Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-t7czq Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-27T18:01:10.780Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Risky Inquiry: Developing an Ethics for Philosophical Practice

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  07 August 2023

Rima Basu*
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, Claremont McKenna College, 850 N. Columbia Ave., Claremont, CA 91711
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Philosophical inquiry strives to be the unencumbered exploration of ideas. That is, unlike scientific research, which is subject to ethical oversight, it is commonly thought that it would either be inappropriate, or that it would undermine what philosophy fundamentally is, if philosophical research were subject to similar ethical oversight. Against this, I argue that philosophy is in need of a reckoning. Philosophical inquiry is a morally hazardous practice with its own risks. There are risks present in the methods we employ, risks inherent in the content of the views under consideration, and risks to the subjects of our inquiry. Likely, there are more risks still. However, by starting with the identification of these three risks we can demonstrate not only why an ethics of practice is needed but also which avenues are the most promising for developing an ethics for philosophical practice. Although we might just be in the business of asking questions, we do not merely, in virtue of engaging in philosophical inquiry, absolve ourselves of responsibility for the risks that inquiry incurs.

Type
Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of Hypatia, a Nonprofit Corporation

Scientific research often directly involves experimenting on human subjects, or it indirectly affects people in other ways. Given this, it is not an open question whether we need ethical guidelines for scientific research. With regard to whether we should develop ethical guidelines for philosophical research, however, there are serious doubts. For example, when Yannik Thiem and their colleagues spoke with editors of philosophy journals as part of a white paper on publication ethics, the authors noted that there was little agreement on any ethical guidelines for philosophical inquiry that go beyond sanctions for verbatim plagiarism. They note:

Those who had concerns about developing shared principles and best practices of publication ethics often pointed to the fact that verbatim plagiarism is already agreed upon as unethical and sanctioned when discovered, and imposing any further norms on philosophical scholarship and publishing in philosophy should be avoided so that the free exploration of ideas and circulation of research remain unencumbered. (Thiem et al. Reference Thiem, Sealey, Ferrer, Trott and Kennison2019)

Here we see the commonly held idea that an ethics for philosophical practice is out of place or even improper given the kind of thing that philosophical inquiry strives to be. Philosophical inquiry, unlike scientific inquiry, is the unencumbered exploration of ideas. That is, whereas scientific inquiry is rightly subject to ethical oversight, it would be inappropriate to subject philosophical inquiry to similar ethical oversight. Against this—that it would be inappropriate to subject philosophical inquiry to similar ethical oversight—in this article I argue that philosophical inquiry is a morally hazardous practice. Philosophical inquiry has its own set of ethical and epistemological challenges that suggest we need to develop an ethics for philosophical practice.

To make this argument I will start by demonstrating how we can develop an ethics for philosophical practice by looking at the debate about values in science and how an ethics of practice was developed for scientific inquiry. We already have a good model for understanding how practices of inquiry could be constrained by moral considerations. Thus, rather than risk reinventing the wheel, we should see whether lessons from scientific inquiry can be applied to the more general practice of philosophical inquiry itself. However, in order to use the ethics of scientific practice as a model for developing an ethics of philosophical practice, we face two problems that must be addressed. First, our research doesn't seem as consequential as research in the sciences and social sciences. That is, our work doesn't pipeline into policy in quite the ways that scientific research does. Second, our research methods don't look much like those of the sciences. The kinds of risks that eventuate in the course of scientific inquiry might not arise in the case of philosophical inquiry.

I argue against these objections across sections I and II, and I demonstrate that several practical and moral risks do arise in the course of philosophical inquiry. There are risks present in the methods we employ, risks inherent in the content of the views under consideration, and risks to the subjects of our inquiry. There are likely further risks still. However, in identifying these three risks we can begin the work of demonstrating both how philosophical inquiry is a morally hazardous practice and why an ethics of practice is needed.

In section III, I turn to a second set of challenges that seek to undermine both the strength and the relevance of the analogy between scientific inquiry and philosophical inquiry. Both challenges turn on whether philosophical inquiry is fundamentally different in kind from scientific inquiry, and both concern the question of whether developing an ethics of practice undermines the goal of philosophical inquiry itself. As we saw in the opening quote, an ethics of philosophical practice seems at odds with a conception of philosophical inquiry in which we freely explore questions, consequences be damned. I argue, however, that although we might just be in the business of asking questions, we do not merely, in virtue of engaging in philosophical inquiry, absolve ourselves of responsibility for the risks that inquiry incurs.

I. On Consequential Research

As Heather Douglas has noted, ethical lapses in scientific research, such as the Tuskegee experiment, have forced practitioners in the sciences to reckon with the serious ethical challenges involved with experimenting on human subjects and human communities (Douglas Reference Douglas2014; Reference Douglas, Cartwight and Montuschi2015; Reference Douglas and Humphreys2016). These ethical lapses, both with respect to how the research is conducted (for example, Tuskegee) and the outcomes of the research (for example, atomic bombs), have pushed both the sciences and the social sciences to develop codes of professional ethics. Returning to the subject matter of philosophical inquiry, the idea that philosophy has practical consequences that should constrain how we conduct our research is often, perhaps understandably, met with a kind of incredulity. If there are any practical risks associated with doing philosophy, we think not of the paradigmatic examples in the sciences of either Tuskegee or the atomic bomb, but of Socrates being executed by the state or the murder of this journal's namesake, Hypatia. Despite how frequently people compare themselves to Socrates on Twitter in response to being “canceled,” such risks are small for professional philosophers.Footnote 1 Furthermore, given philosophy's supposed lack of progress over the centuries, one could be forgiven for doubting the practical impact of philosophy on the world. Nonetheless, I think we should resist this view of philosophy for two reasons.

First, I take this view to be undermined by the continued practice of philosophy; after all, why continue to do philosophy in the first place, if such a view is right? Perhaps philosophical practice is continued through the mere intellectual edification to be found in posing and contemplating questions. However, as I'll note in section III, there are reasons to doubt this conception of philosophical practice. Second, such a conception of philosophy ignores the close connection between critical theory, applied philosophy, philosophy of science, and feminist philosophy, all of which clearly count as philosophy of consequence, that is, philosophy that has a public-facing component.Footnote 2 Furthermore, bioethicists are a notable exception to the idea that philosophers are ill-suited to contribute to policy. For a more pernicious example that clearly demonstrates the practical consequence of philosophical inquiry, consider Katelyn Burns's reporting in Vox of the influence of transexclusionary radical feminist arguments in the recently decided Supreme Court cases Bostock v. Clayton County and R. G. & G. R. Harris Funeral Homes v. EEOC and Aimee Stephens (and in turn the contrasting Brief of Philosophy Professors as Amici Curiae in Support of the Employees).Footnote 3 As Burns notes, Kathleen Stock's “work is cited in several amici briefs to the Supreme Court in the Stephens case, showing how gender-critical academia is assisting to legitimize anti-trans policy positions” (Burns Reference Burns2019).

As these examples demonstrate, philosophers, and in turn our work, is of consequence. If it's appropriate to have ethical oversight to stave off rare high-impact events in scientific research, it doesn't strike me as terribly out of place to also institute such a rule for philosophical inquiry. It is naïve and irresponsible to think that philosophy takes place in a vacuum, and not in a society rich with real-world consequences and practical import. We cannot ignore the increasingly pressing need to take seriously the idea that there could be constraints on philosophical inquiry, that is, the need to develop an ethics of practice for philosophical inquiry.

The task of answering the challenge of developing an ethics of practice for philosophical inquiry can seem daunting. As Thiem and their colleagues’ white paper on publication ethics in philosophy demonstrates, the issues within this domain are wide-ranging. As the authors note, the issues include, but are not limited to, what distinguishes verbatim plagiarism from plagiarism of ideas—this is an especially pressing question in humanities fields where the scholarly products of our work are ideas—to determining best practices for research involving marginalized and vulnerable populations (Thiem et al. Reference Thiem, Sealey, Ferrer, Trott and Kennison2019). Further, and related to concerns about plagiarism, how do you use the insights and experiences of marginalized and vulnerable groups without verging into the territory of appropriation? However, we do not need to start from scratch to answer these questions posed by Thiem and their colleagues. Fruitful answers can be found by comparing scientific practice to philosophical practice. Exploring the answers to the question of the responsibilities of scientists qua scientists can help us get a handle on the responsibilities of philosophers qua philosophers.Footnote 4

In thinking about the place of values in guiding scientific inquiry, Richard Rudner is the first to caution that the scientist qua scientist must consider the “the importance, in the typically ethical sense, of making a mistake in accepting or rejecting the hypothesis” (Rudner Reference Rudner1953, 2; emphasis in the original).Footnote 5 Such mistakes can come in varying degrees and lead to similarly varying degrees of caution the scientist must exercise. For example, you need a much higher degree of confirmation regarding the safety of an experimental drug than you would for determining whether a stamp-making machine is defective. The difference between the two ultimately rests on a distinctively moral difference, namely, the moral consequences of getting it wrong.

Returning to Burns's reporting, in a world where transmisogynistic violence is rampant, to contribute to a philosophical discourse that would further encourage or justify such violence carries with it high moral risks, and those risks ought to constrain how we conduct philosophical inquiry on such matters (Burns Reference Burns2019). That is, we cannot playfully debate the dignity or humanity of others in the same way we might debate whether there are tables or just simples arranged table-wise.Footnote 6 The relevant sense of “cannot” here is the moral sense. When it comes to theorizing about others, that is, treating others as objects of our inquiry, there are important moral risks present that raise the stakes of the debate and make it even more imperative that we treat the subjects of our inquiry with the right kind of respect. For example, some ways of asking a question inherently demean or dehumanize the group of whom the question is asked. There are at least two risks here: a risk inherent in the content of the views under consideration and a risk to the subjects of our inquiry. These risks, however, can not only come apart but also run together in complicated ways.

Audrey Yap has argued that philosophical inquiry can result in hidden costs to both the inquirer and the people being inquired about (Yap Reference Yap2021). To make this point she employs María Lugones's notion of world-traveling (Lugones Reference Lugones1987)—for example, the ways nondominantly situated peoples learn to code-switch—to argue that doing this work in academic contexts can often cost the traveler something important in at least two ways. First, one might feel (and often rightly feel) exploited. In virtue of your positioning you might routinely be called upon to educate others about your community.Footnote 7 Another risk one takes on is that your work may be appropriated. As Emmalon Davis argues, as marginalized knowers produce knowledge, that work may be taken up by those outside of the community, and in that uptake the connection to the marginalized group responsible for the knowledge production may be severed, lost, or disguised (Davis Reference Davis2018). In other work, Davis describes the following double bind for marginalized practitioners: one's work often only gets uptake when it's about one's own group, but at the same time that work gets discredited for not being “objective” (Davis Reference Davis and Lackey2021). And further still, as Yap notes while drawing on the work of the Kahnawake scholar Audra Simpson, sometimes the work we do in the community related to our identities can leave us as outsiders to our own community (Yap Reference Yap2021). As Simpson writes, “can I do this and still come home; what am I revealing here and why? Where will this get us? Who benefits from this and why?” (Simpson Reference Simpson2007, 78).

These are costs incurred by the subjects of our philosophical inquiry, and sometimes these costs are exacerbated when the inquirer is the subject of their own inquiry. Even with all of these costs outlined, we've likely not exhausted the costs of inquiry to either the subjects of the inquiry or the inquirer themselves. For example, this discussion demonstrates that risks can also eventuate differently based not only on who is conducting the inquiry; another complicating factor is the context of the inquiry. For example, John Stuart Mill famously noted the following constraint on when it's permissible to ask some questions:

Even opinions lose their immunity, when the circumstances in which they are expressed are such as to constitute their expression as a positive instigation to some mischievous act. An opinion that corn-dealers are starvers of the poor, or that private property is robbery, ought to be unmolested when simply circulated through the press, but may justly incur punishment when delivered orally to an excited mob assembled before the house of a corn-dealer. (Mill Reference Mill1998, 62)Footnote 8

As I noted earlier, in a world where transmisogynistic violence is rampant, to contribute to a philosophical discourse that would further encourage such violence carries with it high moral risks, and those risks ought to constrain how we conduct philosophical inquiry on such matters. Although in section II I'll articulate how some methods of inquiry can violate expectations of respect and thus, in Mill's terms, perhaps should not circulate “unmolested,” the following basic point remains: what risks are present and how these risks shape our obligations when conducting philosophical inquiry can shift according to both who is asking the questions and the contexts in which those questions are asked.Footnote 9

The implication of the identification of these various risks suggests a kind of moral encroachment on the norms governing philosophical inquiry. Traditionally, moral encroachment is the idea that the evidential support you need to be epistemically justified in believing something can vary according to the moral stakes.Footnote 10 For example, believing that someone is a waiter because of the color of their skin is a paradigmatically racist belief. However, there might be contexts in which the color of someone's skin is excellent evidence that they are a waiter. Moral encroachers argue that although you have what looks like otherwise strong evidence on which to base your belief, because of the moral risks involved, that is, racism, you should be held to a higher justificatory standard than in other contexts where such moral risks are absent. Similarly, as we saw from Rudner, the level of evidential support required for being justified in believing that an experimental drug is safe is higher than the level of evidential support required for being justified in believing that a stamp-making machine is defective.Footnote 11 So, when it comes to answering the question of how to do philosophy in a way that treats people with proper respect, I suggest that one strategy is to implement a version of this moral encroachment framework. That is, there are moral stakes associated with the moral risks not only with regard to what questions we ask and make room for, but stakes for the people whom those questions are about.

II. On Respectful Research

With regard to philosophical inquiry, there are two ways to spell out what being held to higher standards might mean. First, the moral stakes of our inquiry can raise the evidential threshold we must cross with respect to how confident we can be that our inquiry will not cause harm or that our inquiry will not wrong those we're inquiring about. Second, the moral stakes might determine what questions ought to be considered live options or which options one should be agnostic about. That is, related to the first, the evidential threshold one must cross to present certain views on a question—to treat them as a live option—may be higher for some questions than others. Inquiry involves commitments; in asking questions we introduce those commitments into the common ground, and perhaps there are some things that shouldn't be admitted into the common ground.

Two sets of challenges remain here, however. First, what does it take to treat others with proper respect within the practice of philosophical inquiry? To sketch a possible answer, we can turn to a related debate: what it takes to treat others with proper respect within our thoughts. Second, one might have some new worries about the strength of this analogy between the responsibilities of scientists qua scientists and the responsibilities of philosophers qua philosophers. First, the arguments so far for the risks involved in philosophical inquiry rest on similarities to the risks involved in scientific inquiry. A disanalogy between the forms of inquiry could be pushed as follows: the real difference between philosophy and science is that science, unlike philosophy, relies primarily on induction, whereas philosophy relies on deduction. Only induction allows for inductive risk, so as long as we stick to a purely deductive method then there are no risks involved in philosophical inquiry.Footnote 12 And second, one might worry that mitigating the risks involved in doing philosophy may undermine the philosophical enterprise itself. I will take each of these challenges in turn. I will answer the first set of challenges in this section, and then turn to the second set of challenges in section III.

Apart from the practical risks, an additional moral risk comes with the abstract theoretical methodology that characterizes much of philosophical inquiry. Our objector will likely try to press the point that whereas unethical scientific experiments violate human rights, philosophical thought experiments do not violate any such rights. This risk involved in scientific inquiry and practice is why scientific methodologies must be subject to institutional review boards (IRBs). As Douglas has noted, scientists have “responsibilities to treat human and animal subjects with a high level of respect and to submit methodologies involving such subjects for review (e.g., to IRBs) to ensure that high standards are being met” (Douglas Reference Douglas2014, 968). Our objector notes that there is no similar process for vetting philosophical methodologies. Presumably they'd argue that this is because there are no similar moral risks involved in philosophical inquiry and practice. Such an objection, however, is working with an impoverished idea of what the ethics of research are.Footnote 13

Consider closely the phrase “responsibilities to treat human and animal subjects with a high level of respect.” Respect in experimentation can take familiar forms in scientific experimentation, for example, obtaining informed consent or simply not torturing test subjects. Respect, however, will include all kinds of things not obviously within this range. IRBs exist not only to ensure that ethical constraints apply to scientific research that makes direct interventions in people's lives, but also to the social sciences and disciplines like ethnography. In order to take seriously the worry that we may be failing in our obligations to others when conducting philosophical inquiry, we need a broader understanding of our obligations to others that already underpins the work that IRBs do, namely, that as researchers we have obligations to the broader community our research either involves or affects. We've already established that there are at least two risks involved in philosophical inquiry: risks inherent in the content of the views under consideration and risks to the subjects of our inquiry. There are likely still further risks, and simply because IRBs don't currently vet philosophical research doesn't mean they shouldn't.

In virtue of engaging in this practice of philosophical inquiry, we're well positioned to think about the kinds of ethical risks that are already at issue in the sciences and about whether those same risks, or variants of those risks, emerge for the work that we do. I cannot here hope to give a complete answer to the question of what respect in philosophical experimentation should look like, but I can gesture toward at least one avenue for developing such an account that emerges from the recent literature on doxastic wronging. Doxastic wronging is the thesis that we can wrong others in virtue of what we believe about them. Although this view is controversial, the arguments given in its support also support the less controversial view that we could wrong others in how we go about asking questions about them.Footnote 14 Demonstrating the weaker claim is all we need to make plausible the idea that additional moral risks emerge in the context of philosophical inquiry.

The challenge we face is that conducting inquiry about others seems to necessitate a certain abstraction and a certain removal from the standard moral relationships we find ourselves in. This sentiment is echoed in an open letter by Linda Martín Alcoff and many colleagues, where the authors state that, “[w]e should conduct our research freely and responsibly, without treating other people's lives as though they are abstract thought experiments” (Alcoff et al. Reference Alcoff, Ásta, Bauer and Bettcher2019). This form of abstract philosophical inquiry seems to require taking an objective stance toward the subjects of our inquiry. As P. F. Strawson notes: “To adopt the objective attitude to another human being is to see him, perhaps, as an object of social policy; as a subject for what, in a wide range of sense, might be called treatment; as something certainly to be taken account, perhaps precautionary account, of; to be managed or handled or cured or trained; perhaps simply to be avoided” (Strawson Reference Strawson1962/2008, 190). We adopt this objective attitude when the agent is excluded from ordinary human relationships, for example, when they are a child. Furthermore, this management, handling, training, or avoidance need not occur at the level of action, but also at the level of thought. For example, a therapist ought to take the objective attitude toward their patient to have the distance necessary for what is required of their role. The objective attitude, importantly for the questions of philosophical inquiry that interest us, can be taken up out of intellectual curiosity. If philosophical inquiry can take the form of asking questions about the worthwhileness of someone's life, about whether it is morally permissible to engage in a discriminatory practice, about what status individuals are to be afforded, to do such inquiry we must choose to view those who will be affected by the conclusions of our arguments as objects of study. In so doing, we cannot have, or we actively choose not to have, an ordinary interpersonal relationship with those we are theorizing about.Footnote 15 In doing so, we no longer reason with them, but rather reason about them.Footnote 16

Consider also María Lugones and Elizabeth Spelman's critique of white feminist philosophy. They note (in a hispana voice), “there is nothing that necessitates that [white/Anglo feminists] understand our world: understand, that is, not as an observer understands things, but as a participant understands them” (Lugones and Spelman Reference Lugones and Spelman1983, 576; emphasis added). Although not necessarily the same as the objective-stance and participant-stance distinction that one finds in Strawson, we see here again an articulation of the idea that there are risks involved in abstraction that go beyond mere epistemic risk, that is, the risk of abstracting away important details of the case and being led away from the truth in that abstraction. When you abstract, you perceive arrogantly, as Marilyn Frye argues (Frye Reference Frye1983). Similarly, when you abstract, you run the risks that emerge from no longer knowing with others when their perspectives may be essential to the subject at hand (see Pohlhaus Reference Pohlhaus2006). That is, you run the epistemic risk of missing valuable information that ought to inform your theorizing, but crucially you run the additional, distinctively moral risk of failing to treat others as they ought to be treated. To make this idea of “failing to treat others as they ought to be treated” clearer, let us consider the harms that emerge from not being sensitive to this risk.

Take, for example, a prominent philosopher giving a keynote at a conference. The risks present in the content of their presentation, combined with the risks present in their choice of abstract methodology, is likely going to place them in a position to undermine the standing of threatened groups when they argue that members of that group ought to be discriminated against. What has been neglected is an additional risk that they ought to be sensitive to, which concerns the standing of the group they're inquiring about. This example is, of course, not merely a fanciful philosophical thought to play with, but rather is the event that prompted the first draft of this paper. I am referring here to the reaction to Richard Swinburne's keynote at a conference for the Society of Christian Philosophers. In his keynote address, Swinburne put forward an argument that many objected to on moral grounds. This argument compared homosexuality to a disability, and the argument was reasonably taken to be offensive to both the LGBTQ community and to people with disabilities. In response, organizer Michael Rea issued an apology. After issuing the apology, he came under attack for doing so. Second, when Christina Van Dyke suggested that the ideas advanced in the keynote are responsible for “incalculable harm to vast numbers of disadvantaged people,” she was mocked for appealing to some abstract, and supposedly laughable, notion that people could be harmed by a philosophy keynote.

I believe Swinburne's keynote did constitute a wrong toward members of the marginalized communities he was theorizing about, and it is a good example of all three of the general risks involved in philosophical inquiry: the risk present in the choice of method, the view itself, and the risks to the subjects of the inquiry. That is, the wrongs that stem from the keynote involve both the expressive harms that come from the publicity of his position as a keynote speaker, the method of abstraction, and disrespect for the subjects of his inquiry. On the first point, consider the signal that inviting problematic speakers to an event sends. Norms of invitations require that you treat the invited speaker respectfully. As Jeremy Fantl argues, “[t]his explains why the most harmful consequences of abusive speech in a university setting include debilitating feelings of isolation and estrangement. . . . [I]f you feel that the group shares the speaker's attitudes or even just thinks of them as a live hypothesis—then it is very difficult to feel like you are a member of the group” (Fantl Reference Fantl2018, 188). The wrong here is a kind of betrayal trauma. Borrowing from Jennifer Freyd, Fantl notes that “[b]etrayal trauma is a kind of trauma that ‘occurs when the people or institutions on which a person depends for survival significantly violate that person's trust or well-being’” (189; see Freyd Reference Freyd, Reyes, Elhai and Ford2008, 76). These sentiments are echoed explicitly in t philosopher's explanation for leaving the philosophy profession. She notes that she has “been driven off social media because of feelings of stress, vulnerability, anger, and pain that surface whenever there is new trans-related philosophical news” (t philosopher 2019). She no longer feels that philosophy offers her a community, and these violations of trust have had a serious effect on her well-being. There is something worse about the publicity of a keynote, but even arguments that lack this level of publicity can betray a failure to demonstrate respect.Footnote 17

In defense of the argument that beliefs can wrong, I've previously argued that beliefs about others commit us to content that represents perspectival claims about that individual's status in the world (see Basu Reference Basu and Lackey2021). Our beliefs mediate our interpersonal relations with others, and in so doing, our beliefs carry moral weight and can themselves be the source of moral wrongdoing. If we consider the act of inquiry, when we play devil's advocate and entertain arguments just for the sake of argument, we are doing something when we put the argument forward, we are revealing something about ourselves, our commitments, and how we relate to the subject/s of our inquiry. In inquiry we may not be as committed to the content as when we believe, but inquiry into other persons nonetheless mediates our relationship to those persons. The wrong here is an interpersonal one; the wrong here is a relational one. When conducting philosophical inquiry, we are not thereby absolved from the moral recommendation to do better by one another. That is, given that philosophical inquiry reflects your commitments to subjects of your inquiry, there is an extra demand, an extra burden, on the inquirer to assure the subjects of your inquiry that you do not in fact have a deficiency of moral respect for them.

To sum up where we have now arrived, although certain moral risks involving scientific experimentation are absent in philosophical thought experiments, we see a distinctive kind of moral risk arise in the latter context. This is the risk of not treating others as we ought, or more simply, a risk of treating the subjects of our inquiry as objects. This is a risk that emerges from the abstraction that characterizes much of philosophical inquiry, so it is a risk distinctive of the methods we choose to employ. Relatedly, we can ask whether there are some questions that are beyond the philosophical pale. Perhaps there are some questions that one cannot ask in a way that is compatible with orienting toward others with dignity and treating them as beings who are worthy of respect, that is, questions concerning whether they are deserving of dignity or respect, as we've previously discussed with regard to risks that might be inherent in the content of view. Although I cannot settle this question here, it is one of the risks we must determine how to balance. And in asking that question, we see that philosophical inquiry finds itself in a similar position as scientific inquiry in requiring an ethics of practice.

III. On the Strength and Relevance of the Analogy

The second set of challenges an ethics for philosophical practice must contend with concerns both the strength and relevance of the analogy between scientific inquiry and philosophical inquiry. First, an objection could be raised that the real difference between philosophical inquiry and scientific inquiry is that scientific inquiry relies primarily on induction whereas philosophy relies primarily on deduction. For example, someone giving a metaphysical view of womanhood through conceptual analysis is engaging in a different form of inquiry than the kind of predictive inquiry that scientific practice is aimed at. My answer here will be quick, and I again draw on resources from philosophy of science. The more you narrow what philosophy is and aims to do in order to cut its ties with anything resembling practical import as discussed in section I, the less well that model of philosophy will serve us as a general model of philosophical research. For example, consider John Dupré's explanation of why physics is a bad model to employ when thinking through questions about the place of values in scientific inquiry:

There are plenty of more or less wholly value-free statements, but they achieve that status by restricting themselves to things that are of merely academic interest to us. This is one reason that physics has been a sometimes disastrous model for the rest of science. We hardly want to limit science to the investigation of things that don't matter much to us one way or the other. The application of assumptions appropriate only to things that don't matter to those that do is potentially a disastrous one. (Dupré Reference Dupré2012, 65)Footnote 18

Perhaps there will be fewer harms attached to methods of inquiry that are the most abstract, and in those cases our inquiry can continue unrestrained. Restricting ourselves to such a narrow conception of philosophical inquiry, however, ignores the breadth of what philosophical inquiry seeks to question. As soon as the subject of that inquiry concerns actual people in the actual world, risks will enter into the picture again, and we need an account of how we ought to respond to these risks. That is, we cannot escape the need to develop an ethics of philosophical practice by retreating to more abstraction.

A more challenging objection is that mitigating the risks involved in doing philosophy might undermine the philosophical enterprise itself. As Graham Priest notes (and as feminist philosophers of science have noted more generally [see Antony Reference Antony, Antony and Witt2002; Anderson Reference Anderson2004]), a certain dogmatism is essential to scientific inquiry. According to Priest, what distinguishes philosophical inquiry from other intellectual endeavors is how central the development of a critical attitude is to philosophy (Priest Reference Priest2006).

The conception of philosophy that Priest offers is philosophy as critique. According to this conception, unlike other disciplines like mathematics, history, or the sciences, when it comes to philosophy “there is nothing that may not be challenged” (Priest Reference Priest2006, 201). This conception of philosophy has three salient features. First, philosophy is subversive. Second, philosophy is unsettling. And third, philosophy challenges everything; it is of “universal import” (203). That is, as philosophers, we are in the business of asking questions designed to unsettle, and as a result, often questions that also upset. Crucially, the critical attitude at the core of philosophical inquiry is unrestrained. Thus, to impose limits on inquiry or to impose boundaries on what questions may be asked is to undermine the philosophical enterprise itself. This is the sense in which perhaps addressing the moral risks I previously outlined is antithetical to philosophical practice.Footnote 19 Furthermore, according to Priest (Reference Priest2006), we must not only question everything, but we are also allowed to use our most adversarial methods to do so in the interests of unsettling others and being subversive. However, this conception of philosophy as critique obscures what it is we in fact do when we inquire.

The idealized view of philosophy that has been offered privileges certain kinds of critique and a certain kind of methodology while disallowing other kinds as inconsistent with the philosophical project of open, unfettered inquiry. However, as we'll see, this conception leaves itself open to the critique that philosophy is not engaged in mere critique. That is, one response is to say that critique should be more universally applied. That is, in critiquing philosophical inquiry itself, we should engage in an honest self-assessment of philosophy and this practice of inquiry. If inquiry involves limiting areas open for consideration, perhaps there are moral considerations that shift those limits to ones that are more conscientiously concerned with their effects on the most marginalized.Footnote 20 Relatedly, developing an ethics of philosophical practice may not only involve reconsidering what questions we consider, what boundaries we draw, but also what methodologies we employ in exploring those questions and in mapping conceptual space. That is, our choice of methodology is itself a value judgment, and it is here that we see another familiar argument from the philosophy of science: the demarcation problem (see Longino Reference Longino1995; Reference Longino, Hankinson Nelson and Nelson1996). Methodology-choice is a value-laden choice and it is one of the risks we must be sensitive to when engaging in philosophical inquiry. Given that we are not in fact free to choose any method we wish when engaging in philosophical inquiry, I will canvass an alternative method to the method of critique. I turn now to discussing each of these points in more detail.

On the first point regarding philosophical boundaries, as Kristie Dotson has pointed out, philosophers don't in fact ask questions about everything. There are baked-in limitations on what gets asked. Thus, Priest's framing doesn't capture the way philosophy is actually practiced. As Dotson notes, the questions that get counted as philosophical questions are often “constricted, oppressive, and ethnocentric” (Dotson Reference Dotson2011, 403). Commenting on philosophy's leaky pipeline and its inability to retain the small number of diverse people it manages to attract, Dotson notes that when she watches one or two philosophically trained Black women quit the field of philosophy each year, the final realization that serves as their impetus for quitting “is not, ‘I have failed at philosophy,’ but rather, ‘philosophy has failed me’” (403). Many of the diverse people whom philosophy manages to attract can get pushed out because the questions they ask do not get treated as philosophical questions. As Dotson goes on to note, she routinely gets asked how the questions she's asking count as philosophy (Dotson Reference Dotson2012). That such questions arise strongly suggests that there are background conditions baked into how we do philosophy, and these background conditions make themselves apparent under the guise of disciplinary boundaries.

What Dotson finds is that a certain set of questions and a certain adversarial method in addressing those questions have become privileged. What counts as philosophical are positions that have already been staked out. After all, those are positions that can be critiqued. And given the demographic make-up of the history of philosophy, it is often the case that the questions and philosophical positions that have been staked out do not speak to practitioners like herself. As Dotson puts it: “[A]cademic philosophy is structured in such a way that established trends in philosophical thought delimit what questions can be addressed, and this is reinforced by the dominant conception of philosophy as critique; this effectively marginalizes problems and/or concerns of diverse people that do not fit comfortably within an already set disciplinary agenda” (407). Of course, it is not good that philosophy has these sorts of disciplinary boundaries. How the boundaries have been set up is to exclude practitioners like Dotson. So, according to this first response, although philosophers like Priest might think that philosophical inquiry aims at challenging everything, in actuality, philosophical inquiry is constrained by a disciplinarily enforced border regarding what sorts of questions can be debated and what sorts of questions get uptake. In this regard, philosophical inquiry more closely resembles scientific inquiry, and in developing an ethics of philosophical practice we can't pretend that there aren't boundaries. Instead, what we must do is accept that there are boundaries and determine what they ought to be. In pursuing this normative question, we're now engaging in the same line of inquiry as feminist philosophers of science with regard to whether the value-free ideal is the right model for scientific inquiry.Footnote 21

Philosophers of science have long debated the role of ethical and moral considerations in settling the question of which scientific hypothesis to accept, and as Helen Longino has argued, there is no purely epistemically hallowed set of epistemic virtues or principles in guiding hypothesis selection (Longino Reference Longino1995; Reference Longino, Hankinson Nelson and Nelson1996). For example, the choice between a theory that promotes accuracy on the one hand and novelty on the other depends not on purely epistemic considerations but sociopolitical ones. This is the demarcation problem in philosophy of science, and an analog to it appears in the case of philosophical inquiry. What is the set of epistemic virtues or principles that ought to guide hypothesis selection in philosophical inquiry? Given that we're now asking the same questions, scientific inquiry and philosophical inquiry seem to have much more in common than the initial philosophy as critique objection suggested.

To see a place where we have this value-laden choice about something that seems otherwise purely epistemic, consider the risks we incur in our choice of methodologies. Some ways of engaging in philosophical inquiry carry with them risks of harm that have been outlined in section II. Philosophical inquiry in fact admits of a plurality of methodologies, and our choice between these methodologies (and which we determine to be legitimate or illegitimate) is a value-laden choice. For example, instead of subversion, we might instead seek a methodology that promotes the virtue of illumination.

To arrive at this alternative methodology, let us first consider the assumptions that are baked into the idea that philosophical inquiry is at its roots a subversive practice, designed to wake one from their dogmatic slumber and challenge the status quo. As Talia Mae Bettcher has noted:

[T]his conception of philosophy rests on a highly controversial assumption: namely that for the “prephilosophical man” the “world tends to become obvious” and “common objects rouse no questions” and that this man is “imprisoned in the prejudices derived from common sense.” In short, this is to assume that all appeared well and good before philosophy arrived on the scene: Our common sense, our everyday understanding of the world was, if superficial, happily undisturbed. In other words, this is to assume a close fit between individuals and their “everyday.” (Bettcher Reference Bettcher2019, 8)

As Bettcher goes on to note, this assumption is baseless, and the baselessness of the assumption is clear to those of us for whom the world has never been obvious and our movement through the world as routine has been questioned and challenged. Bettcher notes that for trans people, their version of the “everyday” is “shot through with perplexity, shot through with WTF questions. We live in the WTF. We did not need philosophy to uncover its perplexity. It was already there” (8).

We do of course need to be a bit more careful here. It might be that given one's experiences they'll be more likely to take a skeptical or distanced attitude toward gender norms, social norms, or sexual norms. But it's unclear to what extent that translates to a broader skeptical attitude toward other questions in philosophy, for example, the nature of causation. Nonetheless, we can draw out the general lesson that the value of philosophy stems not from the installation of a critical attitude in a particularly subversive or adversarial mode as there are other ways a critical attitude might be installed. Rather, for certain practitioners and certain approaches to questions, a better method is not critique, but rather illumination. This tension with philosophy of critique offers us a response to the earlier normative question of whether philosophy ought to aspire to a more ideal form of philosophy of critique. The answer we're pushed toward, if we take Bettcher's philosophy as illumination seriously, is “no.” Philosophy as illumination is of course compatible with philosophy as critique, but as Bettcher will go on to note, we need to be better about the questions we close off.Footnote 22

As anyone working on topics concerning race and racism can attest, there will always be an audience member who challenges a paradigmatic example of racism as not in fact racist. There is often nothing satisfactory that one can say, in part because they're not really playing a cooperative game. Bettcher's account can help illuminate the wrong in the lack of cooperation. If one does not take certain presumptions on board or one tries to argue that they're false, as Bettcher argues, then “one is not doing feminist, queer, or trans philosophy at all; one is doing something else. At least on the face of it, this ‘something else’ looks, in part, like an attempt to undermine the validity of these very domains of inquiry” (Bettcher Reference Bettcher2019, 10). The objector might now return to their original question and ask whether acceptance of starting points runs against the spirit of philosophical inquiry. However, just as it is mistaken to think that scientific inquiry has no starting points and that those starting points aren't shot through with value judgments, so too it is a mistake to think that philosophical inquiry has no standardly accepted starting points, as demonstrated here by Bettcher's and Dotson's arguments.

As Bettcher also notes, “the acceptance of starting points is necessary to any philosophical investigation, and the sorts of starting points accepted vary depending upon the philosophical endeavor at hand” (11). Consider, for example, what is inappropriate about raising the skeptical scenarios that we cannot know that trolleys exist (given external-world skepticism) during a talk about trolley cases. There is a time and a place for external-world skepticism, but a talk on trolley cases is clearly not it. Similarly, consider my audience member's resistance to granting the basic starting assumptions about racism as being analogous to an audience member's resistance to granting the basic starting assumption that an external world exists. Furthermore, even the choice of example here ought to be scrutinized. After all, when talking about trolley cases we might be subject to the critique that we are once again using people as abstract objects for the purpose of philosophical play. Not only do we have a case where actual people are being used as thought experiments, the structure of the case elides important features of our actual world that are central to ethical decision making. As Robin James notes, when you put someone at “the helm of [the] trolley, we see that the trolley problem is a fun puzzle to solve precisely because it abstracts away from the physical, emotional, and affective experience of violence and death” (James Reference James2018). The choice of trolley examples itself betrays certain background commitments and assumptions.Footnote 23

IV. Continuing the Conversation

This project can be seen as continuing a conversation started by the Thiem and their colleagues’ white paper on publication ethics (Thiem et al. Reference Thiem, Sealey, Ferrer, Trott and Kennison2019). When thinking about what principles should guide ethical research in philosophy, we need first to articulate what risks are present in the practice and disarm the objection that ethical constraints on the practice of philosophy would undermine the very thing that makes philosophy different from the other disciplines. Philosophy is not unique in being immune from moral criticism. However, the objector gets something right. The ethical guidelines for philosophical practice stem from distinctive risks present in philosophical inquiry that are in some ways different from the risks that give rise to ethical guidelines for other forms of inquiry, for example, scientific inquiry. That is, there are kinds of moral criticism apt for philosophical inquiry that are unique to how it is practiced.

Comparing the need for ethical oversight for philosophical research to the raison d’être for IRBs might suggest that the answer to the lack of ethical oversight for philosophical research is to implement IRB approval for philosophical projects. Although some philosophical work, for example, work in experimental philosophy that involves the recruiting of test subjects, does require IRB approval, philosophical work more generally is exempted from requiring IRB approval. The reason given is that philosophical research is not considered “research.” For example, the US Department of Health & Human Services Office of Research Integrity defines research as follows: “A systematic investigation (i.e., the gathering and analysis of information) designed to develop or contribute to generalizable knowledge.”Footnote 24 Because the philosophical method is considered neither systematic, that is, it doesn't employ the scientific method, nor generalizable, that is, the conclusions about a sample population are not taken to extend to the wider population represented by the sample, the knowledge produced in most philosophical articles doesn't count as research in the way that the term research is used by IRBs. Although this might suggest we have further reason to reject the comparison between scientific research and philosophical research, that would be too quick. That there are different methods and different research outcomes does not eliminate the need for developing an ethics of practice for philosophical inquiry. Rather, what this demonstrates is that the current model of IRB approval is not well-suited to evaluating the particular risks present in the methods employed by philosophers. So, either we ought to expand the definition of research used by IRBs to both include methods beyond the scientific method and a definition of generalizable knowledge that is similarly more expansive, or we should think seriously about alternatives, that is, non-IRB, models for ethical oversight. Either route requires taking seriously that there are ethical concerns that arise in the course of philosophical research and the question of how best to address those concerns.

Further, when evaluating the risks involved in philosophical inquiry, I want to put forward a word of caution: in saying that philosophy is a morally hazardous activity I do not mean to suggest that we should refrain from all philosophical inquiry that carries any sort of risk. We engage in risky activities all the time. However, to answer the question of how much risk we should tolerate, how we should respond to the risks inherent in philosophical practice, we need to first recognize that there are risks. In thinking about how to balance these risks, many open questions remain. For example, as we think about how philosophy is practiced in academia, important dimensions of power and authority will need to be accounted for in a full development of an ethics of practice for philosophy. For example, sometimes dismantling structural injustice will cause harm, and when proposing solutions, those who have been treated unjustly may have a better understanding of what justice requires than those who treat others unjustly do.Footnote 25 That is, as we think about how to balance the risks of inquiry, we must also contend with questions of justice and power. Nonetheless, the goal of this article has been much more modest. As an early step in the conversation, my goal has been to draw attention to at least three such risks: risks present in the methods we employ, risks inherent in the content of the views under consideration, and risks to the subjects of our inquiry.

For more complicating factors, consider Barrett Emerick's arguments concerning the questions that arise at the intersection of free speech and academic freedom that might also arise for what kinds of questions we can responsibly ask and investigate (Emerick Reference Emerick2021). Further, earlier I discussed Dotson's observation that given the demographic make-up of the history of philosophy, it is often the case that the questions and philosophical positions that have been staked out do not speak to practitioners like herself (Dotson Reference Dotson2011). There are, however, even deeper concerns about the history of philosophy and how the demographic make-up of the field may obfuscate and lead our inquiry astray. For example, when Charles Mills critiques the whiteness of philosophy and the white racial frame that shapes philosophical inquiry, he quotes Linda Martín Alcoff's observation that “the ‘society’ about which these philosophers are writing often seems to be composed exclusively of white males” (Mills Reference Mills, Sullivan and Tuana2007, 14; see Alcoff Reference Alcoff1996, 2, n. 1). In addition, perhaps there are also deep structural issues present in how our research is published, the incentive structures present in academia, and as Remco Heesen and Liam Bright have argued with respect to scientific practice, we ought to abolish peer review more generally (Heesen and Bright Reference Heesen and Brightforthcoming). Further still, since the first draft of this article and various revisions, a lot has happened in professional philosophy that demonstrates the ever-growing, pressing need for developing an ethics of philosophical practice. For example, this journal and others have had their own publication ethics controversies, the inaugural issue of The Journal of Controversial Ideas has been published, and even more philosophers have decided to leave a profession that treats their lives as playthings.

I cannot provide all the answers to how we should do philosophy in an ethically responsible way, but I hope this article will provide some much-needed impetus for taking seriously the question of what an ethics of practice ought to look like for philosophical inquiry. An ethical reckoning of philosophy is called for by—and calls out—the very sort of inquiry that philosophy is.

Acknowledgments

The first draft of this article was a Facebook post in 2016. Since that time the development of the core ideas of this article have benefited greatly from each presentation and conversation on the topic. I'm indebted to audiences at USC's Speculative Society, the 2017 Central APA, Amherst College, UC San Diego, NYU's MAP chapter, and the students and attendees of Sarah McGrath's graduate seminar in Spring 2020. Many thanks also to Liam Kofi Bright, Erik Encarnacion, Maegan Fairchild, Gabbrielle Johnson, Zoë Johnson King, Renée Jorgensen, Nicola Kemp, Lauren Leydon-Hardy, Luke Roelofs, Mark Schroeder, and Ralph Wedgwood for conversations and, in some cases, written comments on multiple drafts. Also, a special thanks to several anonymous referees (including the self-described “persnickety” one) for feedback. This article has improved greatly thanks to all of their efforts.

Rima Basu is Assistant Professor of philosophy at Claremont McKenna College. Her work at the intersection of ethics, epistemology, and philosophy of race examines the question of how we ought to relate to one another, and it highlights the epistemic dimensions of wrongs such as racism. Representative publications include “The Wrongs of Racist Beliefs” (Philosophical Studies, 2019), “What We Epistemically Owe to Each Other” (Philosophical Studies, 2019), and “Radical Moral Encroachment” (Philosophical Issues, 2019).

Footnotes

1 It is further worth noting that many examples of prominent “cancellations” are in fact resignations where the respective institutions demonstrated a continued commitment to protecting the academic freedom of the scholars facing protests calling for their resignation.

2 Often, for this very reason, such work is not considered real philosophy (see Dotson Reference Dotson2012). Additionally, for an analysis of the impact of the work of philosophers of science on the field of the sciences more generally, see Khelfaoui et al. Reference Khelfaoui, Yves Gingras and Pradeu2021.

3 Bostock v. Clayton County, 590 U.S. __ (2020). Brief amicus curiae of Philosophy Professors. 3 July 2019. https://www.supremecourt.gov/DocketPDF/17/17-1618/107015/20190703125853982_17-1618%2017-1623%2018-107%20PhilosophyProfessors%20Brief.pdf.

4 Another reason for turning to the question of what are the responsibilities of scientists qua scientists to answer the question of what are the responsibilities of philosophers qua philosophers is that we risk reinventing the wheel unless we explore whether this argument by analogy works. My approach here is greatly influenced by Gabbrielle Johnson's demonstration that current debates about fairness in risk-assessment algorithms are iterations of familiar arguments in feminist philosophy of science about inductive risk and demarcation (Johnson Reference Johnsonforthcoming).

5 This point about the place of values in science has been taken up in more sophisticated and nuanced ways in Longino Reference Longino1987; Reference Longino1995; Reference Longino, Hankinson Nelson and Nelson1996; Douglas Reference Douglas2009; Reference Douglas2014; Reference Douglas, Cartwight and Montuschi2015; Reference Douglas and Humphreys2016; and Johnson Reference Johnsonforthcoming, among others. For a contrary view, see Bright Reference Bright2018.

6 See Bettcher Reference Bettcher2018 for more on this point.

7 See Berenstain Reference Berenstain2016 for more on the concept of epistemic exploitation.

8 Thanks to Nishi Shah for directing me to this passage in Mill. For a somewhat contrasting view, see Barnes Reference Barnes2018. For more on how the right to free speech intersects with academic freedom, see Emerick Reference Emerick2021.

9 Similarly, for pedagogical reasons we might pose a question in a way we wouldn't dream of posing the question were we in a different context. For example, Talia Mae Bettcher notes: “At a lower undergraduate level, I may very cautiously raise the question whether homosexuality is immoral in order to show that there is no good argument that it is. However, I wouldn't dream of raising such a question in an advanced course in LGBT philosophy—for one thing, the posing of the question is heterosexist. I make—and expressly problematize—my concession in the lower division course for pedagogical reasons” (Bettcher Reference Bettcher2019, 17).

10 For accounts of moral encroachment, see Pace Reference Pace2011; Fritz Reference Fritz2017; Moss Reference Moss2018; Basu Reference Basu2019; and Bolinger Reference Bolinger2020.

11 As Quill Kukla (writing as Rebecca Kukla), Jason Stanley, Rima Basu, and Gabbrielle Johnson have noted, the argument from inductive risk in philosophy of science has interesting parallels to the arguments for both pragmatic and moral encroachment (Kukla Reference Kukla2015; Stanley Reference Stanley2016; Basu Reference Basu and Lackey2021; Johnson Reference Johnsonforthcoming).

12 Thanks to Gabbrielle Johnson for not only raising this objection but also suggesting how it should be answered.

13 Another concern one might have is that philosophical research simply does not fall under the purview of IRB approval processes because the methods and knowledge produced by philosophical inquiry are simply not akin to the methods and knowledge produced by the sciences. I take up this worry in section IV.

14 For more on doxastic wronging, see Basu Reference Basu2019; Basu and Schroeder Reference Basu, Schroeder, Kim and McGrath2019; and Basu Reference Basu and Lackey2021. See also Enoch and Spectre Reference Enoch and Spectreforthcoming for some criticisms of the view.

15 This isn't necessarily a bad thing; for example, as I conduct this piece of philosophical inquiry I am taking the objective attitude toward philosophers, as philosophers are my object of study. It is, however, often a bad thing. There may be hard cases to categorize, and we do not wrong merely by taking the objective stance. However, what's important is acknowledging that occupying the objective stance comes with risk of wronging.

16 Notice that this idea can also capture the intuitions underpinning the slogan, “nothing about us without us.”

17 As Elizabeth Anderson and Richard Pildes note, standing is an important social good, part of the “basis for self-respect” that political philosophers take to be more fundamentally important than even distributive claims (Anderson and Pildes Reference Anderson and Pildes2000). You can have your standing eroded by repeated public questioning about whether you have it, and this erosion occurs more quickly when the standing was tenuous or already threatened. Thanks to Renée Jorgensen for helpful discussions of this point. Another aspect of this case worth considering is how the platform of a keynote gives higher-order evidence that the views being presented are the correct views that one ought to have. For more on platforms and how they provide higher-order evidence, see Levy Reference Levy2019.

18 Thanks to Gabbrielle Johnson for bringing this quote to my attention.

19 Although it's true that anything can be questioned, we often bracket certain questions when discussing others. After all, consider the student in your class who continues to bring up external-world skepticism as a challenge to every argument. The student seems to be doing philosophy, in some sense, wrong. Furthermore, even in the sciences we sometimes question the fundamentals, for example, in a Kuhnian crisis. Perhaps in philosophy we just more often call the fundamentals into question, in which case there is no in principle distinction between scientific inquiry and philosophical inquiry, just a difference in degree.

20 See, for example, Robin Dembroff's discussion of how when we ask the question “‘what is a woman?,’ philosophers must be aware that proposed answers bear real-world consequences for people—including persons with intersex variations, women of color, and trans and gender nonconforming persons” (Dembroff Reference Dembroff2021, 1000). Furthermore, as Dembroff further notes, echoing the observations about moral encroachment and the higher stakes involved in some debates, it does not follow from this that what this awareness, this shifting of limits, requires is that we “we should construct whatever definition would least offend, or would best cater to the wishes of these groups. Rather, we take this awareness to place a moral obligation on us to be particularly scrupulous, rigorous, and informed about our subject matter. Doing so requires demonstrating sensitivity to relevant existing literature, both inside and outside of analytic philosophy, as well as understanding this issue's stakes and complexity” (1001).

21 Thanks to Gabbrielle Johnson for many discussions on these topics and for helping me think through framing the issues in this way. See again Douglas Reference Douglas and Humphreys2016; Bright Reference Bright2018; and Johnson Reference Johnsonforthcoming) for more discussion of this debate within philosophy of science.

22 As Dotson argued, we also need to be better about the questions we give space to so that they can be taken up. And as the discussions of power have noted, we need to be better about whose voices should be uplifted given whose voices are already so prevalent in much of philosophical research.

23 Consider also G. E. M. Anscombe's argument that Oxford moral philosophy corrupts the youth by focusing “on examples which are either banal: you have promised to return a book, but . . . and so on; or fantastic: what you ought to do if you had to move forward, and stepping with your right foot meant killing twenty-five fine young men while stepping with your left foot would kill fifty drooling old ones” (Anscombe Reference Anscombe1957, 267).

25 Here we might also consider Douglas's discussion of the moral responsibility of scientists and the difference between role responsibilities and general responsibilities with regard to how much autonomy scientists ought to give up in subjecting their work to moral scrutiny (Douglas Reference Douglas2003).

References

Alcoff, Linda Martín. 1996. Real knowing: New versions of the coherence theory. Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Alcoff, Linda Martín, Ásta, Saray Ayala-Lopez, Bauer, Nancy, Bettcher, Talia Mae, et al. 2019. On philosophical scholarship of gender: A response to “12 leading scholars..” Blog of the APA, August 7. http://blog.apaonline.org/2019/08/07/on-philosophical-scholarship-of-gender-a-response-to-12-leading-scholars/.Google Scholar
Anderson, Elizabeth. 2004. Use of value judgments in science: A general argument, with lessons from a case study of feminist research on divorce. Hypatia 19 (1): 124.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Anderson, Elizabeth, and Pildes, Richard H.. 2000. Expressive theories of law: A general restatement. University of Pennsylvania Law Review 148 (5): 1503–75.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Anscombe, Gertrude Elizabeth Margaret. 1957. Does Oxford moral philosophy corrupt the youth? The Listener 57 (1455). https://projectintegrity.files.wordpress.com/2015/07/does_oxford_moral_philosophy_all.pdf.Google Scholar
Antony, Louise M. 2002. Quine as feminist: The radical import of naturalized epistemology. In A mind of ones own, ed. Antony, L. M. and Witt, C. E.. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Barnes, Elizabeth. 2018. Arguments that harm – and why we need them. The Chronicle of Higher Education, February 18. https://www.chronicle.com/article/arguments-that-harm-and-why-we-need-them/.Google Scholar
Basu, Rima. 2019. Radical moral encroachment: The moral stakes of racist beliefs. Philosophical Issues 29 (1): 923.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Basu, Rima. 2021. A tale of two doctrines: Moral encroachment and doxastic wronging. In Applied Epistemology, ed. Lackey, Jennifer. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Basu, Rima, and Schroeder, Mark. 2019. Doxastic wronging. In Pragmatic encroachment in epistemology, ed. Kim, Brian and McGrath, Matthew. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Berenstain, Nora. 2016. Epistemic exploitation. Ergo 3 (22): 569–90.Google Scholar
Bettcher, Talia Mae. 2018. “When tables speak”: On the existence of trans philosophy (guest post by Talia Mae Bettcher). Daily Nous, May 30. https://dailynous.com/2018/05/30/tables-speak-existence-trans-philosophy-guest-talia-mae-bettcher/.Google Scholar
Bettcher, Talia Mae. 2019. What is trans philosophy? Hypatia 34 (4): 644–67.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bolinger, Renée Jorgensen. 2020. Varieties of moral encroachment. Philosophical Perspectives 34 (1): 526.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bright, Liam Kofi. 2018. Du Bois’ democratic defence of the value free ideal. Synthese 195 (5): 2227–45.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Burns, Katelyn. 2019. The rise of anti-trans “radical” feminists, explained. Vox. September 5. https://www.vox.com/identities/2019/9/5/20840101/terfs-radical-feminists-gender-critical.Google Scholar
Davis, Emmalon. 2018. On epistemic appropriation. Ethics 128 (4): 702–27.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davis, Emmalon. 2021. A tale of two injustices: Epistemic injustice in philosophy. In Applied Epistemology, ed. Lackey, Jennifer. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Dembroff, Robin. 2021. Escaping the natural attitude about gender. Philosophical Studies 178 (3): 9831003.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dotson, Kristie. 2011. Concrete flowers: Contemplating the profession of philosophy. Hypatia 26 (2): 403–9.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dotson, Kristie. 2012. How is this paper philosophy? Comparative Philosophy 3 (1): 329.Google Scholar
Douglas, Heather. 2003. The moral responsibilities of scientists (tensions between autonomy and responsibility). American Philosophical Quarterly 40 (1): 5968.Google Scholar
Douglas, Heather. 2009. Science, policy, and the value-free ideal. Pittsburgh, Pa.: University of Pittsburgh Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Douglas, Heather. 2014. The moral terrain of science. Erkenntnis 79: 961–79.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Douglas, Heather. 2015. Values in social science. In Philosophy of social science: A new introduction, ed. Cartwight, N. and Montuschi, E.. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Douglas, Heather. 2016. Values in science. In The Oxford handbook of philosophy of science, ed. Humphreys, P.. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Dupré, John. 2012. Processes of life: Essays in the philosophy of biology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Emerick, Barrett. 2021. The limits of the rights to free thought and expression. Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 31 (2): 133–52.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Enoch, David. and Spectre, Levi. Forthcoming. There is no such thing as doxastic wrongdoing. Philosophical Perspectives. https://philpapers.org/archive/ENOTIN.pdf .Google Scholar
Fantl, Jeremy. 2018. The limitations of the open mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Freyd, Jennifer. 2008. Betrayal trauma. In Encyclopedia of psychological trauma, ed. Reyes, G., Elhai, J. D., and Ford, J. D.. New York: John Wiley & Sons.Google Scholar
Fritz, James. 2017. Pragmatic encroachment and moral encroachment. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 98 (S1): 643–61.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frye, Marilyn. 1983. The politics of reality. New York: Crossing Press.Google Scholar
Heesen, Remco, and Bright, Liam Kofi. Forthcoming. Is peer review a good idea? British Journal for the Philosophy of Science. https://www.liamkofibright.com/uploads/4/8/9/8/48985425/is_peer_review_a_good_idea_.pdf.Google Scholar
James, Robin. 2018. The other secret twist: On the political philosophy of The Good Place. Los Angeles Review of Books, October 11. https://www.lareviewofbooks.org/article/secret-twist-political-philosophy-good-place/.Google Scholar
Johnson, Gabbrielle M. Forthcoming. Are algorithms value-free? Feminist theoretical virtues in machine learning. Journal of Moral Philosophy. https://www.gmjohnson.com/uploads/5/2/5/1/52514005/are_algorithms_value_free.pdf .Google Scholar
Khelfaoui, Mahdi, Yves Gingras, Maël Lemoine, and Pradeu, Thomas. 2021. The visibility of philosophy of science in the sciences, 1980–2018. Synthese 199: 6219–49.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kukla, Rebecca. 2015. Delimiting the proper scope of epistemology. Philosophical Perspectives 29 (1): 202–16.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Levy, Neil. 2019. No-platforming and higher-order evidence, or anti-anti-no-platforming. Journal of the American Philosophical Association 5 (4): 487502.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Longino, Helen. 1987. Can there be a feminist science? Hypatia 2 (3): 5164.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Longino, Helen. 1995. Gender, politics, and the theoretical virtues. Synthese 104 (3): 383–97.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Longino, Helen. 1996. Cognitive and noncognitive values in science: Rethinking the dichotomy. In Feminism, science, and the philosophy of science, ed. Hankinson Nelson, L. and Nelson, J.. Dordrecht: Kluwer.Google Scholar
Lugones, María C. 1987. Playfulness, “world”-traveling, and loving perception. Hypatia 2 (2): 319.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lugones, María C. and Spelman, Elizabeth V.. 1983. Have we got a theory for you! Feminist theory, cultural imperalism and the demand for “the woman’s voice.” Womens Studies International Forum 6 (6): 573–81.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mill, John Stuart. 1998. On Liberty and Other Essays. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Mills, Charles. 2007. White ignorance. In Race and epistemologies of ignorance, ed. Sullivan, S. and Tuana, N.. Albany: SUNY Press.Google Scholar
Moss, Sarah. 2018. Moral encroachment. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 118 (2): 177205.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pace, Michael. 2011) The epistemic value of moral considerations: Justification, moral encroachment, and James’ “Will to believe.” Noûs 45 (2): 239–68.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pohlhaus, 2006. Knowing (with) Others. Social Philosophy Today 22: 187198.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Priest, Graham. 2006. What is philosophy? Philosophy 81 (2): 189207.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rudner, Richard. 1953. The scientist qua scientist makes value judgments. Philosophy of Science 20 (1): 16.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Simpson, Audra. 2007. On ethnographic refusal: Indigeneity, “voice,” and colonial citizenship. Junctures 9: 6780.Google Scholar
Stanley, Jason. 2016. Is epistemology tainted? Disputatio 8 (42): 135.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Strawson, Peter F. 1962/2008. Freedom and resentment. In Freedom and resentment and other essays. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
t philosopher. 2019. I am leaving academic philosophy because of its transphobia problem. Medium. https://medium.com/@transphilosopher33/i-am-leaving-academic-philosophy-because-of-its-transphobia-problem-bc618aa55712 .Google Scholar
Thiem, Yannik, Sealey, Kris F., Ferrer, Amy E., Trott, Adriel M., and Kennison, Rebecca. 2019. Just ideas? The status and future of publication ethics in philosophy. Publication Ethics. https://publication-ethics.org/white-paper/ .Google Scholar
Yap, Audrey. 2021. Hidden costs of inquiry: Exploitation, world-travelling and marginalized lives. Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 31 (2): 153–73.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed