracken, Thomas, Timimi, Asen, Behr and Beuster4

These two papers, although they argue for opposite conclusions, are both non-reductionist in the sense that they do not propose a radical disavowal of non-biological causal and risk factors. Accordingly, neither falls foul of critical psychiatry's essential position as articulated by Double. A key point on which they differ is a question of emphasis: White and colleagues emphasise genetic and neurological factors, whereas Bracken and colleagues emphasise psychosocial factors. Where should we stand on this point?

There is no doubt that mental health conditions and neurological conditions demonstrate ‘multifactorial pathways’, as White and Colleagues note. Nevertheless, psychosocial factors are more prominent in mental disorders across a wide range of dimensions.Reference Bolton5 To the extent that this is the case, psychiatry differs from neurology in that it ‘has particular expertise in the management of psychosocial factors as well as internal biological factors’.Reference Bolton5 We could take this observation to support the view that, in order to preserve the emphasis on psychosocial factors, we should not collapse the distinction between mental disorders and brain disorders. Or we could decide that the terms of the debate and the forced choice between them are out of keeping with developments in the new mental health sciences. Here, gene–environment interactions, social determinants of health over the life-course, individual psychology and neuroscience are all relevant for an integrated understanding of health. As Derek Bolton puts it: ‘[These] new sciences do not work with ideological battles between the biological, the psychological, and the social, the old parallel universes with poor communication between them; rather they work with all of these factors and the diversity of interplay between them’.Reference Bolton5

There is much work to be done, both empirical and conceptual, to understand how social, psychological and biological factors interact in specific conditions. However, that work applies across the board to all conditions of health-related interest.Reference Hernandez and Blazer6,Reference Bolton and Gillett7 The aim is to move beyond a biopsychosocial model that is integrative only in name and towards one that can provide concrete risk and causal pathways across the range of factors of relevance to a particular health condition.

Critical psychiatry may have run its course, but the critique of psychiatry continues

Where does this leave critical psychiatry? Double's editorial seeks to advance two aims. On one hand, it wants to affirm critical psychiatry's continuing relevance as the defender of the position that ‘functional mental illness should not be reduced to brain disease’. On the other hand, it acknowledges that it might be beneficial ‘to look for the continuities, rather than discontinuities, with orthodox psychiatry’.Reference Double1 On the first aim, we have seen that it is possible to debate whether we should end the distinction between mental disorders and brain disorders without falling into the radical reductionism that critical psychiatry positions itself against. Moreover, as suggested above, the new mental health sciences have moved beyond the terms of this debate and seek genuinely integrative and specific biopsychosocial models of health conditions. Accordingly, in so far as critical psychiatry requires the continuing relevance of its essential position, then it might have run its course. This leaves us with the second aim of the editorial, from which, on Double's own analysis, one gets the sense that there is very little that separates critical psychiatry from ‘orthodox psychiatry’. And that is not a bad thing, for it can be taken by critical psychiatry as a triumph, as evidence that its message has got through.

But critical psychiatry does not exhaust the constructive critique of psychiatry and society, which, as we enter the third decade of the 21st century, is going strong. For example, there are continuing debates on the boundaries of illness and on the definition of mental disorder (e.g.Reference Schuur, Tekin and Bluhm8,Reference Bolton9 ); there are attempts to resolve the classificatory complexity of mental health conditions and to critique the validity of existing classifications (e.g.Reference Huda10Reference Horwitz and Wakefield12); questions continue to be raised about the nature of mental disorders (e.g.Reference Tsou, Tekin and Bluhm13,Reference Simon and Gifford14 ); controversies remain surrounding the efficacy and risks of antidepressant and antipsychotic medications (e.g.Reference Moncrieff15); debates continue on the ethical complexities raised by capacity assessments and coercive interventions (e.g.Reference Cratsley, Tekin and Bluhm16,Reference Radden and Sadler17 ); and challenges to medical concepts and approaches – to medicalisation more generally – are experiencing a resurgence through mental health activism (e.g.Reference Curtis, Dellar, Leslie and Watson18Reference DuBrul22).

In the midst of these exciting and still largely unresolved problems, the version of critical psychiatry presented by Double in his editorial is of historical value; it reminds us of a radically reductionist position that now – in light of developments in the science and philosophy of mental health – appears false and outdated.

About the author

Mohammed Abouelleil Rashed is a Wellcome Trust Institutional Strategic Support Fund Research Fellow in the Department of Philosophy at Birkbeck College, University of London, UK; a Visiting Lecturer in the Department of Philosophy, King's College London; and a medical doctor with postgraduate training in psychiatry.

Footnotes

Declaration of interest: None.

See this issue.

References

Double, DB. Critical psychiatry: an embarrassing hangover from the 1970s? BJPsych Bull 2020; this issue.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
White, PD, Rickards, H, Zeman, A. Time to end the distinction between mental and neurological illnesses. BMJ 2012; 344: e3454.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Fitzgerald, M. Do psychiatry and neurology need a close partnership or a merger? BJPsych Bull 2015; 39: 105–7.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Bracken, P, Thomas, P, Timimi, S, Asen, E, Behr, G, Beuster, C, et al. Psychiatry beyond the current paradigm. Br J Psychiatry 2012; 201: 430–4.10.1192/bjp.bp.112.109447CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Bolton, D. Should mental disorders be regarded as brain disorders? 21st century mental health sciences and implications for research and training. World Psychiatry 2013; 12: 24–5.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hernandez, LM, Blazer, DG. Genes, Behaviour, and the Social Environment: Moving Beyond the Nature/Nurture Debate. National Academies Press, 2006.Google Scholar
Bolton, D, Gillett, G. The Biopsychosocial Model of Health and Disease: New Philosophical and Scientific Developments. Palgrave Macmillan, 2019.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Schuur, R. Mental health and illness: past debates and future directions. In The Bloomsbury Companion to Philosophy of Psychiatry (eds Tekin, Ş., Bluhm, R.): 527–41. Bloomsbury, 2019.Google Scholar
Bolton, D. What is Mental Disorder? An Essay in Philosophy, Science and Values. Oxford University Press, 2008.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Huda, S. The Medical Model in Mental Health: An Explanation and Evaluation. Oxford University Press, 2019.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jablensky, A. Psychiatric classifications: validity and utility. World Psychiatry 2016; 15: 2631.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Horwitz, A, Wakefield, J. The Loss of Sadness: How Psychiatry Transformed Normal Sorrow into Depressive Disorder. Oxford University Press, 2007.Google Scholar
Tsou, J. Philosophy of science, psychiatric classification, and the DSM. In The Bloomsbury Companion to Philosophy of Psychiatry (eds Tekin, Ş., Bluhm, R.): 177–96. Bloomsbury, 2019.Google Scholar
Simon, J. Medical ontology. In Philosophy of Medicine (ed Gifford, F.): 65114. Elsevier, 2011.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moncrieff, J. The Bitterest Pills: The Troubling Story of Antipsychotic Drugs. Palgrave Macmillan, 2013.10.1057/9781137277442CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cratsley, K. The ethics of coercion and other forms of influence. In The Bloomsbury Companion to Philosophy of Psychiatry (eds Tekin, Ş., Bluhm, R.): 283324. Bloomsbury, 2019.Google Scholar
Radden, J, Sadler, J. The Virtuous Psychiatrist: Character Ethics in Psychiatric Practice. Oxford University Press, 2010.Google Scholar
Curtis, T, Dellar, R, Leslie, E, Watson, B. Mad Pride: A Celebration of Mad Culture. Chipmunkapublishing, 2000.Google Scholar
Sen, D. What is Mad Culture? Asylum 2011; 18(1): 56.Google Scholar
Hoffman, G. Public Mental Health without the Health? Challenges and Contributions from the Mad Pride and Neurodiversity Paradigms. In Mental Health as Public Health: Interdisciplinary Perspectives on the Ethics of Prevention (Developments in Neuroethics and Bioethics Vol 2) (eds Cratsley, K, Radden, J): 289326. Elsevier, 2019.Google Scholar
Rashed, MA. Madness and the Demand for Recognition: A Philosophical Inquiry into Identity and Mental Health Activism. Oxford University Press, 2019.10.1093/med/9780198786863.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
DuBrul, S. The Icarus Project: a counter narrative for psychic diversity. J Med Humanit 2014; 35: 257–71.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Submit a response

eLetters

No eLetters have been published for this article.