1. Introduction
This paper is about connected groups in the sense of model-theoretic connected components. Suppose G is an infinite group with some first-order structure. In model theory, we consider several kinds of model-theoretic connected components of G, after passing to a sufficiently saturated extension $G^*$ of G. Let $A\subset G^*$ be a small set of parameters and define (cf. [Reference Bowler, Chen and Gismatullin6, Reference Gismatullin15, Reference Gismatullin, Jagiella and Krupiński17, Reference Gismatullin and Newelski19, Reference Hrushovski, Peterzil and Pillay24, Reference Krupiński and Pillay27, Reference Shelah36]) the following:
-
• ${G^*}^0_A$ (the connected component of G over A) is the intersection of all A-definable subgroups of ${G^*}$ which have finite index in ${G^*}$ .
-
• ${G^*}^{00}_A$ (the type-connected component of G over A) is the smallest subgroup of ‘bounded index’ in ${G^*}$ (bounded relative to $|{G^*}|$ ), that is, type-definable over A.
-
• ${G^*}^{\infty }_A$ (the $\infty $ -connected component of G) is the smallest subgroup of bounded index in ${G^*}$ , that is, A-invariant (invariant under the automorphisms of ${G^*}$ fixing A pointwise).
In the literature ${G^*}^{\infty }_A$ is sometimes denoted by ${G^*}^{000}_A$ [Reference Conversano and Pillay10, Reference Hrushovski, Peterzil and Pillay24, Reference Hrushovski and Pillay25]. The groups ${G^*}^0_A$ , ${G^*}^{00}_A$ , and ${G^*}^{\infty }_A$ are important in the study of groups from a model-theoretic point of view. In general, the quotients ${G^*}/{G^*}^{\infty }_A$ , ${G^*}/{G^*}^{00}_A$ , and ${G^*}/{G^*}^{0}_A$ with the logic topology (where a set is closed if and only if its preimage under the quotient map is type-definable over a small set of parameters), are topological groups which are invariants of the theory $\operatorname {\mathrm {Th}}(G)$ . They do not depend on the choice of saturated extension $G^*$ (cf. [Reference Gismatullin and Newelski19, Proposition 3.3(3)]). We have ${G^*}^{\infty }_A\subseteq {G^*}^{00}_A\subseteq {G^*}^0_A$ ; also, ${G^*}/{G^*}^{0}_A$ is a profinite group, ${G^*}/{G^*}^{00}_A$ is a compact Hausdorff group, and ${G^*}/{G^*}^{\infty }_A$ is a quasi-compact topological group, that is compact but not necessary Hausdorff (cf. [Reference Gismatullin and Newelski19, Proposition 3.5(1)] where we used the notation $G^*_L$ for ${G^*}^{\infty }$ ). Hence, if we equip G with the discrete topology, then for all $A\subseteq G$ the mappings $G \to {G^*}/{G^*}^{00}_A$ and $G \to {G^*}/{G^*}^{0}_A$ are compactifications of G.
We focus on the type-connected component ${G^*}^{00}_A$ and the $\infty $ -connected component ${G^*}^{\infty }_A$ . The goals of the paper are: to study the notions of absolute connectedness and type-absolute connectedness, to give examples of (type-)absolutely connected groups and to derive some applications. We say that a group G, without any additional first-order structure, is absolutely connected [resp. type-absolutely connected] if for all possible first-order expansions $(G,\cdot ,\ldots )$ of G, and for all sufficiently saturated extensions $G^*$ and small $A\subset G^*$ , we have ${G^*}^{\infty }_A = {G^*}$ [resp. ${G^*}^{00}_A = {G^*}$ , for every $A \subseteq G$ ] (see Definitions 3.3 and 4.2).
The main novelty in this approach derives from considering groups equipped with an arbitrary first-order structure. It extends the previous settings (NIP, o-minimal). In many examples these connected components are determined by the group structure alone, that is, by some group-theoretic properties. For example, every uniformly simple group (Section 3) [Reference Gal and Gismatullin14] is absolutely connected.
As an application of our methods we obtain a description of all compactifications of a Hausdorff topological group G as mappings $G\to G^*/H$ , for some type-definable bounded index subgroup H of $G^*$ (where $G^*$ is a sufficiently saturated extension of G). Similar result has been proved by Robinson and Hirschfeld [Reference Hirschfeld21] but in the context of the enlargement $^*G$ from non-standard analysis. As a corollary of Theorem 5.7 we obtain the following characterization of the class of type-absolutely connected groups (Theorem 6.10):
The class of type-absolutely connected groups coincides with the class of discretely topologized minimally almost periodic groups, that is the class of groups without any nontrivial compactifications.
This gives a direct link between notions from topology and model theory. Using this observation and [Reference Shtern38] we can characterize all connected Lie groups which are type-absolutely connected (Remark 6.11). In particular, the topological universal cover $\widetilde {\operatorname {\mathrm {SL}}_2({\mathbb R})}$ of $\operatorname {\mathrm {SL}}_2({\mathbb R})$ is type-absolutely connected (this generalizes results from [Reference Conversano and Pillay10]). Also we introduce and study, in Section 6, the type-connected radical of a group (Definition 6.1).
Other goal of this note is to prove Theorem 7.7 concerning the structure of groups of rational points of split semisimple linear groups (also called Chevalley groups), with the uniform upper bound 12 for the diameter of the absolute connectedness. Recall that a linear group defined over a field k is called split over k or k-split if some maximal torus T in G is split over k, that is, T is isomorphic over k to a direct product of copies of the multiplicative groups ${\mathbb G}_m$ [Reference Borel3, Section 18.6, page 220]. Over an algebraically closed field, every semisimple group is split.
Theorem. 7.7 Let k be an arbitrary infinite field and G be a k-split, semisimple linear algebraic group defined over k. The derived subgroup $[G(k),G(k)]$ of $G(k)$ is 12-absolutely connected. Moreover $[G(k),G(k)]$ is a $\emptyset $ -definable subgroup of $G(k)$ in the pure group language.
The proof of Theorem 7.7 goes through the Gauss decomposition with prescribed semisimple part from [Reference Chernousov, Ellers and Gordeev9]. We first prove absolute connectedness of simply connected semisimple split groups (Theorem 7.5) and then, using universal k-coverings, establish the general case. If G is not simply connected, then the group $[G(k),G(k)]$ might be a proper Zariski dense subgroup of $G(k)$ . For example if $G=\operatorname {\mathrm {PGL}}_n$ , then $[G(k),G(k)] = \operatorname {\mathrm {PSL}}_n(k)$ is a proper subgroup for some fields. Likewise the result of [Reference Platonov35] implies that if G is a non-simply connected semisimple k-split k-group and k is a finitely generated field, then $[G(k),G(k)]$ is a proper subgroup of $G(k)$ .
2. Basic notation and prerequisites
In this section we establish notation and prove some basic facts.
2.1. Group theory
For a group G, elements $a,b\in G$ , and subsets $A,B\subseteq G$ we use the following notation: $A\cdot B = \{ab : a\in A, b \in B\}$ , $a^b = b^{-1}ab$ , $A^B = \bigcup _{a\in A,b\in B}a^b$ , $A^n = \underbrace {A\cdot \ldots \cdot A}_{n\text { times}}$ , $A^{\leq n} = \bigcup _{i\leq n} A^i$ , and $[a,b] = a^{-1}b^{-1}ab$ . The subset $X\subseteq G$ is called normal if $X^G = X$ . The derived series is defined by $G^{(1)} = [G,G]$ , $G^{(n+1)}=\left [G^{(n)},G^{(n)}\right ]$ , $G^{(\lambda )} = \bigcap _{\alpha <\lambda }G^{(\alpha )}$ . A group G is called perfect if $G=[G,G]$ . The perfect core of G is the largest perfect subgroup of G. It is also the intersection of all elements from the transfinite derived series of G. The commutator length of an element $g \in [G,G]$ is the minimal number of commutators sufficient to express g as their product. The commutator width $\operatorname {\mathrm {cw}}^G(X)$ of a subset $X\subseteq G$ is the maximum of the commutator lengths of elements from X or the sign $\infty $ if the maximum does not exist or $X\not \subseteq [G,G]$ . The number $\operatorname {\mathrm {cw}}^G(G)$ is denoted by $\operatorname {\mathrm {cw}}(G)$ . By $Z(G)$ we denote the center and by e the neutral element of G.
2.2. Model theory
We assume that the reader is familiar with basic notions of model theory. The model-theoretic background can be found in [Reference Marker28]. Suppose ${\mathcal M}$ is a model over some language L. We usually work not in ${\mathcal M}$ , but in its saturated elementary extension ${\mathcal M}^*$ , called a monster model. It is $\kappa $ -saturated and $\kappa $ -strongly homogeneous model ${\mathcal M}^*\succ {\mathcal M} $ , for sufficiently big $\kappa $ . By A we always denote some small, that is, $|A|<\kappa $ , set of parameters from ${\mathcal M}^*$ , and by $L(A)$ the set of all L-formulas with parameters from A (also called A-formulas). A-definable means definable by an A-formula; A-type-definable means definable by a conjunction of a family of A-formulas; A-invariant means invariant under the group $\operatorname {\mathrm {Aut}}\left ({\mathcal M}^*/A\right )$ of automorphisms of ${\mathcal M}^*$ stabilizing A pointwise. An equivalence relation E on ${\mathcal M}^*$ is called bounded if E has fewer than $\kappa $ many equivalence classes. It is well known that if E is type-definable over A or A-invariant, then either the number of classes of E is at most $2^{|L(A)|}$ or at least $\kappa $ .
Usually we will deal with groups with some first-order structure, but sometimes we consider groups only in a group language without any extra structure. In the latter case we say that the group is pure. If G is a group, by $G^*$ we denote its monster model. Obviously $G^*$ contains G as a subgroup.
2.3. Boundedness and thickness
Let us recall some notions from [Reference Casanovas, Lascar, Pillay and Ziegler8, Reference Ziegler44]. Fix a model ${\mathcal M}$ over some language L and small $A\subset {\mathcal M}^*$ . A formula $\varphi (\overline {x},\overline {y})\in L(A)$ , with free variables $\overline {x},\overline {y}$ (tuples of same length $|\overline {x}|=|\overline {y}|$ ), is called thick if $\varphi $ is symmetric and for some $n\in {\mathbb N}$ , for every n-sequence $(\overline {a_i})_{i<n}$ from ${\mathcal M}^*$ (where we do not require $\overline {a}_0,\dots , \overline {a}_{n-1}$ to be pairwise distinct) there exist $i<j<n$ such that $\varphi (\overline {a}_i,\overline {a}_j)$ holds in ${\mathcal M}^*$ [Reference Ziegler44, Section 3]. By $\Theta _A(\overline {x},\overline {y})$ we denote the conjunction of all thick formulas over A. The relation $\Theta _A$ is type-definable over A, but is not necessarily transitive. It has the following known properties ([Reference Ziegler44, Lemmas 6 and 7], [Reference Casanovas, Lascar, Pillay and Ziegler8, 1.11 and 1.12]):
-
(2.3.1) If $\Theta _A(\overline {a},\overline {b})$ , then there is a small model $M'\prec M$ containing A, such that $\overline {a}\underset {M'}{\equiv }\overline {b}$ , that is, $\operatorname {\mathrm {tp}}(\overline {a}/M')=\operatorname {\mathrm {tp}}(\overline {b}/M')$ .
-
(2.3.2) If for some small model $M'\prec M$ containing A, $\overline {a}\underset {M'}{\equiv }\overline {b}$ holds, then ${\Theta _A}^2(\overline {a},\overline {b})$ .
2.4. Model-theoretic connected components
Unless otherwise stated, we assume in this subsection that G is a monster model. Let H be an A-invariant subgroup of G. The index $[G:H]$ is either at most $\leq 2^{|L(A)|}$ or at least $\geq \kappa $ . In the first case we say that H has bounded index in G. The following subgroups are called the model-theoretic connected components of G.
-
• $G^{0}_{A} = \bigcap \{ H < G : H \text { is } A \text {-definable and } [G:H] \text { is finite}\}$ .
-
• $G^{00}_{A} = \bigcap \{ H < G : H \text { is type-definable over } A \text { and } [G:H] \text { is bounded} \}$ .
-
• $G^{\infty }_{A} = \bigcap \{ H < G : H \text { is } A \text {-invariant and } [G:H] \text { is bounded}\}$ .
If for every small set of parameters $A\subset G$ , $G^{\infty }_A = G^{\infty }_{\emptyset }$ , then we say that $G^{\infty }$ exists and define it as $G^{\infty }_{\emptyset }$ . Similarly we define existence of $G^{00}$ and $G^{0}$ . By [Reference Gismatullin15], the groups $G^{\infty }_{A} \subseteq G^{00}_{A} \subseteq G^{0}_{A}$ are normal subgroups of G of bounded index. Following the notation from [Reference Gismatullin15, Section 1], define $X_{\Theta _A}=\{a^{-1}b : a,b\in G, \Theta _{A}(a,b)\}$ . Note that $G^{\infty }_{A}$ is generated by $X_{\Theta _A}$ [Reference Gismatullin15, Lemma 2.2(2)]. In [Reference Gismatullin15, Lemma 3.3] we gave another description of $X_{\Theta _A}$ . The key idea is the notion of a thick subset of a group, based on the definition of thick formula.
Definition 2.1 [Reference Gismatullin15, Definition 3.1]
A subset P of an arbitrary group G (not necessarily sufficiently saturated) is called n-thick, where $n\in {\mathbb N}$ , if it is symmetric (that is, $P = P^{-1}$ ) and for every n-sequence $g_1,\ldots ,g_n$ from G, there are $1\leq i<j\leq n$ such that $g_i^{-1}g_j \in P$ . We say that P is thick if P is n-thick for some $n\in {\mathbb N}$ (the condition $g_i^{-1}g_j \in P$ is equivalent to requiring $g_ig_j^{-1} \in P$ , as one can take $g_1^{-1},\ldots ,g_n^{-1}$ instead of $g_1,\ldots ,g_n$ ).
A finite index subgroup is an obvious example of a thick subset. More examples are given in [Reference Bowler, Chen and Gismatullin6, Section 4] and in [Reference Gismatullin15]. A typical example is the following [Reference Gismatullin15, Lemma 3.2(4)]: let for $X\subset G$ and finitely many translates of X cover G (i.e., X is generic), then $P=X^{-1}X$ is thick.
Let us collect below a couple of standard results about thick sets. Suppose G and H are groups (not necessarily sufficiently saturated), $f \colon G \to H$ is an epimorphism, $P, Q \subseteq G$ , $S\subseteq H$ , and $n,m\in {\mathbb N}$ . By $R(n,m)$ we denote the Ramsey number.
Lemma 2.2.
-
(1) If P is n-thick and Q is m-thick, then $P\cap Q$ is $R(n,m)$ -thick.
-
(2) The preimage $f^{-1}(S)$ is n-thick if and only if S is n-thick.
-
(3) If P is n-thick, then $f(P)$ is n-thick.
-
(4) If $H<G$ and P is n-thick in G, then $H\cap P$ is n-thick in H.
Proof $(1)$ Assume that $P\cap Q$ is not $R(n,m)$ -thick and take the sequence $(a_i)_{i<R(n,m)}$ witnessing this. Consider the complete graph on $R(n,m)$ vertices with the following coloring: $\{i,j\}$ is black if and only if ${a_i}^{-1}a_j\not \in P$ , otherwise $\{i,j\}$ is white. By the Ramsey theorem either there is a clique of size n with all black edges, so P is not n-thick, or a clique of size m with white edges, so Q is not m-thick. $(2)$ – $(4)$ are immediate.
Lemma 2.3. The group $G^{\infty }_A$ is generated by the intersection of all A-definable thick subsets of G. More generally, suppose $n\in {\mathbb N}$ . Then $:$
-
(1) $X_{\Theta _A}^n = \bigcap \left \{P^n : P\subseteq G \text { is }A\text {-definable and thick}\right \}$ ,
-
(2) $X_{\Theta _A}^G = \bigcap \left \{P^G : P\subseteq G \text { is }A-\text {definable and thick}\right \}$ ,
-
(3) $X_{\Theta _A}^G \subseteq X_{\Theta _A}^4$ .
Proof $(1)$ is [Reference Gismatullin15, Lemma 3.3]. $(2) \subseteq $ is clear. For $\supseteq $ , take a from the intersection. By $(1)$ for $n=1$ and Lemma 2.2 $(1)$ , the type $p(x,y) = \{a = x^y,\ x \in P : P\subseteq G \text { is }A\text{-definable and thick} \}$ is consistent, so $a\in X_{\Theta _A}^G$ . $(3)$ By (2.3.1) and (2.3.2) we have
where $X_{\underset {M}{\equiv }}=\left \{a^{-1}b : a,b\in G, a\underset {M}{\equiv }b\right \}$ . Moreover $\left (X_{\underset {M}{\equiv }}\right )^{G} \subseteq X_{\underset {M}{\equiv }}^2$ holds. Indeed, if $y\in \left (X_{\underset {M}{\equiv }}\right )^{G}$ , then there are $a,x \in G$ and $h\in \operatorname {\mathrm {Aut}}(G/M)$ such that
Hence, by (※), we get $X_{\Theta _A}^{G} \subseteq X_{\Theta _A}^4$ .
Corollary 2.4. Let G be a group $($ not necessarily sufficiently saturated $)$ . If $P\subseteq G$ is thick, then there exists a thick subset $Q\subseteq P^4$ which is normal and $\emptyset $ -definable in the structure $(G,\cdot ,P)$ , where P is a predicate.
Proof Consider ${\mathcal G} = (G,\cdot , P)$ and let ${\mathcal G}^* = (G^*,\cdot , P^*)$ be a sufficiently saturated extension. By Lemma 2.3, $X_{\Theta _{\emptyset }}^{G^*} \subseteq X_{\Theta _{\emptyset }}^4 \subseteq {P^*}^4$ , and by compactness we can find a thick and $\emptyset $ -definable $Q\subseteq {G^*}$ , with $Q^{G^*} \subseteq {P^*}^4$ .
We need the following standard lemma, which was already in [Reference Gismatullin15, Remark 3.5(2)] and [Reference Bowler, Chen and Gismatullin6, Fact 2.4]. We include the sketch of the proof for the convenience of the reader.
Lemma 2.5. The component $G^{00}_A$ can be written as $\bigcap _{i\in I}P_i$ for some family $\{P_i : i\in I\}$ of thick and A-definable subsets of G such that
Proof Since $G^{00}_A$ is type definable over A of bounded index, there is a family ${\mathcal P}=\{P_i : i\in I\}$ of thick and A-definable subsets such that $G^{00}_A = \bigcap _{i\in I}P_i$ . By using Lemma 2.2(1), we may assume that ${\mathcal P}$ is closed under finite intersections.
Let us prove (†). Fix $i\in I$ . Because $G^{00}_A$ is a group, we have that
Using that G is saturated (compactness argument), there are finite sets $I_1,I_2\subset I$ such that
It is enough to set $P_j:= \bigcap _{i\in I_1\cup I_2}P_i$ .
3. Absolutely connected groups
The aim of the present section is to introduce the notion of (definable) absolute connectedness (Definition 3.3), and give some basic results on it. In short, G is absolutely connected if ${G^*}^{\infty }_A = G^*$ , for every small A, working in any sufficiently saturated extension $G^*$ of any arbitrary expansion of G. We introduce also an auxiliary subclass ${\mathcal W}$ of the class of absolutely connected groups (Definition 3.4).
The symbol $(G,\cdot ,\ldots )$ denotes a group G possibly equipped with extra first-order structure $(\ldots )$ . For example, G might be a definable group in some structure ${\mathcal M}$ . In this case, there is a natural induced structure on G from ${\mathcal M}$ (cf. [Reference Marker28, Section 1.3]). We usually do not assume that G is sufficiently saturated. By $G^*$ we always denote a sufficiently saturated elementary extension of $(G,\cdot ,\ldots )$ .
Proposition 3.1. The following are equivalent $:$
-
(1) ${G^*}^{\infty }$ exists and $G^* = {G^*}^{\infty }$ .
-
(2) There exists $n\in {\mathbb N}$ such that for every parameter-definable thick subset $P\subseteq G$ , $P^n = G$ (see Definition 2.1).
Note that since every thick set P contains the neutral element $P^n = P^{\leq n}$ .
Proof $(2)\Rightarrow (1)$ It is enough to show that $G^* = X_{\Theta _A}^n$ for every small set $A\subset G^*$ . Let $P^* = \varphi (G^*,\overline {a})$ be k-thick and $\overline {a} \subset A$ . Since in G it is true that ‘for every $\varphi $ -definable (with parameters) and k-thick $P\subseteq G$ , $P^n = G$ ’, the same is true in $G^*$ , that is, $\varphi (G^*,\overline {a})^n = G^*$ . Hence, by Lemma 2.3 $(1)$ , $G^* = X_{\Theta _A}^n={G^*}^{\infty }_A$ .
$(1)\Rightarrow (2)$ Suppose (2) fails. Thus, for every $n\in {\mathbb N}$ , there is $P_n\subset G^*$ , definable over some finite $A_n\subset G^*$ and thick, with $P_n^n\neq G^*$ . Let $A=\bigcup _{n\in {\mathbb N}}A_n$ . Then clearly, for every $n\in {\mathbb N}$ , we have $X_{\Theta _A}^n\subseteq {P_n}^n \neq G^*$ . By compactness ${G^*}^{\infty }_A\neq G^*$ , which is impossible.
In the next proposition we consider groups G having the property $G^* = {G^*}^{\infty }$ in all first-order expansions.
Proposition 3.2. Let G be a non-trivial group. The following conditions are equivalent.
-
(1) There exists $n\in {\mathbb N}$ such that for every thick subset $P \subseteq G$ (not necessarily definable), $P^n = G$ .
-
(2) G is infinite and if $G^*$ is a sufficiently saturated extension of any first-order expansion of G, then ${G^*}^{\infty }$ exists and $G^* = {G^*}^{\infty }$ .
Furthermore if $(1)$ holds, then ${G^*}^{\infty } = X_{\Theta _A}^n$ for every small $A\subset G^*$ and arbitrary sufficiently saturated extension $G^*$ of G.
Proof $(1) \Rightarrow (2) G$ is infinite, because otherwise the thick subset $\{e\}$ of G does not fulfill the condition from $(1)$ . The rest of $(2)$ follows easily from Proposition 3.1.
$(2) \Rightarrow (1)$ Suppose, contrary to our claim, that for every $n\in {\mathbb N}$ there is a thick subset $P_n$ of G with $P_n^n\neq G$ . Expand the structure of G by predicates for all $P_n$ . If $G^*$ is a sufficiently saturated extension of G, then clearly for every $n\in {\mathbb N}$ we have $X_{\Theta _{\emptyset }}^n\subseteq {P^*_n}^n \neq G^*$ , so ${G^*}^{\infty }_\emptyset \neq G^*$ , contrary to $(2)$ .
In [Reference Gismatullin and Newelski19, Section 3] we made a link between model-theoretic connected components and strong types. Strong types are fundamental objects in model theory and correspond to orbits on $G^*$ of some canonical subgroups of $\operatorname {\mathrm {Aut}}(G^*)$ . In [Reference Newelski31] Newelski considers the diameters of Lascar strong types. Motivated by his idea we introduce below (Definition 3.3) the notion of $n-$ (definable absolutely connected group, for $n\in {\mathbb N}$ . It turns out that G is n-definable absolutely connected if and only if the Lascar strong type of a sort X in a certain structure $(G,\circ ,X)$ has diameter at most n [Reference Gismatullin and Newelski19, Section 3].
Definition 3.3.
-
(1) A group G is called n-absolutely connected or n-ac, if it satisfies the condition $(1)$ from Proposition 3.2, that is, for every thick subset $P\subseteq G$ , we have $P^n = G$ .
-
(2) We say that a group $(G,\cdot ,\ldots )$ with some first-order structure is n-definably absolutely connected, if for every definable (with parameters) thick $P\subseteq G$ , we have $P^n = G$ .
-
(3) A group is [definably] absolutely connected, if it is n-[definably] absolutely connected, for some $n\in {\mathbb N}$ .
It is clear that every elementary extension of an absolutely connected group is definably absolutely connected.
Let us relate absolute connectedness with simplicity. A group G is called simple, if G has no proper nontrivial normal subgroup. A finer notion is of uniform simplicity. A group G is n-uniformly simple if for every $g\in G\setminus \{e\}$ and $x\in G$ , the element x is the product of n or fewer conjugates of $g^{\pm 1}$ . Obviously uniform simplicity implies simplicity, as if $H\lhd G$ is a nontrivial, there is $g\in H$ , $g\neq e$ , then every $x\in G$ is the product conjugates of $g^{\pm 1}$ , hence $x\in H$ , as H is a normal subgroup. Many examples of uniformly simple groups (e.g., some groups acting on trees) are given in [Reference Gal and Gismatullin14, Reference Gismatullin16].
Observe that for fixed $n\in {\mathbb N}$ , the notion of n-uniform simplicity is a first-order property, expressible in the language of groups $L_G=\{\cdot \}$ . Obviously, every uniformly simple group is absolutely connected. In order to give other examples of absolutely connected groups, we introduce auxiliary classes ${\mathcal W}_n$ , $n\in {\mathbb N}$ of groups. Each ${\mathcal W}_n$ is a proper subclass of the class of absolutely connected groups (Theorem 3.11 and Proposition 8.1).
For $n\in {\mathbb N}$ define
If G is n-uniformly simple, then ${\mathcal G}_n(G) = G\setminus \{e\}$ . In Definition 3.4 we require the set ${\mathcal G}_n(G)$ to be big in a weaker sense.
Definition 3.4. We say that a group G is in class ${\mathcal W}_n$ if
That is, for every $k\in {\mathbb N}$ , there is a sequence $(g_i)_{i<k}$ in G such that $g_i^{-1}g_j\in {\mathcal G}_n(G)$ for all $i<j<k$ . We also define ${\mathcal W}=\bigcup _{n\in {\mathbb N}}{\mathcal W}_n$ .
In Proposition 3.8 and Lemma 3.9 we collect basic properties of absolutely connected groups and groups from the class ${\mathcal W}$ . We give two lemmas for use in the proofs.
Definition 3.5. We say that a subset $P \subseteq G$ is m-generic in G if there are elements $g_1,\ldots ,g_m$ from G, such that $\bigcup _{1\leq i\leq m}P\cdot g_i = G$ .
Lemma 3.6 [Reference Gismatullin15, Lemmas 3.2(4) and 3.6]
-
(1) If P is an m-generic subset of G, $1 \in P$ , and $P = P^{-1}$ , then $P^{3m-2}$ is a subgroup of G of index at most m.
-
(2) If P is m-generic, then $P^{-1}P$ is $(m + 1)$ -thick. If P is m-thick, then P is $(m-1)$ -generic.
Lemma 3.7. Let G be a perfect group with $\operatorname {\mathrm {cw}}(G) = n<\infty $ , and let $A \subseteq G$ be a normal and symmetric subset. If $B < G$ is a solvable subgroup of derived length m and $G = A \cdot B$ , then $G=A^{(4n)^m}$ .
Proof Let C be the set of all commutators. By the assumption $G = C^n$ . We use the following commutator identity:
It is enough to prove $G = A^{\left (4n\right )^k}\cdot B^{(k)}$ for every $k\in {\mathbb N}$ . The case $k=0$ follows from the assumption, as we set $B^{(0)}=B$ . For the induction step, note that (*) implies that $C\subseteq A^{4\left (4n\right )^k}\cdot \left [B^{(k)},B^{(k)}\right ]$ and then $G = A^{{\left (4n\right )}^{k+1}}\cdot B^{(k+1)}$ , since $G = C^n$ and A is a normal subset of G.
Proposition 3.8. Let $f\colon G \to H$ be an epimorphism of groups.
-
(1) If G is n-ac, then H is also n-ac.
-
(2) If H is $n_1$ -ac and $\ker (f)$ is $n_2$ -ac, then G is $(n_1+n_2)$ -ac.
-
(3) If $G = \bigcup _{i\in I}G_i$ and each $G_i$ is n-ac, then G is n-ac.
-
(4) If H is n-ac, G has no subgroups of finite index, and $\ker (f)$ is finite of cardinality m, then G is $n(3m-2)$ -ac.
-
(5) If H is n-ac, G is perfect with $\operatorname {\mathrm {cw}}(G) = r <\infty $ , and $\ker (f)$ is solvable of derived length m, then G is $4n\left (4r\right )^m$ -ac.
Proof Proofs of (1)–(3) are standard. $(4)$ Let $P\subseteq G$ be thick. Then $f(P)^n=H$ , so $G = P^n\cdot \ker (f)$ and $P^{n}$ is right m-generic. By Lemma 3.6 $(1)$ , $G = P^{n(3m-2)}$ . $(5)$ Take a thick subset $P\subseteq G$ . By (2.4), the set $P^4$ contains a normal thick subset Q. Then as in $(4)$ , $G = Q^{n}\cdot \ker (f)$ . By Lemma 3.7, $G = Q^{n\left (4r\right )^m} = P^{4n\left (4r\right )^m}.$
As in Proposition 3.8, we can prove that the class ${\mathcal W}$ is closed under certain operations.
Lemma 3.9.
-
(1) For each $n\in {\mathbb N}$ , the class ${\mathcal W}_n$ is elementary in the pure language of groups and is closed under taking homomorphic images, direct sums, and arbitrary direct products.
-
(2) Let $f\colon G \to H$ be an epimorphism of groups.
-
(a) If $H\in {\mathcal W}_n$ , G has no subgroups of finite index and $\ker (f)$ is finite of cardinality m, then $G\in {\mathcal W}_{n(3m-2)}$ .
-
(b) If $H\in {\mathcal W}_n$ , G is perfect with commutator width $\operatorname {\mathrm {cw}}(G) = r <\infty $ and $\ker (f)$ is solvable of derived length m, then $G\in {\mathcal W}_{n\left (4r\right )^m}$ .
-
Proof $(1)$ This follows from the following remarks: if $f\colon G \to H$ is an epimorphism, then $f\left ({\mathcal G}_n(G)\right ) \subseteq {\mathcal G}_n(H)$ , ${\mathcal G}_n\left (\bigoplus _{i\in I} G_i\right ) = \bigoplus _{i\in I} {\mathcal G}_n\left (G_i\right )$ , and ${\mathcal G}_n\left (\prod _{i\in I} G_i\right ) = \prod _{i\in I} {\mathcal G}_n\left (G_i\right )$ .
$(2)$ The proof is identical to the proof of Proposition 3.8 $(4)$ and $(5)$ .
Remark 3.10. In fact, Proposition 3.8 $(5)$ and Lemma 3.9 $(2b)$ are true under the condition $\operatorname {\mathrm {cw}}^G(\ker (f))<\infty $ , instead of $\operatorname {\mathrm {cw}}(G)<\infty $ . The reason is that Lemma 3.7 can be proved under the assumption that $\operatorname {\mathrm {cw}}^G(B)<\infty $ , instead of $\operatorname {\mathrm {cw}}(G)<\infty $ . We leave the verification of this to the interested reader.
We finish this section by proving that every group from ${\mathcal W}$ is absolutely connected.
Theorem 3.11. Every group from ${\mathcal W}_n$ is $4n$ -absolutely connected.
Proof Let $P\subseteq G$ be a thick subset. We will prove that $P^{4n} = G$ . By Corollary 2.4, there is a thick and normal subset $Q \subseteq P^4$ . Since $G\in {\mathcal W}$ , we have that $Q \cap {\mathcal G}_n(G) \neq \emptyset $ (because otherwise $Q\subseteq G \setminus {\mathcal G}_n(G)$ and then $G \setminus {\mathcal G}_n(G)$ would be thick). Take $g\in Q \cap {\mathcal G}_n(G)$ . Since Q is symmetric, we have that
It is enough to use Definition 3.4.
Examples of absolutely connected groups are given in Sections 7 and 8.
4. Type-absolute connectedness
In this section we use the notation from Section 3. We introduce the concept of type-absolute connectedness: G is type-absolutely connected if ${G^*}^{00}_A = G^*$ , for every small subset A of G and any monster model $G^*$ of G. Note that we restrict A to be a subset of G, not of $G^*$ as in the definition of absolute connectedness. We collect basic properties of type-absolutely connected groups below.
Remark 4.1. The following conditions are equivalent.
-
(1) ${G^*} = {G^*}^{00}_A$ holds.
-
(2) There is no family $\{P_n : n\in {\mathbb N}\}$ of A-definable thick subsets of $G^*$ such that:
-
(a) $P_{n+1}P_{n+1}\subseteq P_n$ , for each $n\in {\mathbb N}$ ,
-
(b) $P_0$ is a proper subset of $G^*$ .
-
Proof $(1)\Rightarrow (2)$ Suppose $\{P_n : n\in {\mathbb N}\}$ is such a family. Then the intersection $H=\bigcap _{n\in {\mathbb N}}P_n$ is a type-definable over A proper subgroup of $G^*$ . Since every $P_n$ is thick, H has bounded index in $G^*$ . Therefore ${G^*}^{00}_A\subseteq H\subseteq P_0\neq G^*$ . $(2)\Rightarrow (1)$ follows by Lemma 2.5.
Definition 4.2. A group G is called type-absolutely connected if for any sufficiently saturated extension $G^*$ of any first-order expansion $(G,\cdot ,\ldots )$ of G, we have $G^* = {G^*}^{00}_G$ . Equivalently (by using Remark 4.1), for an arbitrary family $\{P_n : n\in {\mathbb N}\}$ of thick subsets of G satisfying (4.1 $(2a)$ ), $P_n=G$ holds for every $n\in {\mathbb N}$ .
The equivalence in Definition 4.2 is because of Lemma 2.5 and the following observation:
the thickness can be stated as a first order property, so a subset $P\subseteq G$ is thick if and only if its interpretation $P^* \subseteq G^*$ is thick.
Observe that, every type-absolutely connected group is infinite (as $\{e\}$ is thick in any finite group). Every absolutely connected group is type-absolutely connected. The converse is not true (cf. Corollary 5.4 $(2)$ ). In fact, if G is type-absolutely connected but not absolutely connected, then ${G^*}^{00}_{\emptyset }/{G^*}^{\infty }_{\emptyset }$ is nontrivial for some saturated extension $G^*$ of G.
We prove in Proposition 4.3 a stronger version of Proposition 3.8 $(3)$ for the class of type-absolutely connected groups. In fact Proposition 4.3 is false for absolutely connected groups (cf. Corollary 5.4 $(2)$ ).
Proposition 4.3. If G is generated by a family $\{G_i\}_{i\in I}$ of type-absolutely connected subgroups, then G itself is type-absolutely connected.
Proof Take an arbitrary family $\{P_n : n\in {\mathbb N}\}$ of thick sets in G satisfying Remark 4.1 $(2a)$ . Fix $n\in {\mathbb N}$ , $i\in I$ , and consider $P^\prime _n = G_i\cap P_n$ . Clearly $P^\prime _{n+1}P^\prime _{n+1}\subseteq P^\prime _n$ , so since $G_i$ is type-absolutely connected, $G_i\subseteq P_n$ for any $i\in I$ . Similarly, by Remark 4.1 $(2a)$ , $P_n$ contains any finite product $G_{i_1}\cdot \ldots \cdot G_{i_m}$ . Hence, $P_n=G$ .
The proof of the following proposition is similar to the proof of Proposition 3.8 $(1,2)$ .
Proposition 4.4. Let $f\colon G \to H$ be an epimorphism of groups.
-
(1) If G is type-absolutely connected, then H is also type-absolutely connected.
-
(2) If H and $\ker (f)$ are type-absolutely connected, then G is type-absolutely connected.
-
(3) If H is type-absolutely connected, $\ker (f)$ is finite and G has no subgroups of finite index, then G is type-absolutely connected.
Proposition 4.5. Every type-absolutely connected group is perfect.
Proof First we verify that the abelian groups ${\mathbb Z}/p{\mathbb Z}$ and ${\mathbb Z}\left [\tfrac {1}{p}\right ]/{\mathbb Z}$ , for prime p, are not type-absolutely connected. The group ${\mathbb Z}/p{\mathbb Z}$ is not type-absolutely connected, because is finite. Let $H = {\mathbb Z}\left [\tfrac {1}{p}\right ]/{\mathbb Z}$ . Then H can be viewed as a dense subgroup of the circle group $S^1$ . Let us identify
where the addition is modulo 1. Consider the following collection of neighborhoods of $0$ in $S^1$ :
Observe that each $P_n$ is thick in $S^1$ (in fact is -thick) and
Therefore ${\mathcal P}$ form a collection of thick subsets of $S^1$ , contradicting the condition from Definition 4.2. Since H is dense in $S^1$ , intersections of these neighborhoods with H also work for H. Thus H is not type-absolutely connected.
Suppose, for a contradiction, that there is a non-perfect type-absolutely connected group G. Then by Proposition 4.4 $(1) G/[G,G]$ is type-absolutely connected. The next lemma (which is presumably already known but we could not find a relevant reference) implies that our group $G/[G,G]$ may be mapped homomorphically onto ${\mathbb Z}/p{\mathbb Z}$ or ${\mathbb Z}\left [\tfrac {1}{p}\right ]/{\mathbb Z}$ , which is impossible.
Lemma 4.6. Every abelian group can be homomorphically mapped onto ${\mathbb Z}/p{\mathbb Z}$ or ${\mathbb Z}\left [\tfrac {1}{p}\right ]/{\mathbb Z}$ , for some prime p.
Proof Let G be an abelian group. We may assume that G is infinite, because otherwise G can be mapped onto ${\mathbb Z}/p{\mathbb Z}$ . We may also assume that G is a torsion group. Indeed, suppose that there is $g\in G$ of infinite order. Let $H < G$ be a subgroup of G maximal subject to being disjoint from the set $\{g^n : n\in {\mathbb Z}\setminus \{0\}\}$ . When $G/H \cong {\mathbb Z}$ , G can be mapped onto ${\mathbb Z}/2{\mathbb Z}$ . If $G/H \not \cong {\mathbb Z}$ , then $G/\langle H,g\rangle $ is a nontrivial torsion group (for every $a\in G\setminus H$ , there is n, such that $g^n \in \langle H,a \rangle $ , so $a^m\in \langle H,g \rangle $ for some m). Every torsion abelian group G splits as a direct sum of Sylow p-subgroups $G = \bigoplus _{p\in {\mathbb P}}G_p$ , where each element of $G_p$ has order $p^n$ for some $n\in {\mathbb N}$ . Hence we may assume that $G = G_p$ is a p-group. If $G \neq p\cdot G$ , then $G/pG$ is a vector space over finite field ${\mathbb F}_p$ , so there is a mapping from G onto ${\mathbb Z}/p{\mathbb Z}$ . If $G = pG$ , then G is divisible. By a well-known fact, every divisible abelian group splits as a direct sum of groups isomorphic to ${\mathbb Q}$ or to ${\mathbb Z}\left [\tfrac {1}{p}\right ]$ . Since G is torsion, G can be mapped onto ${\mathbb Z}\left [\tfrac {1}{p}\right ]/{\mathbb Z}$ . This finishes the proof.
Since every type-absolutely connected group is perfect, the natural question arises about the commutator width of these groups. In general, type-absolutely connected group might have infinite commutator width. For instance, by Remark 6.11, the topological universal cover $\widetilde {\operatorname {\mathrm {SL}}_2({\mathbb R})}$ is type-absolutely connected and $\operatorname {\mathrm {cw}}\left (\widetilde {\operatorname {\mathrm {SL}}_2({\mathbb R})}\right )=\infty $ . Proposition 4.7 answers this question for groups from ${\mathcal W}$ (cf. Definition 3.4).
Proposition 4.7. For every $N\in {\mathbb N}$ there is a constant $k_N$ such that every group from ${\mathcal W}_N$ has commutator width at most $k_N$ .
Proof Suppose that for every $k\in {\mathbb N}$ there is $G_k\in {\mathcal W}_k$ with commutator width at least k. Take $g_k\in G_k$ of commutator length at least k. Consider the product $G = \prod _{k\in {\mathbb N}}G_k$ . The group G is in ${\mathcal W}_N$ (Lemma 3.9 $(1)$ ); hence G is perfect. However $G \neq [G,G]$ , because the element $g=(g_k)_{k\in {\mathbb N}}\in G$ has infinite commutator length, so is not in $[G,G]$ .
4.1. Quotients
We give a general remark about the model-theoretic connected components of a quotient group. We use this remark in Remark 7.8. Suppose $f\colon G\to H$ is a surjective homomorphism and G, H, f are A-definable in some structure ${\mathcal M}$ . For example, suppose ${\mathcal M}=G$ and $\ker (f)$ is A-definable subgroup of G. Assume that ${\mathcal M}$ (and so G and H) is sufficiently saturated. We describe the relationship between the connected components of G and H. It is clear that $f\left (G^{\infty }_A\right ) = H^{\infty }_A$ , $f\left (G^{00}_A\right ) = H^{00}_A$ , and $f\left (G^{0}_A\right ) = H^{0}_A$ . Therefore f induces natural surjective homomorphisms $f^{00}\colon G/G^{00}_A \to H/H^{00}_A$ and $f^{\infty }\colon G/G^{\infty }_A \to H/H^{\infty }_A$ .
Remark 4.8. If $\ker (f)$ is absolutely connected, then $f^{-1}(H^{\infty }_A)=G^{\infty }_A$ and $G/G^{\infty }_A \cong H/H^{\infty }_A$ . If $\ker (f)$ is type-absolutely connected, then $f^{-1}(H^{00}_A)= G^{00}_A$ and $G/G^{00}_A \cong H/H^{00}_A$ .
Proof We prove the first part. The intersection $\ker (f)\cap G^{\infty }_A$ is A-invariant bounded index subgroup of $\ker (f)$ ; hence $\ker (f)\subseteq G^{\infty }_A$ . The proof of the second part is similar.
5. Generalized quasimorphisms
Our goal in this section is to construct a group G such that ${G^*}^{00}_{\emptyset }/{G^*}^{\infty }_{\emptyset }$ is far from being abelian (Theorem 5.11). To this aim we first introduce and use the concept of a generalized quasimorphism of a group (Definition 5.2) and then, using certain method of recovering of a compact Hausdorff group from a dense subgroup via standard part map (Theorem 5.7), we construct such an example (Theorem 5.11).
A quasimorphism or pseudocharacter on a group G is a real-valued function $f\colon G \to {\mathbb R}$ such that for some $r\in {\mathbb R}$ , called the defect of f, the following holds $|f(xy)-f(x)-f(y)|<r$ , for all $x,y\in G$ [Reference Kotschick26, Reference Shtern37].
If G is type-absolutely connected, then by Proposition 4.5, every homomorphism from G to $({\mathbb R},+)$ is trivial. However, G might admit many unbounded quasimorphism. For example, a free product $G=G_1*G_2$ of two absolutely connected groups $G_1$ and $G_2$ is type-absolutely connected (Proposition 4.3). The next example provides many unbounded quasimorphisms on G.
Example 5.1. [Reference Shtern37, 5.a] Suppose V and W are nontrivial groups and decompose V into a disjoint union , where $V_+^{-1}=V_-$ (for example, $V_+=\{v\}$ , for $v^2\ne e$ ). Define $s\colon V\to {\mathbb Z}$ as: $s(v)=1$ if $v\in V_+$ , $s(v)=-1$ if $v\in V_-$ and $s(v)=0$ if $v\in V_0$ . Then the map $f\colon V*W \to {\mathbb Z}$ defined as $f(v_1w_1v_2w_2\ldots )=\Sigma s(v_i)$ is an unbounded quasimorphism of defect 3. Note that f is surjective.
Definition 5.2. We say that $f\colon G\to H$ is a generalized quasimorphisms with defect $S\subset H$ if $f(x)f(y)f(xy)^{-1}\in S$ and $f\left (x^{-1}\right )=f(x)^{-1}$ , for all $x,y\in G$ .
Below is a variant of Lemma 2.2 $(2)$ for generalized quasimorphisms.
Proposition 5.3. Suppose $f\colon G\to H$ is a generalized quasimorphism of defect S. Let $P\subseteq H$ be n-thick and define $Q=f^{-1}(SP)\cap f^{-1}(SP)^{-1}$ . Then $:$
-
(1) Q is n-thick in G,
-
(2) if additionally $SP = PS$ and $S=S^{-1}$ , then for each $m\in {\mathbb N},$
$$\begin{align*}Q^m \subseteq f^{-1}\left(S^{2m-1}P^m\right)\cap f^{-1}\left(S^{2m-1}P^m\right)^{-1}.\end{align*}$$
Proof $(1)$ follows from $f(xy^{-1})\in Sf(x)f(y)^{-1}$ . $(2)$ follows from $f^{-1}(A)\cdot f^{-1}(B) \subseteq f^{-1}\left (S^{-1}AB\right )$ for $A,B\subseteq H$ .
Corollary 5.4.
-
(1) Every quasimorphism on an absolutely connected group is a bounded function.
-
(2) Suppose $G_1$ and $G_2$ are infinite groups. The free product $G=G_1*G_2$ is not absolutely connected. If moreover $G_1$ and $G_2$ are type-absolutely connected, then by Proposition 4.3, G is type-absolutely connected. Hence $G^*={G^*}^{00}_{\emptyset }\neq {G^*}^{\infty }_{\emptyset }$ , for some monster model $G^*\succ G$ .
Proof $(2)$ follows from $(1)$ and Example 5.1. $(1)$ Let f be a quasimorphism on G of defect $r\in {\mathbb R}$ . Suppose that $\operatorname {\mathrm {Im}}(f)\subseteq {\mathbb R}$ is unbounded. For each $N\geq 1$ there is a thick subset $P_N$ of $({\mathbb R},+)$ such that
For example as $P_N$ one can take $g^{-1}(-\varepsilon ,\varepsilon )$ , where $g\colon {\mathbb R}\to {\mathbb R}/t{\mathbb Z}$ is the quotient map and some $\varepsilon ,t>0$ . By Proposition 5.3, the group G is not absolutely connected. Indeed
is thick in G and $Q^N\subseteq f^{-1}\left (P_N^N+(-(2N-1)r,(2N-1)r)\right )\neq G$ .
The proof of the proposition below is straightforward. It says that a free product of a family of quasimorphisms is a generalized quasimorphism.
Proposition 5.5. Suppose $\{G_i\}_{i\in I}$ is a family of groups and $f_i\colon G_i \to {\mathbb Z} = x_i{\mathbb Z}$ is a quasimorphism of defect $r_i$ , for $i\in I$ . Let $G=*_{i\in I}G_i$ . Then
is a generalized quasimorphism of defect $S = \bigcup _{i\in I} \bigcup _{k=-r_i}^{r_i} {x_i^k}^{{\mathbb F}_I}$ , where ${\mathbb F}_I$ is a free group of basis $\{x_i\}_{i\in I}$ and ${x_i^k}^{{\mathbb F}_I}$ is the conjugacy class of ${x_i}^k$ in ${\mathbb F}_I$ .
We prove now that every generalized quasimorphism induces a homomorphism after passing to a saturated extension and taking quotient by the subgroup generated by the defect.
Proposition 5.6. Suppose $f\colon G \to H$ is a surjective generalized quasimorphism of defect S, where $S=S^{-1}$ and S is normal in H. Assume that G, H, f, and S are A-definable in some structure ${\mathcal M}$ . Then, for a monster model ${\mathcal M}^*$ of ${\mathcal M}$ , $f^*$ induces an epimorphism
where $\overline {G}=G^*/{G^*}^{\infty }_A$ , $\overline {H}=H^*/{H^*}^{\infty }_A$ , and $\left \langle \overline {S}\right \rangle $ is generated in $\overline {H}$ by $\overline {S}= S^*/{H^*}^{\infty }_A$ .
The components ${G^*}^{\infty }_A$ and ${H^*}^{\infty }_A$ of $G^*$ and $H^*$ in Proposition 5.6 are calculated with respect to the structure on G and H induced from ${\mathcal M}$ .
Proof Since $\overline {H}/\left \langle \overline {S}\right \rangle = H^*/\left \langle S^*\right \rangle {H^*}^{\infty }_A$ , it is enough to check that $f^*({G^*}^{\infty }_A)\subseteq \left \langle S^*\right \rangle {H^*}^{\infty }_A$ . Then it is immediate that $\overline {f}$ is an epimorphism. Since $f(xy)\in S^{-1} f(x)f(y)$ and ${G^*}^{\infty }_A$ is generated by $X_{\Theta _A}$ (cf. Section 2.4) we get $f^*({G^*}^{\infty }_A) = f^*\left (\left \langle X_{\Theta }\right \rangle \right )\subseteq \left \langle S^*\right \rangle \left \langle f^*\left ( X_{\Theta _A}\right )\right \rangle $ . By compactness, Lemma 2.3 $(1)$ , and Proposition 5.3 $(1)$ , we have
so $\left \langle f^*\left ( X_{\Theta _A}\right )\right \rangle \subseteq \left \langle S^*\right \rangle {H^*}^{\infty }_A.$
In Theorem 5.7 below we recover a compact topological group from its dense subgroup.
Theorem 5.7. Suppose C is a compact Hausdorff topological group and $D < C$ is a dense subgroup. Let $\{U_i\}_{i\in I}$ be a family of open subsets of C such that $:$
-
(1) $\{U_i\}_{i\in I}$ is a basis of the topology at the identity e of C, closed under finite intersections,
-
(2) for every $i\in I$ , there is $j\in I$ such that $\overline {U_{j}}^2\subseteq U_i$ and $U_i=U_i^{-1}$ ,
-
(3) $x^{-1}U_ix=U_i$ for $i\in I$ , $x\in C$ .
Suppose D is equipped with some structure ${\mathcal D}=(D,\cdot ,\ldots )$ in a such a way that for some $A\subseteq D$ , $U^\prime _i=U_i\cap D$ is A-definable in ${\mathcal D}$ for each $i\in I (\,\textit{for example}, {\mathcal D} = (D,\cdot ,U^\prime _i)_{i\in I}$ , where each $U^\prime _i$ is a predicate and $A=\emptyset )$ .
Then, for every monster model ${\mathcal D}^*$ , there exists a surjective homomorphism. $\operatorname {\mathrm {st}}\colon {\mathcal D}^* \to C$ , called the standard part map, such that:
-
(a) $\ker (\operatorname {\mathrm {st}})=\bigcap _{i\in I}{U^\prime _i}^*$ is an A-type-definable bounded index normal subgroup of ${\mathcal D}^*$ ,
-
(b) $\operatorname {\mathrm {st}}(d)=d$ , for $d\in D$ ; for a definable subset S of D, if $S^*$ is the interpretation of S in ${\mathcal D}^*$ , then $\operatorname {\mathrm {st}}(S^*)=\overline {S}$ (the closure is taken in C),
-
(c) $\operatorname {\mathrm {st}}$ induces a homeomorphic isomorphism $\widetilde {\operatorname {\mathrm {st}}} \colon {\mathcal D}^*/\ker (\operatorname {\mathrm {st}}) \to C$ , where ${\mathcal D}^*/\ker (\operatorname {\mathrm {st}})$ is endowed with the logic topology.
Proof Since C is compact, each $U_i$ is a generic subset of C (cf. Definition 3.5) and by Lemma 3.6 $(2)$ and $(2)$ , $U_i$ is thick in C. Hence $U^\prime _i = U_i\cap D$ is thick in D (cf. Lemma 2.2 $(4)$ ), and again by Lemma 3.6 $(2)$ , we obtain that $U^\prime _i$ is generic in D.
We define $\operatorname {\mathrm {st}}\colon {\mathcal D}^* \to C$ . Let $x\in {\mathcal D}^*$ . For each $i\in I$ there is $d_i\in D$ such that $x\in d_i {U^\prime _i}^*$ . Hence, the family $\left \{d_i\overline {U_i}\right \}_{i\in I}$ has the finite intersection property in C. By $(2)$ and $(3)$ , there is a unique $y\in C$ such that $\bigcap _{i\in I} d_i\overline {U_i} = \{y\}$ . Indeed, if $y_1,y_2\in \bigcap _{i\in I} d_i\overline {U_i}$ , then $y_2^{-1}y_1\in \bigcap _{i\in I}\overline {U_i}^2 = \{e\}$ . Define $\operatorname {\mathrm {st}}(x)$ as the unique element from $\bigcap _{i\in I} \overline {d_i U_i}$ .
Note the following property, which will be used in the rest of the proof: for $x\in {\mathcal D}^*$ , $d\in D$ , and $i\in I$ , if $x\in d {U^\prime _i}^*$ , then $\operatorname {\mathrm {st}}(x)\in d\overline {U_i}$ .
Since D is dense in C, $\operatorname {\mathrm {st}}$ is surjective. Hence, the first part $(b)$ is true.
It follows from $(1)$ that $\operatorname {\mathrm {st}}^{-1}(e)=\bigcap _{i\in I}{U^\prime _i}^*$ ; hence $(a)$ follows.
Let $x,x'\in {\mathcal D}^*$ . We prove that $\operatorname {\mathrm {st}}(xx')=\operatorname {\mathrm {st}}(x)\operatorname {\mathrm {st}}(x')$ . It is enough to find for each $i\in I$ an element $d\in D$ such that $\operatorname {\mathrm {st}}(xx'),\operatorname {\mathrm {st}}(x)\operatorname {\mathrm {st}}(x')\in d\overline {U_i}$ . Fix $i\in I$ . There is $j\in I$ satisfying $(2)$ and $d_j,d^\prime _j\in D$ such that $x\in d_j {U^\prime _j}^*$ and $x'\in d^\prime _j {U^\prime _j}^*$ . Then
by $(3)$ . Hence $\operatorname {\mathrm {st}}(xx')\in d_jd^\prime _j\overline {U_i}$ . Moreover $\operatorname {\mathrm {st}}(x)\operatorname {\mathrm {st}}(x')\in d_jd^\prime _j {\overline {U_j}}^{d^\prime _j}\overline {U_j}=d_jd^\prime _j\overline {U_j}^2\subseteq d_jd^\prime _j\overline {U_i}$ .
We prove $(b)$ . For $\subseteq $ suppose $s=\operatorname {\mathrm {st}}(s^*)$ , for some $s^*\in S^*$ . By $(1)$ it is enough to prove that for every $i\in I$ , $sU_i\cap S\ne \emptyset $ . Take $j\in I$ such that $\overline {U_{j}}^2\subseteq U_i$ . Suppose $s^*\in d{U^\prime _j}^*$ for $d\in D$ . Then $s\in d\overline {U_j}$ in C and $S^*\cap d{U^\prime _j}^*\ne \emptyset $ in ${\mathcal D}^*$ . Hence, the same is true in ${\mathcal D}$ , that is there is $s'\in S$ , such that $s'\in dU^\prime _j$ . Thus $d\in s' U^\prime _j$ , so $s\in d\overline {U_j} \subseteq s' U_j\overline {U_j}\subseteq s'U_i$ , and then $s'\in sU_i$ . $\supseteq $ follows by compactness.
We prove, using $(b)$ , that $\operatorname {\mathrm {st}}$ induces a continuous isomorphism $\widetilde {\operatorname {\mathrm {st}}}\colon {\mathcal D}^*/\ker (\operatorname {\mathrm {st}}) \to C$ of compact Hausdorff groups, i.e., $\widetilde {\operatorname {\mathrm {st}}}$ is a homeomorphism. It is immediate (see [Reference Pillay33, Section 2]) that the following family forms a basis of the logic topology for closed sets of ${\mathcal D}^*/\ker (\operatorname {\mathrm {st}})$ :
where $Y_{\varphi }=\{x\in D^* : x\ker (st)\cap \varphi (D^*)\ne \emptyset \}=\varphi (D^*)\ker (st)$ . Hence using $(b)$ we get $\widetilde {\operatorname {\mathrm {st}}}\left (Y_{\varphi }/\ker (\operatorname {\mathrm {st}})\right )=\operatorname {\mathrm {st}}(Y_{\varphi })=\operatorname {\mathrm {st}}(\varphi (D^*)) =\overline {\varphi (D)}$ is closed in C.
Remark 5.8. By [Reference Hofmann and Morris23, 1.12], every compact Hausdorff topological group has small normal neighbourhoods, that is, the identity element has a neighbourhood basis consisting of sets invariant under inner automorphisms. Hence, every such group has a basis at the identity satisfying $(1)$ – $(3)$ from Proposition 5.7.
Theorem 5.9. Suppose C is a compact Hausdorff group and $D<C$ is a dense subgroup generated by $D=\langle d_i \rangle _{i\in I}$ . Let $S = \bigcup _{k=-3}^3\bigcup _{i\in I}{d_i^k}^{D}$ . Then there exist a type-absolutely connected group G with some first-order structure, and an epimorphism
where $\overline {S}$ is the closure of S in C.
Proof Let $\{V_i,W_i\}_{i\in I}$ be an arbitrary family of type-absolutely connected groups. For each $i\in I$ take a quasimorphism $f_i\colon V_i*W_i \to {\mathbb Z}$ of defect 3 from Example 5.1. Let $G=*_{i\in I}V_i*W_i$ and $f'=*_{i\in I}f_i$ . Then by Proposition 5.5, $f'\colon G \to {\mathbb F}_I$ is a generalized quasimorphism. Compose $f'$ with the natural epimorphism $i\colon {\mathbb F}_I \to D$ , to get a generalized quasimorphism $f=f'\circ i\colon G \to D$ of defect S. Consider the following structure:
where $U^\prime _j=U_j\cap D$ , for some basis $\{U_j\}_{j\in J}$ of C satisfying (1)–(3) from Proposition 5.7 (cf. Remark 5.8). By Proposition 4.3, G is type-absolutely connected, so by Proposition 5.6 f induces an epimorphism
where $\overline {D}={D^*}/{D^*}^{\infty }_{\emptyset }$ . By Proposition 5.7 there is a continuous epimorphism $\widetilde {\operatorname {\mathrm {st}}}\colon \overline {D}={D^*}/{D^*}^{\infty }_{\emptyset }\to {D^*}/\ker (\operatorname {\mathrm {st}}) \cong C$ , such that $\widetilde {\operatorname {\mathrm {st}}}(\overline {S})$ is the closure of S in C. By composing $\widetilde {\operatorname {\mathrm {st}}}\mod \left \langle \overline {S}\right \rangle $ with $\overline {f}$ we get the desired epimorphism.
We give some applications of Theorem 5.9.
Example 5.10. Let $D=\langle d_1,d_2 \rangle $ be a free group, freely generated by $d_1,d_2$ , let $C=\widehat {D}$ be a profinite completion of D, and let $S\subset D$ be defined as in Theorem 5.9. Then $\left \langle \overline {S}\right \rangle = N(x_1,x_2)$ is the normal closure of $d_1,d_2$ in C (as every conjugacy class in $\widehat {D}$ is closed). Hence, by Theorem 5.9, $\widehat {D}/N(x_1,x_2)$ is a homomorphic image of ${G^*}^{00}_{\emptyset }/{G^*}^{\infty }_{\emptyset }$ , for some type-absolutely connected group G. Recent remarkable result of Nikolov–Segal [Reference Nikolov and Segal32, 1.6] implies that the quotient $\widehat {D}/N(x_1,x_2)$ is abelian.
We now find C, D, and S as in Theorem 5.9, such that $C/\left \langle \overline {S}\right \rangle $ is non-abelian.
The weight $w(G)$ of a topological space G is the minimal cardinal number that a base for the topology on G can have.
Theorem 5.11. Suppose $\{G_n\}_{n\in {\mathbb N}}$ is any family of compact connected Hausdorff topological groups such that each $G_n$ has weight at most $2^{\aleph _0}$ (for example, every compact connected Lie group is such). Then there exists a type-absolutely connected group G such that $\prod _{n\in {\mathbb N}}G_n/ \bigoplus _{n\in {\mathbb N}} G_n$ is a homomorphic image of ${G^*}^{00}_{\emptyset }/ {G^*}^{\infty }_{\emptyset }$ .
If infinitely many of the $G_n$ ’s are non-abelian, then ${G^*}^{00}_{\emptyset }/ {G^*}^{\infty }_{\emptyset }$ is also non-abelian.
Proof Let $C=\prod _{n\in {\mathbb N}}G_n$ . We find a dense subgroup $D<C$ and S witnessing the assumption of Theorem 5.9 and such that $C/\left \langle \overline {S}\right \rangle $ maps homomorphically onto $C/D_1$ where $D_1 =\bigoplus _{n\in {\mathbb N}}G_n$ . By [Reference Hofmann and Morris22, Theorem 4.13], there are $x_n,y_n\in G_n$ such that $\langle x_n,y_n\rangle $ is a dense subgroup of $G_n$ . Consider
as a subset of C (under the natural embedding of $G_n$ into C). Since $D_1$ is dense in C, the subgroup $D=\langle K \rangle $ is also dense in C. Note that K is a compact subset of C, as e is a limit point of K and $K\setminus \{e\}$ is discrete. The set $S = \bigcup _{k=-3}^3\bigcup _{n\in {\mathbb N}}{x_n^k}^{D}\cup {y_n^k}^{D}$ is contained in $S' = \bigcup _{k=-3}^3\bigcup _{n\in {\mathbb N}}{x_n^k}^{C}\cup {y_n^k}^{C}$ . Since K is compact, $S'$ is also compact. Indeed, consider $F\colon C\times C \to C$ , $F(a,b)=a^b$ . As F is continuous, the image $F(K\times C)=S'$ is compact. Hence $\overline {S}\subseteq S'\subset D_1$ , so $C/\left \langle \overline {S}\right \rangle $ maps homomorphically onto $C/D_1 = \prod _{n\in {\mathbb N}}G_n/\bigoplus _{n\in {\mathbb N}}G_n$ . The theorem follows by (5.9).
Every ultraproduct $\prod _{n\in {\mathbb N}}G_n/{\mathcal U}$ is a homomorphic image of $\prod _{n\in {\mathbb N}}G_n/ \bigoplus _{n\in {\mathbb N}} G_n$ . Therefore Theorem 5.11 implies that there exists a type-absolutely connected G such that ${G^*}^{00}_{\emptyset }/ {G^*}^{\infty }_{\emptyset }$ is non-solvable.
6. Radicals and compactifications
In this section we introduce the notion of the type-absolutely connected radical of a group (Definition 6.1). Our goals are to use that notion together with the concept of the von Neumann radical of a group and Theorem 5.7 to:
-
• classify all compactifications of a topological group G as mappings $G\to G^*/H'$ for some type-definable bounded index subgroups $H'$ of $G^*$ (Theorem 6.6 and Remark 6.7);
-
• prove that the class of type-absolutely connected groups coincides with the class of discretely topologized groups with trivial Bohr compactification (Theorem 6.10);
-
• characterize all connected Lie groups which are type-absolutely connected (Remark 6.11);
-
• prove certain result about solvable extensions (Theorem 6.12).
Let us remind that a Lie group is a topological group that has a differentiable manifold structure, which agrees with the topology. Lie groups appear in research in model theory (see, e.g., [Reference Pillay33]).
In 1976 Hirschfeld [Reference Hirschfeld21] described all compactifications of a given group G as quotients of an enlargement $^*G$ (in the sense of non-standard analysis) of G. We obtain a similar result (Theorem 6.6) as a corollary of Theorem 5.7. In our case the quotients have the logic topology. We also give a certain description of a group H such that $G^*/H$ is the universal (the Bohr) compactification of G. A. Pillay (independently) proved that such H can be characterized in another way.
Definition 6.1. For a group G, by ${\mathcal R}_{tc}(G)$ we denote the maximal type-absolutely connected subgroup of G, that is, a subgroup which itself is type-absolutely connected, and contains all type-absolutely connected subgroups of G. We call ${\mathcal R}_{tc}(G)$ the type-absolutely connected radical of G. Existence of ${\mathcal R}_{tc}(G)$ is given by Proposition 4.3.
${\mathcal R}_{tc}(G)$ is a characteristic subgroup of G and is contained (by Proposition 4.5) in every element of the derived series of G, hence is contained in the perfect core of G (the largest perfect subgroup of G). In Section 7 (Theorem 7.7) we prove that for every Chevalley group G, the subgroup ${\mathcal R}_{tc}(G)$ is definable (in the group theory language $L_G=\{\cdot \}$ ) and coincides with $[G,G]$ .
Remark 6.2. ${\mathcal R}_{tc}$ has the following properties:
-
(1) ${\mathcal R}_{tc}({\mathcal R}_{tc}(G))={\mathcal R}_{tc}(G)$ .
-
(2) ${\mathcal R}_{tc}(G/{\mathcal R}_{tc}(G))=\{e\}$ (cf. Proposition 4.4 $(2)$ ).
-
(3) ${\mathcal R}_{tc}(G\times H) = {\mathcal R}_{tc}(G)\times {\mathcal R}_{tc}(H)$ .
-
(4) If $f\colon G\to H$ is a homomorphism, then $f({\mathcal R}_{tc}(G))\subseteq {\mathcal R}_{tc}\left (f(G)\right )$ (by Proposition 4.4 $(1)$ ).
-
(5) For an arbitrary structure on G we have ${\mathcal R}_{tc}(G)\subseteq G \cap {G^*}^{00}_{\emptyset }$ .
We make below the definition of ‘absolutely connected subset of a group’ (cf. Definition 3.3 $(1)$ ) for use in Example 6.5.
Definition 6.3. A subset X of a group G is called an n-absolutely connected if for every thick $P\subseteq G$ , we have $X\subseteq P^n$ .
Remark 6.4. Note that if $X\subseteq G$ is an absolutely connected subset of G which is also A-definable with respect to some structure on G, then $X^*\subseteq G\cap {G^*}^{\infty }_A$ .
Example 6.5. We give an example of a group G for which ${\mathcal R}_{tc}(G)$ is trivial, but for any structure on G, $G \cap {G^*}^{00}_{\emptyset }$ is nontrivial, i.e., where the inclusion in Remark 6.2 $(5)$ is strict. Suppose k is an arbitrary field of characteristic $0$ . Consider
We prove that H is a 4-absolutely connected subset of G (but H itself is not an absolutely connected group, as H is abelian; see Proposition 4.5). Suppose $P\subseteq G$ is thick. By Corollary 2.4, we may assume that $P^4$ is a normal subset of G. Let $h\in H$ . Since $\operatorname {\mathrm {char}}(k)=0$ , thickness of P implies that for some $n\in {\mathbb N}$ , $e\ne h^n\in P^4$ . However h and $h^n$ are conjugate in G, as
Therefore $h\in P^4$ . Since G is solvable, ${\mathcal R}_{tc}(G)$ is trivial. However, if H is $\emptyset $ -definable in G, then $H\subseteq G\cap {G^*}^{\infty }_{\emptyset }\subseteq G\cap {G^*}^{00}_{\emptyset }$ .
We recall the notion of the von Neumann radical (also called the von Neumann kernel) and Bohr compactification. Let G be a topological group. There exist a ‘largest’ compact Hausdorff group $bG$ and a continuous homomorphism $b\colon G\to bG$ such that:
-
• the image $b(G)$ is dense in $bG$ , and
-
• for every continuous homomorphism of dense image $f\colon G\to \widetilde {G}$ , where $\widetilde {G}$ is a compact Hausdorff topological group, there is a unique continuous surjective homomorphism $\widetilde {f}\colon bG \to \widetilde {G}$ such that $f = \widetilde {f}\circ b$ .
The group $bG$ is called the Bohr compactification of G. The kernel of b is called the von Neumann radical of G, and is denoted by ${\mathcal R}_{vN}(G)$ . Note that ${\mathcal R}_{vN}(G)$ depends on the topology on G and is a closed normal subgroup. G is said to be minimally almost periodic if ${\mathcal R}_{vN}(G)=G$ [Reference von Neumann and Wigner30], which means that G has trivial Bohr compactification. At the other end of the spectrum are maximally almost periodic groups, for which the Bohr compactification is injective.
Suppose now that G is a group with some first-order structure, endowed with the discrete topology. Fix $A\subseteq G$ . The subgroup $G\cap {G^*}^{00}_A$ of G is the kernel of the mapping $\iota \colon G\to G^*/{G^*}^{00}_A$ . The group $G^*/{G^*}^{00}_A$ with the logic topology is compact Hausdorff and one can easily check that $\iota (G)$ is dense in $G^*/{G^*}^{00}_A$ (as $A\subseteq G$ ). Therefore $\left (G^*/{G^*}^{00}_A,\iota \right )$ is a compactification of G.
The next proposition is a consequence of Theorem 5.7. For every Hausdorff topological group G equipped with some structure, we give a sufficient condition to recover the Bohr compactification of G, and also all other compactifications of G, as $G\to G^*/H$ , where H is type-definable bounded index subgroup of G.
Theorem 6.6. Suppose $(G,\cdot ,\ldots )$ is a topological Hausdorff group equipped with some first-order structure $(\ldots )$ . Let $\{U_i\}_{i\in I}$ be a basis at the identity of $bG$ satisfying $(1)$ – $(3)$ from Proposition 5.7. Assume that the following subsets of G are definable in $G:$
-
• ${\mathcal R}_{vN}(G) (the\ von\ Neumann\ radical)$ ,
-
• $V_i = b^{-1}(U_i)$ , for $i\in I$ .
Then $G\to G^*/H$ is the Bohr compactification of G, where $H=\bigcap _{i\in I}V_i^*$ . Furthermore, any compactification of G is of the form $G\to G^*/H'$ , for some type-definable over G normal subgroup $H'$ of $G^*$ containing H.
Proof Since ${\mathcal R}_{vN}(G)$ is definable in G, the map $b\colon G\to b(G)$ is interpretable in G (we identify $b(G)$ with $G/{\mathcal R}_{vN}(G)$ ). Therefore working in $G^*$ one can find $b^*\colon G^*\rightarrow b(G)^*$ , which extends b, and also $b(G)^*=G^*/{\mathcal R}_{vN}(G)^*$ . Note that:
-
• the object $b(G)^*$ with the induced structure from $G^*$ is a sufficiently saturated extension of $b(G)$ with the induced structure,
-
• the natural surjective map $G^*/H \to b(G)^*/\bigcap _{i\in I}b(V_i)^*$ is continuous with respect to the logic topology on both groups.
Since $b(G)$ is a dense subgroup of $bG$ , by Theorem 5.7, there is a surjective homomorphism $\operatorname {\mathrm {st}}\colon b(G)^* \to bG$ , satisfying $(a)$ , $(b)$ and $(c)$ from (5.7), that is $\ker (\operatorname {\mathrm {st}})=\bigcap _{i\in I}b(V_i)^*$ . Hence, we have a surjective map $\operatorname {\mathrm {st}}\circ b^*\colon G^* \to bG$ with $\ker (\operatorname {\mathrm {st}}\circ b^*)=H$ and such that $G^*/H \underset {homeo}{\cong } b(G)^*/\ker (\operatorname {\mathrm {st}}) \underset {homeo}{\cong } bG$ .
The furthermore part follows from the first part and the definition of the Bohr compactification.
Remark 6.7. As an immediate corollary of Theorem 6.6 we obtain: under the notation of Theorem 6.6 endow G with the following structure:
which is an expansion of G by some family of open sets (as ${\mathcal R}_{vN}(G)$ is closed), then $G\to bG$ is homeomorphically isomorphic to $G\to G^*/H$ , where H is defined as in Theorem 6.6. Therefore, as has been also observed by A. Pillay in [Reference Gismatullin, Penazzi and Pillay20], H might be seen as a kind of canonical subgroup of $G^*$ . The natural question arises: does H coincides with ${G^*}^{00}_G$ ? If we additionally assume that G is compact and that every definable subset of G is Haar measurable, then one can apply the argument from [Reference Hrushovski, Peterzil and Pillay24, p. 579], to get $H={G^*}^{00}_G$ . Because ${G^*}^{00}_G=\bigcap _{j\in J}W_j$ where each $W_j$ is thick, so is generic (Lemma 3.6). Hence each $W_j$ has positive measure, so $W_j^2$ has non-empty interior and contains some $V_i$ .
We make some comments on groups with discrete topology.
Proposition 6.8. Let G be an arbitrary group with discrete topology.
-
(1) For every sufficiently saturated extension $G^*$ of G, ${\mathcal R}_{vN}(G)\subseteq G\cap {G^*}^{00}_G$ .
-
(2) There exist a family $\{P_i : i\in I\}$ of thick normal subsets of G satisfying $($ (†) $)$ from $($ 2.5 $)$ and such that ${\mathcal R}_{vN}(G)=\bigcap _{i\in I}P_i$ . Moreover ${\mathcal R}_{vN}(G)= G\cap {G^*}^{00}_{\emptyset }$ in the structure $(G,\cdot ,P_i)_{i\in I}$ .
Proof $(1)$ Since $\iota \colon G\to G^*/{G^*}^{00}_G$ is a compactification of G, there is $f\colon bG\to G^*/{G^*}^{00}_G$ such that $\iota = f \circ b$ , so $\ker (b)={\mathcal R}_{vN}(G)\subseteq \ker (\iota )=G\cap {G^*}^{00}_G$ .
$(2)$ Choose by Remark 5.8 a basis $\{U_i : i\in I\}$ of the neighbourhood of identity of $bG$ satisfying $(1)$ – $(3)$ from Theorem 5.7. It is enough to take $P_i=b^{-1}(U_i)$ . We prove the moreover part. Inclusion $\subseteq $ follows from $(1)$ . For $\supseteq $ note that $\bigcap _{i\in I}P^*_i$ is a $\emptyset $ -type-definable bounded index subgroup of $G^*$ , so $\bigcap _{i\in I}P^*_i\supseteq {G^*}^{00}_{\emptyset }$ .
An immediate consequence of Remark 6.2 $(5)$ and Proposition 6.8 $(2)$ (or of Theorem 6.6) is the following.
Corollary 6.9. For an arbitrary topological group G (not necessarily with discrete topology) ${\mathcal R}_{tc}(G)\subseteq {\mathcal R}_{vN}(G)$ .
One can prove (cf. [Reference von Neumann and Wigner30, $5\left(\alpha \right)$ ]) that in Example 6.5, if G is discretely topologized then ${\mathcal R}_{vN}(G)=H$ . That is, ${\mathcal R}_{tc}(G)$ might be a proper subgroup of ${\mathcal R}_{vN}(G)$ . However, by the next theorem, this cannot happen for minimally almost periodic groups.
Theorem 6.10. Consider G with the discrete topology. Then ${\mathcal R}_{vN}(G)=G$ if and only if ${\mathcal R}_{tc}(G)=G$ . That is the class of type-absolutely connected groups coincides with the class of discretely topologized minimally almost periodic groups.
Proof $\Leftarrow $ holds as ${\mathcal R}_{tc}(G)\subseteq {\mathcal R}_{vN}(G)$ . $\Rightarrow $ follows by Proposition 6.8 $(1)$ . Indeed, if ${\mathcal R}_{vN}(G)=G$ , then $G\subseteq {G^*}^{00}_G$ , for any $G^*\succ G$ , so G is type-absolutely connected.
Remark 6.11. Shtern in [Reference Shtern38] described the von Neumann kernel of a connected Lie group and characterized discretely topologized minimally almost periodic connected Lie groups [Reference Shtern38, Section 4, Corollary 2]. Therefore, by Theorem 6.10, this also gives a characterization of connected Lie groups which are type-absolutely connected. Namely, suppose G is a connected Lie group with Levi decomposition $G=SR$ , where R is the solvable radical of G (the largest connected solvable normal subgroup of G) and S is a Levi subgroup. Then ${\mathcal R}_{vN}(G)=G$ with respect to discrete topology on G if and only if S has no nontrivial compact simple factors and $R=[G,R]$ . In particular every semisimple connected Lie group without compact factors, for example, the topological universal cover $\widetilde {\operatorname {\mathrm {SL}}_2({\mathbb R})}$ of $\operatorname {\mathrm {SL}}_2({\mathbb R})$ , is type-absolutely connected. Another proof of this fact can be derived from Theorem 6.12.
We describe how ${\mathcal R}_{vN}$ behaves under solvable extensions.
Theorem 6.12. Suppose $f\colon G \to H$ is an epimorphism of groups with discrete topology. If $\ker (f)$ is solvable of derived length m, then
In particular if ${\mathcal R}_{vN}(H)=H$ (that is, H is type-absolutely connected), then $G^{(m)}\subseteq {\mathcal R}_{vN}(G)$ . If additionally G is perfect, then ${\mathcal R}_{tc}(G)=G$ , so G is type-absolutely connected.
Proof The second part follows from the first part and Theorem 6.10. We prove the first part. By Proposition 6.8 $(2)$ , ${\mathcal R}_{vN}(G)=\bigcap _{i\in I}P_i$ , where each $P_i$ is thick and normal in G.
Claim. For $i\in I$ and $n\in {\mathbb N}$ , $f^{-1}({\mathcal R}_{vN}(H))^{(n)}\subseteq P_i\cdot \ker (f)^{(n)}$ .
Proof of the claim
We prove by induction on n. Take an arbitrary $i\in I$ . Since each $f(P_i)$ is thick in H and $\{f(P_i)\}_{i\in I}$ satisfies (†) from Lemma 2.5, ${\mathcal R}_{vN}(H)\subseteq H\cap {H^*}^{00}_{\emptyset }\subseteq f(P_i)$ , for a suitable $H^*$ . Thus $f^{-1}({\mathcal R}_{vN}(H))\subseteq P_i\cdot \ker (f)$ . This proves the case $n=0$ .
Suppose that the claim is true for n. By $(*)$ from the proof of Lemma 3.7 we get
Since $\ker (f)^{(n+1)}$ is a normal subgroup of G and i is an arbitrary element of I, (†) from Lemma 2.5 implies that $f^{-1}({\mathcal R}_{vN}(H))^{(n+1)}\subseteq P_i\cdot \ker (f)^{(n+1)}$ .
By the claim $f^{-1}({\mathcal R}_{vN}(H))^{(m)}\subseteq P_i$ for each $i\in I$ , so $f^{-1}({\mathcal R}_{vN}(H))^{(m)}\subseteq {\mathcal R}_{vN}(G)$ .
Corollary 6.13. The topological universal cover $\widetilde {\operatorname {\mathrm {SL}}_2({\mathbb R})}$ of $\operatorname {\mathrm {SL}}_2({\mathbb R})$ is type-absolutely connected, but not absolutely connected.
Proof Consider the following exact sequence:
Since $\widetilde {\operatorname {\mathrm {SL}}_2({\mathbb R})}$ is perfect [Reference Wood43] and $\operatorname {\mathrm {SL}}_2({\mathbb R})$ is 12-absolutely connected (Theorem 7.5), Theorem 6.12 implies that $\widetilde {\operatorname {\mathrm {SL}}_2({\mathbb R})}$ is type-absolutely connected. $\widetilde {\operatorname {\mathrm {SL}}_2({\mathbb R})}$ is not absolutely connected by [Reference Conversano and Pillay10] or by Corollary 5.4 $(1)$ . Namely, $\widetilde {\operatorname {\mathrm {SL}}_2({\mathbb R})}$ is isomorphic with $({\mathbb Z}\times \operatorname {\mathrm {SL}}_2({\mathbb R}),\cdot )$ , where $\cdot $ is defined by the rule $(b_1,x_1)\cdot (b_2,x_2) = (b_1+b_2+h(x_1,x_2),x_1x_2)$ , for some 2-cocycle $h\colon \operatorname {\mathrm {SL}}_2({\mathbb R})\times \operatorname {\mathrm {SL}}_2({\mathbb R})\to \{-1,0,1\}$ [Reference Asai1, Theorem 2]. Hence there exists an unbounded quasimorphism $f\colon \widetilde {\operatorname {\mathrm {SL}}_2({\mathbb R})} \to {\mathbb Z}$ of defect 1.
Further results on $\widetilde {\operatorname {\mathrm {SL}}_2({\mathbb R})}$ are in [Reference Gismatullin and Krupiński18].
7. Split semisimple linear groups
The aim of the present section is to prove (see Theorem 7.7) that groups of rational points of split semisimple simply connected linear groups (so in particular Chevalley groups) over arbitrary infinite fields are 12-absolutely connected.
For the class of connected Lie groups ${\mathcal C}_{Lie}$ , in particular for linear groups over ${\mathbb R}$ , we can characterize the subclass ${\mathcal C}_{Lie, tc}$ of ${\mathcal C}_{Lie}$ consisting of type-absolutely connected groups (cf. Remark 6.11). One may expect that some groups from ${\mathcal C}_{Lie, tc}$ are absolutely connected. However it is not true that all groups from ${\mathcal C}_{Lie, tc}$ are absolutely connected, as, for example, $\widetilde {\operatorname {\mathrm {SL}}_2({\mathbb R})}$ is not absolutely connected (Corollary 6.13).
In the case of quasi-simple Chevalley groups over arbitrary infinite fields we have the following result. By [Reference Ellers, Gordeev and Herzog13, Theorem M], there exists a constant d, such that every quasi-simple Chevalley group $G(k)$ over an arbitrary field k is $d\cdot \operatorname {\mathrm {rank}}(G)$ -uniformly simple (see the comment after Definition 3.3). Hence $G(k)$ is in ${\mathcal W}_{d\cdot \operatorname {\mathrm {rank}}(G)}$ (Definition 3.4), so by Theorem 3.11 $G(k)$ is $4d\operatorname {\mathrm {rank}}(G)$ -ac. In fact, we prove that $G(k)$ is in ${\mathcal W}_3$ and so is $12$ -absolutely connected.
By a linear algebraic group we mean an affine algebraic group (cf. [Reference Borel and Tits3, Reference Platonov and Rapinchuk34]). We assume throughout that k is an arbitrary infinite field. All linear groups are assumed to be connected.
We say that a linear algebraic group G is a k-group or that G is defined over k, if the ideal of polynomials vanishing on G is generated by polynomials over k (cf. [Reference Borel and Tits3, AG §11]). By $G(k)$ we denote the group of k-rational points of a k-group G. A Borel subgroup of G is any maximal connected Zariski closed solvable subgroup of G; a subgroup of G is called parabolic if it contains some Borel subgroup. A k-group G is called:
-
• reductive (resp. semisimple), if the unipotent radical ${\mathcal R}_u(G)$ (resp. the solvable radical ${\mathcal R}(G)$ ) of G is trivial,
-
• split over k or k-split if some maximal torus T in G is split over k [Reference Borel and Tits3, 18.6],
-
• absolutely almost simple (resp. almost simple over k or almost k-simple) if G has no proper nontrivial normal connected closed subgroup (resp. defined over k) ([Reference Borel and Tits4, 0.7], [Reference Steinberg41, 1.1.1 and 3.1.2]),
-
• simply connected if G does not admit any nontrivial central isogeny $\pi \colon \widetilde {G} \to G$ ([Reference Platonov and Rapinchuk34, 2.1.13], [Reference Shtern39, 8.1.11], [Reference Steinberg41, 1.5.4 and 2.6.2]).
Every absolutely almost simple k-group is almost k-simple, but the converse is not true in general. However, when G is k-split, semisimple, and simply connected, then these two notions are equivalent. We use this fact in the proof of Theorem 7.5.
For every separable field extension $k'\supseteq k$ there is a functor ${\mathrm {R}}_{k'/k}$ [Reference Borel and Tits4, 6.17] which assigns, by restriction of scalars, to each affine $k'$ -group $H'$ an affine k-group $H = {\mathrm {R}}_{k'/k}\left (H'\right )$ such that $H'(k') \cong H(k)$ .
Lemma 7.1. Every almost k-simple k-split simply connected semisimple k-group G is absolutely almost simple.
Proof By [Reference Borel and Tits4, 6.21(II)] and [Reference Steinberg41, 3.1.2], there exists a finite separable field extension $k'$ of k and absolutely almost simple and simply connected $k'$ -group $G'$ such that $G = {\mathrm {R}}_{k'/k}(G')$ . It is enough to prove that $k'=k$ . Let $T'$ be a maximal $k'$ -split torus of $G'$ . Since G is k-split, by [Reference Shtern39, 16.2.7], $T = {\mathrm {R}}_{k'/k}(T')$ is a maximal k-split torus of G and $\dim (T)=\dim (T')$ . However, by [Reference Borel and Tits4, 6.17], $\dim (T)=\dim (T')[k':k]$ , so $k'=k$ .
Throughout this section unless otherwise is stated we use the following notation [Reference Borel and Tits3, 18.6, Sections 20 and 21]:
-
• G is a connected reductive k-split k-group,
-
• T is a maximal k-split torus in G,
-
• $\Phi = \Phi (T,G)$ is the root system of relative k-roots of G with respect to T (each $\alpha \in \Phi $ is a homomorphism $\alpha \colon T \to k^{\times }$ ); in fact $\Phi $ can be regarded as a root system in ${\mathbb R}^n$ , satisfying the crystallographic condition: $<\alpha ,\beta> = 2\frac {(\alpha ,\beta )}{(\beta ,\beta )} \in {\mathbb Z}$ , for all $\alpha , \beta \in \Phi $ , where $(,)$ is the usual scalar product on ${\mathbb R}^n$ [Reference Borel and Tits3, 14.6 and 14.7],
-
• $\Pi \subset \Phi $ is the simple root system generating $\Phi $ ; that is, every root $\alpha \in \Phi $ can be written as a linear combination of roots from $\Pi $ , where all nonzero coefficients are positive integers or all are negative integers,
-
• $U_{\alpha }$ for $\alpha \in \Phi $ , is the k-root group of G corresponding to $\alpha \in \Phi $ ,
-
• $\Phi ^+$ and $\Phi ^-$ are the sets of all positive and negative k-roots from $\Phi $ ,
-
• U (resp. $U^-$ ) is the group generated by all $U_{\alpha }$ for $\alpha \in \Phi ^+$ (resp. $\alpha \in \Phi ^-$ ).
If $\alpha = \sum _{\beta \in \Pi } k_{\beta }\beta $ is the representation of $\alpha \in \Phi $ with respect to $\Pi $ , then the height of $\alpha $ is $\operatorname {\mathrm {ht}}(\alpha ) = \sum _{\beta \in \Pi }k_{\beta }$ .
For each $\alpha \in \Phi $ the group $U_{\alpha }(k)$ is a connected and unipotent subgroup, normalised by $T(k)$ . In particular [Reference Borel and Tits3, 18.6], there is an isomorphism $x_{\alpha }\colon k \to U_{\alpha }(k)$ such that for $s\in k$ and $t\in T(k)$ ,
More precisely, for $u\in k^{\times }$ , $\alpha \in \Phi $ , define $w_{\alpha }(u) = x_{\alpha }(u) x_{-\alpha }\left (-u^{-1}\right )x_{\alpha }(u)$ and $t_{\alpha }(u) = w_{\alpha }(u) w_{\alpha }(1)^{-1}$ . Furthermore, if G is simply connected, then [Reference Springer40, Lemma 20(c), p. 29] $T(k) = \left \langle t_{\alpha }(u) : u\in k^{\times },\ \alpha \in \Pi \right \rangle $ and the action of $t_{\alpha }(u)$ on the k-root subgroup $U_{\beta }$ is given by the formula
If we fix an ordering on $\Phi ^{+}$ , then for every element $x\in U$ there is a unique tuple $(s_{\alpha })_{\alpha \in \Phi ^{+}}\in k^{\left |\Phi ^{+}\right |}$ , such that x can be uniquely written in the form
where the product is taken in a fixed order. The analogous fact is true for negative roots $\Phi ^{-}$ and $U^-$ .
The next definition is well known for linear algebraic groups [Reference Borel and Tits3, 12.2].
Definition 7.2. An element $t\in T(k)$ is called regular if $C_{G(k)}(t) \cap U(k) = \{e\}$ , where $C_{G(k)}(t)$ is the centralizer of t in $G(k)$ . Equivalently (by (**) and (***)) t is regular if and only if for every root $\beta \in \Phi ^{+}$ , $\beta (t)\neq 1$ .
Proposition 7.4 below is a variant of [Reference Ellers and Gordeev12, Proposition]. In the proof we use the Gauss decomposition in Chevalley groups from [Reference Casanovas, Lascar, Pillay and Ziegler9].
Theorem 7.3. [Reference Casanovas, Lascar, Pillay and Ziegler9, Gauss decomposition Theorem 2.1]
Suppose k is an arbitrary infinite field and G is an absolutely almost simple and simply connected k-split k-group. Then for every noncentral $g\in G(k)$ and $t\in T(k)$ there exist $v\in U^{-}(k), u\in U(k)$ , and $x\in G(k)$ such that $g^x = v\cdot t\cdot u$ .
Proposition 7.4. Suppose that G is an absolutely almost simple and simply connected k-split k-group. Then $G(k) = \left (t^{G(k)}\right )^3$ for every regular element $t\in T(k)$ .
Proof Let $C = t^{G(k)}$ . Consider the following functions:
-
• $\varphi \colon U(k) \to U(k), \ \varphi (u) = [t,u]=t^{-1}u^{-1}tu$ ,
-
• $\psi \colon U^{-}(k) \to U^{-}(k), \ \psi (v) = [v,t^{-1}] = v^{-1}tvt^{-1}$ .
The functions $\varphi $ and $\psi $ are well defined, because $U(k)$ and $U^{-}(k)$ are normal subgroups of $B(k)$ . Since t is regular, $\varphi $ and $\psi $ are injective. In fact, $\varphi $ and $\psi $ are bijections. We prove that $\varphi $ is surjective; the argument for $\psi $ is similar. Consider the central series $U(k)=U_1(k) \rhd U_2(k) \ldots \rhd U_m(k) = \{e\}$ for $U(k)$ , where $U_i(k) = \langle x_{\alpha }(s) : \alpha \in \Phi ^{+}, \operatorname {\mathrm {ht}}(\alpha )\geq i, s\in k\rangle $ . By the Chevalley commutator formula [Reference Borel and Tits3, 14.5 and Remark (2)], we have
Each factor $U_i(k)/U_{i+1}(k)$ is a finite-dimensional vector space over k. Namely, by (***),
By *), $\varphi \left (U_i(k)\right )\subseteq U_i(k)$ ; hence $\varphi $ induces a k-linear transformation
with the matrix $\operatorname {\mathrm {diag}}(1-\alpha (t): \alpha \in \Phi , \operatorname {\mathrm {ht}}(\alpha ) = i)$ . Since t is regular, each $\varphi _{i}$ is a bijection. Now, using (†) one can easily prove, by induction on $1\leq i \leq m-1$ , that for every $u\in U(k)$ , there is $u_i$ such that $u \equiv [t,u_i] \mod U_{i+1}$ . Thus $\varphi $ is surjective.
Claim. $C^2 \supseteq G(k)\setminus Z(G(k))$ .
Proof of the claim
Take an arbitrary $g\in G(k)\setminus Z(G(k))$ . By [Reference Casanovas, Lascar, Pillay and Ziegler9, Theorem 2.1]
Since $\varphi $ and $\psi $ are surjective, for some $g'\in g^G$ there are $v\in U^{-}(k)$ , $u\in U(k)$ satisfying $g' = \psi (v)t^2\varphi (u) = v^{-1}tvu^{-1}tu \in C^2$ .
Our conclusion follows from the claim, because if $x\not \in C^2\cdot C$ , then $xC^{-1}\subseteq G(k)\setminus C^2 \subseteq Z(G(k))$ ; this is impossible since $Z(G(k))$ is finite and C is infinite.
We prove that simply connected split groups are 12-absolutely connected.
Theorem 7.5. Let k be an arbitrary infinite field and let G be a k-split, semisimple, simply connected, k-group. Then $G(k)$ is in ${\mathcal W}_3$ , so $G(k)$ is 12-absolutely connected.
Proof Without loss of generality we may assume that G is absolutely almost simple. Indeed, by [Reference Borel and Tits3, 22.10] and [Reference Steinberg41, 3.1.2], the group G is a direct product $G_1\times \cdots \times G_n$ over k, where each $G_i$ is k-split, semisimple, simply connected, and almost k-simple. Thus $G(k)\cong \prod _{1\leq i \leq n}G_i(k)$ . By Lemma 7.1, every $G_i$ is absolutely almost simple, so by Lemma 3.9 $(1)$ and Theorem 3.11, it is enough to prove that $G_i(k)$ is in ${\mathcal W}_3$ .
By Proposition 7.4 and Theorem 3.11, in order to prove the conclusion of the theorem, one needs to show that the set of non-regular elements in $T(k)$ is non-thick (cf. Definition 2.1). By Definition 7.2, it is enough to find, for each $m\in {\mathbb N}$ , a sequence $(t_i)_{i<m}$ in $T(k)$ such that $\beta (t_i^{-1}t_j)\neq 1$ for $i<j<m$ and $\beta \in \Phi $ .
By (*) and (**), $\beta \left (t_{\alpha }(s)\right ) = s^{<\beta ,\alpha>}$ . Fix some sequence $\left (\lambda _{\alpha }\right )_{\alpha \in \Pi } \subset {\mathbb Z}$ and for $s\in k^{\times }$ , define $a(s) = \prod _{\alpha \in \Pi }t_{\alpha }\left (s^{\lambda _{\alpha }}\right )$ . Then for $i<j<m$ ,
Fix $m\in {\mathbb N}$ . Since the Cartan matrix $\left (<\alpha ,\beta>\right )_{\alpha ,\beta \in \Pi }$ of the irreducible root system $\Phi $ is non-degenerate (cf. [Reference Carter7, Section 3.6]), one can find a sequence $\left (\lambda _{\alpha }\right )_{\alpha \in \Pi }$ of integers such that, for every simple root $\beta \in \Pi $ , the sum $\sum _{\alpha \in \Pi }\lambda _{\alpha }<\beta ,\alpha>$ is positive. Every root $\beta $ is a ${\mathbb Z}$ -linear combination of simple roots with all coefficients positive, or all negative. Moreover $<\cdot ,\cdot>$ is additive in the first coordinate. Hence for all $\beta \in \Phi $ ,
The field k is infinite, so there is $t\in k^{\times }$ such that $\beta \left (a\left (s^i\right )^{-1}a\left (s^j\right )\right )\neq 1$ for every $i<j<m$ . Thus $(t_i)_{i<m} = \left (a\left (s^i\right )\right )_{i<m}$ satisfies our requirements.
Corollary 7.6. Let $\operatorname {\mathrm {SL}}_{\infty }(k)$ be the union $($ the direct limit $)$ of groups $\operatorname {\mathrm {SL}}_n(k)$ , where for $n<m$ , $\operatorname {\mathrm {SL}}_n(k)$ is embedded in $\operatorname {\mathrm {SL}}_m(k)$ in a natural way, that is, $A \mapsto \begin {pmatrix} A & 0 \\ 0 & I \end {pmatrix}$ . Proposition 3.8 $(3)$ and Theorem 7.5 implies that $\operatorname {\mathrm {SL}}_{\infty }(k)$ is 12-absolutely connected.
Now we consider the case when G is k-split but not necessarily simply connected. Our goal is Theorem 7.7 below, which is a more general version of Theorem 7.5.
Every semisimple k-group G has a universal k-covering $\pi \colon \widetilde {G} \to G$ defined over k ([Reference Platonov and Rapinchuk34, Proposition 2.10], [Reference Steinberg41, 2.6.1]); that is, $\widetilde {G}$ is a simply connected k-group and $\pi $ is a central isogeny defined over k.
Denote by $G(k)^+$ the canonical normal subgroup of $G(k)$ generated by the k-rational points of the unipotent radicals of parabolic subgroups of G defined over k [Reference Steinberg41]
Let G be a semisimple k-split k-group and let $\pi \colon \widetilde {G} \to G$ be a universal k-covering of G. Then [Reference Bowler, Chen and Gismatullin5, 6.5 and 6.6]:
-
(1) $\widetilde {G}(k)^+ = \widetilde {G}(k)$ (see, for example, [Reference Springer40, Lemma 64, p. 183]),
-
(2) $\pi \left (\widetilde {G}(k)\right ) = G(k)^+$ and $G(k)^+$ is the derived subgroup $[G(k),G(k)]$ of $G(k)$ (cf. [Reference Bowler, Chen and Gismatullin5, 6.5]).
Theorem 7.7. Let k be an arbitrary infinite field and let G be a k-split, semisimple k-group. Then the derived subgroup $[G(k),G(k)]$ is in ${\mathcal W}_3$ , so it is 12-absolutely connected. Moreover $[G(k),G(k)]={\mathcal R}_{tc}(G(k)) (cf. Section 6)$ and it is $\emptyset $ -definable subgroup of $G(k)$ in the pure group language.
Proof Let $\pi \colon \widetilde {G} \to G$ be a universal k-covering of G. The group $\widetilde {G}$ is simply connected, so by Theorem 7.5, $\widetilde {G}(k)$ is in ${\mathcal W}_3$ . By Lemma 3.9 $(1) \pi \left (\widetilde {G}(k)\right )=G(k)^+=[G(k),G(k)]$ is 12-absolutely connected. Since $G(k)^+\in {\mathcal W}_3$ , one can find $g\in {\mathcal G}_3(G(k)^+)$ (cf. Definition 3.4). Therefore, since $G(k)^+$ is a normal subgroup of $G(k)$ , $G(k)^+$ is definable over g. However, $[G(k),G(k)]$ is $\emptyset $ -invariant, so is definable over $\emptyset $ . As $[G(k),G(k)]$ is absolutely connected, $[G(k),G(k)]\subseteq {\mathcal R}_{tc}(G(k))$ , and ${\mathcal R}_{tc}(G(k))$ is perfect, so ${\mathcal R}_{tc}(G(k)) \subseteq [{\mathcal R}_{tc}(G(k)),{\mathcal R}_{tc}(G(k))] \subseteq [G(k),G(k)]$ .
Theorem 7.7 and Remark 4.8 imply the following remark.
Remark 7.8.
-
(1) Suppose G is a semisimple k-split k-group and $G(k)$ is equipped with some first-order structure. Let $G(k)^{\mathrm ab}$ be $G(k)/[G(k),G(k)]$ with the structure inherited from $G(k)$ and let $G^*$ be any sufficiently saturated extension of $G(k)$ . Then by Remark 4.8, $G^*/{G^*}^{\infty }_{\emptyset } \cong {G(k)^{\mathrm ab}}^*/{{G(k)^{\mathrm ab}}^*}^{\infty }_{\emptyset }$ and $G^*/{G^*}^{00}_{\emptyset } \cong {G(k)^{\mathrm ab}}^*/{{G(k)^{\mathrm ab}}^*}^{00}_{\emptyset }$ . In particular ${G^*}/{G^*}^{\infty }_{\emptyset }$ is abelian. As a corollary of Remark 4.8 we have that for semisimple split groups, model-theoretic connected components can be described in terms of components of the abelianization.
-
(2) Suppose G is a reductive k-split k-group. Then $[G,G]$ is a semisimple k-split k-group [Reference Borel and Tits3, 2.3 and 14.2]. Hence, by Theorem 7.7 the group
$$\begin{align*}G_0 = \left[\left[G,G\right]\left(k\right), \left[G,G\right]\left(k\right)\right]\end{align*}$$is a 12-ac subgroup of $G(k)$ and $G_0 = {\mathcal R}_{tc}(G(k))$ (Lemma 6.1). Furthermore, if $[G,G](k)$ is $\emptyset $ -definable in $G(k)$ , then $G_0$ is $\emptyset $ -definable in $G(k)$ (by Theorem 7.7). In this case $G^*/{G^*}^{\infty }_{\emptyset } \cong {A}^*/{A^*}^{\infty }_{\emptyset }$ , where $A = G(k)/G_0$ .
7.1. Groups over algebraically closed field
We consider the case when $k=K$ is an algebraically closed field. In this subsection we assume that G is a connected linear algebraic K-group.
Any absolutely connected group is perfect (Proposition 4.5). In our context this is also a sufficient condition for absolute connectedness.
Proposition 7.9. The following conditions are equivalent $:$
-
(a) $G(K)$ is absolutely connected,
-
(b) $G(K)$ is perfect.
More precisely, if $\operatorname {\mathrm {cw}}(G(K))=r$ and the solvable radical ${\mathcal R}(G(K))$ is of derived length m, then $G(K)$ is $12(4r)^m$ -absolutely connected.
Proof $(a)\Rightarrow (b)$ follows from Proposition 4.5. For $(b)\Rightarrow (a)$ , note that $H = G/{\mathcal R}(G)$ is a semisimple linear algebraic K-group. As $G(K)$ is perfect, $H(K)$ is perfect and K-split, because every semisimple linear algebraic group is split. Hence by Theorem 7.7, $H(K)$ is in ${\mathcal W}_3$ . It is enough to apply Lemma 3.9 $(2b)$ and Theorem 3.11 to $G(K) \to H(K)$ and $H(K)$ .
If $G(K)$ is perfect, the commutator width of $G(K)$ is at most $2\dim (G)$ [Reference Borel and Tits3, 2.2].
Below is an immediate consequence of Proposition 7.9 and results from Section 6.
Corollary 7.10. The perfect core of $G(K)$ is absolutely connected and equals ${\mathcal R}_{tc}(G(K))$ .
Proposition 7.9 cannot be generalized to a nonsplit groups in general. For example $\operatorname {\mathrm {SO}}_3({\mathbb R})$ is simple as an abstract group (in particular perfect), but is not absolutely connected.
We do not know if the bound $12(4r)^m$ from Proposition 7.9 is asymptotically sharp.
Question 7.11. Is there a constant c such that every perfect linear algebraic group is c-absolutely connected?
8. More examples
In this section we provide more examples of absolutely connected groups. We consider some infinite permutation groups and infinite-dimensional general linear groups.
8.1. Infinite permutation groups
Let $\Omega $ be an infinite set. Consider the alternating group of permutations of $\Omega $ :
The converse of Theorem 3.11 is not true.
Proposition 8.1. $\operatorname {\mathrm {Alt}}(\Omega )$ is 8-absolutely connected but is not in ${\mathcal W}$ .
Proof $\operatorname {\mathrm {Alt}}(\Omega )$ is not in ${\mathcal W}$ because ${\mathcal G}_N(\operatorname {\mathrm {Alt}}(\Omega )) = \emptyset $ , for every $N\in {\mathbb N}$ . To prove the absolute connectedness, take an arbitrary n-thick subset $P\subseteq \operatorname {\mathrm {Alt}}(\Omega )$ . By considering $P^4$ and using Corollary 2.4, we may assume that P is normal. Now it is enough to prove that $P^2 = \operatorname {\mathrm {Alt}}(\Omega )$ .
We claim that P contains any finite product of disjoint even cycles. Take n cycles $(x,a_{1},\ldots ,a_{m})$ , $(x,b_{1},\ldots ,b_{m})$ , $\ldots $ , $(x,z_{1},\ldots ,z_{m})$ , where x is the only common element of these cycles. Since P is n-thick, we may assume that
Therefore P contains every even cycle (because P is normal in $\operatorname {\mathrm {Alt}}(\Omega )$ ). In the same way we can prove that P contains any finite product of disjoint even cycles. Namely, instead of one cycle $(x,a_{1},\ldots ,a_{m})$ , it is enough to consider a product $(x_0,a_{01},\ldots ,a_{0n_0})\circ (x_1,a_{11},\ldots ,a_{1n_1})\circ \cdots \circ (x_k,a_{k1},\ldots ,a_{kn_k})$ of disjoint cycles.
The following two cycles $(x,y,a_1,\ldots ,a_{2p+1})$ and $(x,y,b_1,\ldots ,b_{2q+1})$ are in P, so
is in $P^2$ . Thus $P^2$ contains every product of two disjoint odd cycles. In a similar way, we can prove that every even permutation (which is a disjoint product of even cycles and an even number of odd cycles) is in $P^2$ .
Now we concentrate on the group $\operatorname {\mathrm {Sym}}(\Omega )$ and its normal subgroups. For a cardinal $\kappa $ define $\operatorname {\mathrm {Sym}}^{\kappa }(\Omega ) = \{\sigma \in \operatorname {\mathrm {Sym}}(\Omega ) : |\operatorname {\mathrm {supp}}(\sigma )|<\kappa \}$ . By the previous proposition, $\operatorname {\mathrm {Sym}}^{\aleph _0}(\Omega )$ has an absolutely connected subgroup $\operatorname {\mathrm {Alt}}(\Omega )$ of index 2.
We use the following result of Bertram, Moran, Droste, and Göbel [Reference Borel2, Reference Droste and Göbel11, Reference Moran29].
Theorem [Reference Droste and Göbel11, Theorem, p. 282]
If $\sigma , \tau \in \operatorname {\mathrm {Sym}}(\Omega )$ , $|\operatorname {\mathrm {supp}}(\tau )| \leq |\operatorname {\mathrm {supp}}(\sigma )|$ and $|\operatorname {\mathrm {supp}}(\sigma )|$ is infinite, then $\tau \in \left (\sigma ^{\operatorname {\mathrm {Sym}}(\Omega )}\right )^4$ .
Proposition 8.2. Let $\kappa $ be an uncountable cardinal.
-
(1) If $\kappa = \lambda ^+$ is a successor cardinal, then $\operatorname {\mathrm {Sym}}^{\kappa }(\Omega )$ is in ${\mathcal W}_4$ , so it is 16-absolutely connected.
-
(2) If $\kappa $ is a limit cardinal, then $\operatorname {\mathrm {Sym}}^{\kappa }(\Omega )$ is 16-absolutely connected, but is not in ${\mathcal W}$ .
Proof The group $\operatorname {\mathrm {Sym}}^{\kappa }(\Omega )$ is a normal subgroup of $\operatorname {\mathrm {Sym}}(\Omega )$ and two elements from $\operatorname {\mathrm {Sym}}^{\kappa }(\Omega )$ are conjugate in $\operatorname {\mathrm {Sym}}(\Omega )$ if and only if they are conjugate in $\operatorname {\mathrm {Sym}}^{\kappa }(\Omega )$ . Therefore in the case when $\kappa = \lambda ^+$ is a successor cardinal, from the above theorem we conclude that the group $\operatorname {\mathrm {Sym}}^{\kappa }(\Omega )$ is in ${\mathcal W}_4$ (and non-simple as an abstract group), that is, ${\mathcal G}_4(\operatorname {\mathrm {Sym}}^{\kappa }(\Omega )) = \operatorname {\mathrm {Sym}}^{\kappa }(\Omega ) \setminus \operatorname {\mathrm {Sym}}^{\lambda }(\Omega )$ , and $\left [\operatorname {\mathrm {Sym}}^{\kappa }(\Omega ) : \operatorname {\mathrm {Sym}}^{\lambda }(\Omega )\right ]$ is infinite. When $\kappa $ is a limit cardinal, $\operatorname {\mathrm {Sym}}^{\kappa }(\Omega ) = \bigcup _{\lambda < \kappa } \operatorname {\mathrm {Sym}}^{\lambda }(\Omega )$ . In this case $\operatorname {\mathrm {Sym}}^{\kappa }(\Omega )$ is not in ${\mathcal W}$ , as ${\mathcal G}_N(\operatorname {\mathrm {Sym}}^{\kappa }(\Omega )) = \emptyset $ . However for a successor cardinal $\lambda <\kappa $ , the group $\operatorname {\mathrm {Sym}}^{\lambda }(\Omega )$ is in ${\mathcal W}_4$ . By Theorem 3.11, $\operatorname {\mathrm {Sym}}^{\lambda }(\Omega )$ is 16-absolutely connected and by Proposition 3.8 $(3)$ the same is true for $\operatorname {\mathrm {Sym}}^{\kappa }(\Omega )$ .
8.2. Infinite-dimensional general linear group
The following proposition is derived from the result of Tolstykh [Reference Tits42].
Proposition 8.3. Assume that V is an infinite-dimensional vector space over a division ring D. Then the group $\operatorname {\mathrm {GL}}(V)$ of all linear automorphisms of V is in ${\mathcal W}_{32}$ , so $\operatorname {\mathrm {GL}}(V)$ is 128-absolutely connected.
Proof Call a subspace U of V moietous if $\dim U = \dim V = \operatorname {\mathrm {codim}} U$ . We say that $\pi \in G$ is a moietous involution if there exists a decomposition $V = U \oplus U' \oplus W$ into a direct sum of moietous subspaces, such that $\pi $ on W is the identity and exchanges U and $U'$ . Proposition 1.1 from [Reference Tits42] says that every moietous involution is in ${\mathcal G}_{32}(\operatorname {\mathrm {GL}}(V))$ . In order to prove that $\operatorname {\mathrm {GL}}(V)$ is in ${\mathcal W}_{32}$ simple it is enough to find in $\operatorname {\mathrm {GL}}(V)$ an infinite sequence $(g_i)_{i\in {\mathbb N}}$ , such that for all $i<j\in {\mathbb N}$ the element $g_i^{-1}g_j$ is a moietous involution (so $g_i^{-1}g_j \in {\mathcal G}_{32}(\operatorname {\mathrm {GL}}(V))$ ). Take an infinite decomposition $V = \bigoplus _{i\in {\mathbb N}} V_i$ of V into moietous subspaces. Let $g_i$ be a moietous involution of V with respect to the following decomposition:
such that $g_i(V_{2i}) = V_{2i+1}$ . Then clearly $g_i^{-1}g_j$ for $i\neq j$ is also a moietous involution.
Acknowledgments
The author would like to thank Cong Chen, Alexander Borovik, Antongiulio Fornasiero, Guntram Heinke, Arieh Lev, Anand Pillay, Andrei Rapinchuk, and John Truss for many useful conversations and Dugald Macpherson for suggestions for improving the presentation of the paper.
Funding
The author is supported by the NCN grants 2015/19/B/ST1/01151 and 2014/13/D/ST1/03491 was supported by the Marie Curie Intra-European Fellowship MODGROUP no. PIEF-GA-2009-254123.