1 Introduction
The intellectual movement of Third World Approaches to International Law (TWAIL) is now a well-established strand of critical thought within the international legal discourse. At its core, TWAIL unveils the hierarchical nature of the international legal system and undertakes critical investigations which unearth power relationships within the international community.Footnote 1 While nowadays some may argue that the term TWAIL or the reference to third world States is anachronistic, it is important to understand that TWAIL is not a reference to a particular geographical constellation in international law. This is all the more so if we consider that States traditionally grouped under the ‘third world’ heading have since changed the political, economic or social traits that originally earned them this categorisation.Footnote 2 Rather, TWAIL represents a perspective which is ‘critical of the universalizing mission and occidental authority of Eurocentric international legal scholarship and practice’,Footnote 3 and is not necessarily tied to a geographical Statist space. This reflects first the non-homogeneous ideological make-up of States traditionally considered as belonging to the third world, as well as the fact that nowadays one may often find the wretched and the dispossessed among societies traditionally considered to be part of the Global North. Thus, members of the TWAIL intellectual movement may not always share a geographical space and yet be united in ‘a sensibility and a political orientation’.Footnote 4
Historically, there have been different ways that TWAIL scholars have chosen to engage with international law, varying from complete denunciations of the system to more constructive attempts to deploy existing legal structures with a view to enacting change.Footnote 5 In this chapter, I will sketch out a discussion of customary international law (CIL) interpretation as an example of constructive engagement with international investment law (IIL) from a TWAIL perspective. I will build on the existing TWAIL scholarship, which has engaged in criticism of IIL as a regime and of the theory of CIL as a source of international law (Section 2). Having outlined the existing critique, I will turn to a discussion of CIL interpretation as a potential tool for reconciling some of the harsh, but merited, criticism coming from the TWAIL perspective with a continued engagement with and reliance on international (investment) law.
First, relying on the example of the minimum standard of treatment of aliens (MST) – one of the oldest customary rules of the international investment regime – I will argue that interpretation plays a crucial role in the construction of customary rules and is central to their evolution and continued existence (Section 3). Having established this, I will move to my final argument as to how this awareness of the function of interpretation in CIL can help us constructively engage with IIL from a TWAIL perspective (Section 4). Here, I will outline strategies for interpretation which may be deployed from the TWAIL perspective in order to address the perceived problems in the regime of IIL. Put differently, I will argue that the awareness of what interpretation is and how it functions in CIL opens up new avenues for addressing problems within both particular customary rules and, more generally, international (investment) law. It is at the stage of interpretation of customary rules that particular criticism can be raised and potentially resolved. In this sense, interpretation is a tool that may be utilised to address and potentially improve upon problematic rationales underlying the rule or the larger system in which it operates. While this presents great emancipatory potential with regard to argumentative strategies that may be developed, it also has its limitations. An evaluation of the limitations of the argument as well as some summary observations are thus addressed in the conclusion (Section 5).
2 The Criticism of Customary International Investment Law from the TWAIL Perspective
It is not surprising to observe that TWAIL scholarship is very critical of the regime of IIL. The TWAIL intellectual tradition in international law originates from decolonisation. It is a school of thought which perceives the international legal system as one built on power disparity, exploitation, and unequal relations. On this understanding, international law as a system reflects the interests of powerful States, and these interests are deployed through various legal doctrines including the doctrine of CIL. Here CIL is considered problematic both generally as a category in the sources doctrine,Footnote 6 and more specifically on the level of individual customary rules.Footnote 7 These problems of CIL are set in the wider historical context which links the development of international law to the colonial encounter between European States and the violently colonised non-European world.Footnote 8 It is thus not surprising to find particularly strong criticism among TWAIL scholars aimed at the system of IIL, and the (customary) rules contained therein.Footnote 9
Historically, one of the strongest concerted TWAIL efforts at both criticising and reforming the international economic legal order was the New International Economic Order (NIEO).Footnote 10 This was an initiative of Third World States aided by TWAIL scholars aimed at reforming regimes such as the IIL via a concentrated legislative effort at the United Nations General Assembly. The initiative concerned a reformation of key areas such as foreign direct investment, the rules of nationalisation and expropriation, the criteria applied to compensation, and the fora for dispute settlement in this area.Footnote 11 While highly ambitious, this initiative was met with little success. Pushback from Western States as well as various complex forms of financial domination deployed in the international system undermined the reformative effort, and the battle for a NIEO was largely lost.Footnote 12 The limited success of the NIEO has spurred what some have called a second generationFootnote 13 of TWAIL scholars, more disenchanted with international law, and focused on uncovering its continuously hegemonic traits. It is among this scholarship that much of the criticism of the contemporary IIL system can be found.
A central trait of this criticism revolves around the underlying rationale of IIL. The assumption upon which IIL is constructed is that foreign investment is so essential to economic development that its operation must be facilitated by near absolute protection of the foreign investment/investor.Footnote 14 This assumption, however, remains contested among critical scholars, as case studies demonstrate that foreign investment can be hugely exploitative and damaging to host economies.Footnote 15 This has led Sornarajah to observe that while the potential of foreign investment to aid development must be recognised, the absolute protection of investment in international law enables ‘the instrumentalism of free market fundamentalism’ to fragment international law ‘without paying heed to prescriptions of law relating to the environment, human rights or labour standards’.Footnote 16 Similarly, Odumosu has demonstrated that in the context of investment dispute settlement, this overwhelming focus on investment protection has all but erased legitimate grievances of local populations affected by investments, and also significantly restricted the extent to which host States might balance the protection of foreign investment with the protection of other local interests.Footnote 17
The criticism of the underlying rationale of IIL often goes hand in hand with a critique of its historical origin, as well that of specific customary rules operating in the system. For instance, Kelly traces the customary MST to early natural law doctrines on the freedom of commerce and the rights to hospitality and sociability of Vittoria and Grotius, developed to legitimise the extension of the European colonial empires and the exploitation of peoples and resources encountered in the process.Footnote 18 Similarly, Anghie unpacks the relationship between State responsibility and the customary MST to demonstrate that Western States re-established colonial relationships of power with former colonies through what was ostensibly neutral international law.Footnote 19 Thus, while the formal process of decolonisation got rid of colonial empires, legal doctrines formed in the colonial period survive today and perpetuate problematic logics in the contemporary context of international law. On this point, Pahuja persuasively demonstrates that in moments when the Third World attempted to dispute existing structures in international law (such as with the NIEO), this was met with a response by the First World, which claimed the universality of values so as to discredit attempted alternatives.Footnote 20
A related criticism here is the structure of dispute settlement inIIL. Scholars have pointed out the asymmetry inherent in the fact that while foreign investors may bring suit against host States, the opposite is not true.Footnote 21 Moreover, the rationale inherent in many BITs, trade agreements, and customary rules automatically puts host States on the defensive should there be an attempt to limit foreign investment in favour of the protection of local environment or peoples.Footnote 22 The obvious counter-argument here is that States willingly admit foreign investment by signing BITs or trade agreements, thereby subjecting themselves also to potential dispute settlement and the application of (customary) investment law. However, this argument potentially neglects the larger socio-economic context in which this ‘willingness’ takes place. Moreover, often political elites in States which conclude foreign investment agreements do not, in fact, represent or purport to protect the rights of some local populations, and thus, the asymmetry grows. Investment dispute settlement treats the State as a unitary entity, and as such, the interests of different local communities which might be differently affected by a particular foreign investment project are all subsumed under it.Footnote 23
Having briefly outlined the lines of criticism levelled at customary IIL from the TWAIL perspective, I now turn to a discussion of CIL interpretation as the next step in the argument.
3 The Interpretation of Customary International Investment Law
This section first outlines more generally the nature and role of interpretation in the context of customary international law, before turning to the more concrete example of the customary MST as an illustration of these more general observations.
3.1 What Constitutes Interpretation of Customary International Law
Legal interpretation is the process of determining the scope and content of legal rules. It can be distinguished from rule-identification, which is the act of establishing whether a legal rule exists. Thus, interpretation is the process of discerning or clarifying the meaning of an existing legal rule, and takes place when a general rule is applied to particular facts.
CIL interpretation is the process that takes place after a customary rule has been identified. Once a rule of CIL is identified for the first time through an assessment of State practice and opinio juris, its existence is not restricted to the moment where it was identified for the first time; rather it is a continuous one. When the same rule is invoked in subsequent cases before the same or a different judicial body, the judicial body does not usually go into the exercise of re-establishing that the rule in question is a customary one by reassessing State practice and opinio juris.Footnote 24 Instead, the rule is interpreted within the given legal and factual context of the new case at hand. Moreover, outside of the dispute-settlement context, a customary rule does not only exist in the isolated moments when it is identified for the purposes of a particular case. Rather, its existence in the complex of international legal relations is also a continuous one. In this sense, interpretation allows us to account for the continued existence and operation of a customary rule. Within the timeline of existence of a CIL rule, interpretation takes place after the periods of formation and identification of the rule.Footnote 25 Identification yields a general rule of CIL, based on an inductive analysis of State practice and opinio juris.Footnote 26 It is important to note that a form of interpretive reasoning may also take place at this stage, in the sense of assessment of the relevant practice and opinio juris. The identification exercise includes choices in the selection of certain custom-formative practices over others in order to infer the general rule, as well as the choices in how we describe these practices which lead to the identification of the rule.Footnote 27 The reasoning employed in these choices and descriptions is by necessity interpretative. However, this is not an interpretation of a customary rule because this rule has not been confirmed to exist yet. Rather, what happens at the stage of identification is an evaluation of the evidence of State practice and opinio juris in order to assess whether they qualify for the purposes of establishing a customary rule and whether they in fact point to the existence of a customary rule.Footnote 28 Some scholars do employ the term ‘interpretation’ to also refer to the reasoning that takes place at the stage of identification.Footnote 29 However, a distinction must be maintained between what might be labeled as interpretation at the stage of identification and what is interpretation in the strict sense of an existing CIL rule. This is because these two operations are substantively different with respect to both their content and their outcome. The reasoning employed at identification is concerned with questions about the relevance and weight to be given to evidence of State practice and opinio juris, and the outcome of this reasoning is a binary one – a CIL rule is either determined to exist or it is not. The reasoning employed in interpretation is concerned with the determination of the content of the CIL rule and how this rule applies to the case at hand, and this reasoning may have a variety of outcomes depending on the rule being interpreted and the legal and factual circumstances it is being interpreted in. It is only by distinguishing these two operations that we may adequately capture the fact that the interpretation manifests differently in the context of CIL, that it is subject to a different methodology than that of identification, and it performs specific functions.
A related consideration in this context is who interprets. Formally, international law does not allocate interpretive authority with a single entity. Depending on the circumstances, interpretive authority may lie with a court, a State, or even a non-governmental entity.Footnote 30 All these actors together form the epistemic community of international law, and as such contribute broadly to the way legal rules are interpreted.Footnote 31 Nevertheless, judicial interpretation holds a prominent role in international law.Footnote 32 In the subsequent discussion I focus on judicial interpretation for two reasons. First, because in the practice of international law, questions of interpretation tend to arise in the context of disputes and be formulated with a judge or arbitrator in mind.Footnote 33 Put differently, the bulk of the judicial role in international law consists of interpretation.Footnote 34 In this regard, and without prejudice to the interpretation of CIL by other actors, examples of CIL interpretation are most likely to be found in the jurisprudence of courts and tribunals. Second, because in international law judicial decisions possess what has aptly been described as a ‘centrifugal normative force’ – other international legal actors tend to follow judicial reasoning, and judicial decisions can be ‘substantively constitutive’ of international law.Footnote 35 ‘That normative effect is exacerbated when dealing with unwritten sources of law, in particular customary international law […]: there is no balancing between the text, its authors, and the interpreter in such situations, and the certainty of judicial reasoning holds and intrinsic appeal’.Footnote 36
An examination of jurisprudence dealing with the interpretation of CIL indicates that interpretation performs two important functions in the continued existence of customary rules – a constructive/concretising function and an evolutive function.Footnote 37 The constructive/concretising function refers to the fact that interpretation is the process through which the content of general customary rules is fleshed out and specified. Customary rules are often formulated in broad terms, and require precisely the act of interpretation to arrive at more concrete findings of their content.Footnote 38 In this sense, it is through interpretation that we arrive at more specific sub-elements of a general customary rule, or more specific sub-obligations that flow from it. Merkouris also refers to this as the collapsing function of interpretation.Footnote 39 The evolutive function of interpretation refers to the fact that interpretation is crucial in the continued existence of CIL rules, and their adaptation to new developments of fact or law. Contrary to some views, customary rules are not static legal rules which have no place in modern legal systems.Footnote 40 Rather, customary rules are by their nature dynamic because they move together with the community from whose conduct they emerge. As such, they require interpretation in order to be able to respond to emerging new circumstances.Footnote 41 For an illustration of these two functions relevant to our present discussion, let us briefly consider the example of the customary MST.
3.2 The Interpretation of the Customary MST and the Functions of CIL Interpretation
The customary status of MST is uncontested, and support for this may be found widely among States, tribunals, and scholarly writings. What is, however, in question is its precise content.Footnote 42 As argued above, customary rules necessarily come in a general format, and the MST is one among many examples which confirms this. This is certainly both a virtue and a vice of custom. The generality of customary rules makes them particularly fit to answer to a variety of circumstances, and thus regulate a variety of situations that may arise in international law. In a scenario where multiple legal regimes might interact or bind different actors differently, general customary rules present a least common denominator of legal obligation. In the context of the MST, its customary status means that obligations flowing from it apply to all States, including those that may not have entered into any bilateral investment treaties (BITs), and may also be invoked by any foreign investor irrespective of whether or not their State of origin has entered into a BIT with the State where they’ve made an investment.Footnote 43 Moreover, in new legal situations not covered by conventional rules, customary law may prove a source of regulation that can be extended by analogy.Footnote 44 This is arguably what indeed happened with the customary MST, which had originally broadly applied to the treatment of aliens and was later also extended to the property of aliens as well as their investments. At the same time, the generality of customary rules also leads to vagueness, and this is a challenge to the legal certainty and predictability that actors might desire in particular legal scenarios or in international law more generally. The customary MST has indeed been criticised for its vagueness, its inability to provide clear standards for behaviour, and even its ‘normative weakness’.Footnote 45
Historically, the formulation of the MST is traced back to a 1910 address by the American Secretary of State, Elihu Root, who expressed the view that an international standard is necessary in order to guarantee appropriate treatment by host countries to the nationals of another country.Footnote 46 Root’s formulation, however, was quite vague, and did not in fact provide for a more concrete content of the standard beyond a claim that such a standard existed and was recognised by civilised countries.Footnote 47 A more concrete expression of the content of the MST is ascribed to the US–Mexico Claims Commission in its Neer award.Footnote 48 Much like the formulation expressed by Secretary Root, however, the Neer award did not express the MST with the protection of foreign investments or property in view. Rather, it was concerned with the more specific scenario of alleged failure to investigate the murder of an alien, and the more general standard of denial of justice in the context of treatment of aliens.Footnote 49 Thus, while Neer is considered the classical starting point of MST, both States and tribunals have recognised that MST is not frozen in time to this formulation.Footnote 50 The shift from a more general standard of denial of justice to the more specific rationale of protection of foreign investment and property is not insignificant. As Paparinskis aptly demonstrates in his genealogy of the standard, in post-World War 2 discussions of the MST there is a marked ‘shift of the paradigm that the standard was meant to regulate’, including now a focus on property and the personality of the foreign investor.Footnote 51 This focus on the protection of property rights and protection of foreign investment is the primary area of application of the MST today.Footnote 52
TWAIL scholarship has offered its own take on why this shift occurred.Footnote 53 What we are more concerned with for the purposes of this section is how these changes in perspective were operationalised in the standard by means of interpretation. As the upcoming discussion will demonstrate, while the customary MST was initially expressed in general terms, its content in the context of investment law has been made more concrete and specific through interpretation by various investment tribunals. Moreover, it is also through interpretation that the MST has evolved over time.
Early mentions of the MST as a customary rule relevant in the context of investment protection can be found in the reasoning of the ICJ in the ELSI case. Here, the court acknowledged that the relevant treaty standard of treatment ‘must conform to the minimum international standard’,Footnote 54 and found that this minimum standard includes the element of ‘denial of procedural justice’.Footnote 55 The reasoning of the ICJ with regard to the denial of procedural justice as an element of the customary MST has been referenced by various investment tribunals similarly faced with the need to specify the content of the general customary standard. For instance, in its award in respect of damages, the Pope and Talbot Tribunal relied on the reasoning in ELSI when seeking to define the arbitrariness requisite for a finding of denial of justice as part of the MST.Footnote 56 In Mondev International Ltd, this reference was part of a broader interpretation of the customary MST. Here, the Tribunal began by decoupling the customary MST in the context of investment protection from the minimum standard broadly outlined in Neer.Footnote 57 It then proceeded to interpret the customary MST evolutively so as to account for changes of law that have taken place in the broader legal environment in which the rule operates.Footnote 58 While this may, at first glance, seem expansive, it is interesting to note that the Tribunal also acknowledged the limitations of its interpretive power, and professed to remain within the limits posed by the customary MST.Footnote 59 After examining the relevant legal developments in the period since Neer, the Mondev Tribunal came to the conclusion that under the customary MST investments are entitled to fair and equitable treatment and full protection and security.Footnote 60 Having outlined the content of the customary MST in this way, the Tribunal went on to examine the applicable standard of denial of justice which would render treatment unfair or inequitable. Here it relied, among other, on the reasoning of the ICJ with respect to the nature of arbitrariness as a denial of justice, and accepted the ICJ definition of arbitrary conduct ‘as that which displays a willful disregard of due process of law, … which shocks, or at least surprises, a sense of judicial propriety’.Footnote 61 In addition to the ICJ’s reasoning in ELSI, the Mondev Tribunal also relied on the Azinian Tribunal for an even more detailed interpretation of denial of justice, thus also accepting into its definition elements such as refusal to entertain a suit, undue delay, inadequate administration of justice and malicious misapplication of the law.Footnote 62
I flag this cross-reference to the reasoning of other tribunals because it is illustrative of the role of judicial interpretation in the construction of both customary rules more generally and the customary MST more specifically. In light of the general nature of CIL, it is not at all surprising that courts will borrow from each other when interpreting rules in pari materia. What is noteworthy in this cross-referencing is that the interpretive reasoning does not remain limited to the particular case, but carries over to subsequent cases as well. It is attached to the rule beyond the context of the specific case in that it has specified the content which is now considered to be an expression of the rule. In this sense, interpretation affects the content of the customary rule more generally as it exists continuously in international law. We may similarly observe this in the reasoning of the Loewen Group Inc Tribunal, which relied on the reasoning in Pope & Talbot, ELSI and Mondev to elucidate what would constitute arbitrariness amounting to a denial of justice in breach of the customary MST.Footnote 63 The constructive role of interpretation is illustrated perhaps most strongly by the reasoning of the Tribunal in Waste Management. Here, having surveyed the previous jurisprudence of a number of investment tribunals, the Waste Management Tribunal arrived at the following finding:
Taken together, the S.D. Myers, Mondev, ADF and Loewen cases suggest that the minimum standard of treatment of fair and equitable treatment is infringed by conduct attributable to the State and harmful to the claimant if the conduct is arbitrary, grossly unfair, unjust or idiosyncratic, is discriminatory and exposes the claimant to sectional or racial prejudice, or involves a lack of due process leading to an outcome which offends judicial propriety—as might be the case with a manifest failure of natural justice in judicial proceedings or a complete lack of transparency and candour in an administrative process. In applying this standard it is relevant that the treatment is in breach of representations made by the host State which were reasonably relied on by the claimant.Footnote 64
The Tribunal here comes up with a very specific definition of the customary MST as a set of concrete elements and obligations. I would argue that this kind of construction of the customary MST, as a general rule made up of various specific legal sub-obligations, is a product of interpretation. This is certainly not an entirely novel observation, as several authors have made similar claims as to the ‘umbrella-like’ character of MST.Footnote 65 Building on their observations, I would merely argue more specifically that it is through interpretation particularly that the content of the general customary MST was developed and concretised. Why this is important is because this act of concretisation through interpretation does not remain restricted to the case at hand, but carries over to reasoning in subsequent cases both before the same tribunal and others that might follow it. Thus, we may envisage a general customary rule in case A whose content gets concretised through interpretation to contain element A1, where that element is carried over to the subsequent case B. Should further concretisation through interpretation take place in case B, whereby the customary rule is found to also contain element B1, elements A1 and B1 would now carry over to subsequent case C, and so on. In this way, interpretation affects the content of general customary rules not only for purposes of one specific case but also throughout the continuous existence of that customary rule overall and generally in international law. That this transcends adjudication becomes evident when we consider that often States rely on earlier judicial reasoning to argue the content of customary rules in subsequent cases. Thus, this constructive function of interpretation finds its way into State practice as well, thereby penetrating the very process of custom-creation by States.Footnote 66
While this brief analysis of case law demonstrates how the customary MST has evolved and been constructed through judicial interpretation, this trend has not gone without criticism. For one, scholars have noted that this form of development of the standard through a case-by-case application is not coherent and may lead to discrepancies in the way the standard is applied and enforced.Footnote 67 Furthermore, scholars have criticised this expansion through interpretation for developing investment protection obligations which arguably do not flow from the customary standard or the conduct of States.Footnote 68 For instance, several awards have read into the standard a requirement for a stable and predictable regulatory environment owed to investors,Footnote 69 which does not necessarily flow from the customary MST.Footnote 70 Similarly, and relying on the conviction that the customary MST should be interpreted evolutively,Footnote 71 the Bilcon Tribunal also found that the standard requires a ‘fair opportunity for review’ to be extended to the investor,Footnote 72 which once again is not obvious from the customary MST. On this critical note, it has also been observed that in the context of NAFTA proceedings there is a conflation of the customary MST with the treaty standard enshrined in Article 1105 NAFTA.Footnote 73 Thus, tribunals often make interpretive findings concerning the customary MST by relying on the treaty standard and relevant rules for treaty interpretation, which is problematic.Footnote 74 Nevertheless, it has been observed that the content of the standard is likely to continue being ‘created through the dispute-settlement process’,Footnote 75 and no universal international codification or clarification effort seems imminent.Footnote 76 Bearing these observations in mind, let us now turn to a discussion of how these traits of interpretation in the context of CIL rules may be conducive to a TWAIL engagement with customary IIL.
4 A TWAIL Approach to the Interpretation of Customary International Investment Law
In outlining a potential TWAIL approach to the interpretation of customary international investment law, I join the chorus of critical scholars who have taken the proverbial good with the bad in attempting to devise critique without dismissing international law as a whole. This, I believe, reflects what Sundhya Pahuja has aptly named a ‘critical faith’ – maintaining faith in international law despite firmly comprehending its problematic complicity with power.Footnote 77 At the centre of such an engagement with international law lies the need to deconstruct international law’s claim to universality in order to trace problematic elements and potentially resolve them. This entails recognising ‘both the contingency of any value put forth as universal and the frame of reference supporting the universal claim’.Footnote 78 This I would argue is a task that can be achieved at the stage of interpretation. With this in mind, this section outlines three potential strategies which rely on the constructive and evolutive functions of interpretation in the context of CIL. These strategies represent modes of engagement with customary international investment law from the TWAIL perspective which rely on interpretation in order to draw out and address the problems inherent in the law, without dismissing the system as a whole. They represent what Georges Abi Saab has humorously dubbed ‘operating behind enemy lines’ – a mode of engagement with problematic aspects of international law premised on the understanding that it is better to attempt change from within than from outside.Footnote 79
One might question the value of engaging with international investment law from a TWAIL perspective in this ‘internal’ way. The benefit of this kind of engagement lies in the opportunity to engage familiar professional language that is intelligible to the broader ‘target audience’ (courts, lawyers, States, scholars). Moreover, it also lies in the power to speak and be heard that comes from remaining within an arena of discussion rather than abandoning it.Footnote 80 This type of TWAIL engagement with international law capitalises on the existing structures in order to deploy what might be considered a subversive argument aimed at the amelioration of perceived biases. At the same time, it is important to acknowledge that professionals participating in international legal argumentation have a responsibility of maintaining what has been dubbed a ‘methodological honesty’ in their development of arguments concerning the content and purpose of international legal rules. The persuasiveness of any legal argument depends upon maintaining the idea of international law as a formal system according to which answers to legal questions can be derived from sources and principles whose validity depends on the internal logic of the system.Footnote 81 In this sense, the interpretive strategies suggested below are not attempts to argue in bad faith or misrepresent existing legal rules. Rather, the objective is to explore avenues of argumentation that promote the interpretation of customary rules in a way that accounts for their historically problematic origin and promotes their re-construction in a manner consistent with contemporary developments and values in the broader system.
The interpretive strategies suggested below are informed, amongst others, by the regime bias approach (alternatively also called the regime bias critique) developed by TWAIL scholars engaged with the various legal regimes of international economic governance.Footnote 82 The regime bias approach is aimed at uncovering how rules of the legal regimes making up the international economic order are constructed in a way that disempowers particular members of the system, inconsistently with the ‘liberal promise of even-handedness’.Footnote 83 This approach looks particularly at the way rules of international trade, commerce, and investment are construed, and identifies a differential manner in which the rules are interpreted and applied when the interests of the Third World are at stake.Footnote 84 Some of the main insights of the regime bias approach include the observation that international law is not a neutral and objective set of rules but rather an instrument employed in the context of power relations, and the finding that international institutions may interpret and apply international law in ways that are systemically biased against Third World interests.Footnote 85 For instance, using the example of the Dabhol investment arbitration before the International Chamber of Commerce (ICC), Van Harten argues that the ICC construed its role broadly to include not only arbitration on the basis of the pertinent investment contract but also what was in effect a review of domestic regulatory choices and a disciplining of constituencies in the Third World.Footnote 86 While the main contribution of the regime bias approach is critical, scholars have also used its rationale to propose reform within the international investment regime. For example, Hippolyte advocates for Third World countries to develop their own BIT models, which would focus on modes of investment attuned to their particular concerns, or to establish alternative regional investment arbitration centres.Footnote 87 Similarly, Odumosu flags mechanisms within investment arbitration proceedings such as the amicus curiae brief or public interest arguments, which may be a way for subaltern voices to be heard and considered in the otherwise insular investment proceedings.Footnote 88
The regime bias approach is instructive because it demonstrates the inherent plasticity of legal rules, which becomes apparent at the stage of interpretation. It counters the image of a stable and neutral international investment law regime and reveals some of the biases which are woven into rules during the act of interpretation. Thus, the regime bias approach does not only shed light on certain problematic rationales operating in the investment law regime but also flags interpretation as a viable ‘entry point’ for TWAIL counter-arguments and resistance. Bearing in mind that throughout the analysis in this chapter I have focused on judicial interpretation and the function of interpretation in the dispute settlement context, the strategies sketched below are focused primarily on interpretation in dispute settlement and operate differently depending on one’s positionality in the process.Footnote 89 In this sense, they are also differentially suitable for different actors who might want to engage with international law from the TWAIL perspective.
The first possible strategy in the context of CIL interpretation is advancing evolutive interpretative claims which push for a reconsideration of the rule’s content in light of factual or legal changes in the broader normative environment in which the rule operates. Depending on the rule in question, this would entail different argumentative strategies. For instance, when advancing an evolutive interpretative claim for the customary MST, this type of engagement consists of answering two connected questions: (i) can an argument be made that there is a need to interpret the rule dynamically in order to capture a change in the legal environment in which the rule operates? and (ii) are there competing rationales that may be taken in consideration and affect the interpretation of the rule accordingly? In relation to the first question, in the context of the customary MST, it has been argued persuasively that given the generality of the rule the elements which form part of its content are inherently dynamic and as such require evolutive interpretation.Footnote 90 Claims for evolutive interpretation may thus persuasively be made any time it can be shown that there is a need to interpret the rule dynamically in order to capture a change in the relevant standards or normative environment in which the rule operates. Answering question two entails, as a first step, recognising and stating plainly the rationale that the customary MST is driven by. This rule is largely focused on the protection of foreign investment, premised in turn on the ideology of economic development. Recognising this enables us to situate the historical development of the rule and understand how it has come to be what it is today. Having done that, we are able to evaluate how the rule plays out in the modern context, and which claims regarding its evolution are likely to work. Are there competing rationales – such as, for instance, the protection of the environment or human rights – that may be taken into consideration and that affect the interpretation of the rule accordingly? These may be found in other regimes as relevant treaty rules applicable between the parties, or in competing customary rules which have developed later than the customary MST and afford protection to, for instance, the environment or indigenous peoples. Interpretation entails, amongst other things, a balancing exercise,Footnote 91 and as such, it is capable of striking a balance between the rationale of economic development and these competing interests and competing rationales.
In the context of this strategy of engagement, interpretation functions as a sort of controlled ‘arguing space’ wherein competing argumentative strategies are deployed. This strategy is suited to TWAIL advocates and practitioners participating in relevant litigation. The limits here are of course the forum in which one attempts to advance evolutive interpretative claims, as well as the instructions of the party one is representing. For example, with respect to the limitation posed by the forum, it has been observed that certain formats of investment arbitration, such as ICSID arbitration, are inherently tilted in favour of the protection of foreign investors.Footnote 92 Thus, attempting to argue for evolutive interpretation, which balances the protection of investors with the protection of say the environment or indigenous groups, may not always be successful. With respect to the limitation posed by the party one is representing, it has been observed that the arguments deployed by, for instance, counsel representing States are limited in scope and content by the previous consultations and instructions of their client.Footnote 93 In this regard, any TWAIL arguments advanced by counsel on behalf of a State would be limited accordingly. Another relevant consideration here is that sometimes strategic engagement with litigation in this way may lead to adverse effects if the proposed interpretation is not accepted by courts.Footnote 94 Thus, for instance, an unsuccessful argument for evolutive interpretation may lead to a consolidation of the undesirable content of the rule.
An alternative to this strategy would be the strategy of arguing for a restrictive interpretation of a CIL rule. In the context of the customary MST, this would entail arguing for a stringent customary standard of treatment which has a high threshold of breach. This may involve similar argumentative strategies to the ones described above, only deployed in the ‘opposite direction’. More specifically, it may involve argumentative strategies which hark back to the older Neer standard and early investment arbitration which maintained it, arguing for a limitation of the customary standard to the high threshold described therein. These argumentative strategies may rely on exo-legal findings which show that expanding investment protection in the past has been to the detriment of local communities, and has potentially violated standards of environmental protection, or human and labour rights.Footnote 95 In this context, they may argue that a stringent customary standard, coupled with a balancing exercise, which considers rationales such as public policy or the protection of the local environment or communities, yields a narrow interpretation of the customary MST and the rights and protections extended to the investor. Alternatively, they may rely on a doctrinal positivist argument arguing that the expansion of the customary MST through interpretation is illegitimate and inconsistent with State practice. In this regard, it has been argued, for instance, that arguments which attempt to draw a uniform standard from widespread investment treaties as a form of State practice are unsubstantiated because while these treaties are many in number, their content as to the treatment of investors is varied and fails the uniformity requirement for CIL.Footnote 96 This strategy may be particularly fit for TWAIL advocates or governmental advisors who are representing or advising States.
A final strategy in the context of CIL interpretation is what I would call ‘interpreting against the grain’. This strategy consists of devising innovative arguments as to the (re)interpretation of general customary rules, with a view to forwarding a new rationality previously unexplored in the rule.Footnote 97 In this context, one can rely on existing CIL doctrine more generally and the customary MST more specifically and utilise some of its inherent plasticityFootnote 98 to argue for a possible remoulding of the content. Interpretation here opens a sort of ‘reasoning space’ in which the problematic origin of a rule can be scrutinised and interpretive arguments deployed to resolve it. Can certain past practices and rationalities withstand modern scrutiny when placed against contemporary values espoused in the system? This is one of the central questions that may be asked when an older general customary rule such as the MST is being interpreted in the modern context. The resulting answer is a normative argument which might claim that the protection of investment to the detriment of the environment or human wellbeing is incompatible with contemporary values. A similarly plausible argument in this vein would be that the unitary notion of Statehood inherent in the construction of the investor-State relationship is incompatible with the heterogeneous make-up of States, which often comprise of different communities with varying interests.Footnote 99 This strategy would best fit a TWAIL scholar who develops their argument from the position of scholarship.Footnote 100 On this point, an important caveat is that ‘the authority of scholars is not an institutional, procedural, or social one, but purely an epistemic one’.Footnote 101 The authority of interpretative arguments developed by scholars is limited accordingly.
This strategy may also be suited to an NGO or grassroot movement which has been granted the right to appear as amicus curiae in the context of an investment arbitration. For instance, in the context of ICSID proceedings, pursuant to Rule 37(2) of the Rules of Procedure for Arbitration Proceedings, a non-disputing party may be granted a right to intervene in the proceedings. This kind of intervention is meant to ‘assist the Tribunal in the determination of factual or legal issue related to the proceeding by bringing a perspective, particular knowledge or insight that is different from that of the disputing parties’.Footnote 102 Similar provision for non-disputing party intervention is made in the context of NAFTA proceedings.Footnote 103 This represents the opportunity to inject subaltern voices into the proceedings when their interests are otherwise not represented by the State. Using the tool of a non-disputing party intervention, actors may put forward interpretive arguments which highlight the asymmetry inherent in the investor-State relationship, and the adverse effects this has to the rights and interests of local communities. This strategy is of course limited by the tribunal’s willingness to grant standing to non-disputing parties, as well as the scope of such participation.Footnote 104 For instance, the Glamis Gold Tribunal allowed the Quechan Indian Nation to submit their views as a non-disputing party because it felt that the submission would not cause an undue burden or delay.Footnote 105 On the other hand, the Pezold Tribunal rejected indigenous participation on the reasoning that the rights of indigenous communities fell outside of the scope of the dispute and that allowing for such participation may unfairly prejudice the claimant (investor).Footnote 106 Moreover, it has been argued that even if such participation is granted, the extent to which an investment tribunal would seriously consider the interests of subaltern communities is limited.Footnote 107
A tangential opportunity to the one described here is in the training and education activities undertaken by a TWAIL scholar. For instance, in response to TWAIL scholarship, which has called for a conceptual change in the CIL doctrine, d’Aspremont has argued that a more fruitful avenue to pursue this change would be in the early stages of legal education, by targeting the production of ideas and beliefs about customary international law. The objective here would be to use the malleability of the CIL doctrine to empower scholars and practitioners of the periphery to develop persuasive subversive arguments.Footnote 108
5 Concluding Observations
This chapter has presented an idea for a constructive TWAIL approach to the interpretation of customary international investment law. This idea reflects the view that while there is a lot of relevant and legitimate criticism against the existing system of international investment law, desired change cannot be achieved if one completely dismisses the existing system. Thus, I have sketched out the so-called interpretative strategies which rely on existing structures in international law in order to affect systemic change. The argument developed here is an attempt to reconcile some of the harsh but merited TWAIL criticism with a continued engagement with the existing system of international law.
This argument also has its limitations. First, the conclusions reached in Section 3 with respect to the constructive function of interpretation in the context of the customary MST are preliminary, insofar as they were reached on the basis of a small exploratory sample of investment arbitration cases. In this sense, the conclusions can and should be tested on a broader sample of cases, as well as through examples of other customary rules.Footnote 109 Second, as the discussion in Section 4 illustrates, the strategies for interpretation as potentially deployed from the TWAIL perspective are limited by the role and position of the actor who is trying to deploy them. Finally, the strategies proposed here cannot address all the criticism levelled from the TWAIL perspective. The proposals made in Section 4 are limited to issues which arise, may be argued, and potentially resolved at the stage of interpretation.