Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-m6dg7 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-20T00:36:47.752Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

ITERATING THE COFINALITY-$\omega $ CONSTRUCTIBLE MODEL

Part of: Set theory

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 January 2023

UR YA’AR*
Affiliation:
EINSTEIN INSTITUTE OF MATHEMATICS HEBREW UNIVERSITY OF JERUSALEM EDMOND J. SAFRA CAMPUS GIVAT RAM JERUSALEM 91904, ISRAEL
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

We investigate iterating the construction of $C^{*}$, the L-like inner model constructed using first order logic augmented with the “cofinality $\omega $” quantifier. We first show that $\left (C^{*}\right )^{C^{*}}=C^{*}\ne L$ is equiconsistent with $\mathrm {ZFC}$, as well as having finite strictly decreasing sequences of iterated $C^{*}$s. We then show that in models of the form $L[U]$ we get infinite decreasing sequences of length $\omega $, and that an inner model with a measurable cardinal is required for that.

Type
Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of The Association for Symbolic Logic

1 Introduction

The model $C^{*}$ , introduced by Kennedy, Magidor, and Väänänen in [Reference Kennedy, Magidor and Väänänen5], is the model of sets constructible using the logic $\mathcal {L}(Q_{\omega }^{\mathrm {cf}})$ —first order logic augmented with the “cofinality $\omega $ ” quantifier. To be precise, for a regular cardinal $\kappa $ we define a logic $\mathcal {L}(Q_{\kappa }^{\mathrm {cf}})$ where we add to the syntax of first order logic a quantifier $Q_{\kappa }^{\mathrm {cf}}$ whose semantics are given by

$$\begin{align*}\mathcal{M}\vDash Q_{\kappa}^{\mathrm{cf}}xy\varphi\left(x,y,\bar{b}\right)\iff\underset{{\textstyle \text{is a linear order of cofinality } \kappa}.}{\left\{ \left(c,d\right)\in M^{2}\mid\mathcal{M}\vDash\varphi\left(c,d,\bar{b}\right)\right\} } \end{align*}$$

This logic, first introduced by Shelah [Reference Shelah10], is a proper extension of first order logic, which is fully compact. Using this logic we construct inner models of set theory, akin to Gödel’s constructible universe L:

Definition 1.1. $C_{\kappa }^{*}$ , the class of $\mathcal {L}(Q_{\kappa }^{\mathrm {cf}})$ -constructible sets, is defined by induction:

$$ \begin{align*} L^{\prime}_{0} & =\varnothing,\\ L^{\prime}_{\alpha+1} & =\operatorname{Def}_{\mathcal{L}(Q_{\kappa}^{\mathrm{cf}})}\left(L^{\prime}_{\alpha}\right),\\ L_{\beta}' & =\bigcup_{\alpha<\beta}L_{\alpha}'\,\,\,\text{for limit } \beta,\\ C_{\kappa}^{*} & =\bigcup_{\alpha\in \mathbf{Ord}}L^{\prime}_{\alpha}, \end{align*} $$

where for any logic $\mathcal {L}$ extending first-order logic and a set M,

$$\begin{align*}\operatorname{Def}_{\mathcal{L}}\left(M\right):=\left\{ \left\{ a\in M\mid\left(M,\in\right)\vDash_{\mathcal{L}}\varphi\left(a,\bar{b}\right)\right\} \mid\varphi\in\mathcal{L};\,\bar{b}\in M^{<\omega}\right\}. \end{align*}$$

We focus on the case $\kappa =\omega $ and denote $C^{*}:=C_{\omega }^{*}$ . As shown in [Reference Kennedy, Magidor and Väänänen5], $C^{*}$ is a model of $\mathrm {ZFC}$ , and in fact it is the same as $L[\mathbf {Ord}_{\omega }]$ where $\mathbf {Ord}_{\omega }=\{\alpha \in \mathbf { Ord}\mid \mathrm {cf}\left (\alpha \right )=\omega \}$ . Like in the case of L, one can phrase the formula “ $V=C^{*}$ ”, i.e., $\forall x\exists \alpha (x\in L^{\prime }_{\alpha })$ where $L^{\prime }_{\alpha }$ is the $\alpha $ th level in the construction of $C^{*}$ . Unlike L, however, it is not always true that $C^{*}\vDash V=C^{*}$ , which is equivalent to the question whether $\left (C^{*}\right )^{C^{*}}=C^{*}$ . This is clearly the case if $V=L$ , so the interesting question is whether this can hold with $C^{*}\ne L$ . In Section 2 we show that this is consistent relative to the consistency of $\mathrm {ZFC}$ . Next we investigate the possibilities of $C^{*}\nvDash V=C^{*}$ . In such a case, it makes sense to define recursively the iterated $C^{*}$ s:

$$ \begin{align*} C^{*0} & =V,\\ C^{*\left(\alpha+1\right)} & =\left(C^{*}\right)^{C^{*\alpha}}\,\text{ for any } \alpha,\\ C^{*\alpha} & =\bigcap_{\beta<\alpha}C^{*\beta}\,\,\text{ for limit } \alpha. \end{align*} $$

This type of construction was first investigated by McAloon [Reference McAloon8] regarding $\mathrm {HOD}$ , the class of hereditarily ordinal definable sets, where he showed that it is equiconsistent with $\mathrm {ZFC}$ that there is a strictly decreasing sequence of iterated $\mathrm {HOD}^{\mathrm{s}}$ of length $\omega $ , and the intersection of the sequence can be either a model of $\mathrm {ZFC}$ or of $\mathrm {ZF+\neg AC}$ . Harrington also showed (in unpublished notes; cf. [Reference Zadrożny14]) that the intersection might not even be a model of $\mathrm {ZF}$ . Jech [Reference Jech4] used forcing with Suslin trees to show that it is possible to have a strictly decreasing sequence of iterated $\mathrm {HOD}^{\mathrm{s}}$ of any arbitrary ordinal length, and later Zadrożny [Reference Zadrożny13] improved this to an $\mathbf {Ord}$ length sequence. In [Reference Zadrożny14] Zadrożny generalized McAloon’s method and gave a more flexible framework for coding sets by forcing, which he used to give another proof of this result. $\mathrm {HOD}$ can be described also as the model constructed using second order logic (as shown by Myhill and Scott [Reference Myhill, Scott and Scott9]), so it is natural to ask which of the results for $\mathrm {HOD}$ apply to other such models, specifically to $C^{*}$ . In Section 3 we show that unlike the case of $\mathrm {HOD}$ , without large cardinals we can only have finite decreasing sequences of iterated $C^{*\mathrm{s}}$ , and that the existence of an inner model with a measurable cardinal is equivalent to the existence of an inner model with a strictly decreasing $C^*$ sequence of length $\omega $ .

2 Relative consistency of “ $V=C^{*} \ne L$

In this section we follow the method of Zadrożny [Reference Zadrożny14] to obtain the following result:

Theorem 2.1. If $\mathrm {ZFC}$ is consistent then so is $\mathrm {ZFC}+V=C^{*}\ne L\,+$ $2^{\aleph _{0}}=\aleph _{1}$ .

The ideaFootnote 1 of Zadrożny’s proofs, which are based on results of McAloon’s [Reference McAloon7, Reference McAloon8], is to add a generic object (to make $V\ne L$ ), code it using some other generic object, then code the coding, and so on, iterating until we catch our tail. Our coding tool will be the modified Namba forcing of [Reference Kennedy, Magidor and Väänänen5, Section 6], which adds a countable cofinal sequence to any element of some countable sequence of regular cardinals $>\aleph _{1}$ (and only to them).

Definition 2.2. Suppose $S=\left \langle \lambda _{n}\mid n<\omega \right \rangle $ is a sequence of regular cardinals $>\omega _{1}$ such that every $\lambda _{n}$ occurs infinitely many times in the sequence. Let $\left \langle B_{n}\mid n<\omega \right \rangle $ be a partition of $\omega $ into infinite sets. The modified Namba forcing with respect to S is defined as follows. Conditions are trees T with $\omega $ levels, consisting of finite sequences of ordinals, such that if $\left (\alpha _{0},\dots ,\alpha _{i}\right )\in T$ and $i\in B_{n}$ then:

  1. 1. $\alpha _{i}<\lambda _{n}$ .

  2. 2. $\left |\left \{ \beta \mid \left (\alpha _{0},\dots ,\alpha _{i-1},\beta \right )\in T\right \} \right |\in \left \{ 1,\lambda _{n}\right \} $ .

  3. 3. For every m there are $\alpha _{i+1},\dots ,\alpha _{k-1}$ such that $k\in B_{m}$ and $\left |\left \{ \beta \mid \left (\alpha _{0},\dots ,\alpha _{k-1},\beta \right )\in T\right \} \right |=\lambda _{m}$ .

A condition $T'$ extends another condition T, $T'\leq T$ , if $T'\subseteq T$ .

If $\left \langle T_{n}\mid n<\omega \right \rangle $ is a generic sequence of conditions, then the stems of the trees $T_{n}$ form a sequence $\left \langle \alpha _{n}\mid n<\omega \right \rangle $ such that $\left \langle \alpha _{i}\mid i\in B_{n}\right \rangle $ is cofinal in $\lambda _{n}$ . Thus, in the generic extension $\mathrm {cf}\left (\lambda _{n}\right )=\omega $ for all $n<\omega $ , and KMV show that these are the only regular cardinals that change their cofinality to $\omega $ . Furthermore, it is shown that revised countable support iterations of this forcing preserves $\omega _{1}$ .

In [Reference Kennedy, Magidor and Väänänen5, Theorem 6.7], these tools are used to produce a model of $\mathrm {ZFC}+V=C^{*}\ne L\,+ 2^{\aleph _{0}}=\aleph _{2}$ , but this requires an inaccessible cardinal (as proven there as well). Here we show that we can get a model of $\mathrm {ZFC}+V=C^{*}\ne L$ from $\mathrm {ZFC}$ alone, and this model will satisfy $2^{\aleph _{0}}=\aleph _{1}$ . These two results covers all possibilities, since in [Reference Kennedy, Magidor and Väänänen5, Corollary to Theorem 5.20], it is shown that the statement $V=C^{*}$ implies that $2^{\aleph _{0}}\in \left \{ \aleph _{1},\aleph _{2}\right \} $ , and for any $\kappa>\aleph _{0} \ 2^{\kappa }=\kappa ^{+}$ .

We say that a set X is nice if it is a countable set of ordinals which does not contain any of its limit points, and such that $L[X]$ agrees with L on $\omega _{1}$ and on regular cardinals starting from $\aleph _{\sup X+2}$ . Note that if $S\in L$ is a countable sequence of regular L cardinals $> \aleph _{1}$ , and X is generic for the modified Namba forcing corresponding to S, then X is nice as the size of the forcing is $\leq \aleph _{\sup X+1}$ (we assume GCH, at least starting from this point). Assume $V=L\left [A_{0}\right ]$ where $A_{0}$ is nice. Set $\mathbb {P}_{0}=\left \{ 1\right \} $ , and inductively we assume that $\mathbb {P}_{n}$ forces the existence of a nice set of ordinals $A_{n}$ , denote $\xi _{n}=\sup A_{n}$ and we set $\mathbb {P}_{n+1}=\mathbb {P}_{n}*\dot {\mathbb {Q}}_{n+1}$ where $\dot {\mathbb {Q}}_{n+1}$ is the modified Namba forcing to add a Namba sequence $E_{\alpha }$ to each $\aleph _{\xi _{n}+\alpha +2}^{L}$ such that $\alpha \in A_{n}$ (note that by niceness, $\aleph _{\xi _{n}+\alpha +2}^{L}$ is still a regular uncountable cardinal in $V^{\mathbb {P}_{n}}$ ). We can require that $E_{\alpha }\subseteq \left (\aleph _{\xi _{n}+\alpha +1}^{L},\aleph _{\xi _{n}+\alpha +2}^{L}\right )$ , so that $A_{n+1}:=\bigcup \left \{ E_{\alpha }\mid \alpha \in A_{n}\right \} $ does not contain any of its limit points, and as we noted, it is nice. $\mathbb {P}_{\omega }$ is the full support (which is in our case also the revised countable support) iteration. Let $G\subseteq \mathbb {P}_{\omega }$ generic, and denote $A=\bigcup _{n<\omega }A_{n}$ . By the properties of the modified Namba forcing, for any $\gamma $ , $V\left [G\right ]\vDash \mathrm {cf}\left (\aleph _{\gamma +2}^{L}\right )=\omega $ iff $\gamma =\xi _{n}+\alpha $ for $\alpha \in A_{n}$ .

Remark 2.3.

  1. 1. $\xi _{n+1}=\aleph _{\xi _{n}\cdot 2}^{L}$ , so inductively depends only $A_{0}$ and not on the generics. $\xi _{\omega }:=\sup A$ satisfies $\xi _{\omega }=\aleph _{\xi _{\omega }}^{L}$ and is of cofinality $\omega $ .

  2. 2. From $\operatorname {otp}(A_{0})$ and A we can inductively reconstruct each $A_{n}$ $A_{0}$ is the first $\operatorname {otp}(A_{0})$ elements of A, and if we know $A_{n}$ , then $A_{n+1}$ are the first $\operatorname {otp}(A_{n})\cdot \omega $ elements of A above $\sup A_{n}$ .

  3. 3. Hence for each n, $\operatorname {otp}(A_{n})=\operatorname {otp}(A_{0})\cdot \omega ^{n}$ .

  4. 4. If $\alpha \in A_{n}$ , then $E_{\alpha }=A\cap \left (\aleph _{\xi _{n}+\alpha +1}^{L},\aleph _{\xi _{n}+\alpha +2}^{L}\right )$ .

Proposition 2.4. $\left (C^{*}\right )^{V\left [G\right ]}=L\left [A\right ]=V\left [G\right ]$ .

Proof By the properties of the modified Namba forcing, at each stage of the iteration the only cardinals of $L\left [A_{0}\right ]$ receiving cofinality $\omega $ are the ones in $A_{n}$ . The whole iteration will also add new $\omega $ sequences to $\sup A$ , but this already had cofinality $\omega $ as we noted earlier. So $V[G]\vDash \mathrm {cf}\left (\gamma \right )=\omega $ iff either $V\vDash \mathrm {cf}\left (\gamma \right )=\omega $ or there is n s.t. $V\vDash \mathrm {cf}\left (\gamma \right )=\aleph _{\xi _{n}+\alpha +2}^{L}$ for $\alpha \in A_{n}$ . And on the other hand, if $\alpha \in A$ then $V\left [G\right ]\vDash \mathrm {cf}\left (\aleph _{\xi _{n}+\alpha +2}^{L}\right )=\omega $ . So

$$\begin{align*}A=\bigcup_{n<\omega}\left\{ \alpha\in[\xi_{n-1},\xi_{n})\mid V\left[G\right]\vDash\mathrm{cf}\left(\aleph_{\xi_{n}+\alpha+2}^{L}\right)=\omega\right\} \in\left(C^{*}\right)^{V\left[G\right]} \end{align*}$$

(where $\xi _{-1}=0$ ); hence $L\left [A\right ]\subseteq \left (C^{*}\right )^{V\left [G\right ]}$ .

As we noted, for every $\alpha \in A$ , $E_{\alpha }$ can be reconstructed from A and $\alpha $ , so $\left \langle E_{\alpha }\mid \alpha \in A\right \rangle $ is in $L\left [A\right ]$ . G can be reconstructed from this sequence; hence $V\left [G\right ]\subseteq L\left [A\right ]\subseteq \left (C^{*}\right )^{V\left [G\right ]}$ , so the equality follows.

To finish the proof of Theorem 2.1, we start with a model of $V=L$ + “there is no inaccessible cardinal,” and take, e.g., $A_{0}=\omega $ . Then $L[A]$ will satisfy $V=C^{*}\ne L$ , and $2^{\aleph _{0}}=\aleph _{1}$ will still hold since by [Reference Kennedy, Magidor and Väänänen5, Theorem 6.7], violating CH in a model of $V=C^{*}$ requires an inaccessible cardinal.Footnote 2

3 Iterating $C^{*}$

Theorem 3.1. If $\mathrm {ZFC}$ is consistent then so is the existence of a model with a decreasing $C^{*}$ -sequence of any given finite length.

Proof Going back to the proof of Theorem 2.1, we note that for any n,

$$\begin{align*}\left(C^{*}\right)^{L\left[\bigcup_{k=0}^{n+1}A_{k}\right]}=L\left[\bigcup_{k=0}^{n}A_{k}\right]: \end{align*}$$

$A_{n}$ can be computed from $A_{n+1}$ using the cofinality- $\omega $ quantifier, which gives $\supseteq $ , and on the other hand, from $\bigcup _{k=0}^{n}A_{k}$ we know exactly which ordinals will have cofinality $\omega $ in $L\left [\bigcup _{k=0}^{n+1}A_{k}\right ]$ , which gives $\subseteq $ . So by starting, e.g., from $A_{0}=\omega $ , $L\left [\bigcup _{k=0}^{n}A_{k}\right ]$ has the decreasing $C^{*}$ chain

$$\begin{align*}L\left[\bigcup_{k=0}^{n}A_{k}\right]=C^{*0}\supsetneq C^{*1}\supsetneq\cdots\supsetneq C^{*n}=L. \end{align*}$$

We now show that without large cardinals this is best possible.

Lemma 3.2. Let $E=\left \{ \alpha <\omega _{2}^{V}\mid \mathrm {cf}\left (\alpha \right )=\omega \right \} $ .

  1. 1. If $0^{\sharp }$ does not exist, then $C^{*}=L\left [E\right ]$ .

  2. 2. If there is no inner model with a measurable cardinal, then $C^{*}=K\left [E\right ]$ where K is the Dodd–Jensen core model.

Proof 1. Clearly $E\in C^{*}$ so $L\left [E\right ]\subseteq C^{*}$ . Let $\alpha \in \mathbf {Ord}$ . If $\mathrm {cf}\left (\alpha \right )\geq \omega _{2}^{V}$ then also $L\vDash \mathrm {cf}\left (\alpha \right )\geq \omega _{2}^{V}$ so in particular $L\vDash \mathrm {cf}\left (\alpha \right )>\omega $ . If $\mathrm {cf}\left (\alpha \right )<\omega _{2}^{V}$ , let $A\subseteq \alpha $ be cofinal, so $\left |A\right |\leq \aleph _{1}$ . By the covering theorem, there is $B\in L$ , $A\subseteq B\subseteq \alpha $ s.t. $\left |B\right |=\aleph _{1}+\left |A\right |=\aleph _{1}$ . Let $\bar {\alpha }=\operatorname {otp}(B)$ , so $\bar {\alpha }<\omega _{2}^{V}$ , and $\mathrm {cf}\left (\alpha \right )=\mathrm {cf}\left (\bar {\alpha }\right )$ , so $\mathrm {cf}\left (\alpha \right )=\omega $ iff $\bar {\alpha }\in E$ .

To summarize, we get that for every $\alpha $ , in $L\left [E\right ]$ we can determine whether $\mathrm {cf}\left (\alpha \right )=\omega $ or not, so $C^{*}\subseteq L\left [E\right ]$ .

2. The proof is exactly the same, noting that $K\subseteq C^{*}$ by [Reference Kennedy, Magidor and Väänänen5, Theorem 5.5], and that our assumption implies the covering theorem holds for K.

Theorem 3.3. If there is no inner model with a measurable cardinal, then there is $k<\omega $ such that $C^{*k}=C^{*(k+1)}$ .

Proof By applying Lemma 3.2 clause 2 inside each $C^{*n}$ , for every n we have $C^{*(n+1)}=K\left [E_{n}\right ]$ where

$$\begin{align*}E_{n}=\left\{ \alpha<\omega_{2}^{C^{*n}}\mid C^{*n}\vDash\mathrm{cf}\left(\alpha\right)=\omega\right\}. \end{align*}$$

The sequence $\left \langle \left (\omega _{1}^{C^{*n}},\omega _{2}^{C^{*n}}\right )\mid n<\omega \right \rangle $ is non-increasing in both coordinates; hence it stabilizes. Let k be such that $(\omega _{1}^{C^{*k}},\omega _{2}^{C^{*k}})=(\omega _{1}^{C^{*(k+1)}},\omega _{2}^{C^{*(k+1)}})$ , and we claim that $C^{*(k+1)}=C^{*(k+2)}$ . To simplify notation we assume w.l.o.g. $k=0$ , i.e., $\omega _{i}^{C^{*}}=\omega _{i}^{V}$ for $i=1,2$ (so we can omit the superscript) and we want to show that $\left (C^{*}\right )^{C*}=C^{*}$ . We have

$$ \begin{align*} C^{*} & =K\left[\left\{ \alpha<\omega_{2}\mid V\vDash\mathrm{cf}\left(\alpha\right)=\omega\right\} \right]=K\left[E_{0}\right],\\ \left(C^{*}\right)^{C*} & =K\left[\left\{ \alpha<\omega_{2}\mid C^{*}\vDash\mathrm{cf}\left(\alpha\right)=\omega\right\} \right]=K\left[E_{1}\right]. \end{align*} $$

Clearly $E_{1}\subseteq E_{0}$ . On the other hand, if $\alpha \in \omega _{2}\mathord {\smallsetminus } E_{1}$ , this means that $C^{*}\vDash \mathrm {cf}\left (\alpha \right )=\omega _{1}$ , and since $\omega _{1}^{C^{*}}=\omega _{1}$ , we get that also $V\vDash \mathrm {cf}\left (\alpha \right )=\omega _{1}$ , so $\alpha \in \omega _{2}\mathord {\smallsetminus } E_{0}$ , thus $E_{1}=E_{0}$ , and our claim is proved.

Our next goal is to show that this is precisely the consistency strength of a decreasing sequence:

Theorem 3.4. If there is an inner model with a measurable cardinal, then there is an inner model in which the sequence $\left \langle C^{*n}\mid n<\omega \right \rangle $ is strictly decreasing.

We work in $L[U]$ where U is a normal ultrafilter on $\kappa $ , and denote by $M_{\alpha }$ the $\alpha $ th iterate of $L[U]$ by U, $j_{\alpha ,\beta }:M_{\alpha }\to M_{\beta }$ the elementary embedding, $\kappa _{\alpha }=j_{0,\alpha }(\kappa )$ and $U^{(\alpha )}=j_{0,\alpha }(U)$ .

In [Reference Kennedy, Magidor and Väänänen5, Theorem 5.16] the authors show that if $V=L[U]$ then $C^{*}=M_{\omega ^{2}}\left [E\right ]$ where $E=\left \{ \kappa _{\omega \cdot n}\mid n<\omega \right \} $ . We improve this by showing that $C^{*}$ is unchanged after adding a Prikry sequence to $\kappa $ , and then investigate the $C^{*}$ -chain of $L[U]$ . First we prove two useful lemmas.

Lemma 3.5. $E=\left \{ \kappa _{\omega \cdot n}\mid n<\omega \right \} $ is generic over $M_{\omega ^{2}}$ for the Prikry forcing on $\kappa _{\omega ^{2}}$ defined from the ultrafilter $U^{(\omega ^{2})}\in M_{\omega ^{2}}$ .

Proof We use Mathias’s characterization of Prikry forcing:

Fact 3.6 (Mathias, cf. [Reference Mathias6]).

Let M be a transitive model of $\mathrm {ZFC}$ , U a normal ultrafilter on $\kappa $ , then $S\subseteq \kappa $ of order type $\omega $ is generic over M for the Prikry forcing defined from U iff for any $X\in U$ , $S\mathord {\smallsetminus } X$ is finite.

So we need to show that for any $X\in U^{(\omega ^{2})}$ , $E\mathord {\smallsetminus } X$ is finite. The ultrafilter $U^{(\omega ^{2})}$ is defined by $X\in U^{(\omega ^{2})}$ iff $\exists \alpha <\omega ^{2}\ \left \{ \kappa _{\beta }\mid \alpha \leq \beta <\omega ^{2}\right \} \subseteq X$ . For $X\in U^{(\omega ^{2})}$ , choose some $\alpha <\omega ^{2}$ such that $\left \{ \kappa _{\beta }\mid \alpha \leq \beta <\omega ^{2}\right \} \subseteq X$ , then $E\mathord {\smallsetminus }\alpha =\left \{ \kappa _{\omega \cdot n}\mid \omega \cdot n<\alpha \right \} $ , and since $\kappa _{\omega ^{2}}=\sup \left \{ \kappa _{\omega \cdot n}\mid n<\omega \right \} $ , this set is finite. Hence $E=\left \{ \kappa _{\omega \cdot n}\mid n<\omega \right \} $ satisfies the characterization.

Lemma 3.7. For any $\beta <\kappa $ and any $\alpha $ , $M_{\beta }\vDash \mathrm {cf}\left (\alpha \right )=\kappa $ iff $V\vDash \mathrm {cf}\left (\alpha \right )=\kappa $ .

Proof $\kappa $ is regular in V; thus it is regular in every $M_{\beta }$ which is an inner model of V. If $M_{\beta }\vDash \mathrm {cf}\left (\alpha \right )=\kappa $ , then there is a cofinal $\kappa $ -sequence in $\alpha $ (in both $M_{\beta }$ and V), and since $\kappa $ is regular we get $V\vDash \mathrm {cf}\left (\alpha \right )=\kappa $ . If $V\vDash \mathrm {cf}\left (\alpha \right )=\kappa $ , then the same argument rules out $M_{\beta }\vDash \mathrm {cf}\left (\alpha \right )<\kappa $ . So the only case left to rule out is $V\vDash \mathrm {cf}\left (\alpha \right )=\kappa \ \land \ M_{\beta }\vDash \mathrm {cf}\left (\alpha \right )>\kappa $ . If $\beta =\gamma +1$ , then $M_{\beta }$ is contained in $M_{\gamma }$ and closed under $\kappa $ -sequences in it, so they agree on cofinality $\kappa $ , and by induction we get that they agree with V as well. So assume $\beta $ is limit and let $\left \langle \alpha _{\eta }\mid \eta <\kappa \right \rangle $ be a cofinal sequence in $\alpha $ . By definition of the limit ultrapower, each $\alpha _{\eta }$ is of the form $j_{\bar {\beta },\beta }(\bar {\alpha }_{\eta })$ for some $\bar {\beta }<\beta $ . We can also assume that each such $\bar {\beta }$ is large enough so that $\alpha \in \operatorname {Range}(j_{\bar {\beta },\beta })$ . Since $\beta <\kappa $ , there is some $\bar {\beta }$ fitting $\kappa $ many $\alpha _{\eta }$ s, so without loss of generality we can assume $\bar {\beta }$ fits all of them. We can assume $\bar {\beta }>0$ so $\kappa $ is a fixed point of $j_{\bar {\beta },\beta }$ . If $\bar {\alpha }=\sup \left \{ \bar {\alpha }_{\eta }\mid \eta <\kappa \right \} $ Footnote 3 then, since $\alpha =\sup \left \{ j_{\bar {\beta },\beta }(\bar {\alpha }_{\eta })\mid \eta <\kappa \right \} $ and $\alpha \in \operatorname {Range}(j_{\bar {\beta },\beta })$ , we must have that $\alpha =j_{\bar {\beta },\beta }(\bar {\alpha })$ . $\bar {\alpha }$ is of cofinality $\kappa $ in V, so by the induction hypothesis also in $M_{\bar {\beta }}$ , hence by elementarity $M_{\beta }\vDash \mathrm {cf}\left (\alpha \right )=\kappa $ .

Proposition 3.8. If $V=L[U]$ where U is a measure on $\kappa $ , G is generic for Prikry forcing on $\kappa $ , then $\left (C^{*}\right )^{V\left [G\right ]}=\left (C^{*}\right )^{V}$ .

Proof After forcing with Prikry forcing, the only change of cofinalities is that $\kappa $ becomes of cofinality $\omega $ . So $V\left [G\right ]\vDash \mathrm {cf}\left (\alpha \right )=\omega $ iff $V\vDash \mathrm {cf}\left (\alpha \right )\in \left \{ \omega ,\kappa \right \} $ . We now follow the proof of [Reference Kennedy, Magidor and Väänänen5, Theorem 5.16].

Consider $M_{\omega ^{2}}$ , the $\omega ^{2}$ iterate of V, and let $E=\left \{ \kappa _{\omega \cdot n}\mid n<\omega \right \} $ . As we noted above, by [Reference Kennedy, Magidor and Väänänen5, Theorem 5.16] we know that $\left (C^{*}\right )^{V}=M_{\omega ^{2}}\left [E\right ]$ , so it is enough to show that also $\left (C^{*}\right )^{V[G]}=M_{\omega ^{2}}\left [E\right ]$ .

Fix an ordinal $\alpha $ . As in the proof of [Reference Kennedy, Magidor and Väänänen5, Theorem 5.16], $V\vDash \mathrm {cf}\left (\alpha \right )=\omega $ iff $M_{\omega ^{2}}\left [E\right ]\vDash \mathrm {cf}\left (\alpha \right )\in \left \{ \omega \right \} \cup E\cup \left \{ \sup E\right \} $ . Regarding cofinality $\kappa $ –by Lemma 3.7, $V\vDash \mathrm {cf}\left (\alpha \right )=\kappa $ iff $M_{\omega ^{2}}\vDash \mathrm {cf}\left (\alpha \right )=\kappa $ . As we noted, $M_{\omega ^{2}}=L[u']$ where $u' $ is a measure on $\kappa _{\omega ^{2}}$ and by Lemma 3.5, E is Prikry generic over it; hence, since cofinality $\kappa $ is unaffected by Prikry forcing on $\kappa _{\omega ^{2}}$ , we get $V\vDash \mathrm {cf}\left (\alpha \right )=\kappa $ iff $M_{\omega ^{2}}\left [E\right ]\vDash \mathrm {cf}\left (\alpha \right )=\kappa $ . Putting these facts together, in $M_{\omega ^{2}}\left [E\right ]$ we can detect whether $V\vDash \mathrm {cf}\left (\alpha \right )\in \left \{ \omega ,\kappa \right \} $ , so we know whether $V\left [G\right ]\vDash \mathrm {cf}\left (\alpha \right )=\omega $ ; hence we can construct $\left (C^{*}\right )^{V\left [G\right ]}$ inside $M_{\omega ^{2}}\left [E\right ]$ .

The other direction of the proof is almost the same as in [Reference Kennedy, Magidor and Väänänen5, Theorem 5.16]: E is the set of ordinals in the interval $(\kappa ,\kappa _{\omega ^{2}})$ which have cofinality $\omega $ in $V\left [G\right ]$ and are regular in the core model,Footnote 4 which is contained in any $C^{*}$ , so $E\in \left (C^{*}\right )^{V\left [G\right ]}$ , and from E one can define $M_{\omega ^{2}}$ , so $M_{\omega ^{2}}[E]\subseteq \left (C^{*}\right )^{V\left [G\right ]}$ .

Now we can analyze the $C^{*}$ -chain of $V=L[U]$ . We stick to the notation $C^{*\alpha }$ , starting from $C^{*0}=L[U]=M_{0}$ , with $M_{\alpha }$ being the $\alpha $ th iterate of $L[U]$ and $\kappa _{\alpha }$ the $\alpha $ th image of the measurable cardinal. So by [Reference Kennedy, Magidor and Väänänen5, Theorem 5.16] we have $C^{*1}=M_{\omega ^{2}}\left [E_{1}\right ]$ for $E_{1}=\left \{ \kappa _{\omega \cdot n}\mid n<\omega \right \} $ . As we noted earlier $M_{\omega ^{2}}$ is also of the form $L[U']$ for the measurable $\kappa _{\omega ^{2}}$ , and by Lemma 3.5, $E_{1}$ is Prikry generic over it, so by Proposition 3.8,

$$\begin{align*}C^{*2}=\left(C^{*}\right)^{M_{\omega^{2}}[E_1]}=\left(C^{*}\right)^{M_{\omega^{2}}}, \end{align*}$$

which is again the $\omega ^{2}$ th iterate of $M_{\omega ^{2}}$ , i.e., $M_{\omega ^{2}+\omega ^{2}}$ , plus the corresponding sequence– $E_{2}=\left \{ \kappa _{\omega ^{2}+\omega \cdot n}\mid n<\omega \right \} $ . So $C^{*2}=M_{\omega ^{2}\cdot 2}\left [E_{2}\right ]$ . We can continue inductively, and get the following:

Theorem 3.9. If $V=L[U]$ then for every $1\leq m<\omega \ C^{*m}=M_{\omega ^{2}\cdot m}\left [E_{m}\right ]$ where $M_{\alpha }$ is the $\alpha $ th iterate of V, $\kappa _{\alpha }$ the $\alpha $ th image of the measurable cardinal, and $E_{m}=\left \{ \kappa _{\omega ^{2}\cdot (m-1)+\omega \cdot n}\mid n<\omega \right \} $ .

To see that this gives us a strictly decreasing sequence of models, consider the following. For every m, $\kappa _{\omega ^{2}\cdot m}$ is the single measurable in $M_{\omega ^{2}\cdot m}$ , by which we iterate, so it remains regular in all subsequent models, in particular in $M_{\omega ^{2}\cdot (m+1)}$ . Since $E_{m+1}$ is Prikry generic for $\kappa _{\omega ^{2}\cdot (m+1)}$ which is larger than $\kappa _{\omega ^{2}\cdot m}$ , the latter remains regular in $M_{\omega ^{2}\cdot (m+1)}[E_{m+1}]$ , while in $M_{\omega ^{2}\cdot m}[E_{m}]$ it is singular, so indeed

$$\begin{align*}C^{*m}=M_{\omega^{2}\cdot m}\left[E_{m}\right]\ne M_{\omega^{2}\cdot(m+1)}\left[E_{m+1}\right]=C^{*(m+1)}. \end{align*}$$

This concludes the proof of Theorem 3.4.

To analyze $\left (C^{*\omega }\right )^{L[U]}$ , we will use the following theorem, due to Bukovský [Reference Bukovský1, Reference Bukovský2] and Dehornoy [Reference Dehornoy3]:

Fact 3.10. If $\kappa $ is measurable, $M_{\alpha }$ is the $\alpha $ th iterate of V by a normal ultrafilter on $\kappa $ , and $\kappa _{\alpha }$ is the $\alpha $ th image of $\kappa $ , then for any limit ordinal $\lambda $ exactly one of the following holds:

  1. 1. If $\exists \alpha <\lambda $ s.t. $M_{\alpha }\vDash \mathrm {cf}\left (\lambda \right )>\omega $ then $\bigcap _{\alpha <\lambda }M_{\alpha }=M_{\lambda }.$

  2. 2. If $\lambda =\alpha +\omega $ for some $\alpha $ , then $\left \langle \kappa _{\alpha +n}\mid n<\omega \right \rangle $ is Prikry generic over $M_{\lambda }$ and $\bigcap _{\alpha <\lambda }M_{\alpha }=M_{\lambda }\left [\left \langle \kappa _{\alpha +n}\mid n<\omega \right \rangle \right ].$

  3. 3. Otherwise, $\bigcap _{\alpha <\lambda }M_{\alpha }$ is a quasi-generic extension of $M_{\lambda }$ , hence satisfies $\mathrm {ZF}$ , but doesn’t satisfy $\mathrm {AC}$ .

Corollary 3.11. If $V=L[U]$ then $C^{*\omega }=\bigcap _{\alpha <\omega ^{3}}M_{\alpha }$ and it satisfies $\mathrm {ZF}$ but not $\mathrm {AC}$ .

Proof By definition and our previous calculation,

$$\begin{align*}C^{*\omega}=\bigcap_{m<\omega}C^{*m}=\bigcap_{1\leq m<\omega}M_{\omega^{2}\cdot m}\left[E_{m}\right] \end{align*}$$

and for each $m\geq 1$ , $E_{m} \notin M_{\omega ^{2}\cdot (m+1)} [E_{m+1}]$ so

$$\begin{align*}\bigcap_{1\leq m<\omega}M_{\omega^{2}\cdot m}\left[E_{m}\right]=\bigcap_{m<\omega}M_{\omega^{2}\cdot m}=\bigcap_{\alpha<\omega^{3}}M_{\alpha}. \end{align*}$$

Since $\omega ^{3}$ is of cofinality $\omega $ but not of the form $\alpha +\omega $ , the conclusion follows from Fact 3.10 clause 3.

4 Conclusion and open questions

We summarize what is now known in terms of equiconsistency:

  1. 1. $\mathrm {ZFC}$ is equiconsistent with $V=C^{*}\ne L\,+ \ 2^{\aleph _{0}}=\aleph _{1}$ .

  2. 2. Existence of an inaccessible cardinal is equiconsistent with $V=C^{*}+$ $2^{\aleph _{0}}=\aleph _{2}$ .

  3. 3. Existence of a measurable cardinal is equiconsistent with $\forall n<\omega (C^{*n}\supsetneq C^{*(n+1)})$ and $C^{*\omega }\vDash \mathrm {ZF+\neg AC}$ .

Compared to the results regarding $\mathrm {HOD}$ , the following questions remain open:

Question 4.1.

  1. 1. Is it possible, under any large cardinal hypothesis, that $\forall n<\omega $ $C^{*n}\supsetneq C^{*(n+1)}$ and $C^{*\omega }\vDash \mathrm {ZFC}$ ? More generally, for which ordinals $\alpha $ can we get a decreasing $C^{*}$ sequence of length $\alpha $ ?

  2. 2. Is it possible, under any large cardinal hypothesis, that $\forall n<\omega $ $C^{*n}\supsetneq C^{*(n+1)}$ and $C^{*\omega }\nvDash \mathrm {ZF}$ ?

A natural first attempt towards answering the first question would be to try and work in a model with more measurable cardinals. However, it seems that it would require at least measurably many measurables: in a forthcoming paper [Reference Ya’ar12], we generalize [Reference Kennedy, Magidor and Väänänen5, Theorem 5.16] and our Proposition 3.8 and show the following:

Theorem 4.2. Assume $V=L\left [\mathcal {U}\right ]$ where $\mathcal {U}=\left \langle U_{\gamma }\mid \gamma <\chi \right \rangle $ is a sequence of measures on the increasing measurables $\left \langle \kappa ^{\gamma }\mid \gamma <\chi \right \rangle $ where $\chi <\kappa ^{0}$ . Iterate V according to $\mathcal {U}$ where each measurable is iterated $\omega ^{2}$ many times, to obtain $\left \langle M_{\alpha }^{\gamma }\mid \gamma <\chi ,\alpha \leq \omega ^{2}\right \rangle $ , with iteration points $\left \langle \kappa _{\alpha }^{\gamma }\mid \gamma <\chi ,\alpha \leq \omega ^{2}\right \rangle $ , and set $M^{\chi }$ as the directed limit of this iteration. Let G be generic over V for the forcing adding a Prikry sequence to every $\kappa ^{\gamma }$ . Set for every $\gamma <\chi \ E^{\gamma }=\left \langle \kappa _{\omega \cdot n}^{\gamma }\mid 1\leq n<\omega \right \rangle $ and $\hat {E}^{\gamma }=\left \langle \kappa _{\omega \cdot n}^{\gamma }\mid 0\leq n<\omega \right \rangle $ then

$$ \begin{align*} \left(C^{*}\right)^{V} & =M^{\chi}\left[\left\langle E^{\gamma}\mid\gamma<\chi\right\rangle \right],\\\left(C^{*}\right)^{V\left[G\right]} & =M^{\chi}[\langle \hat{E}^{\gamma}\mid\gamma<\chi\rangle ]. \end{align*} $$

So, if $V=L\left [\mathcal {U}\right ]$ as above, $C^{*}$ is of the form $L\left [\mathcal {U}_{1}\right ]\left [G_{1}\right ]$ for some sequence of measures and a sequence of Prikry sequences on its measures, and so $C^{*2}$ is again of that form, where we iterated the measures in $\mathcal {U} \ \omega ^{2}\cdot 2$ many times and add Prikry sequences. So again, as we’ve done here, we’ll get that $C^{*\omega }$ is the intersection of the models $M_{\omega ^{2}\cdot n}^{\chi }$ where we iterated each measure $\omega ^{2}\cdot n$ times. This is due to the facts that changing the order of iteration between the measures doesn’t change the final result, and that the Prikry sequences “fall out” during the intersection. Now, we don’t have a complete analysis of intersections of iterations by more than one measure, but Dehornoy proves the following more general fact:

Fact 4.3 [Reference Dehornoy3, Section 5.3, Proposition 3].

For every $\alpha $ let $N_{\alpha }$ be the $\alpha $ th iteration of V by some measure. Assume $\lambda $ is such that for every $\alpha <\lambda $ , $N_{\alpha }\vDash \mathrm {cf}(\lambda )=\omega $ but there is no $\rho $ such that $\lambda =\rho +\omega $ . Then if M is a transitive inner model of $\mathrm {ZFC}$ containing $\bigcap _{\alpha <\lambda }N_{\alpha }$ , then there is some $\alpha <\lambda $ such that $N_{\alpha }\subseteq M$ .

So, if we take $N_{\alpha }$ to be the iteration of V by the first measure in $\mathcal {U}$ , we get that $C^{*\omega }$ contains $\bigcap _{\alpha <\omega ^{3}}N_{\alpha }$ , but doesn’t contain any $N_{\alpha }$ for $\alpha <\omega ^{3}$ , so $C^{*\omega }$ cannot satisfy $\mathrm {AC}$ .

Furthermore, a recent result by Welch [Reference Welch11] shows that under the assumption that $O^{k}$ (O-kukri) doesn’t exist, i.e., there is no elementary embedding of an inner model with a proper class of measurables to itself (and in particular no measurable limit of measurables), the characterization $\left (C^{*}\right )^{V}=M^{\chi }\left [\left \langle E^{\gamma }\mid \gamma <\chi \right \rangle \right ]$ holds for any $\chi \leq \mathbf {Ord}$ , and it seems likely that the analysis of the iterated $C^{*}$ will be the same as well. Hence a different approach, or larger cardinals, would be required to answer this question.

A different line of inquiry stems from the following fact:

Fact 4.4 [Reference Kennedy, Magidor and Väänänen5].

If there is a proper class of Woodin cardinals then the theory of $C^{*}$ is unchanged by forcing.

So the question whether $C^{*}\vDash V=C^{*}$ cannot be changed under forcing in the presence of class many Woodin cardinals. If the sequence of $C^{*\alpha }$ is definable (perhaps up to some ordinal) then this will also be in the theory of $C^{*}$ (note that on the face of it even the sequence up to $\omega $ may not be definable).

Question 4.5. What can be deduced on the sequence of iterated $C^{*}$ from a proper class of Woodin cardinals?

Acknowledgments

I would like to thank my advisor, Prof. Menachem Magidor, for his guidance and support without which this work would not have been possible. I would also like to thank the anonymous referee for their comments and suggestions.

Footnotes

1 I’d like to thank Kameryn Williams for his exposition of this and related results in his blog—http://kamerynjw.net/2019/12/04/omegath-hod.html.

2 It can in fact be proved that our forcing does not add new reals in general, but as we are looking for a consistency result this is not required.

3 Note that we can’t assume this sequence is in $M_{\bar {\beta }}.$

4 Note that here we had to avoid $\kappa $ which also satisfies this.

References

Bukovský, L., Changing cofinality of a measurable cardinal (an alternative proof) . Commentationes Mathematicae Universitatis Carolinae, vol. 14 (1973), no. 4, pp. 689698.Google Scholar
Bukovský, L., Iterated ultrapower and Prikry’s forcing . Commentationes Mathematicae Universitatis Carolinae, vol. 18 (1977), no. 1, pp. 7785.Google Scholar
Dehornoy, P., Iterated ultrapowers and Prikry forcing . Annals of Mathematical Logic, vol. 15 (1978), no. 2, pp. 109160.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jech, T. J., Forcing with trees and ordinal definability . Annals of Mathematical Logic, vol. 7 (1975), no. 4, pp. 387409.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kennedy, J., Magidor, M., and Väänänen, J., Inner models from extended logics: Part 1 . Journal of Mathematical Logic, vol. 21 (2021), no. 2, p. 2150012.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mathias, A. R. D., On sequences generic in the sense of Prikry . Journal of the Australian Mathematical Society, vol. 15 (1973), no. 4, pp. 409414.Google Scholar
McAloon, K., Consistency results about ordinal definability . Annals of Mathematical Logic, vol. 2 (1971), no. 4, pp. 449467.Google Scholar
McAloon, K., On the sequence of models ${\mathrm{HOD}}_n$ . Fundamenta Mathematicae, vol. 82 (1974), no. 1, pp. 8593.Google Scholar
Myhill, J. and Scott, D., Ordinal definability , Axiomatic Set Theory (Scott, D. S., editor), Proceedings of Symposia in Pure Mathematics, vol. XIII, American Mathematical Society, Providence, 1971, pp. 271278.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shelah, S., Generalized quantifiers and compact logic . Transactions of the American Mathematical Society, vol. 204 (1975), pp. 342364.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Welch, P. D., ${C}^{\ast }$ in $L\left[E\right]$ -models below ${O}^k$ . Personal communication, 2022.Google Scholar
Ya’ar, U., Models for short sequences of measures in the cofinality- $\omega$ constructible model, preprint, 2021, arxiv:2109.04523.Google Scholar
Zadrożny, W., Transfinite descending sequences of models ${\mathrm{HOD}}^{\alpha }$ . Annals of Mathematical Logic, vol. 20 (1981), no. 2, pp. 201229.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zadrożny, W., Iterating ordinal definability . Annals of Pure and Applied Logic, vol. 24 (1983), no. 3, pp. 263310.Google Scholar