Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-gb8f7 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-23T19:31:54.535Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Autonomy, Violence, and Consent in the Obstetric Field

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  08 November 2024

Andrés Restrepo-Sánchez*
Affiliation:
Department of Anthropology, University of Iowa, US
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Obstetric violence is a structural form of gender, medical, and sexual violence perpetrated by health providers and institutions during pregnancy, birth, and postpartum. It can produce physical, psychological, and symbolic harm to pregnant/birthing people and their families. Obstetric violence results from structural conditions in the technocratic model of birth and the acceptance of biomedicine as the authoritative knowledge in health care. This phenomenon produces patients’ loss of autonomy and capacity to provide informed consent, which increases their vulnerability to unjustified medical procedures, resulting in negative birth experiences. In this paper, I argue that individual autonomy is necessary but not sufficient for legitimately consenting to obstetric care and preventing violence. The liberal framework of individual autonomy often ignores that childbirth is a social event where multiple individuals and cultural factors influence the consent process. Consequently, I discuss the role of relational autonomy in obstetric decision-making and describe some structural barriers that negatively intervene in this process. Finally, I propose that doulas and midwives can help nurture autonomy and caregiving skills in obstetric patients and health providers. This strategy protects the informed consent process, prevents obstetric violence, and can be effective in recentering childbirth in pregnant people and their families.

Type
Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BYCreative Common License - NCCreative Common License - SA
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-ShareAlike licence (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-sa/4.0/), which permits non-commercial re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the same Creative Commons licence is included and the original work is properly cited. The written permission of Cambridge University Press must be obtained for commercial re-use.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2024. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of Hypatia, a Nonprofit Corporation

1. Obstetric violence and autonomy loss

Obstetric violence refers to pregnant and birthing people’sFootnote 1 perceived experiences of loss of autonomy, consent, and abuse perpetrated by health providers and institutions in the context of pregnancy, birth, and postpartum. This phenomenon can produce physical, psychological, or symbolic harm. It has been classified as a type of gender, medical, sexual, epistemic, and reproductive violence, a violation of human rights, and a clear case of reproductive injustice. Obstetric violence results from structural health inequalities (Sadler et al. Reference Sadler, Santos, Ruiz-Berdún, Skoko, Gillen and Clausen2016; Abadía Barrero Reference Barrero and Ernesto2022), the unequal knowledge/power relations between patients and providers in clinical settings (Foucault Reference Foucault1976), and the hegemony of biomedical discourses in modern obstetrics that reduce pregnant and birthing people to passive subjects during their care (Gopal Reference Gopal2017; O’Brien Reference O’Brien2023). Sometimes studied along gynecological violence, which “encompasses a range of [violent] practices carried out by healthcare providers within the framework of gynecological care” (Cárdenas-Castro and Salinero-Rates Reference Cárdenas-Castro and Salinero-Rates2023, para. 2), obstetric violence scholarship and activism have vastly grown in the past two decades (Kitzinger Reference Kitzinger2006; Díaz-Tello Reference Diaz-Tello2016; Cohen Shabot Reference Cohen Shabot2016, Reference Cohen Shabot2020, Reference Cohen Shabot2021a–Reference Cohen Shabotb; Quattrocchi Reference Quattrocchi2019; Castro and Savage Reference Castro and Savage2019; Nalepa Reference Nalepa2020; Paula et al. 2020; Williamson Reference Williamson2021; Campbell Reference Campbell2021; Berzon and Cohen Shabot Reference Berzon and Cohen Shabot2023; Cantor Reference Cantor2023; Davis-Floyd and Premkumar Reference Davis-Floyd and Premkumar2023; Sargent and Davis-Floyd Reference Sargent and Davis-Floyd2023).

Obstetric violence encompasses multiple forms of dehumanizing treatment and medical abuse.Footnote 2 Some of these practices include unnecessary interventions, movement restrictions, prolonged fasting, routine episiotomies, frequent unjustified vaginal examinations, verbal threatening, shaming, scolding, and other actions experienced as violent by the pregnant/birthing person during their care (Castañeda et al. Reference Castañeda, Hill and Johnson Searcy2022; Cohen Shabot and Sadler Reference Cohen Shabot and Sadler2023). In 2014, the World Health Organization recognized that abuse, disrespect, and mistreatment during childbirth were present in health facilities, affecting women’s dignity and rights (WHO 2014). Their statement responded to extensive efforts of scholars, activists, and policymakers denouncing longstanding abusive practices experienced by obstetric patients worldwide (Davis Reference Davis2018; Mejía Merino et al. Reference Merino, María and David Arango Urrea2018; Jojoa-Tobar et al. Reference Jojoa-Tobar, Darío Cuchumbe-Sánchez, Briyith Ledesma-Rengifo, Cristina Muñoz-Mosquera, María Paja Campo and Pablo Suarez-Bravo2019; Vallana-Sala Reference Vallana-Sala2019). Importantly, Indigenous, Black, Latinx, impoverished, queer, undocumented, young, and disabled people disproportionally experience this type of violence (Levine Reference Levine2008; Berry Reference Berry2010; Davis Reference Davis, Rivkin-Fish, Brodwin and Shaw2019; Rogerson Reference Rogerson2019; Strong Reference Strong2020; Grotti and Brightman Reference Grotti and Brightman2021; Gleason et al. Reference Gleason, Patricia Molina Berrío, Marcela Lopez Ríos and María Mejìa Merino2021).

Like other forms of medical and gender violence, obstetric violence is a multi-layered phenomenon connected to broader sociopolitical and economic inequalities, a manifestation of structural violence (Farmer Reference Farmer2004). It is another link in “the continuum of violence” (Kelly Reference Kelly1987; Cockburn Reference Cockburn2004) and “the violence of everyday life” (Das Reference Das2007) that entrap feminized bodies worldwide. Latin American countries have led the initiative to define and criminalize obstetric violence in the legal sphere (Quattrocchi and Magnone Reference Quattrocchi and Magnone2020). In 2007 Venezuela was the first country to describe obstetric violence in the “Organic Law on Women’s Right to a Life Free from Violence.”Footnote 3 México, Chile, Argentina, and Colombia also addressed the problem and have provided recommendations for a humanized and respectful childbirth experience. Unfortunately, there is no updated information in these countries about the reported number of cases of obstetric violence or the people persecuted for it. This suggests an important gap between legislative provisions and their effective application. For instance, in the last report from 2010, only seven cases of obstetric violence had entered the Venezuelan specialized courts, and none had been resolved (CEM-UCV et al. 2011).

In addition to the physical and emotional harm—the main focus of most studies—obstetric violence produces a loss of autonomy and decision-making capacity (Cohen Shabot Reference Cohen Shabot2020). According to Rössler (Reference Rössler2002, 144), “The normatively guiding idea forming the basis of the concept of autonomy is that we, each of us independently, are free and able both to choose and to live the life that will be good for us.” Autonomy loss is clearly stated in the 2007 Venezuelan legislation when defining obstetric violence:

[Obstetric violence is] The appropriation of women’s bodies and reproductive processes by healthcare providers, which is expressed in a hierarchic dehumanizing treatment, an abuse of medicalization, and the pathologization of natural processes, producing a loss of autonomy and free decision-making capacity in women regarding their bodies and sexuality, all of which has a negative impact in their quality of life. (Art. 15.13; emphasis added)

Pregnant people’s loss of autonomy over their bodies hinders their capacity to consent to or deny medical interventions. It contributes to traumatic birth experiences, feelings of disempowerment,Footnote 4 loneliness, lack of recognition, and detachment from those attending their labor (Urrea-Mora Reference Urrea-Mora2014; Cohen Shabot Reference Cohen Shabot2016; Cohen Shabot and Sadler Reference Cohen Shabot and Sadler2023). Additionally, it fuels an extremely paternalistic model of care, characterized by accepting Western biomedicine as the authoritative knowledge during childbirth (Jordan Reference Jordan1983). Authoritative knowledge “helps to explain how the disempowerment and objectification of pregnant people creates a culture of silence, which ultimately dissuades individuals and their partners from engaging in active decision-making during childbirth” (Cantor Reference Cantor2023, 164). Medical authoritative knowledge directly targets the informed consent process and patients’ autonomy about their care.

In response to the structural conditions of a health system that re/produces unequal power relationships and coercive decision-making, Western bioethicists proposed a patient-centered model of care emphasizing individual autonomy as the primary—sometimes even exclusive—ethical principle to guide medical decisions (Rybak Reference Rybak2009; Mapes et al. Reference Mapes, DePergola and McGee2020). Beauchamp and Childress (Reference Beauchamp and Childress1994) initially proposed individual autonomy as one of four principles of common morality in biomedical ethics, along with beneficence, nonmaleficence, and justice. For these authors, individual autonomy in healthcare is a universal, reflexive “autonomous choice” process that allows people to make informed, intentional, and rational decisions. Beauchamp and Childress (Reference Beauchamp and Childress1994) defined autonomy as a capacity and liberty that health providers should consider along with the other three principles in their praxis and research (Cudney Reference Cudney2014; Flanigan Reference Flanigan2016). Despite the relevance of individual autonomy in healthcare, the traditional bioethical approach has been highly criticized for its pretended universality. This model often ignores structural hierarchies, sociocultural differences, and relationships mediating decision-making (Turner Reference Turner2009; Banerjee Reference Banerjee2022).

In this article, I critique the liberal bioethical framework of individual autonomy applied to obstetric settings because it ignores the relational nature of childbirth—and healthcare in general. I argue that individual autonomy is necessary but not sufficient for legitimately consenting to obstetric care and preventing violence. This does not mean that relationality should just be introduced into the concept of autonomy as an inherent aspect of it. Instead, I stress that autonomy, even during relational contexts, is reached only when someone “is able to decide about the relational context of action itself—to decide with whom and in what relationships she wants to live, which obligations she is willing to accept, and which personal projects she wishes to pursue” (Rössler Reference Rössler2002, 148). Childbirth is one of those relational contexts. It is a biosocial event that includes interactions between the pregnant person, their baby, and a group of health professionals, birth attendants, partners, and family members (Osamor and Grady Reference Osamor and Grady2016). I argue that, in addition to individual autonomy, we must address autonomy in relation to the cultural context and its multiple actors during obstetric decision-making and care.

Unfortunately, the exercise of both individual and relational autonomy have multiple structural barriers in common. Some of these problems include racism, sexism, poverty, incarceration, lower education, and power differentials that constrain obstetric patients and their families from providing free, informed consent about their care. To tackle these barriers, I highlight the role of birth advocates like midwives and doulas, who often serve as bridges between biomedical-oriented health professionals and pregnant/birthing people needing care. In addition to other structural changes required for a “deeply humanistic” model of birth (Davis-Floyd Reference Davis-Floyd1992, Reference Davis-Floyd2008), doulas and midwives can help nurture autonomy and caregiving skills (Bhandary Reference Bhandary2020) in obstetric patients and health providers. This strategy protects the informed consent process, prevents obstetric violence, and can be an effective way to recenter childbirth experiences in pregnant people and their families.

To develop my argument, I analyze the definition of informed consent proposed by the American College of Obstetricians and Gynecologists (ACOG) and review some causes of mistrust felt by pregnant and birthing people. I explain how testimonial injustice (Fricker Reference Fricker2007) leads to an extremely paternalistic model of care and reinforces medical authoritative knowledge. Then, I expand on the definition of individual autonomy proposed by medical bioethics, highlight its limitations, and criticize the expected archetype of the “Reasonable Mother” resulting from it. I call for advancing upon a definition and inclusion of relational autonomy in obstetric settings following the work of philosophers, anthropologists, and bioethicists applying relational autonomy to similar health contexts. Aligned with an intersectional feminist approach (Crenshaw Reference Crenshaw1991), I expose some structural conditions affecting the informed consent process. These barriers manipulate individual and relational autonomy and open the door for obstetric violence (i.e., obstetric racism, socioeconomic disparities, and legal coercion). Finally, I address the need for a structural reform of the model of birth and the inclusion of doulas and midwives in the healthcare team. I propose that these birth workers can help nurture the autonomy and caregiving skills presented by Bhandary (Reference Bhandary2016, Reference Bhandary2020) in her Theory of Liberal Dependency Care. Autonomy and caregiving skills are fundamental to ensuring just obstetric care and protecting the informed consent process of pregnant/birthing people and their families.

2. Informed consent and “unreliable” obstetric patients

According to ACOG (2021), “the goal of the informed consent process is to provide patients with information that is necessary and relevant to their decision making … and to assist patients in identifying the best course of action for their medical care” (e34). Usually, informed consent takes the form of a physical document signed before the patient undergoes any treatment. However, a signed document “does not guarantee that the patient’s values and priorities have been taken into consideration in a meaningful way and that the ethical requirements of informed consent have been met” (ACOG 2021, e34). Informed consent requires a conversation between health providers and patients to develop trust and respect, which ultimately aims to provide good care (Flanigan Reference Flanigan2016). Obtaining the patient’s signature on a document, often difficult to understand due to medical and legal terminology, should not be considered proper informed consent (Martín-Badia et al. Reference Martín-Badia, Obregón-Gutiérrez and Goberna-Tricas2021). These documents might work as legal evidence to protect the institution during lawsuits. However, they rarely demonstrate that health providers followed the ethical procedures required for obtaining patients’ informed consent about their care.

Informed consent is supposed to be a patient-centered, individualized, and continued processFootnote 5 that includes all risks and benefits of the available treatment options and respects the patient’s values and priorities (ACOG 2021). Ultimately, the consent process should look at patients’ self-determination, ideally reaching a consensus between the patient and provider about the most reasonable treatment plan. In other words, it is a “mutual sharing of information between the clinician and patient to facilitate the patient’s active engagement in their treatment” (Campbell Reference Campbell2021, 66). If a health provider fails to obtain informed consent before a medical procedure, the patient may have a valid malpractice claim for any harm related to the procedure (Mann Reference Mann2004). Malpractice—failing to provide a proper standard of care resulting in patient harm—is one of the most common legal claims confronting the medical field. Notably, the doula community has popularized the BRAIN acronym for making informed decisions during childbirth. BRAIN stands for benefits, risks, alternatives, intuition, + nothing (Doula to Others 2018). With this tool, doulas teach patients and their families to explore the benefits, risks, and alternatives of each procedure with their providers. It encourages people to listen to their intuition and ultimately make the best choice for their situation, which can be doing nothing, waiting, or moving forward (Doula to Others 2018).

The doctrine of informed consent, as presented above, shifted throughout the twentieth century (Campbell Reference Campbell2021). First, it relied on a physician-based standard, which focused on the decision-making process from the perspective of the “reasonable medical practitioner” and their scientific standards. Under this model, patients presumed physicians knew what was best for them. Doctors were assumed to be unbiased and objective, with the expertise to make healthcare decisions for their patients. Later, bioethicists criticized this approach for its “excessive paternalism,” the lack of patient agency, and the immunity it granted to physicians during legal trials despite their malpractice. Eventually, lawmakers in the United States changed their perspective on consent by demanding health professionals provide their patients with all the information needed to make informed choices. Instead of passive receptors of care, patients were now considered “reasonable subjects” with the capacity to decide for themselves (Campbell Reference Campbell2021). In specific life-altering procedures, such as sterilization and end-of-life treatment, the informed consent process became more rigorous, in some cases requiring a mandatory waiting period before the consent is valid.Footnote 6

For legal purposes, most adult patients are presumed to have autonomous decision-making, which gives them the right to accept or refuse medical treatment (ACOG 2021). The exception to this rule is when a health professional determines “mental incompetence” in their patient, a strongly ableist category that scholars on neurodivergence and disability have criticized. Under “mental incompetence”—sometimes referred to in the past as feeblemindedness—people have been confined, devaluated, and excluded from moral and political theories, denying their capacity for individual autonomy, a chief marker of moral personhood (Davy Reference Davy2015; Lira Reference Lira2022; Di Giulio Reference Di Giulio2024). Despite these critiques, the doctrine of informed consent in healthcare still relies on the assessment of “mentally competent reasonable patients,” a category that does not apply to children, unconscious or intoxicated patients, or people with some mental disabilities, all assumed incapable of providing meaningful consent (Flanigan Reference Flanigan2016).

Surprisingly, health personnel often count birthing people as another group incapable of providing rational consent, and there are historical explanations for this mistrust. Villarmea (Reference Villarmea2021) says that physicians have fallaciously assumed that women are irrational, extremely sensitive, and emotional since the notion of the migratory uterus appeared in texts of ancient Egyptians. The misconception of a “wandering womb” that moves freely through the body, generating disease and unpredictable behavior, connects to the idea of wombs as animals present in Plato’s Timaeus: “The womb is an animal which longs to generate children” (cited in Villarmea Reference Villarmea2021, 38). The myth of the migratory uterus persisted for centuries in European academic medicine, serving as an etiology (the cause of a disease) for emotional volubility and imagined disorders like “hysteria.” We may think that modern medicine is far from such bizarre myths. However, “the pervasive construction of the uterus as an element that renders women wild, uncontrollable, and irrational continues to influence contemporary obstetrics” (Villarmea Reference Villarmea2021, 22).Footnote 7

The persistent notion that wombs govern people’s behavior has led healthcare workers to assume that women, and especially pregnant/birthing people, are not responsible for their actions, have no discernment capacities, and their emotional fluctuations make them incapable of making rational decisions. There is a persistent erroneous perception that people with a uterus cannot fulfill the requirements of “reasonable patients” and, therefore, cannot provide informed consent about their care. Living proof of this misconception is when health personnel infantilize obstetric patients and treat them as victims of pathological conditions requiring intervention (Vallana-Sala Reference Vallana-Sala2019). Instead of physiological processes, pregnancy and childbirth are seen as moments in patients’ lives where the uterus “takes control of the entire body,” and people’s actions become irrational (Villarmea Reference Villarmea2021). This sustained mental deficiency fallacy has not only produced medical violence but has also been used to deny women access to citizenship, their right to vote, and their autonomy for deciding about their bodies (Villarmea Reference Villarmea2021).

Additionally, some health providers working in maternity care erroneously believe that their patients are incompetent to provide informed consent because of the physiological and psychological changes occurring during pregnancy. “For decades, the concept of ‘mommy brain’ (also referred to as baby brain, mom brain, momnesia, and pregnancy brain) has permeated what it is to be a mother” (McCormack et al. Reference McCormack, Callaghan and Pawluski2023, 335). “Mommy brain” refers to a supposed memory deficit and impaired mental capacity that manifests during pregnancy and postpartum. This idea is not only scientifically inaccurate but hides the positive adaptations that emerge in parental brains, including caregiving expertise and better emotional regulation (McCormack et al. Reference McCormack, Callaghan and Pawluski2023, 335). Parents experience a neurologic developmental period known as “matrescence,” which is similar to the morphological brain modifications that occur in adolescence. While “mommy brain” denotes brain dysfunction, “matrescence” speaks of neuroplasticity and adaptation to new life demands. “The term matrescence, the process of becoming a mother, was first coined by the anthropologist Dana Raphael [1973], and later expanded by Aurélie Athan [2016] to include ‘a developmental passage where a woman transitions, through pre-conception, pregnancy and birth, surrogacy, or adoption to the postnatal period and beyond’” (Orchard et al. Reference Orchard, Rutherford, Holmes and Jamadar2023, 303). Davis-Floyd (Reference Davis-Floyd1992) attributes the term to the midwife and professor Denis Walsh (Reference Walsh2006). Importantly, “matrescence” (later known as “external gestation”) is not only a hormonal change but a social and cultural adaptation to parenting.

Some health providers have also used the pain and emotional distress experienced during childbirth as excuses for ignoring informed consent. “Health workers may interpret suffering as a barrier to voluntarism if a patient is seen as making her decision out of desperation rather than her previously held values” (Roberts 2003, cited in Flanigan Reference Flanigan2016, 229). However, empirical research into the effect of pain on deliberative competence shows that, while pain may change a person’s decisions during childbirth, it does not undermine their potential to give informed consent or to know what is better for their overall well-being (Flanigan Reference Flanigan2016). Moreover, ACOG (2016, 2021) has repeatedly stated that neither pregnancy nor childbirth pain are exceptions to consider obstetric patients as rational, capable subjects with the right to accept or refuse treatment for themselves and their fetuses.

Other scholars situate the medical professionals’ belief that birthing people are incapable of giving consent in the high-risk or emergency situation they face during labor, a time when making decisions can be challenging (Hawkins et al. Reference Hawkins, Redley and Holland2011; Flanigan Reference Flanigan2016). The language of risk in obstetric contexts is highly relevant. Obstetricians classify all pregnancies on a risk scale according to their expected outcome, where the safest pregnancy can be is “low risk,” meaning only one baby in cephalic presentationFootnote 8 without additional factors requiring medical intervention. It is true that childbirth always implies some risk and that the active phase of labor (when the cervix dilates from 6 to 10 cm and contractions become stronger and more regular) is not the most optimal scenario for decision-making.Footnote 9 However, the potential or actual risks during any stage of childbirth should not be a reason for health personnel to forcibly perform or deny any procedures on their patients. According to ACOG (2016), obstetricians should follow the informed consent process even during emergencies; otherwise, the pregnant person can experience those procedures as violent or intrusive.

According to Cohen Shabot (Reference Cohen Shabot2016), “childbirth also has a deeply sexual dimension that the medicalized model has almost completely erased: childbirth is a product of pregnancy, itself a product (almost always) of sexual intercourse. Moreover, childbirth (except in Caesarean sections) involves our genitals” (241). The sexual dimension of pregnancy and childbirth is often permeated by health professionals’ patriarchal constructs of feminine sexuality. While female bodies (and those assumed to be female) are interpreted as submissive, passive, non-assertive, and at the service of others, pregnant bodies will continue to be portrayed as available objects open to manipulation and control (Kingma Reference Kingma2021). It is not coincidental that some birthing people describe events of obstetric violence as rape, equating medical abuse to various forms of physical and verbal sexual assault (Kitzinger Reference Kitzinger2006; Cohen Shabot Reference Cohen Shabot2016; Mardorossian Reference Mardorossian2019; Restrepo-Sánchez Reference Restrepo-Sánchez2024). Sexist stereotypes of birthing people may explain, in part, why “the appropriation of women’s bodies” is a crucial part of the definition of obstetric violence (in the Venezuela law of Reference Venezuela2007).

Structural sexism, historical and cultural misconceptions of pregnancy, birth pain, or emergency situations are not valid reasons to invalidate a pregnant/birthing person’s consent. Most pregnant/birthing people meet the “reasonable patient” capacity to “understand information that is relevant to [their] choice, communicate a choice, appreciate the consequences of [their] choice, and compare [their] choice to alternatives” (Appelbaum 2007, cited in Flanigan Reference Flanigan2016, 227). When health providers do not acknowledge that pregnant and birthing people are “reasonable patients,” they are exercising epistemic violence in the form of preemptive testimonial injustice. “Testimonial injustice occurs when prejudice causes a hearer to give a deflated level of credibility to a speaker’s word” (Fricker Reference Fricker2007, 1). Testimonial injustice is a form of patient objectification and constitutes a common form of obstetric violence (De Barros Gabriel and Guimarães Santos Reference De Barros Gabriel and Guimarães Santos2020; Massó Guijarro Reference Guijarro2023), often led by identity prejudice—“a label for prejudices against people qua social type” (Fricker Reference Fricker2007, 4). Other forms of epistemic obstetric violence occur when medical authoritative knowledge excludes pregnant/birthing people from the production of knowledge in medicine, including their participation in clinical research (Bellón Sánchez Reference Bellón Sánchez2014).

3. Individual and relational autonomy during childbirth

Individual autonomy, understood as a person’s sense of self-determination and ability to act on their own values and interests, has been the crucial pillar of the informed consent process in healthcare. However, in addition to “mental incompetence” (explained in the previous section), this principle has other restrictions. Children, for example, have special protections from the moment they are born. Despite being considered incapable of consent, “Courts are generally authorized to make medical decisions in the interest of a child even when the child’s parents disagree” (Dare 2009, cited in Flanigan Reference Flanigan2016, 225). During public health emergencies, governments may impose obligatory quarantines and vaccinations to prevent a contagious person from threatening the lives of others. In both cases, the individual autonomy of some subjects is limited for the perceived benefit of others. In the case of maternal care, should this rationale of protecting someone’s well-being over another’s autonomy apply to unborn infants? According to the US Constitutional Court, fetuses are not covered under the definition of “constitutional personhood” protected by the Fourteenth Amendment (1868). Therefore, pregnant and birthing people in the US should have the right to make individual choices about their health, even if those decisions represent danger for themselves or their fetuses.Footnote 10

In line with this idea, Flanigan (Reference Flanigan2016) argues that obstetricians should only consider the mother’s and not the baby’s autonomy: “Though there are strong moral reasons for women in labor to mitigate the risks to unborn infants, they would not violate anyone’s rights by failing to do so, whereas forced interventions during childbirth would violate the mother’s medical rights” (226) and constitute a form of obstetric violence.Footnote 11 Pregnant people are allowed to make medically inadvisable choices during childbirth, like refusing a C-section that may compromise the fetus’ well-being. Even when these decisions are “morally risky,” they should not justify medical coercion or forced treatments (Flanigan Reference Flanigan2016, 234). The ownership of medical rights by the pregnant/birthing person, and not by the unborn infant, protects patients’ autonomy and rests on the existential and relational constructs of personhood as a state of value (White Reference White2013).

Some paradigms in maternity care rely on the assumption that parents are willing to make sacrifices for their children, so not prioritizing the fetus represents a violation of pregnant people’s autonomy. About this argument, Kingma (Reference Kingma2021) explains that “these presumptions hold true only because, and only insofar as, women, as autonomous agents, take on the value of altruistic maternal sacrifice (to at least some extent), as well as the value of love and care to the degree that another’s pain is one’s own (again at least to some extent)” (461). Parental sacrifice is not a violation of individual autonomy but a reaffirmation of it. Not all parents are willing to risk their health for their unborn children’s well-being. However, for those who prioritize their fetus’s health over their own, their decision is grounded in and is ultimately an expression of individual autonomy.

Other authors have explored the role of individual autonomy in risky situations of reproductive care where morbidity and mortality are higher. Some examples include a patient’s request for vaginal birth in a second pregnancy after a cesarean (Rybak Reference Rybak2009) or the use of assisted reproductive technologies after a renal transplant (Lockwood Reference Lockwood1999). In these situations, it is important to ensure a more thoughtful informed consent process, emphasizing evidence-based recommendations and additional advice from medical academic committees. However, despite the increased risk, medical personnel should not violate patients’ individual autonomy over their bodies. This would result in malpractice and reproductive violence. “The experience of non-consensual medical intervention is often extremely traumatic for patients” (Flanigan Reference Flanigan2016, 233). Moreover, it has been widely documented that people who experience traumatic births and other forms of medical violence have a higher risk of post-traumatic stress disorder and postpartum depression symptoms (Olza Reference Olza2013; Junqueira et al. Reference Junqueira, Rattner and Bauermann2017; Martinez et al. Reference Martinez, Rodríguez, Hernández and Miguel Martínez2021).

Western cultures often equate individual autonomy with independence, self-sufficiency, and self-directedness, characteristics of the Cartesian ideal of a rational man (Osamor and Grady Reference Osamor and Grady2016). The current emphasis on individual autonomy in healthcare exalts self-determination and self-government, core principles of Western democracies, and “neoliberal philosophies and policies that emphasize individual responsibility and ‘choice’” (Rajtar Reference Rajtar2018, 185). Individual autonomy operates under the paradigm of patients being autonomous, reasonable individuals, detached from cultural factors that could potentially bias their decisions. Applied to maternal care, the “Reasonable Mother” emerges as the archetypical subject in the neoliberal obstetric establishment. The Reasonable Mother complies with the expectation of obstetric patients exercising their individual autonomy in isolation, making rational decisions about themselves and their babies without the influence of their context and culture. A Reasonable Mother accepts medical authoritative knowledge (Jordan Reference Jordan2023), engrains herself in the technocratic model of birth (Davis-Floyd Reference Davis-Floyd1992), and, consequently, becomes the perfect victim for symbolic, epistemic, and obstetric violence (Bourdieu and Wacquant Reference Bourdieu and Wacquant1992; Fricker Reference Fricker2007; Cohen Shabot Reference Cohen Shabot2021b; Castro and Frías Reference Castro and Frías2022).

The Reasonable Mother is only one phase of the “modern woman” expected from liberal societies (Van Hollen Reference Van Hollen2003). This relentless subject exculpates the institutions of patriarchal capitalism, blames other women for their disadvantaged positions, exercises intense surveillance over other bodies, and constantly calls for endless work on the self, centering the notions of empowerment and choice (Rottenberg et al. 2020, cited in Darling Reference Darling2022). For a Reasonable Mother, womanhood and motherhood are often inseparable; thus, she engages in “body projects” of intensive self-regulation, self-transformation, and the disavowal of any aspects of embodiment that are non-compliant with the values of containment and optimization (Darling Reference Darling2022). Sometimes, the structural demands for performing “good motherhood” translate into violence in the delivery room, with “gendered shame” playing a crucial role in reifying laboring women mainly as mothers-to-be (Cohen Shabot and Korem Reference Cohen Shabot and Korem2018).

Individual autonomy also plays a central role in the discourse of white liberal feminists fighting for reproductive rights, with the “pro-choice” movement as a remarkable example. Generally, people who identify as “pro-choice” believe in their right to control their own bodies, including their capacity to decide when and whether to have children. In contrast, people who want abortion to be illegal and inaccessible—often using conservative Christian rhetoric to support their views—self-identify as “pro-life.” In many scenarios, these are considered outdated terms: “‘Pro-choice’ and ‘pro-life’ labels don’t reflect the complexity of how most people actually think and feel about abortion. Some people and organizations, including Planned Parenthood, don’t use these terms anymore” (Planned Parenthood 2024, para. 5). The Reproductive Justice Movement, as described by Loretta Ross and Rickie Solinger, “refuses the logic of individual choice. It clarifies how one’s health, sovereignty, and capacity for family formation are intimately entwined with the broader social, political, and cultural landscape” (Murillo and Fixmer-Oraiz Reference Murillo and Fixmer-Oraiz2021, 762). The problem with individual autonomy, as reproductive justice scholars have constantly argued, is that it ignores that people make reproductive choices in contexts influenced by power dynamics and shaped by cultural values, beliefs, norms, and traditions.

Autonomy is instrumentally essential for decision-making about care seeking, utilization of services, and choosing or declining treatment options. However, while individual autonomy is crucial, more is needed to understand the consent process in obstetric settings. Giving birth is a communal experience that includes (at least) the pregnant person and their baby and (often) a group of health professionals, family members, and birth workers. The social dimension of childbirth influences decision-making, inviting us to problematize the autonomous, Reasonable Mother archetype. Critiques of the liberal individual autonomy model propose that autonomy is a multidimensional process connected to different aspects of social life. People rarely make their healthcare decisions in isolation. Cultural models of health and disease, community rules, and care providers’ advice influence our decisions (Shih et al. Reference Shih, Rapport, Hogden, Bierbaum, Hsu, Boyages and Braithwaite2018). Furthermore, relationships of interdependence, such as friendship, kinship, love, care, and obligation, play a preponderant role in health choices, including the ones taken during childbirth (Gammeltoft Reference Gammeltoft2008; Osamor and Grady Reference Osamor and Grady2016).

Under the framework of relational autonomy, people make decisions with and supported by others, and their goals are usually mixed up with the decisions of others (Cohen Shabot Reference Cohen Shabot2020). The relational here is not limited to intimate relationships among people but to interconnected relationships with institutional structures, law, civil society, and multiple religious and secular discursive traditions (Nedelsky Reference Nedelsky2011, Dokumacl Reference Dokumacl2020). The idea of relational autonomy has roots in early feminist accounts of womanhood, as we can read in the description of de Beauvoir’s carnal subject, a being never isolated nor purely mental: “De Beauvoir’s subject [in contrast to the Cartesian subject] is ambiguous in that it is always situated, particularly embodied, located in a concrete time and place, and thus singularly itself—but also always carnally open and reaching out, and thus more than (only) itself” (Cohen Shabot Reference Cohen Shabot2020, 7). Herring (Reference Herring2014) offers us a rich and compelling feminist study of the relational self—versus the individual self—and states that relational autonomy challenges the traditional conception of individual autonomy, which is built on a patriarchal liberal conception of the subject (Cohen Shabot Reference Cohen Shabot2020).

Mackenzie and Stoljar (Reference Mackenzie and Stoljar2000) developed a rich anthology of contemporary feminist theories of agency. These authors critique the notions of individualism and retheorize autonomy as compatible with social interdependency. To explain their theoretical move, Mackenzie and Stoljar (Reference Mackenzie and Stoljar2000) distinguish between procedural and substantive accounts of autonomy. The procedural accounts relate to individual autonomy, which relies upon rational reflection and the agent’s independence of their beliefs, attitudes, desires, and values. Procedural autonomy is “content-neutral,” disconnected from interdependent relations and cultural contexts. In contrast, substantive accounts of autonomy are connected to our desires, beliefs, and values, which cannot be separated from internalized oppressive structures and societal norms (Mackenzie and Stoljar Reference Mackenzie and Stoljar2000). Therefore, substantive—and not merely procedural—accounts of autonomy matter for understanding how people’s autonomy works under oppression.

Oshana (Reference Oshana2006) provides another essential contribution to theorizing social-relational autonomy. According to this author, we must consider the overall autonomy of a subject instead of their episodically autonomous actions; autonomy requires power and authority, making it impossible for subalternized subjects to be truly autonomous. Being autonomous is to be free from oppressive structures (Oshana Reference Oshana2006). In contrast, Mackenzie and Stoljar (Reference Mackenzie and Stoljar2000) and Bhandary (Reference Bhandary2016) defend the possibility of achieving autonomy, at least to a certain degree, even under oppressive structures. Their perspective highlights agency and the pursuit of freedom as essential aspects of the subaltern’s independence mission. According to MacDonald (Reference MacDonald2010), relational autonomy should conceive external forces to the agent not simply as threats or barricades; it must address dependence as constitutive of autonomy and transform it to allow for interdependent relationships to be balanced with power and agency. When people negotiate between different social features, including their desires, values, available options, and oppressive structures, they exercise “an account of socially embedded agency that is fundamentally and essentially social” (Webster Reference Webster2021, 117). This type of agency is different from shared agency—“which explores what it takes for two or more individuals to act together” (Webster Reference Webster2021, 118)—and it can exist even under circumstances of oppression.

From the ethics of care, Held (Reference Held and Olsaretti2018) states that “human beings [are] vulnerable, dependent, above all interconnected, rather than [resembling] the rational, self-sufficient, autonomous individuals of the liberal traditions on which our reigning models of law and politics, and the moralities that expand them, are built” (231). A relational conception of the self closely connects care ethics with relational autonomy (Keller Reference Keller1997). Interestingly, Bhandary (Reference Bhandary2016), a liberal care ethicist, rejects the concept of “bare autonomy” present in the liberal theory of Hume and Rawls, pointing out that “people’s current choices arise from a cultural context with forms of prescriptive socialization that make choices within these cultures autonomous in only a very minimal sense” (54). For Bhandary (Reference Bhandary2016), “choices are made in specific contexts that are personal, familial, social, political, cultural, and temporal, and they are shaped by the availability of options and by our conceptualizations of those options” (55), which aligns with the principles of relational autonomy.

Researchers have analyzed relational autonomy and its limitations in the decision-making process of multiple health situations. Some of the cases include refusing blood transfusions by Jehovah’s Witnesses (Rajtar Reference Rajtar2018), chemotherapy options for breast cancer patients (Shih et al. Reference Shih, Rapport, Hogden, Bierbaum, Hsu, Boyages and Braithwaite2018), and palliative care guidelines in critically ill patients in the intensive care unit (Mapes et al. Reference Mapes, DePergola and McGee2020). One of the studies that examined relational autonomy in gynecological and obstetric settings was developed by Kaplan et al. (Reference Kaplan, Kandodo, Sclafani, Raine, Norris, Chemey, Khan and Chunda2017). The authors associated the limited autonomy of rural Malawi women with their increased risk of developing obstetric fistula after birth. During interviews, Kaplan et al. found that the “last word” on labor and delivery resided in the husband’s authority. Men often sought the advice of the elderly women in the village and prioritized their opinions over those of their wives and the doctors providing antenatal care. This study illustrates the multiple actors involved in reproductive decision-making and how relational autonomy could harm individual autonomy and birth outcomes. However, Kaplan et al. (Reference Kaplan, Kandodo, Sclafani, Raine, Norris, Chemey, Khan and Chunda2017) also found that young women in Malawi were not passive victims; they had subversive ways of expressing their reproductive autonomy, for example, secretly using contraception without informing their husbands.

Relational autonomy is particularly relevant during obstetric care, and its violation can be considered a form of obstetric violence. According to Cohen Shabot (Reference Cohen Shabot2020), “cutting the original links to our bodies and the world that constitute our phenomenological condition” (1) is a form of obstetric violence. Women and birthing people not only suffer in their physical bodies. In addition, health personnel often exclude partners, birth advocates, and support networks from the birthing rooms (Cohen Shabot Reference Cohen Shabot2020). This practice damages “the social, communal character of childbirth … [increasing] vulnerability, banning support and demolishing relationships and interdependence between laboring women and their significant others during childbirth” (Cohen Shabot Reference Cohen Shabot2020, 2). Feelings of isolation and abandonment are common among birthing people in institutionalized environments with strict protocols for patient visits. Unsurprisingly, the protocols and restrictions established during the COVID-19 pandemic, some of which are still in place, have dramatically increased the number of situations involving giving birth in isolation (Hussein Reference Hussein2020; Sadler et al. Reference Sadler, Leiva and Olza2020).

With the normalization of authoritative knowledge and the medicalization of birth in Western societies (Davis-Floyd and Cheyney Reference Davis-Floyd and Cheyney2019; Sargent and Davis-Floyd Reference Sargent and Davis-Floyd2023), some health professionals may be afraid to cede ground to family members or other birth attendants because this could affect their autonomy. Decreased professional autonomy is defined as a lowered decision-making level, decreased job status, or inability to voice their professional opinion in the workplace. As de Jonge (1998) explains, “Job autonomy is of high importance as it protects healthcare professionals against somatic complaints, psychological distress in their work, and burnout” (cited in Perdok et al. Reference Perdok, Cronie, Schellevis and Verhoeven2017, 68). However, literature shows that good collaboration in maternity care between professionals, patients, and family members enhances the value of relational consent and improves the quality of care, job-related well-being, and satisfaction for health personnel (Perdok et al. Reference Perdok, Cronie, Schellevis and Verhoeven2017). A support network during childbirth enhances pregnant people’s capacity to be autonomous, evaluate options, and make better decisions while promoting better working conditions for health providers (Hunt and Ells Reference Hunt and Ells2011; Shih et al. Reference Shih, Rapport, Hogden, Bierbaum, Hsu, Boyages and Braithwaite2018).

Structural conditions can affect both individual and relational autonomy. Multiple situations distort the informed consent process, constraining a pregnant/birthing person’s autonomy and increasing adverse health outcomes. These circumstances constitute what Campbell (Reference Campbell2021) calls an “informed consent gap,” a disjuncture between patient-centered care, the law in practice, and the healthcare delivery system. Many structural barriers increase the informed consent gap and reproduce structural violence in the health system (Galtung Reference Galtung1969; Farmer Reference Farmer2004). Despite not being exclusive to gynecological and obstetric care, I review three of these barriers (i.e., racism, socioeconomic disparities, and legal coercion) to understand better the structural challenges that pregnant/birthing people and their families navigate in the health system. These barriers should be understood as “interlocking systems of oppression,” as proposed by the Combahee River Collective (in Moraga and Anzaldúa Reference Moraga and Anzaldúa2015), or as intersectional dynamics of inequality with multiplicative effects (Crenshaw Reference Crenshaw1991).

In Reproductive injustice, Davis (Reference Davis, Rivkin-Fish, Brodwin and Shaw2019) exposed the precarious situation of Black mothers in the US health system. She attributed this fact to “obstetric racism,” explaining that Black women had far worse outcomes in maternal mortality and morbidity than their white counterparts, even in similar socioeconomic statuses. For Davis (Reference Davis, Rivkin-Fish, Brodwin and Shaw2019), racism works when health personnel dehumanize Black bodies by denying their pain or believing they have a higher pain threshold, a misconception with roots in the American history of chattel slavery. The relationship between Black bodies and pain resistance is an arbitrary assessment that often justifies medical and pharmacological treatment delays (Davis Reference Davis2018). Health providers can influence patients’ decisions with their racial prejudices about what some bodies need (like a higher/lower dose of analgesics during childbirth), even without making explicit recommendations about it (Campbell Reference Campbell2021). Obstetric racism is part of a medical continuum of violence that historically has used the pseudoscience of eugenics and social Darwinism to exploit Black bodies for medical experimentation, unauthorized autopsies, and even grave robbing (Washington Reference Washington2008). Importantly, the experiences of pregnancy and birth of Black and other Women of Color “are shaped not simply by violence and coercion by patriarchal institutions but also by the multifaceted ways in which gender interacts with interlocking systems of race, class, age, ability, sexuality, and nation” (Chinyere Oparah and Bonaparte Reference Chinyere Oparah and Bonaparte2016).

Socioeconomic conditions also affect pregnant and birthing people’s autonomy and consent. In a literature review about women’s autonomy in “low-income countries,” Osamor and Grady (Reference Osamor and Grady2016, 191) found that “many such societies still have strong social structures that rigidly define the roles of men and women, usually encoded in religious, tribal, and social traditions.” It is crucial to acknowledge that “low income” indicates a country’s location in the global economy, often due to legacies of colonialism. Socioeconomic conditions are highly influenced by structures of oppression such as racism, ageism, colonialism, ableism, and cis-heterosexism, all of which are correlated and directly influence women’s autonomy (Kaplan et al. Reference Kaplan, Kandodo, Sclafani, Raine, Norris, Chemey, Khan and Chunda2017). Low income does not have a causal relationship with patriarchy or conservative cultural traditions. Still, one cannot freely opt for the “best maternal care” within a health system facing precarious economic conditions, including a lack of resources and personnel. More qualitative studies should be developed to improve the instruments that assess autonomy in precarious contexts, especially being careful not to reproduce the narrative of the “trapped/poor women without agency” in the Global South.Footnote 12

The surveillance of the legal system over healthcare creates additional problems for people’s autonomy. In rare cases when a pregnant person’s medical choices threaten to endanger her unborn child’s life or health, courts have demanded the performance of C-sections, forced hospital detentions, and other intrauterine procedures against the person’s will (Flanigan Reference Flanigan2016). This legal practice violates the patient’s individual autonomy, personhood, medical rights, and even the autonomy of the health professional forced to perform the procedure. Some studies in the US have also documented that lawsuits for negligence and malpractice are typical strategies patients use to gain large amounts of money in different health situations (Mann Reference Mann2004). As a response, some obstetricians have opted for “defensive medicine,” which often implies manipulating their patients’ decisions to choose what they consider the less risky situation. Defensive obstetric care is one of the explanations for the high rate of C-sections worldwide (Mann Reference Mann2004) and the perpetuation of unnecessary procedures, such as routine episiotomies, prolonged fasting, and limitation of movement without medical justification.

Among many other structural barriers, racism, economic inequality, and defensive medicine due to legal surveillance negatively impact people’s individual and relational autonomy, manipulate the decision-making process, and increase the informed consent gap. In the last section, I propose a strategy to counter some of the problems present during obstetric informed consent. I follow Bhandary’s (Reference Bhandary2020) suggestion to cultivate autonomy and caregiving skills and apply them to the informed consent process of pregnant and birthing people. The proposal highlights the role of doulas and midwives in transforming the technocratic model of birth into a humanistic one (Davis-Floyd Reference Davis-Floyd1992). Implemented with other structural changes, autonomy and caregiving skills are crucial to achieving more satisfactory and just care.

4. Autonomy and caregiving skills: towards a humanistic model of birth and informed consent

Foundational feminist and anthropological work on birth and reproduction has demonstrated that birth is shaped by its geographical and historical contexts. The birth model reflects systems of knowing, beliefs, and practices of the community, often reproducing existing power relations (Kay Reference Kay1982; Jordan Reference Jordan1983; Ginsburg and Rapp Reference Ginsburg and Rapp1991; Van Hollen Reference Van Hollen1994). With the emergence of modern obstetrics, the knowledge and control over childbirth moved from midwives to specialized doctors, confining obstetric care to the hospital walls (Wertz and Wertz Reference Wertz and Wertz1977; Ehrenreich and English Reference Ehrenreich and English1973; Gopal Reference Gopal2017; Basile Reference Basile2019). The resulting model of birth was based on vigilance and interventionism over patients’ bodies, normalizing routinary painful technologies like forceps and vacuum extractions (Davis-Floyd Reference Davis-Floyd1992; Martin Reference Martin1987; Van Hollen Reference Van Hollen2003; Inhorn Reference Inhorn2009).

In Birth as an American rite of passage, Davis-Floyd (Reference Davis-Floyd1992) describes the different Western birth models that became popular in the transition of childbirth from home to hospital: “The industrial model of birth and its successor, the technocratic model, metaphorize and conceptualize the human body as a machine and treat it as such” (60). In these models, “the female body has long been viewed as an abnormal, unpredictable, and inherently defective machine” (Davis-Floyd Reference Davis-Floyd1992, 61), and the woman’s reproductive tract is treated like a birthing apparatus that doctors can control and manipulate. According to Davis-Floyd (Reference Davis-Floyd1992), the technocratic model of birth and healthcare has 12 tenets, including mind-body separation, objectification of the patient, alienation of practitioners from their patients, and standardization and hierarchical organization of care. Of special interest for this paper is the seventh tenet: the authority and responsibility are inherent in the practitioner, not the patient (Davis-Floyd Reference Davis-Floyd1992, 73). In the technocratic model of birth, physicians and institutions hold the power, and when this happens, the patient lacks agency.

Davis-Floyd (Reference Davis-Floyd1992) also explains that, since the emergence of humanism as an ideology in the 1970s, some nurses and physicians have made efforts to humanize technomedicine, leading the way to a new model of birth. The humanistic model follows evidence-based medicine—“the conscientious, explicit and judicious use of current best evidence in making decisions about the care of individual patients” (Sackett et al. in Davis-Floyd Reference Davis-Floyd1992, 78). Some of the tenets of this model include the mind-body connection, the patient as a relational subject, a focus on disease prevention, and the information, decision-making, and responsibility shared between patient and practitioner (Davis-Floyd Reference Davis-Floyd1992). In a deeply humanistic model of birth, the doctrine of informed choice is a fundamental pillar for any medical intervention. Midwives, community health workers, and doulas have been crucial in transforming the technocratic model of birth into a humanistic one, but there is still much to be done.

As many pregnant people still give birth in a technocratic model of healthcare, finding others who can advocate for their rights, provide emotional and physical support, and ensure their individual and relational autonomy is vital. This is where midwives and doulas become key allies for pregnant/birthing people and their families (Doenmez et al. Reference Doenmez, Jaime Cidro, Hayward, Wodtke and Nychuk2022; Salinas et al. Reference Salinas, Salinas and Kahn2022). According to Ford (Reference Ford2021), doulas are “supplementary providers who play a key role in improving maternity care” (114). They are people trained to provide nonmedical physical, emotional, and informational support during pregnancy, childbirth, and postpartum. In contrast to midwives, physicians, or nurses, a doula’s presence during labor and birth is continuous and uninterrupted (Basile Reference Basile2019). One of the main objectives of doulas is to rehumanize the birth experience, acting as kind and compassionate caregivers (Mahoney and Mitchell Reference Mahoney and Mitchell2017). Both doulas and midwives recenter the knowledge of birthing people and help them to advocate for their bodily autonomy in institutional settings. These workers disrupt the biomedical authoritative knowledge, privilege connection, and place value and priority on the everyday nonmedical bodily knowledge, intuition, and experiences of birthing people (Davis-Floyd and Davis Reference Davis-Floyd and Davis1996; Basile Reference Basile2019).

Radical doulas and radical midwives are a subgroup within the birth movement that draws on several perspectives of reproductive justice and third-wave feminism: intersectional theory, postmodernist, and postcolonial feminism, celebrating the multiplicity and contradiction of youth culture activism (Basile Reference Basile2019). Radical doulas “serve as a bridge between the political act of care and the legal practice of consent. In many ways, they ‘translate’ between these, helping clients discover their capabilities and desires and then acting as clients’ ‘voice,’ advocating for their interests, and mediating consent” (Ford Reference Ford2021, 118). The bridging role of doulas and midwives is similar to that of HIV/AIDS educators and rehabilitation counselors in health systems across the world (Chiu et al. Reference Chiu, Boomer and Conyers2019) or the mediation that rape advocates perform during forensic nursing investigations (Mulla Reference Mulla2014). All these supporting figures ultimately defend patients’ rights and interests in healthcare settings, fighting against institutional barriers, medical violence, and other forms of mistreatment and abuse.

Importantly, not only midwives and doulas work towards a humanized model of birth. Rodrigues Duarte et al. (Reference Rodrigues Duarte, Rosário Soanno Marchiori, Vidal Vieira Guerra and Machado Pimentel2020) explored the role of obstetric nurses working under a woman-centered care approach, protecting the relational autonomy of patients during childbirth. Their study showed that nurses’ performance was “based on practices that respected the physiology of childbirth, such as welcoming, physical and emotional support to the parturient woman,Footnote 13 stimulating non-invasive and non-pharmacological pain relief practices … and encouraging the companion of the woman’s choice” (907). Their actions resulted in a better quality of care, a reduction in episiotomies, and fewer instrumental deliveries. Davis-Floyd and Premkumar (Reference Davis-Floyd and Premkumar2023) also showed that some obstetricians globally have shifted from technocratic to humanistic practices, opening the path for “deeply humanistic” models in countries like Brazil, India, Hungary, Canada, and Turkey. However, none of these figures should be seen as inherently good caregivers. Fraser (Reference Fraser1998) showed that midwives—and I would add, other “superficial humanist” birth workers (Davis-Floyd and Premkumar (Reference Davis-Floyd and Premkumar2023)—could also reproduce medical power structures, perpetuate white racial purity ideas, and suffer from the oppressive actions of state agents that dismiss their authority.

Despite the coercive nature of birth workers’ regulation by the medical establishment, doulas, midwives, and other humanistic health workers can make an important difference in pivoting towards a humanistic model of birth. One plausible strategy consists of deeply humanistic workers nurturing autonomy skills in pregnant/birthing people and caregiving skills in health providers who still work under technocracy. According to Bhandary (Reference Bhandary2020), “liberal dependency care requires that existing societies support the cultivation of autonomy capacities, or skills” (97). Society must intend to achieve a high level of autonomy and caregiving skills throughout the population as a matter of justice “because they are a precondition for the veracity of judgments about justice” (98). These skills are also fundamental to function as a society, safeguard us against oppressive structures, and provide dependency care, which is “direct care that must be provided by a care-giver to the person needing care (the charge) for the continued survival of the charge” (Bhandary Reference Bhandary2016, 43). All human beings require dependency care to survive during the first years of life, and many people benefit from it when they experience any disease, temporary injury, or permanent physical or mental disability (Bhandary Reference Bhandary2016). I consider that people during pregnancy, labor, and postpartum benefit from dependency care.

Bhandary adapted her set of autonomy skills from the feminist autonomy theory of Diana Tietjens Meyers (Reference Meyers1989, Reference Meyers2002) and the thought of John Stuart Mill (Reference Mill and Collini1989a–b). From Meyers, Bhandary (Reference Bhandary2020) takes “the skills of communication, introspection, memory, analytical reasoning, imagination, and self-nurturing” (108), and from Mill, the “critical capacities of observation, perceptual parsing, and discriminating among possibilities” (107).Footnote 14 Autonomy skills allow individuals to identify when a policy or practice affects their individuality and decision-making, in addition to “articulate in their own ways who they are and what they value” (Bhandary Reference Bhandary2020, 101). Bhandary’s (Reference Bhandary2020) autonomy skills are “compatible with a wide range of ways of life and personal choices” (104). They do not require that people live in any particular way in their private lives but remain critical enough to protect people against being manipulated by dominant discourses and norms (Bhandary Reference Bhandary2020). Autonomy skills are valuable on many levels and help people make rational decisions about relationships, work, economy, religion, group affiliations, study, and others.

The Meyersian autonomy skills of imagination and self-nurturing are particularly valuable (Bhandary Reference Bhandary2020) for the case presented in this article. Pregnant people can use imaginative skills to envision other possibilities—like a more humanized and respectful model of care during labor—which is crucial for inspiring and developing new laws and clinical protocols. Additionally, self-nurturing enables patients denigrated by the medical establishment to maintain their sense of self-worth, which is generally lost under violent obstetric scenarios, and to regain their physical and psychological equilibrium after facing traumatic birth experiences.

Recognizing and fighting against structural oppressions like the ones mentioned in this article is essential for providing free, informed consent and safeguarding pregnant/birthing people from unconsented, violent medical practices. Structural change is difficult, but autonomy skills can make a positive impact, especially when considering autonomy as choice and action rather than a universal feature and ideal for all people (Westlund Reference Westlund2009). For example, through her autonomy skills, an Indigenous pregnant woman belonging to a community that performs rituals with the placenta could identify that a hospital protocol that discards placentas as biological waste violates her individuality and cultural traditions. She may identify that these protocols are not culturally sensitive and may have a racial bias that coerces people’s decision-making about the final disposition of what was once part of their bodies. Furthermore, she might act by filing a complaint against the hospital, which ultimately can trigger the implementation of a more humanized birth protocol.

Through nurturing autonomy skills in their patients, doulas and midwives can shorten the gap between the objectified passive subject of the technocratic model of birth and the autonomous, relational subject of the humanistic model. Following the example above, the birthing Indigenous woman would probably not manage the language of medical protocols and would require the assistance of someone trained in culturally sensitive care. A doula or midwife in the health team can be the opportunity to advocate for this woman’s communication, capacity of observation, and discrimination among possibilities. Nurturing autonomy does not mean that the humanistic health worker will speak for the pregnant/birthing person, a situation that can easily fall into violent silencing. Instead, they make the patient and their family the center of the care process, reinforcing their individual and relational autonomy to evaluate, consent, or deny any intervention. Ideally, patients and family members should receive reinforcement of autonomy skills during the preconception visit (suggested for planned pregnancies), prenatal controls, and postpartum. The language of this training should be accessible to patients, avoid medical jargon or confusing physiological explanations, and ideally, it should include everyone expected in the delivery room.

Regarding caregiving skills, Bhandary (Reference Bhandary2020) states that “Most people have a natural ability to care, but this ability is differentially cultivated through social expectations, formal training, experience, and apprenticeships” (142). Based on the work of care ethicists like Tronto, Ruddick, Noddings, and Kittay, Bhandary (Reference Bhandary2020) proposes two basic and generalizable caregiving skills necessary for any form of dependency care: attentiveness and responsiveness. “Attentiveness is noticing the needs of the person cared for, which includes a grasp of life from the charge’s point of view, including the charge’s abilities, physical location, and feelings. Varying degrees of empathy are included within the skill of attentiveness” (Bhandary Reference Bhandary2020, 143). Attentiveness requires paying attention to the other person, being receptive, and putting one’s arrogance aside. “Responsiveness is a skill of acting in response to the needs of the dependent person, and it includes a volitional component: the person has to muster the will to act. This skill is functionally secondary to attentiveness, because if a caregiver responds to needs that have been incorrectly grasped, then they will not provide good care” (Bhandary Reference Bhandary2020, 143–44). Under responsiveness, any intervention that the patient has not properly consented, even if coming from the “good intention” of the health team, will not be good care.

As Bhandary (Reference Bhandary2020) recognizes, “Caregiving requires additional skills and knowledge that vary based on the specified activity. Consequently, the skills of responsiveness and attentiveness have to be supplemented by relevant knowledge for the task at hand and corresponding practice-specific skills” (144). Nurses and doctors, for example, require medical knowledge and technical competence to perform procedures, which constitute the base of Western medical/nursing schools. However, to provide humanistic care during childbirth, I argue that health professionals must learn—at least—the caregiving skills of attentiveness and responsiveness. Doulas and midwives are often trained under a different, more holistic/humanistic model of care that already recognizes the relevance of these skills (Davis-Floyd Reference Davis-Floyd1992). Thus, they are essential to teach other health team members the need to develop these additional skills for providing good care.

In her Theory of Liberal Dependency Care, Bhandary (Reference Bhandary2020) proposes that public education must design a curriculum that teaches children basic autonomy and caregiving skills. Developing autonomy and caregiving skills takes time, so this should be a combined effort between school, family, and other institutions. For obstetric settings, I propose that doulas, midwives, and other humanistic birth workers assume the responsibility of reinforcing these skills to pregnant/birthing people, their families, and the rest of the healthcare team. Nurturing autonomy and caregiving skills is a crucial strategy to respect individual and relational autonomy, counter the elevated incidence of obstetric violence, and return the agency of childbirth to pregnant/birthing people and their families. It is a way of moving from the technocratic to a humanistic model of birth.

Following the approach of restorative justice, health professionals working under technocracy have a moral duty to learn caregiving skills and respect their patients’ autonomy. This is a way to repair the harm that the medical establishment has caused to pregnant/birthing people over time. “When put into practice, the restorative process itself can vary considerably, but typically requires bilateral dialog between offender and victim (and sometimes representatives of the affected community) who attempt to find a shared understanding of the harm done and how to recover from it” (Okimoto et al. Reference Okimoto, Konradt, Krys and Dawson2022, 63). Doulas and midwives can be the bridges between health professionals and patients in this restorative justice process of birth model transformation.

Even though autonomy and caregiving skills are valuable resources to battle obstetric violence and protect patients’ autonomy and consent, there are many other strategies that health systems must implement to stop violence and transform the birth model. For example, scholars have proposed a restructuration of the healthcare professions’ curriculum, a revision of the bureaucratic institutional procedures limiting access to health services, and the implementation of birthing teams with decolonial, intersectional, and feminist caregiving approaches (Urrea-Mora Reference Urrea-Mora2014; Diaz-Tello Reference Diaz-Tello2016; Davis Reference Davis2018). I believe that a joint effort of all these strategies can help reduce the cases of traumatic births and increase favorable healthcare experiences for pregnant and birthing people.

In this article, I presented the relationship between autonomy, consent, and violence in obstetric care settings. I explained the relevance of individual and relational autonomy to provide informed consent in healthcare and described some of the structural barriers that manipulate this process, including obstetric racism, socioeconomic disparities, and legal coercion. Finally, I presented the nurturing of autonomy and caregiving skills as a strategy to face obstetric violence and ensure the free exercise of people’s autonomy in the decision-making processes regarding their obstetric health. It is important to address that autonomy, relational or not, has been a powerful ideal in the Western context since the Enlightenment. However, autonomy is not “a universal ideal of human agency that provides the standard by which to judge a person’s status as a full agent and a fortiori his or her deservingness of our respect as an equal” (Herr Reference Herr2018, 208). For non-Western societies that do not embrace autonomy as a hyper-good or that function under alternative models of care, other categories might be more useful (Herr Reference Herr2018).

It is also essential to acknowledge that historical misinterpretation of women’s bodies and their capacity for reasoning continues to influence how health professionals interact with their patients and doubt their judgment. Even though some health personnel interpret the critical moment of birth as an emergency, influenced by pain and cognitive changes during pregnancy, we must remember that ACOG states that pregnancy and labor are not exceptions to the principle of decision in capable patients. Furthermore, “forced compliance [to any medical intervention] raises profoundly important issues about patient rights, respect for autonomy, violations of bodily integrity, power differentials, and gender equality” (ACOG 2016, 1). In other words, any medical intervention performed on a patient without informed consent violates their rights and can be experienced as violent.

Other scholars have explored the causes and consequences of obstetric violence but have paid less attention to the ontological dimensions of autonomy, decision-making, and relationality in healthcare. Through this paper, I have engaged with philosophical and anthropological perspectives on autonomy, theories of care, and bioethics to contribute to the literature on gender and medical violence. Further studies, especially those that explore the meaning of autonomy in different populations and cultures, more accurate ways of measuring it, and good ways of teaching autonomy and caregiving skills are necessary to expand our understanding of this phenomenon. Health personnel working in obstetric care must recenter patient autonomy as a core principle of ethical practice, including the relational, cultural, and contextual aspects of the decision-making process. Recentering autonomy in the informed consent process can be an effective way of preventing obstetric violence.

Acknowledgments

I thank Dr Asha Bhandary for her teaching in the Ethics seminar that originated the first version of this paper, Dr Elana Buch for her revisions and advice, and the anonymous reviewers and editorial team of Hypatia for their insightful suggestions. I acknowledge the economic support of Fulbright Colombia.

Andrés Restrepo-Sánchez is a PhD candidate in Anthropology and teaching assistant at the University of Iowa, USA. He has a BS in Nursing, an MA in Cultural Studies, and an MA in Anthropology. His research interests include feminist approaches to care, violence, reproductive justice, and Colombian history. His dissertation project examines the experiences of obstetric violence and birth reform in Medellín, Antioquia, and their relation to other forms of structural violence in the country and region.

Footnotes

1 I use “pregnant and birthing people” or “person with a uterus” instead of “women” to recognize that other sex/gender subjectivities (i.e., trans men, non-binary, agender, and gender-fluid people) have the capacity to get pregnant but not necessarily self-identify as “women.” In medical literature, it is common to find the use of “women” and “mother” instead of other more inclusive terms. When referring to other author’s work, I maintain their use of categories.

2 Recently, health professionals have contested the use of obstetric violence as a “misnomer” that “can be seen as quite strong and emotionally charged,” suggesting instead the use of “obstetric mistreatment” (Chervenak et al. Reference Chervenak, Pollet, Gordon, Combs, Bornstein, Lewis, Katz, Warman and Grünebaum2024, S1139). However, scholars in Latin America and elsewhere recognize the theoretical and political relevance of naming this problem as a form of gender and sexual violence (Cohen Shabot Reference Cohen Shabot2016; Cohen Shabot and Korem Reference Cohen Shabot and Korem2018). According to Pickles (Reference Pickles2023), the dominant discourse “should not be one formulated by the healthcare sector (as is the case with ‘mistreatment’) given their leading role in abuse and violence during childbirth” (628); instead, we should promote and embrace pregnant/birthing people’s conceptualizations of the phenomenon. Despite its multiple usages, stakes, and contestations, obstetric violence has a niche in the academic and legal literature (Lappeman and Swartz Reference Lappeman and Swartz2021; Lévesque and Ferron-Parayre Reference Lévesque and Ferron-Parayre2021). Like other categories describing particular forms of violence, its transitive nature “needs to be recontextualized to meet the demands of today” (Burnett Reference Burnett2021, 1007), which requires further anthropological, sociological, and phenomenological studies.

3 Events that the 2007 Venezuelan legislation describes as obstetric violence are: “(1) Untimely and ineffective attention of obstetric emergencies; (2) Forcing the woman to give birth in a supine position, with legs raised, when the necessary means to perform a vertical delivery are available; (3) Impeding the early attachment of the child with his/her mother without a medical cause thus preventing the early attachment and blocking the possibility of holding, nursing or breastfeeding immediately after birth; (4) Altering the natural process of low-risk delivery by using acceleration techniques, without obtaining voluntary, expressed and informed consent of the woman; (5) Performing delivery via cesarean section, when natural childbirth is possible, without obtaining voluntary, expressed, and informed consent from the woman” (Art. 51).

4 Other authors have engaged more closely with women dis/empowerment and community resistance in multiple scenarios, which distances from this paper’s emphasis on individual and relational autonomy. For further exploration, I recommend readings on women’s empowerment in contexts of war (Albayrak et al. Reference Albayrak, Cankurtaran, Bahar-Özvarış and Erdost2022), domestic violence (Diallo and Voia Reference Diallo and Voia2016), and disability (Mason Reference Mason2015).

5 Obtaining continuous consent has been emphasized in cases of sexual violence. “Consenting to one activity, one time, does not mean someone gives consent for other activities or for the same activity on other occasions. For example, agreeing to kiss someone doesn’t give that person permission to remove your clothes. Having sex with someone in the past doesn’t give that person permission to have sex with you again in the future.” (RAINN 2024, para. 4). For more on the use of language in cases of sexual assault, see Ehrlich (Reference Ehrlich1998, Reference Ehrlich2001) and Lockwood Harris (Reference Lockwood Harris2018).

6 Some reproductive justice scholars and feminist activists have criticized this compulsory waiting period as a barrier to obtaining basic healthcare services like sterilization or abortion, especially among communities with limited resources and access to health providers. For more on this critique, see Rowlands and Thomas (Reference Rowlands and Thomas2020).

7 Historically, the womb represented a threat not only to people’s rationality but also to the well-being of others, especially the fetus. In Policing pregnant bodies, Crowther (Reference Crowther2023) explains that from the time of Aristotle and Hippocrates, medical and philosophical writers accepted that fetuses were nourished in the womb by their mother’s blood, which was often equated to menstrual blood, believed toxic by the Greeks. Thus, the pregnant body both nourished and poisoned the fetus. Menstruating women were sometimes compared to basilisks (as stated in the text On the nature of things attributed to Paracelsus), and “the notions that menstruating women could cause wine to sour, milk to curdle, and mirrors to become cloudy were integral to both popular and scientific understandings of women’s bodies” (Crowther Reference Crowther2023, 93).

8 This fetal presentation is considered ideal for labor. It consists of the baby positioned head-down, facing the parent’s back, and the head ready to enter the pelvis into the vaginal canal.

9 In an ideal scenario, obstetricians should discuss all the possible outcomes, interventions, benefits, and risks with their patients during prenatal visits. Patients should be encouraged to present a birth plan—a document containing their preferences during labor and delivery. A birth plan has no contractual characteristics with the health provider and may vary according to the patient’s health status. Still, it is a valuable tool for exercising the patient’s autonomy. Midwives, doulas, and other humanistic birth workers strongly advocate for developing birth plans for all pregnant people (Amram et al. Reference Amram, Klein, Mok, Simkin, Lindstrom and Grant2014, Davis-Floyd and Premkumar Reference Davis-Floyd and Premkumar2023).

10 The definition of “personhood” is not universal and depends on each country’s legal system. I use the US legal definition of constitutional personhood for this article, which may change after the Supreme Court’s Dobbs v. Jackson Women’s Health Organization decision.

11 To support her position, Flanigan (Reference Flanigan2016) revisits Thomson’s (Reference Thomson1971) famous thought experiment about the moral status of fetuses in abortion cases. Thompson explains that when the fetus is connected to the mother and depends on her to survive, the decision to separate it from her, even if it dies, can be “indecent” but permissible. For Thompson, the mother maintains the right that her body should not be used as a machine against her will to sustain another’s life.

12 Measuring autonomy is crucial to understanding how women and pregnant/birthing people achieve the health outcomes they want for themselves and how autonomy depends on cultural contexts. It is clear that “the standard questions used in measuring autonomy may not be equally valid across different cultural contexts” (Osamor and Grady Reference Osamor and Grady2016 199). However, some variables that researchers can consider are: social support structures, communication skills, decision-making power in specific contexts, and the personal dimensions of adequacy, self-assurance, and achievement orientation (Lifton Reference Lifton1983).

13 A woman who is in labor.

14 Bhandary (Reference Bhandary2020) provides a detailed explanation of each autonomy skill in her Theory of Liberal Dependency Care and discusses the concept of “political autonomy” in Rawls and Nussbaum.

References

Barrero, Abadía, Ernesto, César. 2022. Salud en ruinas: La destrucción capitalista del cuidado médico en el Instituto Materno Infantil de Bogotá. Bogota: Universidad del Rosario. https://doi.org/10.12804/urosario9789585000186.Google Scholar
American College of Obstetricians and Gynecologists (ACOG). 2016. Committe Opinion Number 664: Refusal of medically recommended treatment during pregnancy. Obstetrics & Gynecology 127 (6): e175e182. https://doi.org/10.1097/AOG.0000000000001485.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
American College of Obstetricians and Gynecologists (ACOG). 2021. Committee Opinion Number 819: Informed consent and shared decision making in obstetrics and gynecology. Obstetrics & Gynecology 137 (2): e34e41. https://doi.org/10.1097/AOG.0000000000004247.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Albayrak, Hande, Cankurtaran, Özlem, Bahar-Özvarış, Şevkat and Erdost, Türküler. 2022They taught us not only our rights as women, but also how to live”: Gender-based violence and empowerment experiences of Syrian women in Turkey and the role of women and girls safe spaces: A qualitative study.” Health Care for Women International 43 (7–8): 946963. https://doi.org/10.1080/07399332.2021.1975120.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Amram, Natalie Lea, Klein, Michael C., Mok, Heidi, Simkin, Penny, Lindstrom, Kathie, and Grant, Jalana. 2014. How birth doulas help clients adapt to changes in circumstances, clinical care, and client preferences during labor. Journal of Perinatal Education 23 (2): 96103. https://doi.org/10.1891/1058-1243.23.2.96.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Banerjee, Dwaipayan. 2022. Provincializing bioethics: Dilemmas of end-of-life care in an Indian ICU. American Ethnologist 49 (3): 318–31. https://doi.org/10.1111/amet.13092.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Basile, Monica. 2019. Radical doulas, childbirth activism, and the politics of embodiment. In Body battlegrounds, ed. Chris Bobel and Samantha Kwan. Nashville, TN: Vanderbilt University Press. https://doi.org/10.2307/j.ctv16759ws.6.Google Scholar
Beauchamp, Tom L., and Childress, James F., eds. 1994. Principles of biomedical ethics. 4th ed. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Bellón Sánchez, Silvia. 2014. Obstetric violence: Medicalization, authority abuse and sexism within Spanish obstetric assistance. A new name for old issues? Master’s Degree in Women’s and Gender Studies, Utrecht University. https://studenttheses.uu.nl/handle/20.500.12932/18094.Google Scholar
Berry, Nicole S. 2010. Unsafe motherhood: Mayan maternal mortality and subjectivity in post-war Guatemala. Fertility, Reproduction, and Sexuality 21. New York: Berghahn Books.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Berzon, Corinne, and Cohen Shabot, Sara. 2023. Obstetric violence and vulnerability: A bioethical approach. International Journal of Feminist Approaches to Bioethics 16 (1): 5276. https://doi.org/10.3138/IJFAB-16.2.02.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bhandary, Asha. 2016. Liberal dependency care. Journal of Philosophical Research 41: 4368. https://doi.org/10.5840/jpr201662767.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bhandary, Asha. 2020. Freedom to care: Liberalism, dependency care, and culture. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Bourdieu, Pierre, and Wacquant, Loïc J. D.. 1992. An invitation to reflexive sociology. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Burnett, Camille. 2021. Commentary on the article “How gentle must violence against women be in order to not be violent? Rethinking the word ‘violence’ in obstetric settings,” Reframed within a critical discourse orientation. Violence against Women 27 (8): 1001–08. https://doi.org/10.1177/1077801221996474.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Campbell, Colleen. 2021. Medical violence, obstetric racism, and the limits of informed consent for black women. Michigan Journal of Race and Law 26 (2): 4775. https://doi.org/10.36643/mjrl.26.sp.medical.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cantor, Allison R. 2023. “Yo trato de no llorar”: Rethinking obstetric violence in Costa Rica. Medical Anthropology 42 (2): 163–76. https://doi.org/10.1080/01459740.2023.2166410.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Cárdenas-Castro, Manuel, and Salinero-Rates, Stella. 2023. The continuum of violence against women: Gynecological violence within the medical model in Chile. Sexual and Reproductive Healthcare 37: 100891. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.srhc.2023.100891.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Castañeda, Angela N., Hill, Nicole, and Johnson Searcy, Julie, eds. 2022. Obstetric violence: Realities, and resistance from around the world. 1st ed. Toronto: Demeter Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Castro, Arachu, and Savage, Virginia. 2019. Obstetric violence as reproductive governance in the Dominican Republic. Medical Anthropology 38 (2): 123–36. https://doi.org/10.1080/01459740.2018.1512984.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Castro, Roberto, and Frías, Sonia M., eds. 2022. Violencia obstétrica y ciencias sociales: Estudios críticos en América Latina. Cuernavaca: UNAM, Centro Regional de Investigaciones Multidisciplinarias.Google Scholar
Centro de Estudios de la Mujer de la Universidad Central de Venezuela, Araña Feminista Red de Colectivos de Mujeres, and Iniciativa por los Derechos Sexuales. 2011. Informe sobre la República Bolivariana de Venezuela 12° Ronda del Examen Periódico Universal. https://www.ohchr.org/sites/default/files/lib-docs/HRBodies/UPR/Documents/session12/VE/CEM-UVC-CentroEstudiosMujerUniversidadCentral-spa.pdf.Google Scholar
Chervenak, Frank A., Renee McLeod-Sordjan, Pollet, Susan L., Monique De Four Jones, Gordon, Mollie R., Combs, Adriann, Bornstein, Eran, Lewis, Dawnette, Katz, Adi, Warman, Ashley, and Grünebaum, Amos. 2024. Obstetric violence is a misnomer. American Journal of Obstetrics and Gynecology 230 (3): S113845. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.ajog.2023.10.003.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Chinyere Oparah, Julia, and Bonaparte, Alicia D., eds. 2016. Birthing justice: Black women, pregnancy, and childbirth. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Chiu, Yung-Chen Jen, Boomer, K. B., and Conyers, Liza M.. 2019. The impact of psychosocial factors on health and retention outcomes for people living with HIV: Implications for rehabilitation counselors and educators. Rehabilitation Counseling Bulletin 62 (2): 94107. https://doi.org/10.1177/0034355218755304 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cockburn, Cynthia. 2004. The continuum of violence: A gender perspective on war and peace.” In Sites of Violence, ed. Wenona Giles and Jennifer Hyndman. University of California Press.Google Scholar
Cohen Shabot, Sara. 2016. Making loud bodies “feminine”: A feminist-phenomenological analysis of obstetric violence. Human Studies 39: 231–47. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10746-015-9369-x.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cohen Shabot, Sara. 2020. We birth with others: Towards a Beauvoirian understanding of obstetric violence. European Journal of Women’s Studies 28 (2): 213–28. https://doi.org/10.1177/1350506820919474.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cohen Shabot, Sara. 2021a. Why “normal” feels so bad: Violence and vaginal examinations during labour – a (feminist) phenomenology. Feminist Theory 22 (3): 443–63. https://doi.org/10.1177/1464700120920764.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cohen Shabot, Sara. 2021b. “You are not qualified—leave it to us”: Obstetric violence as testimonial injustice. Human Studies 44 (4): 635–53. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10746-021-09596-1.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cohen Shabot, Sara, and Korem, Keshet. 2018. Domesticating bodies: The role of shame in obstetric violence. Hypatia 33 (3): 384401. https://doi.org/10.1111/hypa.12428.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cohen Shabot, Sara, and Sadler, Michelle. 2023. “My soul hurt, and I felt as if I was going to die”: Obstetric violence as torture. Hypatia 38 (3): 607–27. https://doi.org/10.1017/hyp.2023.72.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Crenshaw, Kimberle. 1991. Mapping the margins: Intersectionality, identity politics, and violence against women of color. Stanford Law Review 43 (6): 1241–99. https://doi.org/10.2307/1229039.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Crowther, Kathleen M. 2023. Policing pregnant bodies: From Ancient Greece to post-Roe America. Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cudney, Paul. 2014. What really separates casuistry from principlism in biomedical ethics. Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 35 (3): 205–29. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11017-014-9295-3.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Darling, Orlaith. 2022. “The moment you realise someone wants your body”: Neoliberalism, mindfulness and female embodiment in Fleabag. Feminist Media Studies 22 (1): 132–47. https://doi.org/10.1080/14680777.2020.1797848 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Das, Veena. 2007. Life and words: Violence and the descent into the ordinary. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Davis, Dána-Ain. 2018. Obstetric racism: The racial politics of pregnancy, labor, and birthing. Medical Anthropology 38 (7): 560–73. https://doi.org/10.1080/01459740.2018.1549389 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Davis, Dána-Ain. 2019. Reproductive injustice: Racism, pregnancy, and premature birth, ed. Rivkin-Fish, Michele, Brodwin, Paul, and Shaw, Susan. New York: New York University Press.Google Scholar
Davis-Floyd, Robbie E. 1992. Birth as an American rite of passage. 3rd ed. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Davis-Floyd, Robbie E 2008. The technocratic model of birth. In Medical anthropology, ed. Cecil G. Helman. Abingdon, UK: Routledge. https://doi.org/10.4324/9781315249360-22.Google Scholar
Davis-Floyd, Robbie, and Cheyney, Melissa. 2019. Birth in eight cultures: Brazil, Greece, Japan, Mexico, the Netherlands, New Zealand, Tanzania, United States. Long Grove, IL: Waveland Press, Inc.Google Scholar
Davis-Floyd, Robbie, and Davis, Elizabeth. 1996. Intuition as authoritative knowledge in midwifery and homebirth. Medical Anthropology Quarterly 10 (2): 237–69. https://doi.org/10.1525/maq.1996.10.2.02a00080.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Davis-Floyd, Robbie, and Premkumar, Ashish, eds. 2023. Obstetricians speak: On training, practice, fear, and transformation. 1st ed. Anthropology of Obstetrics and Obstetricians, vol. 1. New York, NY: Berghahn Books.Google Scholar
Davy, Laura. 2015. Philosophical inclusive design: Intellectual disability and the limits of individual autonomy in moral and political theory. Hypatia 30 (1): 132–48. https://doi.org/10.1111/hypa.12119.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
De Barros Gabriel, Alice, and Guimarães Santos, Breno Ricardo. 2020. The epistemic injustice of obstetric violence. Estudos Feministas 28 (2): e60012. https://doi.org/10.1590/1806-9584-2020V28N260012.Google Scholar
Diallo, S. A., and Voia, M. 2016. The threat of domestic violence and women empowerment: The case of West Africa. African Development Review 28 (1): 92103. https://doi.org/10.1111/1467-8268.12169 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Diaz-Tello, Farah. 2016. Invisible wounds: Obstetric violence in the United States. Reproductive Health Matters 24 (47): 5664. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.rhm.2016.04.004.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Di Giulio, Marco. 2024. Motherhood, mental incompetence, and the denial of reproductive autonomy in the early years of Israeli statehood. Journal of Social History 57 (4): 550–77. https://doi.org/10.1093/jsh/shad087.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dokumacl, Plnar. 2020. Toward a relational approach? Common models of pious women’s agency and pious feminist autonomy in Turkey. Hypatia 35 (2): 243–61. https://doi.org/10.1017/hyp.2020.4.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Doenmez, Caroline Fidan Tyler, Jaime Cidro, Stephanie Sinclair, Hayward, Ashley, Wodtke, Larissa, and Nychuk, Alexandra. 2022. Heart work: Indigenous doulas responding to challenges of Western systems and revitalizing Indigenous birthing care in Canada. BMC Pregnancy and Childbirth 22 (1): 41. https://doi.org/10.1186/s12884-021-04333-z.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Doula to Others. 2018. Using BRAIN acronym for informed choices. Doula to Others (blog). Accessed May 17, 2024. https://doulatoothers.com/using-brain-acronym-informed-choices/.Google Scholar
Ehrenreich, Barbara, and English, Deirdre. [1973] 2010. Witches, midwives, and nurses: A history of women healers. 2nd ed. New York: Feminist Press at CUNY.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ehrlich, Susan. 1998. The discursive reconstruction of sexual consent. Discourse and Society 9 (2): 149–71. https://doi.org/10.1177/0957926598009002002.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ehrlich, Susan. 2001. Representing rape: Language and sexual consent. London: Routledge. https://doi.org/10.4324/9780203459034.Google Scholar
Farmer, Paul. 2004. An anthropology of structural violence. Current Anthropology 45 (3): 305–25. https://doi.org/10.1086/382250.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Flanigan, Jessica. 2016. Obstetric autonomy and informed consent. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 19 (1): 225–44. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-015-9610-8.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ford, Andrea. 2021. Attuned consent: Birth doulas, care, and the politics of consent. Frontiers: A Journal of Women Studies 42 (2): 111–32. https://doi.org/10.1353/fro.2021.0018.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Foucault, Michel. 1976. Discipline and punish: The birth of the prison. 2nd ed. New York: Knopf Doubleday.Google Scholar
Fraser, Gertrude Jacinta. 1998. African American midwifery in the South: Dialogues of birth, race, and memory. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fricker, Miranda. 2007. Epistemic injustice: Power and the ethics of knowing. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Galtung, Johan. 1969. Violence, peace, and peace research. Journal of Peace Research 6 (3): 167–91. https://doi.org/10.1177/002234336900600301.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gammeltoft, Tine M. 2008. Figures of transversality: State power and prenatal screening in contemporary Vietnam. American Ethnologist 35(4): 570–87. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1548-1425.2008.00099.x CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ginsburg, Faye, and Rapp, Rayna. 1991. The politics of reproduction. Annual Review of Anthropology 20 (1): 311–43. https://doi.org/10.1146/annurev.an.20.100191.001523.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Gleason, Emily Gaffney, Patricia Molina Berrío, Diana, Marcela Lopez Ríos, Jennifer, and María Mejìa Merino, Cristina. 2021. “Parir no es un asunto de etnia, es un asunto de humanidad’: Experiencias frente a la violencia obstétrica durante la atención al parto en mujeres indígenas. Salud Colectiva 17: e3727. https://doi.org/10.18294/sc.2021.3727.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gopal, Meena. 2017. Traditional knowledge and feminist dilemmas. Experience of the midwives of the Barber caste in South Tamil Nadu. In Feminists and Science, ed. Sumi Krishna and Gita Chadha, vol. 2. New Delhi: SAGE Publications India Pvt, Ltd.Google Scholar
Grotti, Vanessa, and Brightman, Marc. 2021. Migrant hospitalities in the Mediterranean: Encounters with alterity in birth and death. Cham: Springer International Publishing. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-56585-5.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hawkins, R., Redley, M., and Holland, A. J.. 2011. Duty of care and autonomy: How support workers managed the tension between protecting service users from risk and promoting their independence in a specialist group home. Journal of Intellectual Disability Research 55 (9): 873–84. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1365-2788.2011.01445.x.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Held, Virginia. 2018. The ethics of care. In The Oxford handbook of distributive justice, ed. Olsaretti, Serena. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Herr, Ranjoo Seodu. 2018. Islamist women’s agency and relational autonomy. Hypatia 33 (2): 195215. https://doi.org/10.1111/hypa.12402.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Herring, Jonathan. 2014. Relational autonomy and family law. Cham: Springer International Publishing AG. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-04987-8.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hunt, Matthew R., and Ells, Carolyn. 2011. Partners towards autonomy: Risky choices and relational autonomy in rehabilitation care. Disability and Rehabilitation 33 (11): 961–67. https://doi.org/10.3109/09638288.2010.515703.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hussein, Julia. 2020. COVID-19: What implications for sexual and reproductive health and rights globally? Sexual and Reproductive Health Matters 28 (1): 1746065. https://doi.org/10.1080/26410397.2020.1746065.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Inhorn, Marcia Claire, ed. 2009. Reproductive disruptions: Gender, technology, and biopolitics in the new millennium. 1st pbk ed. New York: Berghahn Books. https://doi.org/10.1515/9780857455635.Google Scholar
Jojoa-Tobar, Elisa, Darío Cuchumbe-Sánchez, Yuler, Briyith Ledesma-Rengifo, Jennifer, Cristina Muñoz-Mosquera, María, María Paja Campo, Adriana, and Pablo Suarez-Bravo, Juan. 2019. Violencia obstétrica: Haciendo visible lo invisible. Salud UIS 51 (2): 135–46. https://doi.org/10.18273/revsal.v51n2-2019006.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jordan, Brigitte. 1983. Birth in four cultures. 3rd ed. Montreal: Eden Press.Google Scholar
Jordan, Brigitte. 2023. Authoritative knowledge and its construction. In Childbirth and authoritative knowledge, ed. Robbie E. Davis-Floyd and Carolyn F. Sargent. Berkeley: University of California Press. https://doi.org/10.2307/jj.2711580.5.Google Scholar
Junqueira, Karina, Rattner, Daphne, and Bauermann, Muriel. 2017. Institutional violence and quality of service in obstetrics are associated with postpartum depression. Revista de Saúde Pública 51 (69): 111. https://doi.org/10.1590/S1518-8787.2017051006549.Google Scholar
Kaplan, Julika Ayla, Kandodo, Jonathan, Sclafani, Joseph, Raine, Susan, Jennifer Blumenthal-Barby, Norris, Alison, Abigail Norris-Turner, Chemey, Elly, John Michael Beckham, Khan, Zara, and Chunda, Reginald. 2017. An investigation of the relationship between autonomy, childbirth practices, and obstetric fistula among women in rural Lilongwe District, Malawi. BMC International Health and Human Rights 17 (17): 110. https://doi.org/10.1186/s12914-017-0125-3.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kay, Margarita Artschwager, ed. 1982. Anthropology of human birth. Philadelphia: F. A. Davis.Google Scholar
Keller, Jean. 1997. Autonomy, relationality, and feminist ethics. Hypatia 12 (2): 152–64. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1527-2001.1997.tb00024.x.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kelly, Liz. 1987. The continuum of sexual violence. In Women, violence and social control, ed. Jalna Hanmer and Mary Maynard. London: Palgrave Macmillan UK. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-349-18592-4_4.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kingma, Elselijn. 2021. Harming one to benefit another: The paradox of autonomy and consent in maternity care. Bioethics 35: 456–64. https://doi.org/10.1111/bioe.12852.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kitzinger, Sheila. 2006. Birth as rape: There must be an end to “just in case” obstetrics. British Journal of Midwifery 14 (9): 544–45. https://doi.org/10.12968/bjom.2006.14.9.21799.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lappeman, Maura, and Swartz, Leslie. 2021. How gentle must violence against women be in order to not be violent? Rethinking the word “violence” in obstetric settings. Violence Against Women 27 (8): 9871000. https://doi.org/10.1177/1077801221996444.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lévesque, Sylvie, and Ferron-Parayre, Audrey. 2021. To use or not to use the term “obstetric violence”: Commentary on the article by Swartz and Lappeman. Violence Against Women 27 (8): 1009–18. https://doi.org/10.1177/1077801221996456.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Levine, Nancy E. 2008. Alternative kinship, marriage, and reproduction. Annual Review of Anthropology 37 (1): 375–89. https://doi.org/10.1146/annurev.anthro.37.081407.085120.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lifton, P. D. 1983. Measures of autonomy. Journal of Personality Assessment 47 (5): 514–23. https://doi.org/10.1207/s15327752jpa4705_12.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Lira, Natalie. 2022. Laboratory of Deficiency: Sterilization and Confinement in California, 1900–1950s. Oakland, CA: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Lockwood, Gillian M. 1999. At the coalface: Medical ethics in practice. Pregnancy, autonomy, and paternalism. Journal of Medical Ethics 25: 537–40. https://doi.org/10.1136/jme.25.6.537.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lockwood Harris, Kate. 2018. Yes means yes and no means no, but both these mantras need to go: Communication myths in consent education and anti-rape activism. Journal of Applied Communication Research 46 (2): 155–78. https://doi.org/10.1080/00909882.2018.1435900.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
MacDonald, Fiona. 2010. Relational group autonomy: Ethics of care and the multiculturalism paradigm. Hypatia 25 (1): 196212. https://doi:10.1111/j.1527-2001.2010.01091.x.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mackenzie, Catriona, and Stoljar, Natalie, eds. 2000. Relational autonomy: Feminist perspectives on autonomy, agency, and the social self. New York and Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mahoney, Mary, and Mitchell, Lauren. 2017. Who cares? How doulas engage in radical acts of kindness. Women’s Health Activist 42 (4): 9.Google Scholar
Mann, Rosemary J. 2004. The interface between legal and ethical issues in reproductive health. Journal of Midwifery and Women’s Health 49 (3): 182–87. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.jmwh.2004.01.004.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Mapes, Marianna V., DePergola, Peter A., and McGee, William T.. 2020. Patient-centered care and autonomy: Shared decision-making in practice and a suggestion for practical application in the critically ill. Journal of Intensive Care Medicine 35 (11): 1352–55. https://doi.org/10.1177/0885066619870458.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mardorossian, Carine M. 2019. “Birth rape”: Laboring women, coaching men, and natural childbirth in the hospital setting. In Framing the rape victim. Ithaca, NY: Rutgers University Press. https://doi.org/10.36019/9780813566047-005.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Martin, Emily. [1987] 2001. The woman in the body: A cultural analysis of reproduction. Boston: Beacon Press.Google Scholar
Martín-Badia, Júlia, Obregón-Gutiérrez, Noemí, and Goberna-Tricas, Josefina. 2021. Obstetric violence as an infringement on basic bioethical principles: Reflections inspired by focus groups with midwives. International Journal of Environmental Research and Public Health 18 (12553): 115. https://doi.org/10.3390/ijerph182312553.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Martinez, Sergio, Rodríguez, Julian, Hernández, Antonio, and Miguel Martínez, Juan. 2021. Factors associated with postpartum post-traumatic stress disorder (PTSD) following obstetric violence: A cross-sectional study. Journal of Personalized Medicine 11 (338): 111. https://doi.org/10.3390/jpm11050338.Google Scholar
Guijarro, Massó, Ester. 2023. Obstetric violence as epistemic injustice: Childbirth trouble. Salud colectiva 19: e4464. https://doi.org/10.18294/sc.2023.4464.Google Scholar
Mason, C. L. 2015. “Cripping” the World Bank. International Feminist Journal of Politics 17 (3): 435–53. https://doi.org/10.1080/14616742.2014.941252.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McCormack, Clare, Callaghan, Bridget L., and Pawluski, Jodi L.. 2023. It’s time to rebrand “mommy brain.” JAMA Neurology 80 (4): 335–36. https://doi.org/10.1001/jamaneurol.2022.5180.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Merino, Mejía, María, Cristina, Lida Faneyra Zapata, Diana Patricia Molina Berrio, and David Arango Urrea, Juan. 2018. Dehumanization during delivery: Meanings and experiences of women cared for in the Medellín public network. Investigación y Educación en Enfermería 36 (1): e03. https://doi.org/10.17533/udea.iee.v36n1e03.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Meyers, Diana T. 1989. Self, society, and personal choice. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Meyers, Diana T. 2002. Gender in the mirror: Cultural imagery and women’s agency. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mill, John Stuart. 1989a. On liberty. In On liberty, and other writings, ed. Collini, Stefan. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Mill, John Stuart. 1989b. The subjection of women. In On liberty, and other writings, ed. Collini, Stefan. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Moraga, Cherríe, and Anzaldúa, Gloria, eds. 2015. This bridge called my back: Writings by radical women of color. 4th ed. Albany, NY: SUNY Press.Google Scholar
Mulla, Sameena. 2014. The violence of care: Rape victims, forensic nurses, and sexual assault intervention. New York: New York University Press.Google Scholar
Murillo, Lina-Maria, and Fixmer-Oraiz, Natalie. 2021. Reproductive justice in the heartland: Mothering, maternal care, and race in twenty-first-century Iowa. In Maternal theory: Essential readings, ed. Andrea O’Reilly. Bradford, Ontario: Demeter Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nalepa, Elizabeth. 2020. Naming obstetric violence as a social problem. Practicing Anthropology 42 (2): 4244. https://doi.org/10.17730/0888-4552.42.2.42.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nedelsky, Jennifer. 2011. Law’s relations: A relational theory of self, autonomy, and law. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
O’Brien, Elizabeth. 2023. Surgery and salvation: The roots of reproductive injustice in Mexico, 1770-1940. Durham, NC: University of North Carolina Press. https://doi.org/10.5149/9781469675893_obrien.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Okimoto, Tyler G., Konradt, Udo, Krys, Sabrina, and Dawson, Niamh. 2022. A person-centered approach to understanding endorsement of restorative justice in response to workplace mistreatment. Social Justice Research 35 (1): 6287. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11211-021-00377-w.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Olza, Ibone. 2013. PTSD and obstetric violence. Midwifery Today 105: 4849. https://doi.org/10.1186/1471-2393-12-88.Google Scholar
Orchard, Edwina R., Rutherford, Helena J. V., Holmes, Avram J., and Jamadar, Sharna D.. 2023. Matrescence: Lifetime impact of motherhood on cognition and the brain. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 27 (10): 974. https://doi:10.1016/j.tics.2023.06.002.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Osamor, Pauline E., and Grady, Christine. 2016. Women’s autonomy in health care decision-making in developing countries: A synthesis of the literature. International Journal of Women’s Health 8: 191202. https://doi.org/10.2147/IJWH.S105483.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Oshana, Marina. 2006. Personal autonomy in society. Aldershot: Ashgate.Google Scholar
Paula, Enimar de, Valdecyr Herdy Alves, Diego Pereira Rodrigues, Felipe de Castro Felicio, Renata Corrêa Bezerra de Araújo, Rosilda Alves da Silva Isla Chamilco, and Vivian Linhares Maciel Almeida. 2020. Obstetric violence and the current obstetric model, in the perception of health managers. Texto & Contexto—Enfermagem 29 (January): e20190248. https://doi.org/10.1590/1980-265X-TCE-2019-0248.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Perdok, Hilde, Cronie, Doug, Cecile van der Speld, Jeroen van Dillen, Ank de Jonge, Marlies Rijnders, Irene de Graaf, Schellevis, François G., and Verhoeven, Corine J.. 2017. Experienced job autonomy among maternity care professionals in the Netherlands. Midwifery 54: 6772. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.midw.2017.07.015.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Pickles, Camilla. 2023. “Obstetric violence,” “mistreatment,” and “disrespect and abuse”: Reflections on the politics of naming violations during facility-based childbirth. Hypatia 38 (3): 628–49. https://doi.org/10.1017/hyp.2023.73.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Planned Parenthood. 2024. Can you explain what “pro-choice” and “pro-life” means? Accessed May 17, 2024. https://www.plannedparenthood.org/blog/can-you-explain-what-pro-choice-means-and-pro-life-means.Google Scholar
Quattrocchi, Patrizia. 2019. Obstetric violence observatory: Contributions of Argentina to the international debate. Medical Anthropology 38 (8): 762–76. https://doi.org/10.1080/01459740.2019.1609471.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Quattrocchi, Patrizia, and Magnone, Natalia. 2020. Violencia obstétrica en América Latina: Conceptualización, experiencias, medición y estrategias. Remedios de Escalada, Buenos Aires, Argentina: EDUNLa. Colección Cuadernos del ISCo. https://doi.org/10.18294/9789874937506 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rajtar, Małgorzata. 2018. Relational autonomy, care, and Jehovah’s Witnesses in Germany. Bioethics 32: 184–92. https://doi.org/10.1111/bioe.12424.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Rape, Abuse & Incest National Network (RAINN). 2024. What consent looks like? Accessed May 17, 2024. https://www.rainn.org/articles/what-is-consent#:∼:text=How%20does%20consent%20work%3F,same%20activity%20on%20other%20occasions.Google Scholar
Restrepo-Sánchez, Andrés. 2024. “Birth rape”? A linguistic analysis of obstetric violence as sexual violence Women and Language 47 (1): 5–36. https://doi.org/10.34036/WL.2024.003.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rodrigues Duarte, Micheliana, Valdecyr Herdy Alves, Diego Pereira Rodrigues, Rosário Soanno Marchiori, Giovanna, Vidal Vieira Guerra, Juliana, and Machado Pimentel, Mariana. 2020. Perception of obstetric nurses on the assistance to childbirth: Reestablishing women’s autonomy and empowerment. Revista Online de Pesquisa Cuidado É Fundamental 12: 903–08. https://doi.org/10.9789/2175-5361.rpcfo.v12.7927.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rogerson, Jennifer J. M. 2019. Privileges of birth: Constellations of care, myth, and race in South Africa. New York: Berghahn Books. https://doi.org/10.2307/j.ctv1dwq1j2.Google Scholar
Rössler, Beate. 2002. Problems with autonomy. Hypatia 17 (4): 143–62. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1527-2001.2002.tb01077.x.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rowlands, Sam, and Thomas, Kevin. 2020. Mandatory waiting periods before abortion and sterilization: Theory and practice. International Journal of Women’s Health 12: 577–86. https://doi.org/10.2147/IJWH.S257178.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Rybak, EA. 2009. Hippocratic ideal, Faustian bargain, and Damocles’ sword: Erosion of patient autonomy in obstetrics. Journal of Perinatology 29: 721–25. https://doi.org/10.1038/jp.2009.123.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Sadler, Michelle, Leiva, Gonzalo, and Olza, Ibone. 2020. COVID-19 as a risk factor for obstetric violence. Sexual and Reproductive Health Matters 28 (1): 14. https://doi.org/10.1080/26410397.2020.1785379.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Sadler, Michelle, Santos, Mário J. D. S., Ruiz-Berdún, Dolores, Gonzalo Leiva Rojas, Skoko, Elena, Gillen, Patricia, and Clausen, Jette A.. 2016. Moving beyond disrespect and abuse: Addressing the structural dimensions of obstetric violence. Reproductive Health Matters 24 (47): 4755. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.rhm.2016.04.002.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Salinas, Juan L., Salinas, Manisha, and Kahn, Megan. 2022. Doulas, racism, and whiteness: How birth support workers process advocacy towards women of color. Societies 12 (19): 115. https://doi.org/10.3390/soc12010019 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sargent, Carolyn F., and Davis-Floyd, Robbie. 2023. Childbirth and authoritative knowledge: Cross-cultural perspectives. Berkeley: University of California Press. https://doi.org/10.2307/jj.2711580.Google Scholar
Shih, Patti, Rapport, Frances, Hogden, Anne, Bierbaum, Mia, Hsu, Jeremy, Boyages, John, and Braithwaite, Jeffrey. 2018. Relational autonomy in breast diseases care: A qualitative study of contextual and social conditions of patients’ capacity for decision-making. BMC Health Services Research 18 (818): 110. https://doi.org/10.1186/s12913-018-3622-8.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Strong, Adrienne. 2020. Documenting death: Maternal mortality and the ethics of care in Tanzania. Oakland, CA: University of California Press. https://doi.org/10.1525/luminos.93.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thomson, Judith Jarvis. 1971. A defense of abortion. Philosophy and Public Affairs 1 (1): 4766.Google Scholar
Turner, Leigh. 2009. Anthropological and sociological critiques of bioethics. Journal of Bioethical Inquiry 6 (1): 8398. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11673-008-9130-5.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Urrea-Mora, Fanny Consuelo. 2014. Respeto a la autonomía de mujeres gestantes en salud: Diálogo bioética-género. Revista Colombiana de Bioética 9: 193236. https://doi.org/10.18270/rcb.v9i3.747 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vallana-Sala, Viviana Valeria. 2019. “It’s nice to make them but not have them”: Analysis of obstetric violence during delivery care in Colombia. Revista Ciencias de La Salud 17: 128–44. https://doi.org/10.12804/revistas.urosario.edu.co/revsalud/a.8125.Google Scholar
Van Hollen, Cecilia. 1994. Perspectives on the anthropology of birth. Culture, Medicine and Psychiatry 18 (4): 501–12. https://doi.org/10.1007/BF01565852.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Van Hollen, Cecilia. 2003. Birth on the threshold: Childbirth and modernity in South India. Berkeley: University of California Press. https://doi.org/10.1525/9780520935396.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Venezuela, República Bolivariana de. 2007. Ley Orgánica Sobre el Derecho de las Mujeres a una Vida Libre de Violencia. Gaceta Oficial de la República Bolivariana de Venezuela.Google Scholar
Villarmea, Stella. 2021. Reasoning from the uterus: Casanova, women’s agency, and the philosophy of birth. Hypatia 36: 2241. https://doi.org/10.1017/hyp.2020.45.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Walsh, Denis J. 2006. “Nesting” and “matrescence” as distinctive features of a free-standing birth centre in the UK. Midwifery 22 (3): 228–39. http://doi:10.1016/j.midw.2005.09.005.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Washington, Harriet A. 2008. Medical apartheid: The dark history of medical experimentation on Black Americans from colonial times to the present. New York: Anchor Books.Google Scholar
Webster, Aness Kim. 2021. Socially embedded agency: Lessons from marginalized identities. In Oxford studies in agency and responsibility, vol. 7, ed. David Shoemaker. Oxford: Oxford University Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780192844644.003.0006.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wertz, Richard W., and Wertz, Dorothy C.. 1977. Lying-in: A history of childbirth in America. New York: Free.Google Scholar
Westlund, Andrea C. 2009. Rethinking relational autonomy. Hypatia 24 (4): 2649. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1527-2001.2009.01056.x.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
White, Frederick J. 2013. Personhood: An essential characteristic of the human species. Linacre Quarterly 80 (1): 7497. https://doi.org/10.1179/0024363912Z.00000000010.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Williamson, K. Eliza. 2021. The iatrogenesis of obstetric racism in Brazil: Beyond the body, beyond the clinic. Anthropology and Medicine 28 (2): 172–87. https://doi.org/10.1080/13648470.2021.1932416.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
World Health Organization. 2014. The prevention and elimination of disrespect and abuse during facility-based childbirth: WHO statement. Geneva: World Health Organization.Google Scholar