Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-mkpzs Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-26T19:27:56.009Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

HIERARCHICAL INCOMPLETENESS RESULTS FOR ARITHMETICALLY DEFINABLE EXTENSIONS OF FRAGMENTS OF ARITHMETIC

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  02 July 2021

RASMUS BLANCK*
Affiliation:
DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY, LINGUISTICS AND THEORY OF SCIENCE UNIVERSITY OF GOTHENBURG BOX 200, SE-405 30, GOTHENBURG, SWEDENE-mail: [email protected]
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

There has been a recent interest in hierarchical generalizations of classic incompleteness results. This paper provides evidence that such generalizations are readily obtainable from suitably formulated hierarchical versions of the principles used in the original proofs. By collecting such principles, we prove hierarchical versions of Mostowski’s theorem on independent formulae, Kripke’s theorem on flexible formulae, Woodin’s theorem on the universal algorithm, and a few related results. As a corollary, we obtain the expected result that the formula expressing “ $\mathrm {T}$ is $\Sigma _n$ -ill” is a canonical example of a $\Sigma _{n+1}$ formula that is $\Pi _{n+1}$ -conservative over $\mathrm {T}$ .

Type
Research Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2021. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of Association for Symbolic Logic

1 Introduction

There has been a recent interest in hierarchical generalizations of classic incompleteness results [Reference Chao and Seraji5, Reference Kikuchi and Kurahashi23, Reference Kurahashi27, Reference Salehi and Seraji40]. A sample result, generalizing the Gödel–Rosser incompleteness theorem, and independently proved by both Kikuchi and Kurahashi [Reference Kikuchi and Kurahashi23] and Salehi and Seraji [Reference Salehi and Seraji40], is:

Theorem 1.1. Let $\mathrm {T}$ be a $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -definable, $\Sigma _n$ -sound extension of $\mathrm {PA}$ . Then there is a $\Pi _{n+1}$ sentence that is undecidable in $\mathrm {T}$ .

In this paper I argue that such hierarchical generalizations can often be obtained from the original proofs by replacing certain principles used in the proofs by appropriately formulated hierarchical versions, while the essence of the arguments remains the same. The hierarchical principles, once appropriately formulated, are in turn often provable by appropriate generalizations of the core concepts employed in the proofs of the ordinary ones, but even so, there is no single source to which to turn for them. Both Smoryński [Reference Smoryński45] and Beklemishev [Reference Beklemishev1] give good partial accounts of the syntactical side, and Poizat [Reference Poizat35] gives a hierarchical perspective on the basic model theory of arithmetic, including model-theoretic proofs of hierarchical versions of Gödel’s first and second incompleteness theorems. Still, I find certain aspects lacking. With this in mind, one aim of this paper is to collect a number of principles that may be useful to the reader who herself wishes to prove hierarchical incompleteness results without having to reinvent the wheel.

These principles are then put to use to prove a number of general incompleteness results for arithmetically definable extensions of fragments of $\mathrm {PA}$ . The goal is not to prove the sharpest or most general results (in fact some of the results follow from each other), but rather to exemplify how the hierarchical principles enter into more or less well-known proof methods. Even so, the results presented here improve on some results of Chao and Seraji [Reference Chao and Seraji5], Kikuchi and Kurahashi [Reference Kikuchi and Kurahashi23], and Salehi and Seraji [Reference Salehi and Seraji40], and sharpen some of Blanck [Reference Blanck3], Hamkins [Reference Hamkins18], Lindström [Reference Lindström28], and Woodin [Reference Woodin, Heller and Woodin48]. These sharpenings are in terms of gauging the amount of induction needed for the proofs, bringing the (in this particular sub-field largely ignored) fragments-of-arithmetic perspective to attention.

In order to state the results in a more general form, I have chosen to consider only extensions of $\mathrm {I}\Delta _0 + \mathrm {exp}$ , although under the somewhat unusual name $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _0 + \mathrm {exp}$ . This allows for formulating results for extensions of, e.g., $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _n + \mathrm {exp}$ , ensuring that partial satisfaction predicates are well behaved even for $n=0$ . While it is sometimes possible to push the background theory below $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _0 + \mathrm {exp}$ , I have refrained from doing so, to instead focus on the more general hierarchical picture.

2 Notation and conventions

The expressions $\exists x \leq t \phi (x)$ and $\forall x \leq t \phi (x)$ are used as shorthand for $\exists x (x \leq t \land \phi (x))$ and $\forall x (x\leq t \rightarrow \phi (x))$ , where t is some term in the language of arithmetic. The initial quantifiers of these formulae are bounded and a formula containing only bounded quantifiers is a bounded formula. Let $\Delta _0 = \Sigma _0 = \Pi _0$ be the class of bounded formulae.

The arithmetical hierarchy is defined as follows. A formula is $\Sigma _{n+1}$ iff it is of the form $\exists x_1 \dots x_m \pi (x_1,\dots ,x_m)$ where $\pi $ is a $\Pi _n$ formula (that may contain other variables than $x_1,\dots ,x_m$ ). Similarly, a formula is $\Pi _{n+1}$ iff it is of the form $\forall x_1 \dots x_m \sigma (x_1,\dots ,x_m)$ where $\sigma $ is a $\Sigma _n$ formula. $\Delta _n(\mathcal {M})$ ( $\Delta _n(\mathrm {T})$ ) is the set of $\Sigma _n$ formulae that are equivalent to $\Pi _n$ formulae in a given model $\mathcal {M}$ (theory $\mathrm {T}$ ). Throughout the paper $\Gamma $ denotes either $\Sigma _{n+1}$ or $\Pi _{n+1}$ , and we always assume only that $n\geq 0$ .

Theories are understood as sets of sentences, thought of as the set of nonlogical axioms of the theory. $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _n$ is the theory obtained by adding induction for $\Sigma _n$ formulae to Robinson’s arithmetic $\mathrm {Q}$ , while $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _0 + \mathrm {exp}$ is $\mathrm {Q}$ plus $\Sigma _0$ -induction plus an axiom stating that the exponentiation function is total. We assume that all theories denoted $\mathrm {T}$ , etc., are consistent, arithmetically definable, extensions of $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _0 + \mathrm {exp}$ .

$\mathrm {T}$ is $\Gamma $ -sound iff for all $\Gamma $ sentences $\unicode{x3b3} $ , if $\mathrm {T} \vdash \unicode{x3b3} $ , then $\mathbb {N} \models \unicode{x3b3} $ . The converse implication is sometimes known as $\Gamma $ -completeness: hence $\mathrm {T}$ is $\Gamma $ -complete iff for all $\Gamma $ sentences $\unicode{x3b3} $ , if $\mathbb {N} \models \unicode{x3b3} $ , then $\mathrm {T} \vdash \unicode{x3b3} $ . $\mathrm {S}$ is $\Gamma $ -conservative over $\mathrm {T}$ iff for all $\Gamma $ sentences $\unicode{x3b3} $ , if $\mathrm {S} \vdash \unicode{x3b3} $ , then $\mathrm {T} \vdash \unicode{x3b3} $ .

We rely on a coding of finite sets and sequences in $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _0 + \mathrm {exp}$ , as developed by Hájek & Pudlák [Reference Hájek and Pudlák17, chap. I.1]. The set $\Sigma _0(X)$ is obtained by adding atomic formulae of the form $t \in X$ (where t is any term) and closing under propositional connectives and bounded quantifiers. The set $\Sigma _1(X)$ is obtained from $\Sigma _0(X)$ in the usual manner.

Let $\varepsilon $ be Ackermann’s membership relation: $n\varepsilon a$ expresses “the nth bit of the binary expansion of a is $1$ .” In other words, a can be regarded as a code for the set consisting of all n such that $n\varepsilon a$ . Then a is a z-piece of $\phi (x)$ if $\forall n < z (n\varepsilon a \leftrightarrow \phi (n))$ .

If $\phi (x)$ is any formula, $\ulcorner \phi (x) \urcorner $ denotes the numeral for the Gödel number of $\phi (x)$ under some fixed Gödel numbering, but we make no typographical distinction between natural numbers and the corresponding numerals. We use Feferman’s dot notation $\ulcorner \phi (\dot {x})\urcorner $ to represent the Gödel number of the sentence obtained by replacing the variable x with the actual value of x; hence x is free in $\ulcorner \phi (\dot {x})\urcorner $ . The notation $:=$ is used to express equality between formulae. Let $\top := 0 = 0$ and $\bot := \lnot \top $ . Let $\phi ^0 := \lnot \phi $ and $\phi ^1 := \phi $ . Footnote 1

A relation X is numerated in $\mathrm {T}$ by a formula $\phi $ iff $X = \{\langle k_1,\dots ,k_n \rangle \in \omega ^n : \mathrm {T} \vdash \phi (k_1,\dots ,k_n)\}$ , and binumerated by $\phi $ in $\mathrm {T}$ if $\lnot \phi $ also numerates the complement of X. A relation X is correctly numerated by $\phi $ if $\phi $ numerates X and for all $k_1,\dots ,k_n$ , $\mathrm {T} \vdash \phi (k_1,\dots ,k_n)$ iff $\phi (k_1,\dots ,k_n)$ is true. A function f is strongly representable in $\mathrm {T}$ iff there is a formula $\phi (x_1,\dots ,x_n,y)$ that numerates $f(x_1,\dots ,x_n) = y$ in $\mathrm {T}$ , and moreover, if $f(k_1,\dots ,k_n) = m$ , then $\mathrm {T} \vdash \forall y (\phi (k_1,\dots ,k_n,y) \rightarrow y = m)$ .

Given a formula $\tau (z)$ , let $\mathrm {Prf}_\tau (x,y)$ be a formula expressing “y is a proof of the formula x from the set of sentences satisfying $\tau (z)$ .” Let $\mathrm {Pr}_\tau (x)$ be the formula $\exists y \mathrm {Prf}_\tau (x,y)$ , and let $\mathrm {Con}_\tau $ be the sentence $\lnot \mathrm {Pr}_\tau (\ulcorner \bot \urcorner )$ . Whenever $\tau (z)$ is $\Sigma _{n+1}$ , $\mathrm {Pr}_\tau (x)$ is equivalent to a $\Sigma _{n+1}$ formula in the real world. For any formula $\tau (x)$ , the notation $(\tau + z)(x)$ is used as shorthand for $\tau (x) \lor x = z$ . This convention is used in expressions such as $\mathrm {Prf}_{\tau + z}(x)$ .

Models of arithmetic are denoted $\mathcal {M}$ , etc., while the respective domains are denoted M, etc. The standard model is denoted $\mathbb {N}$ and its domain is $\omega $ . If $\mathcal {M}$ is non-standard, then the standard system of $\mathcal {M}$ , $\mathrm {SSy}(\mathcal {M})$ , is the collection of sets $X \subseteq \omega $ such that for some $a \in M$ , $X = \{ n \in \omega : \mathcal {M} \models n\varepsilon a\}$ . Then X is coded in $\mathcal {M}$ , and a is a code for X.

A relation $X \subseteq M^n$ is $\Gamma $ -definable in $\mathcal {M}$ (with parameters) iff there is a tuple $\overline {b}\in M$ and a formula $\phi (x_1,\dots ,x_n, \overline {y}) \in \Gamma $ such that $X = \{\langle m_1,\dots ,m_n \rangle \in M^n : \mathcal {M} \models \phi (m_1,\dots ,m_n,\overline {b})\}$ . Whenever this terminology is used without specifying a model $\mathcal {M}$ , it is assumed that $\mathcal {M} = \mathbb {N}$ . Thus, in particular, a $\Gamma $ -definition of a theory $\mathrm {T}$ is a $\Gamma $ formula $\tau (x)$ such that $\mathrm {T} = \{ \phi : \mathbb {N} \models \tau (\ulcorner \phi \urcorner ) \}$ .

For each $\Gamma $ , $\mathrm {Th}_\Gamma (\mathcal {M})$ is the set of $\Gamma $ sentences true in $\mathcal {M}$ , that is, the set $\{ \phi \in \Gamma : \mathcal {M} \models \phi \}$ . If $\mathcal {M}$ is a submodel of $\mathcal {N}$ , and for all $\overline {a} \in M$ and $\unicode{x3b3} (\overline {x}) \in \Gamma $ , $\mathcal {M} \models \unicode{x3b3} (\overline {a})$ iff $\mathcal {N} \models \unicode{x3b3} (\overline {a})$ , then $\mathcal {N}$ is a $\Gamma $ -elementary extension of $\mathcal {M}$ . If $\mathcal {M} \models \sigma $ for some $\Sigma _{n+1}$ sentence $\sigma $ , and $\mathcal {N}$ is a $\Sigma _n$ -elementary extension of $\mathcal {M}$ , then $\mathcal {N} \models \sigma $ . $\mathcal {N}$ is an end-extension of $\mathcal {M}$ (or, equivalently, $\mathcal {M}$ is an initial segment of $\mathcal {N}$ ) iff $\mathcal {M}$ is a submodel of $\mathcal {N}$ , and whenever $a \in M$ and $b \in N$ , and $\mathcal {N}\models b < a$ , then $b \in M$ .

Let $\emptyset ^{(n)}$ denote the nth Turing jump of the empty set (see, e.g., [Reference Rogers39, p. 254]). For each n, let $\langle \varphi _i^n : i \in \omega \rangle $ be an acceptable (in the sense of Rogers [Reference Rogers39, exercise 2.10]) enumeration of the functions that are recursively enumerable (r.e.) in $\emptyset ^{(n)}$ ; these are the partial n-recursive functions. For each partial n-recursive function $\varphi _e^n$ , let the eth n-r.e. set $W_e^n$ be the domain of $\varphi _e^n$ . If f is a function such that $f \simeq \varphi _e^n$ for some e, then e is an n-index for f.

3 Preliminary principles

This section presents a number of suitably formulated principles that are useful in proving hierarchical incompleteness results of the kind given in Theorem 1.1. The basic versions of these principles can be found scattered across the literature, and none of them should be too surprising to the reader familiar with, e.g., Hájek and Pudlák [Reference Hájek and Pudlák17], Kaye [Reference Kaye22], Lindström [Reference Lindström29], and Smoryński [Reference Smoryński45].

The essence of the generalizations presented in this paper is that r.e. theories are replaced by $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -definable ones, and that the base theory is pushed down as far as it will go below $\mathrm {PA}$ . On some occasions the theories have to satisfy additional constraints such as $\Sigma _n$ -soundness or $\Pi _n$ -completeness for the generalization to go through, and whenever this is the case that will be pointed out explicitly.

3.1 Basics, representability, recursion theory

Many textbooks in metamathematics rely on some version of the fact that Robinson’s arithmetic $\mathrm {Q}$ is $\Sigma _1$ -complete: it proves all true $\Sigma _1$ sentences. This has the consequence that every r.e. set can be numerated in $\mathrm {Q}$ by a $\Sigma _1$ formula, which in turn allows for representing the theorem set of $\mathrm {Q}$ in $\mathrm {Q}$ and proving the first incompleteness theorem. Many proofs of these facts rely on $\Delta _0$ being closed under bounded quantification, and $\mathrm {Q}$ deciding all $\Delta _0$ sentences.

Since the aim of this paper is to generalize incompleteness results to $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -definable theories rather than r.e. ones, there is a need for establishing a similar correspondence between $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -definable sets and theories sufficient to represent them. On these higher levels, the roles of $\Delta _0$ and $\mathrm {Q}$ are played by the classes $\Sigma _0(\Sigma _{n})$ and the theories $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _n + \mathrm {Th}_{\Pi _n}(\mathbb {N})$ , respectively. Establishing this relationship is the goal of this subsection.

The following four observations (see, e.g., [Reference Smoryński43, lemma 0.3], [Reference Hájek16, lemma 2.2], [Reference Beklemishev1, lemma 2.9], [Reference Kikuchi and Kurahashi23, proposition 3.7]) serve as the starting point for the analogy between $\mathrm {Q}$ and $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _n + \mathrm {Th}_{\Pi _n}(\mathbb {N})$ .

Fact 3.2 (Basic properties of soundness and completeness).

  1. 1. $\mathrm {T}$ is consistent iff $\mathrm {T}$ is $\Sigma _0$ -sound.

  2. 2. $\mathrm {T}$ is $\Pi _n$ -complete iff $\mathrm {T}$ is $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -complete.

  3. 3. $\mathrm {T}$ is $\Sigma _n$ -sound iff $\mathrm {T}$ is $\Pi _{n+1}$ -sound iff $\mathrm {T} + \mathrm {Th}_{\Sigma _{n+1}}(\mathbb {N})$ is consistent.

  4. 4. If $\mathrm {T}$ is consistent and $\Pi _n$ -complete, then $\mathrm {T}$ is $\Sigma _n$ -sound.

While the usual formulation of Gödel’s theorem pertains to r.e., consistent theories, the hierarchically formulated Theorem 1.1 is stated for $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -definable, $\Sigma _n$ -sound theories. In light of the preceding fact, consistency and $\Sigma _0$ -soundness are equivalent, so the ordinary statement fits nicely into the hierarchical statement of the theorem. However, inspection of the published proofs of Theorem 1.1 reveals that $\Pi _n$ -complete theories enter the argument in an indispensable way. In the proof by Kikuchi & Kurahashi [Reference Kikuchi and Kurahashi23], $\Pi _n$ -completeness of $\mathrm {T}$ can be explicitly assumed, since in the case where $\mathrm {T}$ is not $\Pi _n$ -complete, it fails to prove all true $\Pi _n$ sentences and can hardly prove all true $\Pi _{n+1}$ sentences. By contrast, the proof by Salehi & Seraji [Reference Salehi and Seraji40] bypasses assuming $\Pi _n$ -completeness of $\mathrm {T}$ by instead constructing a $\Pi _{n+1}$ sentence that is independent of the $\Pi _n$ -complete $\mathrm {T} + \mathrm {Th}_{\Pi _n}(\mathbb {N})$ , a theory whose consistency is guaranteed by the $\Sigma _n$ -soundness of $\mathrm {T}$ . That sentence is, a fortiori, also independent of $\mathrm {T}$ .

The most conservative generalization of “r.e., consistent” is therefore “ $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -definable, $\Pi _n$ -complete, and consistent” rather than “ $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -definable, $\Sigma _n$ -sound.” As is clear from Theorem 1.1, the assumption of $\Pi _n$ -completeness of $\mathrm {T}$ is sometimes excessively strong, and mere $\Sigma _n$ -soundness is indeed enough for some further applications as well. In those cases, the proofs rely on the consistency of $\mathrm {T} + \mathrm {Th}_{\Pi _n}(\mathbb {N})$ , as in the proof by Salehi & Seraji [Reference Salehi and Seraji40]. In other cases, however, the $\Pi _n$ -completeness is indispensable for the generalization to go through.Footnote 2

The analogy with regard to soundness and completeness therefore goes as follows. Since $\mathrm {Q}$ is $\Pi _0$ -complete, it is also $\Sigma _{1}$ -complete, and since it is also consistent it follows that $\mathrm {Q}$ is $\Sigma _0$ -sound and therefore also $\Pi _1$ -sound. Now consider $\mathrm {Th}_{\Pi _n}(\mathbb {N})$ : This theory is $\Pi _n$ -complete and therefore also $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -complete; it is consistent and therefore $\Pi _{n+1}$ -sound.

The role of $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _n$ in the analogy between $\mathrm {Q}$ and $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _n + \mathrm {Th}_{\Pi _n}(\mathbb {N})$ becomes clear through the next fact. Its proof will take up most of the remainder of this subsection.

Fact 3.3.

  1. 1. Every $\Sigma _n$ - (or $\Pi _n$ -) definable relation on $\omega $ is binumerated by a $\Sigma _n$ (or $\Pi _n$ ) formula in $\mathrm {Q} + \mathrm {Th}_{\Pi _n}(\mathbb {N})$ .

  2. 2. Every $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -definable relation on $\omega $ is numerated by a $\Sigma _{n+1}$ formula in $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _n + \mathrm {Th}_{\Pi _n}(\mathbb {N})$ .

  3. 3. Every function from $\omega ^k$ to $\omega $ that is recursive in $\emptyset ^{(n)}$ is strongly representable by a $\Sigma _{n+1}$ formula (with particularly nice properties) in $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _{n} + \mathrm {exp} + \mathrm {Th}_{\Pi _n}(\mathbb {N})$ .Footnote 3

The first item is immediately seen to be true, since $\mathrm {Q} + \mathrm {Th}_{\Pi _n}(\mathbb {N})$ is consistent, $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -complete, and $\Pi _{n+1}$ -sound. The second and third items are elaborated on below, but first we need a few more stepping stones to help out in the constructions.

Fact 3.4 (Parametric diagonal lemma).

  1. 1. For every $\Gamma $ formula $\unicode{x3b3} (x,y)$ , we can effectively find a $\Gamma $ formula $\xi (x)$ such that

    $$ \begin{align*} \mathrm{Q} \vdash \forall x (\xi(x) \leftrightarrow \unicode{x3b3}(x,\ulcorner \xi\urcorner))\text{.} \end{align*} $$
  2. 2. For every $\Gamma $ formula $\unicode{x3b3} (x,y)$ , we can effectively find a $\Gamma $ formula $\xi (x)$ such that, for each k,

    $$ \begin{align*} \mathrm{Q} \vdash \xi(k) \leftrightarrow \unicode{x3b3}(k,\ulcorner \xi(k)\urcorner))\text{.} \end{align*} $$

Bibliographical remark. Item 1. of the above is essentially due to Montague [Reference Montague33, lemma 1]. The proof by Ehrenfeucht and Feferman [Reference Ehrenfeucht and Feferman10, lemma 1] of 2. actually suffices to prove 1.; see also [Reference Smoryński44] for a discussion of the development of the diagonal lemma.

Fact 3.5 (Generalized Craig’s trick).

For any $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -definable theory $\mathrm {T}$ , defined by a $\Sigma _{n+1}$ formula $\sigma (z)$ , there is a deductively equivalent theory $\mathrm {S}$ , defined by a formula $\pi (x)$ that is $\Pi _n$ in $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _n$ . Moreover, $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _{n+1} \vdash \forall x (\mathrm {Pr}_\sigma (x) \leftrightarrow \mathrm {Pr}_\pi (x))$ .Footnote 4

Bibliographical remark. Craig’s [Reference Craig7] formulation pertains to r.e. theories, for which there exist deductively equivalent theories with primitive recursive definitions. An early hierarchical generalization is due to Grzegorczyk et al. [Reference Grzegorczyk, Mostowski and Ryll-Nardzewski14, theorem 2.2.C]. The hierarchical formulation presented here follows by inspection of a proof by Kurahashi [Reference Kurahashi27, proposition 9].

Convention. In light of Craig’s trick, we may assume that any $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -definable theory is in fact $\Pi _n$ -defined. In what follows, we write $\mathrm {Prf}_{\mathrm {T}}(x,y)$ to denote (ambiguously) any formula $\mathrm {Prf}_\tau (x,y)$ where $\tau $ is a $\Pi _n$ binumeration of $\mathrm {T}$ in $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _n + \mathrm {Th}_{\Pi _n}(\mathbb {N})$ , and moreover, this formula can be assumed to be $\Pi _n$ . Consequently, $\Pr _{\mathrm {T}}(x)$ is $\Sigma _{n+1}$ and $\mathrm {Con}_{\mathrm {T}}$ is $\Pi _{n+1}$ in $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _n$ .

Fact 3.6 [Reference Hájek and Pudlák17, lemmata I.2.9 and I.2.14 and theorem I.2.25].

  1. 1. In $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _n$ , both $\Sigma _n$ and $\Pi _n$ are closed under bounded quantifiers.Footnote 5

  2. 2. $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _n \vdash \mathrm {I}\Sigma _0(\Sigma _n)$ .

  3. 3. Each $\Sigma _0(\Sigma _n)$ formula is $\Delta _{n+1}$ in $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _n$ .

All the pieces are now in place to prove a, sometimes useful, lemma from which Fact 3.3(2) follows immediately. The proof highlights the steps where induction and the additional truth from the standard model is required. For the statement of the lemma, recall that a relation X is correctly numerated by $\phi $ in $\mathrm {T}$ if $\phi $ numerates X in $\mathrm {T}$ , and for all $k_1,\dots ,k_n$ , $\mathrm {T} \vdash \phi (k_1,\dots ,k_n)$ iff $\phi (k_1,\dots ,k_n)$ is true.

Lemma 3.7. Let $\mathrm {T}$ be any $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -definable, $\Pi _n$ -complete, and consistent extension of $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _n$ and let $R(x_1,\dots ,x_m)$ be any $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -definable relation. There is a $\Sigma _{n+1}$ formula $\phi (x_1,\dots ,x_m)$ that correctly numerates R in $\mathrm {T}$ .

Proof. Let $\rho (x_1,\dots ,x_m)$ define R. We may assume that $\rho (x_1,\dots ,x_m)$ is of the form $\exists z \pi (x_1,\dots , x_m,z)$ with $\pi \in \Pi _n$ . Let $\phi (x_1,\dots ,x_m)$ be such that, for all $k_1,\dots ,k_m$ , $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _n + \mathrm {Th}_{\Pi _n}(\mathbb {N})$ proves

$$ \begin{align*} \phi(k_1,\dots,k_m) \leftrightarrow \exists z (\pi(k_1,\dots,k_m,z) \land \forall y\leq z \lnot \mathrm{Prf}_{\mathrm{T}}(\ulcorner \phi(k_1,\dots,k_m) \urcorner, y))\text{.} \end{align*} $$

Recall that if $\mathrm {T}$ is $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -definable, then there is a deductively equivalent $\Pi _n$ definition of $\mathrm {T}$ , and $\mathrm {Prf}_{\mathrm {T}}(x,y)$ is therefore equivalent to a $\Pi _n$ formula in $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _n$ . Then

$$ \begin{align*} \pi(k_1,\dots,k_m,z) \land \forall y\leq z \lnot \mathrm{Prf}_{\mathrm{T}}(\ulcorner \phi(k_1,\dots,k_m) \urcorner, y) \end{align*} $$

is a $\Sigma _0(\Sigma _n)$ formula, and is therefore, by Fact 3.6, equivalent to a $\Delta _{n+1}$ formula in $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _n$ . It follows that $\phi $ is equivalent to a $\Sigma _{n+1}$ formula in $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _n$ .

Suppose $R(k_1,\dots ,k_m)$ . Then $\mathbb {N} \models \rho (k_1,\dots ,k_m)$ , so there is then an i such that $\mathbb {N} \models \pi (k_1,\dots ,k_m,i)$ . Since $\pi $ is $\Pi _n$ and $\mathrm {Th}_{\Pi _n}(\mathbb {N})$ is $\Pi _n$ -complete, it follows that $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _n + \mathrm {Th}_{\Pi _n}(\mathbb {N}) \vdash \pi (k_1,\dots ,k_m,i)$ . Suppose, for a contradiction, that $\mathrm {T} \nvdash \phi (k_1,\dots ,k_m)$ . By Fact 3.3(1),

$$ \begin{align*} \mathrm{I}\Sigma_n + \mathrm{Th}_{\Pi_n}(\mathbb{N}) \vdash \lnot \mathrm{Prf}_{\mathrm{T}}(\ulcorner \phi(k_1,\dots,k_m)\urcorner,p), \end{align*} $$

for all p. It follows that

$$ \begin{align*} \mathrm{I}\Sigma_n + \mathrm{Th}_{\Pi_n}(\mathbb{N}) \vdash \forall y \leq i \lnot \mathrm{Prf}_{\mathrm{T}}(\ulcorner \phi(k_1,\dots,k_m) \urcorner, y)\text{,} \end{align*} $$

so $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _n + \mathrm {Th}_{\Pi _n}(\mathbb {N}) \vdash \phi (k_1,\dots ,k_m)$ , and $\mathrm {T} \vdash \phi (k_1,\dots ,k_m)$ .

Conversely, suppose $\mathrm {T} \vdash \phi (k_1,\dots ,k_m)$ , and let p be a proof of $\phi (k_1,\dots ,k_m)$ in $\mathrm {T}$ . Then $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _n + \mathrm {Th}_{\Pi _n}(\mathbb {N}) \vdash \mathrm {Prf}_{\mathrm {T}}(\ulcorner \phi (k_1,\dots ,k_m)\urcorner , p)$ . It follows that

$$ \begin{align*} \mathrm{I}\Sigma_n + \mathrm{Th}_{\Pi_n}(\mathbb{N}) \vdash \forall y \leq z\lnot \mathrm{Prf}_{\mathrm{T}}(\ulcorner \phi(k_1,\dots,k_m)\urcorner, y) \rightarrow z < p\text{.} \end{align*} $$

Suppose, for a contradiction, that $\lnot R(k_1,\dots ,k_m)$ . Then for all i,

$$ \begin{align*} \mathrm{I}\Sigma_n + \mathrm{Th}_{\Pi_n}(\mathbb{N}) \vdash \lnot \pi(k_1,\dots,k_m,i)\text{.} \end{align*} $$

It follows that $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _n + \mathrm {Th}_{\Pi _n}(\mathbb {N}) \vdash \lnot \exists z < p \pi (k_1,\dots ,k_m,z)$ . We get

$$ \begin{align*} \mathrm{I}\Sigma_n + \mathrm{Th}_{\Pi_n}(\mathbb{N}) \vdash \lnot \exists z (\pi(k_1,\dots,k_m, z) \land \forall y \leq z \lnot \mathrm{Prf}_{\mathrm{T}}(\ulcorner \phi(k_1,\dots,k_m)\urcorner, y))\text{,} \end{align*} $$

whence $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _n + \mathrm {Th}_{\Pi _n}(\mathbb {N}) \vdash \lnot \phi (k_1,\dots ,k_m)$ , and $\mathrm {T} \vdash \lnot \phi (k_1,\dots ,k_m)$ .

It remains to show that $\mathrm {T} \vdash \phi (k_1,\dots ,k_m)$ iff $\phi (k_1,\dots ,k_m)$ is true. The implication from right to left is trivial, since $\phi $ is $\Sigma _{n+1}$ in $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _n$ and $\mathrm {Th}_{\Pi _n}(\mathbb {N})$ is $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -complete. For the other direction, suppose $\mathrm {T} \vdash \phi (k_1,\dots ,k_m)$ , and let p be the least such proof. Then

$$ \begin{align*} \mathrm{I}\Sigma_n + \mathrm{Th}_{\Pi_n}(\mathbb{N}) \vdash \forall y \leq z\lnot \mathrm{Prf}_{\mathrm{T}}(\ulcorner \phi(k_1,\dots,k_m)\urcorner, y) \rightarrow z < p\text{.} \end{align*} $$

Suppose further that there is no $i < p$ such that $\pi (k_1,\dots ,k_m,i)$ . Then, as before, $\mathrm {T} \vdash \lnot \phi (k_1,\dots ,k_m)$ , a contradiction. Thus there is an $i < p$ such that $\pi (k_1,\dots ,k_m,i)$ is true. Since p is minimal, $\forall y \leq i \lnot \mathrm {Prf}_{\mathrm {T}}(\ulcorner \phi (k_1,\dots ,k_m)\urcorner ,y)$ , so

$$ \begin{align*} \exists z (\pi(k_1,\dots,k_m,z) \land \forall y\leq z \lnot \mathrm{Prf}_{\mathrm{T}}(\ulcorner \phi(k_1,\dots,k_m) \urcorner, y))\end{align*} $$

is true, and therefore $\phi (k_1,\dots ,k_m)$ is true, as desired.

Bibliographical remark. The correct representability of $\Sigma _1$ relations in $\mathrm {Q}$ is due to Ehrenfeucht and Feferman [Reference Ehrenfeucht and Feferman10]. The proof above mimics Lindström's [Reference Lindström29] version of Shepherdson's [Reference Shepherdson42] proof of the same result.

Fact 3.3(2) follows directly from Lemma 3.7, and it only remains to give an argument for Fact 3.3(3). For this we need two more facts, the first being a version of Post’s theorem.

Fact 3.8 [Reference Post36].

A relation is $\Sigma _{n+1}$ iff it is r.e. in $\emptyset ^{(n)}$ .

Fact 3.9 (The selection theorem).

For each $\Sigma _{n+1}$ formula $\phi $ with exactly the variables $x_1,\dots ,x_k$ free, there is a $\Sigma _{n+1}$ formula $\mathrm {Sel}\{\phi \}$ with exactly the same free variables, such that:

  1. 1. $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _n \vdash \forall x_1,\dots ,x_k(\mathrm {Sel}\{\phi \}(x_1,\dots ,x_k) \rightarrow \phi (x_1,\dots ,x_k))$ ;

  2. 2. $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _n \vdash \forall x_1,\dots ,x_k,z(\mathrm {Sel}\{\phi \}(x_1,\dots ,x_k) \land \mathrm {Sel}\{\phi \}(x_1,\dots ,x_{k-1},z) \rightarrow x_k = z)$ ;

  3. 3. $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _n \vdash \forall x_1,\dots ,x_{k-1} (\exists x_k \phi (x_1,\dots ,x_k) \rightarrow \exists x_k \mathrm {Sel}\{\phi \}(x_1,\dots ,x_k))$ .

Proof sketch. We may assume that any given $\Sigma _{n+1}$ formula $\phi (x_1,\dots ,x_k)$ is on the form $\exists w \pi (x_1,\dots ,x_k,w)$ with $\pi \in \Pi _n$ . Let $(w)_i$ denote the ith element of the ordered pair coded by w, and define $\mathrm {Sel}\{\phi \}(x_1,\dots ,x_k)$ to be the formula

$$ \begin{align*} \exists w (\pi(x_1,\dots,x_{k-1},(w)_0,(w)_1) \land \forall u \leq w \lnot \pi(x_1,\dots,x_{k-1},(u)_0,(u)_1) \land (w)_0 = x_k)\text{.} \end{align*} $$

By Fact 3.6, this formula is equivalent in $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _n$ to a $\Sigma _{n+1}$ formula. Using $\Sigma _n$ -induction, it is easy to check that it has the three desired properties.

Bibliographical remark. Smoryński [Reference Smoryński45, theorem 0.6.9] provides a proof of the selection theorem for $n=0$ , and the generalization is straightforward. The numeration below of partial recursive functions is also based on the treatment in Section 0 of his book.

Fact 3.3(3) can now be established as follows: Let f be a k-ary partial n-recursive function; then the relation $f(x_1,\dots ,x_k) = y$ is $\Sigma _{n+1}$ by Fact 3.8. By Fact 3.3(2), this relation is correctly numerated in $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _n + \mathrm {Th}_{\Pi _n}(\mathbb {N})$ by some $\Sigma _{n+1}$ formula $\psi (x_1,\dots ,x_k,y)$ . Finally, by Fact 3.9, f is strongly represented in $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _n + \mathrm {exp} + \mathrm {Th}_{\Pi _n}(\mathbb {N})$ by the $\Sigma _{n+1}$ formula $\mathrm {Sel}\{\mathrm {Sat}_{\Sigma _{n+1}}\}(\ulcorner \psi \urcorner , x_1,\dots ,x_k, y)$ . This concludes the proof of Fact 3.3.

Convention. The partial n-recursive function with index e, $\varphi _e^n$ , can now be defined to be the function whose graph is defined by $\mathrm {Sel}\{\mathrm {Sat}_{\Sigma _{n+1}}\}(e, y_1, \dots , y_k, z)$ in $\mathbb {N}$ . The resulting enumeration is acceptable in the sense of Rogers [Reference Rogers39]. Whenever convenient, $\varphi _e^n(m_1,\dots ,m_i) = k$ is used as a shorthand for $\mathrm {Sel}\{\mathrm {Sat}_{\Sigma _{n+1}}\}(e, m_1,\dots , m_i, k)$ .

To wrap up this subsection, we sketch a proof of a formalized version of the second recursion theorem.

Fact 3.10 (Formalized second recursion theorem).

Let $f : \omega ^2 \to \omega $ be n-recursive. There is an $e \in \omega $ such that

$$ \begin{align*} \mathrm{I}\Sigma_n + \mathrm{exp} + \mathrm{Th}_{\Pi_n}(\mathbb{N}) \vdash \varphi^n_e(y) \simeq f(e,y)\text{.} \end{align*} $$

Proof. Let, by Fact 3.3(3), $\psi (x,y,z)$ be a $\Sigma _{n+1}$ formula strongly representing f in $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _n + \mathrm {exp} + \mathrm {Th}_{\Pi _n}(\mathbb {N})$ . Let, by Fact 3.4, $\unicode{x3b3} (y,z)$ be a formula such that

$$ \begin{align*} \mathrm{I}\Sigma_0 + \mathrm{exp} \vdash \unicode{x3b3}(y,z) \leftrightarrow \mathrm{Sel} \{ \mathrm{\mathrm{Sat}_{\Sigma_{n+1}}} \} (\ulcorner \psi \urcorner, \ulcorner \unicode{x3b3} \urcorner, y,z). \end{align*} $$

Then $e= \ulcorner \unicode{x3b3} \urcorner $ is as desired.

The recursion theorem is usually deployed in the following manner. Define an n-recursive function $f(z,x)$ in stages, using z as a parameter; the resulting function may differ depending on the choice of z. By the recursion theorem, there is then an n-index e such that $\varphi _e^n(x)$ coincides with $f(e,x)$ . This legitimates self-referential constructions where an index of f is being used in the construction of f itself.

Bibliographical remark. The recursion theorem is due to Kleene [Reference Kleene24, theorem XXVII]. Smoryński [Reference Smoryński45, theorem 0.6.12] shows how it can be formalized in (essentially) $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _0 + \mathrm {exp}$ for ( $0$ -)recursive functions.

3.2 Strong provability predicates

A central piece in the proof of Gödel’s incompleteness theorem for r.e. theories $\mathrm {T}$ is the use of formal provability predicates $\mathrm {Pr}_{\mathrm {T}}(x)$ , expressing “x is provable in $\mathrm {T}$ .” In the current setting, with $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -definable theories in focus, the corresponding strong provability predicates $\Pr _{\mathrm {T},\Sigma _{n+1}}(x)$ express “x is provable in $\mathrm {T}$ from true $\Sigma _{n+1}$ sentences.”Footnote 6 To define these predicates, we first need to introduce partial satisfaction predicates.

Fact 3.11 (Partial satisfaction predicates).

For each k and $\Gamma $ , there is a $k+1$ -ary $\Gamma $ formula $\mathrm {Sat}_{\Gamma }(x,x_1,\dots ,x_k)$ such that for every $\Gamma $ formula $\phi (x_1,\dots ,x_k)$ ,

$$ \begin{align*} \mathrm{I}\Sigma_0 + \mathrm{exp} \vdash \forall x_1,\dots,x_k(\phi(x_1,\dots,x_k) \leftrightarrow \mathrm{Sat}_{\Gamma}(\ulcorner \phi \urcorner, x_1,\dots,x_k))\text{.} \end{align*} $$

Hence there is also a $\Gamma $ formula $\mathrm {Tr}_\Gamma (x)$ such that for every $\Gamma $ sentence $\phi $ ,

$$ \begin{align*} \mathrm{I}\Sigma_0 + \mathrm{exp} \vdash \phi \leftrightarrow \mathrm{Tr}_\Gamma(\ulcorner \phi \urcorner)\text{.} \end{align*} $$

Bibliographical remark. Modern proofs of this fact are due to Hájek and Pudlák [Reference Hájek and Pudlák17] and Kaye [Reference Kaye22]. The use of partial satisfaction predicates, however, goes back to Hilbert and Bernays [Reference Hilbert and Bernays19].

Definition 3.12. Let, for each $\Gamma $ , $\mathrm {Prf}_{\mathrm {T},\Gamma }(x,y)$ be the formula

$$ \begin{align*} \exists z(z \in \Gamma \land \mathrm{Tr}_{\Gamma}(z) \land \mathrm{Prf}_{\mathrm{T}+z}(x,y))\text{.} \end{align*} $$

Let $\mathrm {Pr}_{\mathrm {T},\Gamma }(x) := \exists y \mathrm {Prf}_{\mathrm {T},\Gamma }(x,y)$ , and let $\mathrm {Con}_{\mathrm {T},\Gamma } := \lnot \mathrm {Pr}_{\mathrm {T},\Gamma }(\ulcorner \bot \urcorner )$ .

We are mainly interested in the predicates $\mathrm {Pr}_{\mathrm {T},\Sigma _{n+1}}(x)$ . These provability predicates have many similarities with the usual provability predicate. Firstly, if $\mathrm {T}$ is $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -definable, then $\mathrm {Pr}_{\mathrm {T},\Sigma _{n+1}}(x)$ is $\Sigma _{n+1}$ , and $\mathrm {Con}_{\mathrm {T},\Sigma _{n+1}}$ consequently $\Pi _{n+1}$ . Secondly, they satisfy provable $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -completeness and Löb’s derivability conditions. These notions also have their roots with Hilbert and Bernays [Reference Hilbert and Bernays19]; see also [Reference Feferman11, theorem 5.4 and corollary 5.5]. The versions presented here are extracted from [Reference Beklemishev1, propositions 2.10 and 2.11] and [Reference Smoryński45, lemma 3.3.7].

Fact 3.13 (Provable $\Sigma _{m+1}$ -completeness).

Let $\mathrm {T}$ be a $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -definable theory, and let $\sigma (x_1,\dots ,x_k)$ be any $\Sigma _{m+1}$ formula. Then

$$ \begin{align*} \mathrm{I}\Sigma_0 + \mathrm{exp} \vdash \forall x_1,\dots,x_k(\sigma(x_1,\dots,x_k)\rightarrow \mathrm{Pr}_{\mathrm{T},\Sigma_{m+1}}(\ulcorner \sigma(\dot{x}_1,\dots,\dot{x}_k)\urcorner))\text{.} \end{align*} $$

Fact 3.14 (Löb conditions).

If $\mathrm {T}$ is a $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -definable extension of $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _0 + \mathrm {exp}$ , then, for each $m\geq 0$ , and for all sentences $\phi $ , $\psi $ ,

  1. L1. if $\mathrm {T}\vdash \phi $ , then $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _n + \exp + \mathrm {Th}_{\Pi _n}(\mathbb {N}) \vdash \mathrm {Pr}_{\mathrm {T},\Sigma _{m+1}}(\ulcorner \phi \urcorner )$ ;

  2. L2. $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _0 + \mathrm {exp} \vdash \mathrm {Pr}_{\mathrm {T},\Sigma _{m+1}}(\ulcorner \phi \urcorner ) \land \mathrm {Pr}_{\mathrm {T},\Sigma _{m+1}}(\ulcorner \phi \rightarrow \psi \urcorner ) \rightarrow \mathrm {Pr}_{\mathrm {T},\Sigma _{m+1}}(\ulcorner \psi \urcorner )$ ;

  3. L3. $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _0 + \mathrm {exp} \vdash \mathrm {Pr}_{\mathrm {T},\Sigma _{m+1}}(\ulcorner \phi \urcorner ) \rightarrow \mathrm {Pr}_{\mathrm {T},\Sigma _{m+1}}(\ulcorner \mathrm {Pr}_{\mathrm {T},\Sigma _{m+1}}(\ulcorner \phi \urcorner )\urcorner )$ .

Similar statements also hold for formulae:

  1. L1’. if $\mathrm {T}\vdash \forall x \phi (x)$ , then $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _n + \exp + \mathrm {Th}_{\Pi _n}(\mathbb {N}) \vdash \forall x \mathrm {Pr}_{\mathrm {T},\Sigma _{m+1}}(\ulcorner \phi (\dot {x}) \urcorner )$ ;

  2. L2’. $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _0 + \mathrm {exp} \vdash \forall x (\mathrm {Pr}_{\mathrm {T},\Sigma _{m+1}}(\ulcorner \phi (\dot {x}) \urcorner ) \land \mathrm {Pr}_{\mathrm {T},\Sigma _{m+1}}(\ulcorner \phi (\dot {x}) \rightarrow \psi (\dot {x})\urcorner ) \rightarrow \mathrm {Pr}_{\mathrm {T},\Sigma _{m+1}}(\ulcorner \psi (\dot {x}) \urcorner ))$ ;

  3. L3’. $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _0 + \mathrm {exp} \vdash \forall x (\mathrm {Pr}_{\mathrm {T},\Sigma _{m+1}}(\ulcorner \phi (\dot {x}) \urcorner ) \rightarrow \mathrm {Pr}_{\mathrm {T},\Sigma _{m+1}}(\ulcorner \mathrm {Pr}_{\mathrm {T},\Sigma _{m+1}}(\ulcorner \phi (\dot {x}) \urcorner )\urcorner ))$ .

The stronger background theory used in items L1. and L1’. is enough to ensure the numerability of the $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -definable theory $\mathrm {T}$ . For r.e. theories $\mathrm {T}$ , $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _0 + \mathrm {exp}$ suffices.

We now turn our attention to the bounded provability predicates that feature prominently in the sequel. Consider again the $\Sigma _{n+1}$ formula $\mathrm {Pr}_{\mathrm {T},\Sigma _{n+1}}(x)$ for a $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -definable $\mathrm {T}$ . We may assume that there is a $\Pi _n$ formula $\pi (x,y)$ such that

$$ \begin{align*} \mathrm{I}\Sigma_n \vdash \mathrm{Pr}_{\mathrm{T},\Sigma_{n+1}}(x) \leftrightarrow \exists y \pi(x,y)\text{.} \end{align*} $$

Let $\mathrm {Pr}_{\mathrm {T},\Sigma _{n+1}}^k(x)$ be the formula $\exists z \leq k \pi (x,z)$ .Footnote 7 Then, by Fact 3.6, this formula is $\Pi _n$ in $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _n$ , and therefore decidable in $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _n + \mathrm {exp} + \mathrm {Th}_{\Pi _n}(\mathbb {N})$ .Footnote 8 As a consequence, we have strong reflection properties for the bounded proof predicates.

Fact 3.15 (Uniform small reflection).

Let $\mathrm {T}$ be a $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -definable, consistent extension of $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _0 + \mathrm {exp}$ . For each $\phi (x)$ and k, we have:

$$ \begin{align*} \mathrm{I}\Sigma_n + \mathrm{exp} + \mathrm{Th}_{\Pi_{n}(\mathbb{N})}\vdash \forall x (\mathrm{Pr}_{\mathrm{T},\Sigma_{n+1}}^k(\ulcorner\phi(\dot{x})\urcorner) \rightarrow \phi(x))\text{.} \end{align*} $$

Bibliographical remark. A forerunner to this reflection principle is proved by Feferman [Reference Feferman12, lemma 2.18]. The generalization to $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -definable theories is straightforward; see also [Reference Hájek and Pudlák17, lemma III.4.40] for some middle ground: reflection for proofs from true $\Sigma _{n+1}$ sentences for r.e. theories.

Fact 3.16 (Formalized small reflection).

Let $\mathrm {T}$ be a $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -definable, consistent extension of $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _{n+1}$ . Then we have:

$$ \begin{align*} \mathrm{I}\Sigma_0 + \mathrm{exp} \vdash \forall \phi \forall z\mathrm{Pr}_{\mathrm{T},\Sigma_{n+1}}(\ulcorner \mathrm{Pr}_{\mathrm{T},\Sigma_{n+1}}^{\dot{z}}(\ulcorner \phi \urcorner) \rightarrow \phi\urcorner)\text{.} \end{align*} $$

Bibliographical remark. Verbrugge & Visser [Reference Verbrugge and Visser46] show how the small reflection principle can be formalized in (theories weaker than) $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _0 + \mathrm {exp}$ . I am grateful to one of the referees for pointing out a crucial error in an earlier statement of this fact.

3.3 Model theory of arithmetic

The remainder of this section concerns the model theory of arithmetic, building up to a characterization of $\Pi _n$ -conservativity in the spirit of Orey, Hájek, Guaspari, and Lindström. A first step toward that goal is the following miniaturization of the arithmetized completeness theorem in the style of McAloon [Reference McAloon31, theorems 1.7 and 2.2].

Fact 3.17 (The arithmetized completeness theorem).

Fix $m\leq n$ . If $\mathcal {M} \models \mathrm {I}\Sigma _{n+1}$ , and $\mathrm {T}$ is a theory that is $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -definable in $\mathcal {M}$ such that $\mathcal {M} \models \mathrm {Con}_{\mathrm {T},\Pi _m}$ , then there is a $\Sigma _m$ -elementary end-extension of $\mathcal {M}$ satisfying $\mathrm {T}$ .

The proof of the arithmetized completeness theorem rests on the following version of the low basis theorem by Hájek & Pudlák [Reference Hájek and Pudlák17, corollary I.3.10(1)]:

Fact 3.18 (Low basis theorem).

Provably in $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _{n+1}$ , each dyadic unbounded $\Delta _{n+1}$ tree has an unbounded $LL_{n+1}$ branch.

Here, a tree is a set of finite binary sequences that is closed under taking initial segments. A branch through a tree is a subtree that is linearly ordered under the relation “being an initial segment of.” See [Reference Hájek and Pudlák17, chap. I.3(b)] for more details. A definition of the class $LL_{n+1}$ used in the statement of the low basis theorem can be found in [Reference Hájek and Pudlák17, chap. I.2(d)]. The only properties of $LL_{n+1}$ sets that are used in the proof of the arithmetized completeness theorem are that $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _{n+1}$ proves induction for $\Sigma _1(LL_{n+1})$ sets, and that every set recursive in an $LL_{n+1}$ set is itself $LL_{n+1}$ [Reference Hájek and Pudlák17, I.2.78–79)].

For the proof of the arithmetized completeness theorem, we also rely on $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _{n+1}$ being able to define formalized versions of syntactic and semantic notions such as “formula,” “term,” “theory,” “satisfaction,” and “model,” so that the relevant constructions can be carried out within $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _{n+1}$ itself. The reader is again referred to [Reference Hájek and Pudlák17], especially Chapter I.4, for a detailed development of these concepts. The generalization to $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -definable theories is straightforward, and fits safely within $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _{n+1}$ .

Proof of the arithmetized completeness theorem.

Fix $m\leq n$ . Let $\mathcal {M} \models \mathrm {I}\Sigma _{n+1}$ and let $\mathrm {T}$ be a theory $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -definable in $\mathcal {M}$ such that $\mathcal {M}\models \mathrm {Con}_{\mathrm {T},\Pi _{m}}$ . Reason in $\mathcal {M}$ :

Since $\mathrm {T}$ is $\Sigma _{n+1}$ and we have $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _{n+1}$ , we may assume $\mathrm {T}$ to be $\Pi _n$ -defined and Henkinized. Let $\psi _0,\psi _1,\dots $ be an enumeration of all sentences. Define a dyadic tree T by

$s \in T$ iff there is no $p \leq s $ such that p is a proof of contradiction in $\mathrm {T}$ from the true $\Pi _{m}$ sentences plus $\{ \psi _i^{(s)_i} : i < l(s)\}$ .

The proof relation for $\mathrm {T} + \mathrm {Th}_{\Pi _{m}}(\mathcal {M})$ is $\Pi _{n}$ in $\mathcal {M}$ , so the tree T is at most $\Delta _{n+1}$ in $\mathcal {M}$ . Then $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _{n+1}$ suffices to show that T is unbounded, so by Fact 3.18 there is an unbounded $LL_{n+1}$ branch $B = \{b_0,b_1,\dots \}$ through T.

Let $\hat {\mathrm {T}} = \{ \psi _i : b_i = 1\}$ . Then $\hat {\mathrm {T}}$ is recursive in the $LL_{n+1}$ branch B, and is therefore $LL_{n+1}$ itself. A term model $\mathcal {K}$ satisfying $\mathrm {T} + \mathrm {Th}_{\Pi _{m}}(\mathcal {M})$ can then be read off $\hat {\mathrm {T}}$ in the usual way. Finally, note that $\mathcal {K}$ is recursive in $\hat {\mathrm {T}}$ and therefore $LL_{n+1}$ . Using induction for $\Sigma _1(LL_{n+1})$ (provided by $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _{n+1}$ ), we can now define an $LL_{n+1}$ embedding f of $\mathcal {M}$ onto an initial segment of $\mathcal {K}$ by letting $f(0) = 0^{\mathcal {K}}$ and $f(x+1) =$ the $\mathcal {K}$ -successor of $f(x)$ .

The next few facts are used in the proof of the generalized Orey–Hájek characterization.

Fact 3.19 (Overspill).

Let $\mathcal {M} \models \mathrm {I}\Sigma _{n+1}$ . Suppose that $a \in M$ and that $\phi (x,y)$ is a $\Sigma _0(\Sigma _{n+1})$ formula such that $\mathcal {M} \models \phi (k,a)$ for all $k\in \omega $ . Then there is a $b \in M \setminus \omega $ such that $\mathcal {M} \models \forall x \leq b \phi (x,a)$ .

Bibliographical remark. The notion of overspill is originally due to Robinson [Reference Robinson38], while the hierarchical version stated here is from [Reference Hájek and Pudlák17, corollary IV.1.16].

Fact 3.20. If $\mathcal {M}$ is a non-standard model of $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _{n+1}$ , and $\phi (x)$ is a $\Sigma _{n+1}$ formula which may include parameters from $\mathcal {M}$ , then $\{ k \in \omega : \mathcal {M} \models \phi (k)\}$ is coded in $\mathcal {M}$ .

It follows that if $\mathcal {M} \models \mathrm {I}\Sigma _{n+1}$ , then $\mathrm {Th}_{\Sigma _{n+1}}(\mathcal {M})$ is coded in $\mathcal {M}$ .

Fact 3.21 [Reference McAloon32], cf. [Reference D'Aquino8].

If $\mathcal {M}$ is a countable non-standard model of $\mathrm {I}\Delta _0$ , and $\mathrm {T}$ is $\Sigma _1$ -sound, then for every non-standard $c \in M$ , there is a non-standard initial segment of $\mathcal {M}$ below c that is a model of $\mathrm {T}$ .

Fact 3.22 (Refined Friedman embedding theorem).

If $\mathcal {M}$ and $\mathcal {N}$ are countable non-standard models of $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _{n+1}$ then the following are equivalent:

  1. 1. $\mathcal {M}$ is embeddable as a $\Sigma _n$ -elementary initial segment of $\mathcal {N}$ ;

  2. 2. $\mathrm {SSy}(\mathcal {M}) = \mathrm {SSy}(\mathcal {N})$ and $\mathrm {Th}_{\Sigma _{n+1}}(\mathcal {M}) \subseteq \mathrm {Th}_{\Sigma _{n+1}}(\mathcal {N})$ .

Bibliographical remark. This refinement of Friedman’s [Reference Friedman, Mathias and Rogers13] embedding theorem for $n=0$ is due to Ressayre [Reference Ressayre and Simpson37, theorem 1.I] and Dimitracopoulos and Paris [Reference Dimitracopoulos and Paris9, corollary 2.4], independently. The hierarchical generalization is straightforward, and has been worked out by Cornaros [Reference Cornaros6, corollary 15].

We are now ready to prove the final fact: an excerpt of a generalization of the Orey–Hájek–Guaspari–Lindström characterization of interpretability. For extensions of $\mathrm {PA}$ , the equivalence of 1. and 3. is due to Guaspari [Reference Guaspari15, theorem 6.5(1)]. The equivalence of 1. and 2. for finitely axiomatizable theories seems to have been known to experts for some time, while the equivalence of 2. and 3. for r.e. extensions of fragments of $\mathrm {PA}$ is stated without proof by Blanck and Enayat [Reference Blanck and Enayat4, theorem 2.11]. With the previous facts of this section in place, the generalization to $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -definable theories presents no further difficulties.

Fact 3.23 (OHGL characterization).

Let $\mathrm {S}$ and $\mathrm {T}$ be $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -definable, consistent extensions of $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _{n+1}$ , and suppose that $\mathrm {S}$ is also $\Pi _n$ -complete. The following are equivalent:

  1. 1. $\mathrm {S}$ is $\Pi _{n+1}$ -conservative over $\mathrm {T}$ ;

  2. 2. for all $k\in \omega $ , $\mathrm {T} \vdash \mathrm {Con}_{\mathrm {S},\Sigma _{n+1}}^k$ ;

  3. 3. every countable model $\mathcal {M}$ of $\mathrm {T}$ with $\mathrm {S} \in \mathrm {SSy}(\mathcal {M})$ has a $\Sigma _n$ -elementary extension to a model of $\mathrm {S}$ .

Proof. 1. $\Rightarrow $ 2. Suppose that $\mathrm {S}$ is $\Pi _{n+1}$ -conservative over $\mathrm {T}$ . By Fact 3.15 and $\Pi _n$ -completeness of $\mathrm {S}$ , $\mathrm {S} \vdash \mathrm {Con}_{\mathrm {S},\Sigma _{n+1}}^k$ for all $k\in \omega $ . But $\mathrm {Con}_{\mathrm {S},\Sigma _{n+1}}^k$ is at most $\Pi _{n+1}$ , so $\mathrm {T} \vdash \mathrm {Con}_{\mathrm {S},\Sigma _{n+1}}^k$ for all $k \in \omega $ .

2. $\Rightarrow $ 3. Suppose $\mathrm {T} \vdash \mathrm {Con}_{\mathrm {S},\Sigma _{n+1}}^k$ for all $k \in \omega $ . Let $\mathcal {M}$ be a countable model of $\mathrm {T}$ and suppose that $\mathrm {S} \in \mathrm {SSy}(\mathcal {M})$ . Since $\mathrm {T}$ extends $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _{n+1}$ , it follows that $\mathrm {Con}_{\mathrm {S},\Sigma _{n+1}}^k$ is at most $\Pi _{n+1}$ , and we can use overspill to get $\mathcal {M} \models \mathrm {Con}_{\mathrm {S},\Sigma _{n+1}}^c$ for some non-standard $c\in M$ . By Fact 3.21, there is a submodel $\mathcal {M}_0 \models \mathrm {PA}$ of $\mathcal {M}$ , all of whose elements are below c, and there is some non-standard a below c that codes $\mathrm {Th}_{\Sigma _{n+1}}(\mathcal {M})$ . This ensures that $\mathcal {M}_0 \models \mathrm {Con}_{\mathrm {S} + \{m:m\varepsilon a\}}$ , so Fact 3.17 guarantees the existence of an end-extension $\mathcal {K}$ of $\mathcal {M}_0$ , satisfying $\mathrm {S} + \{m:m\varepsilon a\}$ and therefore also $\mathrm {S} + \mathrm {Th}_{\Sigma _{n+1}}(\mathcal {M})$ .

At this point, the situation is that $\mathrm {SSy}(\mathcal {M}) = \mathrm {SSy}(\mathcal {M}_0) = \mathrm {SSy}(\mathcal {K})$ , $\mathcal {M}$ and $\mathcal {K}$ are countable, and $\mathrm {Th}_{\Sigma _{n+1}}(\mathcal {M}) \subseteq \mathrm {Th}_{\Sigma _{n+1}}(\mathcal {K})$ . Then Fact 3.22 ensures that $\mathcal {M}$ can be embedded as a $\Sigma _n$ -elementary initial segment of $\mathcal {K}$ .

3. $\Rightarrow $ 1. Prove the contrapositive statement by assuming that $\mathrm {S}$ is not $\Pi _{n+1}$ -conservative over $\mathrm {T}$ . Then there is a $\Pi _{n+1}$ sentence $\pi $ such that $\mathrm {S} \vdash \pi $ but $\mathrm {T}+ \lnot \pi $ is consistent. Let $\mathcal {M} \models \mathrm {T}+ \lnot \pi $ . If $\mathcal {K} \models \mathrm {S}$ were a $\Sigma _n$ -elementary extension of $\mathcal {M}$ , then $\mathcal {K}$ would satisfy both $\pi $ and $\lnot \pi $ , a contradiction.

4 Applications

The goal of this section is to prove a handful of hierarchical incompleteness results, using the tools we reviewed in the previous one. The first such result stems from Mostowski [Reference Mostowski34, theorem 2], who proved that whenever $\{\mathrm {T}_i: i \in \omega \}$ is an r.e. family of consistent, r.e. theories extending $\mathrm {Q}$ , then there is a $\Pi _1$ formula that is simultaneously independent over these theories. Here, we understand the concept of an independent formula in the following way:

Definition 4.24. A formula $\xi (x)$ is independent over $\mathrm {T}$ if, for every $g : \omega \to \{0,1\}$ , the theory $\mathrm {T} + \{ \xi (k)^{g(k)}\}$ is consistent. Recall that $\xi (k)^0= \lnot \xi (k)$ and $\xi (k)^1 = \xi (k)$ .

While one of Mostowski’s accomplishments was the simultaneous independence over a whole r.e. family of theories, this aspect of his result is deliberately ignored here. Instead, we focus on how to construct formulae independent over $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -definable theories.

Theorem 4.25. Let $\mathrm {T}$ be a $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -definable, $\Sigma _n$ -sound extension of $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _n + \mathrm {exp}$ . Then there is a $\Sigma _{n+1}$ formula $\xi (x)$ that is independent over $\mathrm {T}$ .

Proof. Define a function $f(x)$ by the stipulation that $f(m) = k$ iff there is a proof p of $\varphi ^n_m(m) \neq k$ in $\mathrm {T}$ , and for each $q<p$ and $k_0 \leq k$ , q is not a proof of $\varphi ^n_m(m) \neq k_0$ in $\mathrm {T}$ .

Since $\mathrm {T}$ is $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -definable, there is a deductively equivalent $\Pi _n$ -definition of $\mathrm {T}$ . Hence, the relation $f(x) = y$ is r.e. in $\emptyset ^{(n)}$ , and therefore partial n-recursive. Let e be an n-index for f, and let $\xi (x)$ be the formula

$$ \begin{align*} \exists z (\varphi^n_e(e) = z \land \mathrm{Sat}_{\Sigma_{n+1}}(z,x))\text{.} \end{align*} $$

Since $\mathrm {T}$ extends $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _n$ , we may assume that both $\varphi ^n_x(y) = z$ and $\xi (x)$ are equivalent in $\mathrm {T}$ to $\Sigma _{n+1}$ formulae. The proof that $\xi (x)$ is as desired has two parts. The first part shows that $\mathrm {T} + \varphi ^n_e(e) = k$ is consistent for each $k\in \omega $ .

Suppose, for a contradiction, that $\mathrm {T} + \varphi ^n_e(e) = k$ is inconsistent for some $k\in \omega $ . We may assume that k is the least such number. Then $\mathrm {T} \vdash \varphi ^n_e(e) \neq k$ with some minimal proof p, so $f(e) = \varphi ^n_e(e) = k$ by definition. With $\mathrm {T}$ extending $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _n$ , we have $\mathrm {T} + \mathrm {Th}_{\Pi _{n}}(\mathbb {N}) \vdash \varphi ^n_e(e) = k$ by Fact 3.3(3). But then $\mathrm {T} + \mathrm {Th}_{\Pi _{n}}(\mathbb {N})$ is inconsistent, which by Fact 3.2 contradicts the assumption that $\mathrm {T}$ is $\Sigma _n$ -sound. Hence the theory $\mathrm {T} + \varphi ^n_e(e) = k$ is consistent for any choice of $k \in \omega $ .

In this final part of the proof, we show that $\xi (x)$ is independent over $\mathrm {T}$ . Let g be any function from $\omega $ to $\{0,1\}$ and let $X = \{ \xi (k)^{g(k)} : k\in \omega \}$ . Let Y be any finite subset of X, and let Z be the set $\{k: \xi (k) \in Y\}$ . Let $\zeta (x) := x \varepsilon a$ , where a is a code for the finite set Z; then $\zeta $ binumerates Z in $\mathrm {Q}$ .

Reason in the consistent theory $\mathrm {T} + \varphi ^n_e(e) = \ulcorner \zeta \urcorner $ :

If $\xi (x)$ , then $\varphi ^n_e(e) = z \land \mathrm {Sat}_{\Sigma _{n+1}}(z,x)$ for some z. But z is unique and $\varphi ^n_e(e) = \ulcorner \zeta \urcorner $ , so $\mathrm {Sat}_{\Sigma _{n+1}}(\ulcorner \zeta \urcorner ,x)$ and therefore $\zeta (x)$ .

Conversely, observe that since $\varphi ^n_e(e) = \ulcorner \zeta \urcorner $ , $\xi (x)$ follows from $\zeta (x)$ by Fact 3.11 and $\exists $ -introduction.

Hence the theory $\mathrm {T} + \forall x (\xi (x) \leftrightarrow \mathrm {Sat}_{\Sigma _{n+1}}(\ulcorner \zeta \urcorner ,x))$ is consistent. If $k \in Z$ , then $\mathrm {T} \vdash \mathrm {Sat}_{\Sigma _{n+1}}(\ulcorner \zeta \urcorner ,k)$ , so $\mathrm {T} + \forall x (\xi (x) \leftrightarrow \mathrm {Sat}_{\Sigma _{n+1}}(\ulcorner \zeta \urcorner ,x)) \vdash \xi (k)$ , and similarly for $k \notin Z$ . Hence the consistent theory $\mathrm {T} + \forall x (\xi (x) \leftrightarrow \mathrm {Sat}_{\Sigma _{n+1}}(\ulcorner \zeta \urcorner ,x))$ proves all the sentences in Y, so $\mathrm {T} + Y$ is consistent. By compactness, it follows that $\mathrm {T} + X$ is consistent, and therefore $\xi (x)$ is independent over $\mathrm {T}$ .

The Gödel–Rosser incompleteness Theorem 1.1 for arithmetically definable theories follows immediately from the result above. While the generalization to arithmetically definable theories is new, the basic idea of this proof is due to Kripke [Reference Kripke26, corollary 1.1], who used it to rederive Mostowski’s result from his own theorem on the existence of flexible formulae. Here, we understand flexibility in the following sense:

Definition 4.26. A formula $\unicode{x3b3} (x)$ is flexible for $\Gamma $ over $\mathrm {T}$ if, for every $\delta (x) \in \Gamma $ , the theory $\mathrm {T} + \forall x (\unicode{x3b3} (x) \leftrightarrow \delta (x))$ is consistent.

The definitions used by Kripke obscure the original content of his theorem, but, in hindsight, his proof yields that for every consistent, r.e. extension $\mathrm {T}$ of $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _0 + \mathrm {exp}$ , there is a $\Sigma _{n+1}$ formula that is flexible for $\Sigma _{n+1}$ over $\mathrm {T}$ . Striving for some unification, we derive a hierarchical version of Kripke’s theorem by generalizing a result of Lindström’s [Reference Lindström28, proposition 2]; which in turn is a generalization of both Mostowski’s and Kripke’s results, as well as of Scott’s famous lemma used to realize countable Scott sets as standard systems of models of $\mathrm {PA}$ [Reference Scott and Dekker41].

Theorem 4.27. Let $\mathrm {T}$ be a $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -definable extension of $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _{m} + \mathrm {exp}$ , with $m\geq n$ . For every $\Sigma _m$ formula $\phi (x)$ , there is a $\Sigma _{m+1}$ formula $\unicode{x3b3} (x)$ such that for every $g : \omega \to \{0,1\}$ , if

$$ \begin{align*} \mathrm{T}_g = \mathrm{T} + \{ \phi(k) ^{g(k)}:k\in\omega\} \end{align*} $$

is $\Sigma _n$ -sound, then $\unicode{x3b3} (x)$ is flexible for $\Sigma _{m+1}$ over $\mathrm {T}_g$ .

Proof. Fix n and let $\phi (x) \in \Sigma _m$ , with $m\geq n$ . Let $f(s,\ulcorner \eta \urcorner ) = \ulcorner \sigma \urcorner $ iff the following holds:

  1. 1. s is binary sequence of length $k + 1$ ;

  2. 2. there is a proof p of $\lnot \forall x (\eta (x) \leftrightarrow \sigma (x))$ in $\mathrm {T} + \phi (0)^{(s)_0} + \dots + \phi (k)^{(s)_k}$ ;

  3. 3. for every $q<p$ and any $\ulcorner \sigma _0\urcorner \leq \ulcorner \sigma \urcorner $ , q is not a proof of $\lnot \forall x (\eta (x) \leftrightarrow \sigma _0(x))$ in $\mathrm {T} + \phi (0)^{(s)_0} + \dots + \phi (k)^{(s)_k}$ .

Here $(s)_k$ denotes the kth element of the sequence s.

Since $\mathrm {T}$ is $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -definable, there is a deductively equivalent $\Pi _n$ -definition of $\mathrm {T}$ . Hence, the relation $f(x,y) = z$ is r.e. in $\emptyset ^{(n)}$ , and therefore partial n-recursive. Let e be an n-index for f.

Let $\mathrm {Seq}_\phi (x)$ be the formula

$$ \begin{align*} \forall y < l(x)(y \varepsilon x \leftrightarrow \phi(y)), \end{align*} $$

where $l(x)$ denotes the length of x (this is the formula “x is a $l(x)$ -piece of $\phi $ ”). Whenever $\phi (x)$ is $\Sigma _m$ , $\mathrm {Seq}_\phi (x)$ is $\Sigma _0(\Sigma _m)$ , and since $\mathrm {T} \vdash \mathrm {I}\Sigma _m$ , it is $\Delta _{m+1}$ in $\mathrm {T}$ . Let, by Fact 3.4, $\unicode{x3b3} (x)$ be such that

$$ \begin{align*} \mathrm{T} \vdash \forall x(\unicode{x3b3}(x) \leftrightarrow \exists s \exists z(\mathrm{Seq}_\phi(s) \land \varphi^n_e(s, \ulcorner \unicode{x3b3} \urcorner)= z \land \mathrm{Sat}_{\Sigma_{m+1}}(z,x)))\text{.} \end{align*} $$

Since $\mathrm {T} \vdash \mathrm {I}\Sigma _m$ and $m\geq n$ , the formula strongly representing f in $\mathrm {T} + \mathrm {Th}_{\Pi _{n}}(\mathbb {N})$ is equivalent to a $\Sigma _{n+1}$ formula in $\mathrm {T}$ . It follows that $\unicode{x3b3} (x)$ is equivalent to a $\Sigma _{m+1}$ formula in $\mathrm {T}$ .

Suppose, for a contradiction, that there is a $g : \omega \to \{0,1\}$ and a $\sigma (x) \in \Sigma _{m+1}$ such that $\mathrm {T}_g$ is $\Sigma _n$ -sound, but $\mathrm {T}_g + \forall x(\unicode{x3b3} (x) \leftrightarrow \sigma (x))$ is inconsistent. If there are more than one such $\sigma (x)$ for a given g, consider the one with the least Gödel number. There is then an initial subsequence s of g, of length $k+1$ for some k, such that p is a proof of $\lnot \forall x(\unicode{x3b3} (x) \leftrightarrow \sigma (x))$ in $\mathrm {T} + \phi (0)^{(s)_0} + \dots + \phi (k)^{(s)_k}$ . Let s be the initial subsequence of g corresponding to the least such p.

It is now clear that neither p nor any $q <p$ can be a proof of $\lnot \forall x(\unicode{x3b3} (x) \leftrightarrow \sigma _0(x))$ in $\mathrm {T} + \phi (0)^{(s)_0} + \dots + \phi (k)^{(s)_k}$ for any formula $\sigma _0(x)$ whose Gödel number is less than $ \ulcorner \sigma \urcorner $ . Hence, by definition, $f(s,\ulcorner \unicode{x3b3} \urcorner ) = \ulcorner \sigma \urcorner $ , and by Fact 3.3,

$$ \begin{align*} \mathrm{T} + \mathrm{Th}_{\Pi_{n}}(\mathbb{N}) \vdash \varphi^n_e(s, \ulcorner \unicode{x3b3} \urcorner) = \ulcorner \sigma\urcorner\text{.} \end{align*} $$

By choice of s, $\mathrm {T}_g \vdash \mathrm {Seq}_\phi (\ulcorner s \urcorner )$ , so $\mathrm {T}_g + \mathrm {Th}_{\Pi _{n}}(\mathbb {N}) \vdash \forall x (\unicode{x3b3} (x) \leftrightarrow \sigma (x))$ by an argument similar to that in the proof of Theorem 4.25. Then $\mathrm {T}_g +\mathrm {Th}_{\Pi _{n}}(\mathbb {N})$ is inconsistent, contradicting the assumption that $\mathrm {T}_g$ was $\Sigma _n$ -sound.

By choosing $\phi (x)$ as $\top $ in the construction above, we obtain the expected hierarchical version of Kripke’s theorem. A similar, but not entirely correct, claim is made by Blanck [Reference Blanck3, theorem 4.8].

Corollary 4.28. Let $\mathrm {T}$ be a $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -definable, $\Sigma _n$ -sound extension of $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _n + \mathrm {exp}$ . For all $m\geq n$ , there is a $\Sigma _{m+1}$ formula $\unicode{x3b3} (x)$ that is flexible for $\Sigma _{m+1}$ over $\mathrm {T}$ .

Mostowski’s theorem for r.e. extensions of $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _0 + \mathrm {exp}$ then follows immediately by using the method described in the proof of Theorem 4.25. A similar argument also yields Scott’s lemma.

The next objective is to show how the hierarchical version of Kripke’s theorem can be formalized in $\Pi _n$ -complete extensions of $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _{n+1}$ . A similar, but not entirely correct, claim is made by Blanck [Reference Blanck3, theorem 5.8]. The present proof is a minor modification of an argument of Blanck [Reference Blanck3, theorem 5.1].

Theorem 4.29. Let $\mathrm {S}$ be a $\Pi _n$ -complete, consistent extension of $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _{n+1}$ , and let $\mathrm {T}$ be $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -definable. For all $m \geq n$ , there is a $\Sigma _{m+1}$ formula $\unicode{x3b3} (x)$ such that:

  1. 1. $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _{n+1} \vdash \mathrm {Con}_{\mathrm {T},\Sigma _{n+1}} \rightarrow \forall x \lnot \unicode{x3b3} (x)$ ;

  2. 2. if $\sigma (x) \in \Sigma _{m+1}$ , then every model of $\mathrm {S} + \mathrm {Con}_{\mathrm {T},\Sigma _{n+1}}$ has a $\Sigma _n$ -elementary extension to a model of $\mathrm {T} + \forall x (\unicode{x3b3} (x) \leftrightarrow \sigma (x))$ .

Proof. Fix n, and let $\phi (x,z)$ be the $\Sigma _{n+1}$ formula $\mathrm {Pr}_{\mathrm {T},\Sigma _{n+1}}(\ulcorner \varphi ^n_{\dot {x}}(\dot {x}) \neq \dot {z} \urcorner )$ . Let e be the Gödel number of $\phi (x,z)$ .

Recall that $\varphi ^n_x(y) = z$ is shorthand for $\mathrm {Sel}\{\mathrm {Sat}_{\Sigma _{n+1}}\}(x,y,z)$ . Therefore, by Fact 3.9(1) we have

(1) $$ \begin{align} \mathrm{I}\Sigma_{n+1} \vdash \forall z (\varphi^n_{e}(e) = z \rightarrow \mathrm{Sat}_{\Sigma_{n+1}}(e,e,z))\text{,} \end{align} $$

so by construction of $\phi (x,z)$ and choice of e,

(2) $$ \begin{align} \mathrm{I}\Sigma_{n+1} \vdash \forall z (\varphi^n_{e}(e) = z \rightarrow \mathrm{Pr}_{\mathrm{T},\Sigma_{n+1}}(\ulcorner \varphi^n_{e}(e) \neq \dot{z}\urcorner))\text{.} \end{align} $$

By Fact 3.13,

(3) $$ \begin{align} \mathrm{I}\Sigma_{n+1} \vdash \forall z (\varphi^n_{e}(e) = z \rightarrow \mathrm{Pr}_{\mathrm{T},\Sigma_{n+1}}(\ulcorner \varphi^n_{e}(e) = \dot{z}\urcorner))\text{,} \end{align} $$

so (2) and (3) together with Fact 3.14 give

(4) $$ \begin{align} \mathrm{I}\Sigma_{n+1} \vdash \forall z (\mathrm{Con}_{\mathrm{T},\Sigma_{n+1}} \rightarrow \varphi^n_{e}(e) \neq z)\text{.} \end{align} $$

Now, observe that

(5) $$ \begin{align} \mathrm{I}\Sigma_{n+1} \vdash \exists z \lnot \mathrm{Con}_{\mathrm{T} + \varphi^n_{e}(e) = \dot{z},\Sigma_{n+1}} \leftrightarrow \exists z \mathrm{Pr}_{\mathrm{T},\Sigma_{n+1}}(\ulcorner \varphi^n_{e}(e) \neq \dot{z}\urcorner)\text{.} \end{align} $$

By construction of $\phi (x,z)$ , the right hand side of the equivalence of (5) is identical to $\exists z \phi (e,z)$ , and by Fact 3.11, we have

(6) $$ \begin{align} \mathrm{I}\Sigma_{n+1} \vdash \exists z \phi(e,z) \leftrightarrow \exists z \mathrm{Sat}_{\Sigma_{n+1}}(e,e,z)\text{.} \end{align} $$

Therefore, by Fact 3.9(3) and the convention on $\varphi ^n_{e}$ , (5) gives

(7) $$ \begin{align} \mathrm{I}\Sigma_{n+1} \vdash \exists z \lnot \mathrm{Con}_{\mathrm{T} + \varphi^n_{e}(e) = \dot{z},\Sigma_{n+1}} \leftrightarrow \exists z (\varphi^n_{e}(e) = z)\text{.} \end{align} $$

Together with (4), this implies

(8) $$ \begin{align} \mathrm{I}\Sigma_{n+1} \vdash \forall z (\mathrm{Con}_{\mathrm{T},\Sigma_{n+1}} \rightarrow \mathrm{Con}_{\mathrm{T}+\varphi^n_{e}(e) = \dot{z},\Sigma_{n+1}})\text{.} \end{align} $$

Then the $\Sigma _{m+1}$ formula $\unicode{x3b3} (x) := \exists z (\varphi ^n_{e}(e) = z \land \mathrm {Sat}_{\Sigma _{m+1}}(z,x))$ is as desired, and the first part of the theorem follows directly from (4). For the second part, let $\mathcal {M}$ be any model of $\mathrm {S} + \mathrm {Con}_{\mathrm {T},\Sigma _{n+1}}$ , and let $\sigma (x)$ be any $\Sigma _{m+1}$ formula. By (8), we immediately get $\mathcal {M} \models \mathrm {Con}_{\mathrm {T}+\varphi ^n_e(e) = \ulcorner \sigma \urcorner ,\Sigma _{n+1}}$ . Moreover, since $\mathrm {S}$ is a $\Pi _n$ -complete extension of $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _{n+1}$ , and $\mathrm {T}$ is $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -definable, the theory $\mathrm {T} + \varphi ^n_e(e) = \ulcorner \sigma \urcorner $ is $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -definable in $\mathcal {M}$ , using Craig’s trick. By Fact 3.17, there is then a $\Sigma _{n}$ -elementary end-extension $\mathcal {K}$ of $\mathcal {M}$ that satisfies $\mathrm {T} + \varphi ^n_e(e) = \ulcorner \sigma \urcorner $ . Since $\mathcal {K}$ satisfies $\varphi ^n_e(e) =\ulcorner \sigma \urcorner $ , it follows that $\mathcal {K} \models \forall x (\unicode{x3b3} (x) \leftrightarrow \sigma (x))$ , as desired.

Corollary 4.30. Let $\mathrm {S}$ be a $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -definable, $\Pi _n$ -complete, and consistent extension of $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _{n+1}$ , and let $\unicode{x3b3} (x)$ be as in the proof of Theorem 4.29. Then, for each $\sigma (x) \in \Sigma _{m+1}$ with $m\geq n$ , $\mathrm {S} + \forall x (\unicode{x3b3} (x) \leftrightarrow \sigma (x))$ is $\Pi _{n+1}$ -conservative over $\mathrm {S} + \mathrm {Con}_{\mathrm {S},\Sigma _{n+1}}$ .

The next theorem has a different flavor than the earlier ones, and is a generalization of Woodin’s theorem on the universal algorithm [Reference Woodin, Heller and Woodin48]; see also [Reference Blanck and Enayat4, theorem 3.1]. A version for r.e. extensions of $\mathrm {PA}$ is independently due to Hamkins [Reference Hamkins18, theorem 18], and the proof presented here uses a method that I learned from Shavrukov. The particular Solovay-style construction used in the proof is similar to the ones used by Berarducci [Reference Berarducci2] and Japaridze [Reference Japaridze21].

Theorem 4.31. Let $\mathrm {T}$ be a $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -definable, $\Pi _n$ -complete, and consistent extension of $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _{n+1}$ . There is a $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -definable set $W_e$ such that:

  1. 1. $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _{n+1} + \mathrm {Th}_{\Pi _n}(\mathbb {N}) \vdash \text {``}W_e\text { is finite''}$ ;

  2. 2. $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _{n+1} + \mathrm {Th}_{\Pi _n}(\mathbb {N}) \vdash \mathrm {Con}_{\mathrm {T},\Sigma _{n+1}} \rightarrow W_e = \emptyset $ ;

  3. 3. for each countable model $\mathcal {M} \models \mathrm {T}$ , if s is an $\mathcal {M}$ -finite set such that $\mathcal {M} \models W_e \subseteq s$ , then there is a $\Sigma _n$ -elementary extension of $\mathcal {M}$ satisfying $\mathrm {T} + W_e = s$ .

Proof. The set $W_e$ is defined (in $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _{n+1} + \mathrm {Th}_{\Pi _n}(\mathbb {N})$ and in the real world) as follows, using the formalization of the recursion theorem (Fact 3.10). At the same time, an auxiliary function $r(x)$ is defined.

Stage $0$ : Set $W_{e,0} = \emptyset $ , and $r(0) = \infty $ .Footnote 9

Stage $x+1$ : Suppose $r(x) = m$ . There are two cases:

Case A: s is a finite set such that $s \supseteq W_{e,x}$ , $k < m$ , and x witnesses a $\Sigma _{n+1}$ formula $\sigma (s)$ such that k is a proof in $\mathrm {T} + \mathrm {Th}_{\Sigma _{n+1}}(\mathbb {N})$ of $\forall t (\sigma (t) \rightarrow W_e \neq t)$ . Should there be more than one eligible candidate for either k or s, then choose the least such k, and then the least s corresponding to that k. Then set $W_{e,x+1} = s$ and $r(x+1) = k$ .

Case B: Otherwise, set $W_{e,x+1} = W_{e,x}$ and $r(x+1) = m$ .

Let $W_e = \bigcup _x W_{e,x}$ .

To prove 1., reason as follows: Since the proof relation for $\mathrm {T} + \mathrm {Th}_{\Sigma _{n+1}}(\mathbb {N})$ is $\Delta _{n+1}$ in $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _{n+1} + \mathrm {Th}_{\Pi _n}(\mathbb {N})$ , $W_e$ is r.e. in $\emptyset ^{(n)}$ , and therefore $\Sigma _{n+1}$ by Fact 3.8. Provably in $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _{n+1} + \mathrm {Th}_{\Pi _n}(\mathbb {N})$ , we have that $W_{e,x+1} \supseteq W_{e,x}$ , and $r(x+1) \leq r(x)$ , so by the $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -least number principle (which is available thanks to $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -induction), there is a limit $R = \lim _x r(x)$ . For each x with $W_{e,x+1} \neq W_{e,x}$ , $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _{n+1}+ \mathrm {Th}_{\Pi _n}(\mathbb {N})$ proves $r(x+1) < r(x)$ , whence there can only be finitely many such x. So $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _{n+1} + \mathrm {Th}_{\Pi _n}(\mathbb {N})\vdash \text {``}W_e \text { is finite.''}$

Note also that $\mathrm {T} \vdash R> k$ for all $k \in \omega $ . To show this, fix $k \in \omega $ and argue in $\mathrm {T}$ :

Suppose $R \leq k$ . Let y be minimal such that $r(y+1) = R$ . Then $W_e = W_{e,y+1} = s$ for some s such that R is a proof in $\mathrm {T} + \mathrm {Th}_{\Sigma _{n+1}}(\mathbb {N})$ of $\forall t (\sigma (t) \rightarrow W_e \neq t)$ , where $\sigma (s)$ is a true $\Sigma _{n+1}$ formula.

But, by Fact 3.15,

since $\forall t (\sigma (t) \rightarrow W_e \neq t)$ is proved from a true $\Sigma _{n+1}$ sentence with a proof not exceeding k, it must be true. Since $\sigma (s)$ is true, $W_e \neq s$ is also true, and the contradiction proves $R> k$ .

To prove 2., argue for the contrapositive statement in $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _{n+1} +\mathrm {Th}_{\Pi _{n}}(\mathbb {N})$ :

If $W_e = s \neq \emptyset $ , then $\mathrm {Pr}_{\mathrm {T},\Sigma _{n+1}}^m(\ulcorner \forall t (\sigma (t) \rightarrow W_e \neq t)\urcorner )$ for some m and some true $\Sigma _{n+1}$ formula $\sigma (s)$ . The relation $s \subseteq W_{e,x}$ is $\Delta _{n+1}$ by Fact 3.6(3), so $\mathrm {Pr}_{\mathrm {T},\Sigma _{n+1}}(\ulcorner \dot {s} \subseteq W_e \urcorner )$ follows by Fact 3.13. Now reason inside $\mathrm {Pr}_{\mathrm {T},\Sigma _{n+1}}$ :

There is some $u = W_e$ with $u \supseteq s$ , so by construction, $\sigma '(u)$ is true, and $\mathrm {Pr}_{\mathrm {T},\Sigma _{n+1}}^k(\ulcorner \forall t (\sigma '(t) \rightarrow W_e \neq t)\urcorner )$ for some $k\leq m$ and some $\Sigma _{n+1}$ formula $\sigma '(u)$ .

Apply Fact 3.16, and continue reasoning inside $\mathrm {Pr}_{\mathrm {T},\Sigma _{n+1}}$ :

Then $\forall t (\sigma '(t) \rightarrow W_e \neq t)$ and $\sigma '(u)$ , so $W_e \neq u$ .

Then $\mathrm {Pr}_{\mathrm {T},\Sigma _{n+1}}(\ulcorner \exists u(W_e = u \land W_e \neq u)\urcorner )$ , so Fact 3.14 gives $\lnot \mathrm {Con}_{\mathrm {T},\Sigma _{n+1}}$ as desired.

To prove 3., first fix $m \in \omega $ . By Fact 3.15, there is a proof k in $\mathrm {T}$ of

$$ \begin{align*} \forall t (\mathrm{Pr}^m_{\mathrm{T}, \Sigma_{n+1}}(\ulcorner W_e \neq \dot{t} \urcorner) \rightarrow W_e \neq t)\text{.} \end{align*} $$

Now reason in $\mathrm {T}$ :

Consider any finite $s \supseteq W_e$ , and suppose x is a proof $\leq m$ of $W_e \neq s$ in $\mathrm {T} + \mathrm {Th}_{\Sigma _{n+1}}(\mathbb {N})$ . Then $s \supseteq W_{e,x+1}$ , and therefore $r(x+1) \leq k$ by construction of $r(x+1)$ : here $\mathrm {Pr}^m_{\mathrm {T}, \Sigma _{n+1}}(\ulcorner W_e \neq \dot {s} \urcorner )$ is $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _{n+1}$ -equivalent to a true $\Sigma _{n+1}$ sentence playing the role of $\sigma (s)$ . But $k < R \leq r(x+1)$ , and the contradiction proves $\mathrm {Con}^m_{\mathrm {T} + W_e = \dot {s}, \Sigma _{n+1}}$ .

Therefore for all $m\in \omega $ , $\mathrm {T} \vdash \forall s \supseteq W_e \,\, \mathrm {Con}^m_{\mathrm {T} + W_e=\dot {s}, \Sigma _{n+1}}$ .

For the final part of the proof, let $\mathcal {M}$ be any countable model of $\mathrm {T}$ , and let s be any $\mathcal {M}$ -finite set such that $\mathcal {M} \models W_e \subseteq s$ . Since $\mathrm {T}$ is a $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -definable, $\Pi _{n}$ -complete extension of $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _{n+1}$ , Facts 3.11 and 3.20 imply that $\mathrm {T} + \mathrm {Th}_{\Sigma _{n+1}}(\mathcal {M}) + W_e = s \in \mathrm {SSy}(\mathcal {M})$ . Since $\mathrm {T} \vdash \mathrm {Con}^m_{\mathrm {T} + W_e = \dot {s}, \Sigma _{n+1}}$ for all $m\in \omega $ , Fact 3.23 guarantees the existence of a $\Sigma _n$ -elementary extension of $\mathcal {M}$ satisfying $\mathrm {T} + W_e = s$ , which concludes the proof of the theorem.

Corollary 4.32. With $\mathrm {T}$ as in Theorem 4.31, $\lnot \mathrm {Con}_{\mathrm {T},\Sigma _{n+1}}$ is $\Pi _{n+1}$ -conservative over $\mathrm {T}$ .

Proof. Every countable model of $\mathrm {T}$ has a $\Sigma _n$ -elementary extension satisfying $W_e \neq \emptyset $ , and therefore also $\mathrm {T} + \lnot \mathrm {Con}_{\mathrm {T},\Sigma _{n+1}}$ by the theorem. By Fact 3.23, the conclusion follows.Footnote 10

The set $W_e$ defined in Theorem 4.31 can be used to prove results of a more Kripkean variety, by using the information contained in $W_e$ as codes for other sets. The next result is of this kind, and improves on Theorem 7.21 of [Reference Blanck3] by generalizing to arithmetically definable theories. A version for r.e. extensions of $\mathrm {PA}$ is independently due to Hamkins [Reference Hamkins18, theorem 22(1)], who also noted that there is a very short proof of it from Theorem 4.31.

Theorem 4.33. Let $\mathrm {T}$ be a $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -definable, $\Pi _n$ -complete, and consistent extension of $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _{n+1}$ . For all $m \geq n$ , there is a $\Sigma _{m+2}$ formula $\unicode{x3b3} (x)$ such that:

  1. 1. $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _{n+1} + \mathrm {Th}_{\Pi _n}(\mathbb {N}) \vdash \mathrm {Con}_{\mathrm {T},\Sigma _{n+1}} \rightarrow \forall x \lnot \unicode{x3b3} (x)$ ;

  2. 2. for every $\sigma (x) \in \Sigma _{m+2}$ , every countable model of $\mathrm {T}$ has a $\Sigma _n$ -elementary extension satisfying $\mathrm {T} + \forall x(\unicode{x3b3} (x) \leftrightarrow \sigma (x))$ .

Proof sketch. It is straightforward to adapt the construction in the proof of Theorem 4.31 to produce an $\mathcal {M}$ -finite binary sequence $S_e$ , rather than a set [Reference Blanck and Enayat4, Reference Hamkins18, Reference Woodin, Heller and Woodin48]. Assume an enumeration of $\Sigma _{m+2}$ formulae in which every $\Sigma _{m+2}$ formula occurs infinitely often, and that every finite binary sequence codes such a formula. Let $\unicode{x3b3} (x)$ be the formula $\exists z (S_e = z \land \mathrm {Sat}_{\Sigma _{m+2}}(z,x))$ . Since $S_e = z$ is at most $\Sigma _{n+2}$ and $m \geq n$ , it follows that $\unicode{x3b3} (x)$ is $\Sigma _{m+2}$ .

Pick any $\sigma (x) \in \Sigma _{m+2}$ , let $\mathcal {M}$ be any countable model of $\mathrm {T}$ and let s be $S_e$ as calculated within $\mathcal {M}$ . By assumption on the enumeration of $\Sigma _{m+2}$ formulae, there is an $\mathcal {M}$ -finite sequence $t \supseteq s$ such that t codes $\ulcorner \sigma (x) \urcorner $ . By the sequence version of Theorem 4.31, there is a $\Sigma _n$ -elementary extension $\mathcal {K}$ of $\mathcal {M}$ in which $S_e =t$ . Then $\unicode{x3b3} (x)$ coincides with $\sigma (x)$ in $\mathcal {K}$ , and therefore is as desired.

The question remains to which extent $m+2$ can be replaced by $m+1$ in the statement of Theorem 4.33. Some partial answers are already available: Theorem 4.31 gives a positive answer restricted to $\Sigma _{m+1}$ formulae $\sigma (x)$ whose extension is $\mathcal {M}$ -finite and for which $\mathcal {M} \models \forall x (\unicode{x3b3} (x) \rightarrow \sigma (x))$ , while Theorem 4.29 can be seen as giving a partial positive answer that is restricted to models of $\mathrm {T} + \mathrm {Con}_{\mathrm {T},\Sigma _{n+1}}$ . Blanck [Reference Blanck3, chap. 7.4] lists several other partial answers to this question in a setting where $\mathrm {T}$ is an r.e. extension of $\mathrm {PA}$ and $n=0$ . By using the principles of Section 3 of the present paper, those constructions can be easily modified to give equally unsatisfactory answers in the present setting. The salient remaining question is as follows:

Question. Let $\mathrm {T}$ be a $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -definable, $\Pi _n$ -complete, and consistent extension of $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _{n+1}$ . Is there a $\Sigma _{n+1}$ formula $\unicode{x3b3} (x)$ such that:

  1. 1. $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _{n+1} + \mathrm {Th}_{\Pi _n}(\mathbb {N}) \vdash \mathrm {Con}_{\mathrm {T},\Sigma _{n+1}} \rightarrow \forall x \lnot \unicode{x3b3} (x)$ ;

  2. 2. for every $\sigma (x) \in \Sigma _{n+1}$ , every countable model of $\mathrm {T} + \forall x(\unicode{x3b3} (x) \rightarrow \sigma (x))$ has a $\Sigma _n$ -elementary extension satisfying $\mathrm {T} + \forall x(\unicode{x3b3} (x) \leftrightarrow \sigma (x))$ ?

5 Discussion

By inspecting the results proved in Section 4, we see two classes of $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -definable theories emerging:

  1. 1. $\Sigma _n$ -sound extensions of $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _n + \mathrm {exp}$ ; and

  2. 2. $\Pi _n$ -complete, consistent extensions of $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _{n+1}$ .

As suggested by Theorem 1.1, theories in the first class are strong enough for some applications. These include the results of Salehi & Seraji [Reference Salehi and Seraji40] and Kikuchi & Kurahashi [Reference Kikuchi and Kurahashi23], together with Theorems 4.25 and 4.27 (and their corollaries) of the present paper. This success relies on the fact that $\Sigma _n$ -soundness of $\mathrm {T}$ guarantees the consistency of $\mathrm {T} + \mathrm {Th}_{\Pi _{n}}(\mathbb {N})$ , in which the n-recursive functions can be strongly represented by a formula that is $\Sigma _{n+1}$ in the presence of $\Sigma _n$ -induction.

The second class of theories is required to prove results on $\Sigma _n$ -elementary extensions of models of $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -definable theories, for example results on partial conservativity via the OHGL characterization (Theorem 4.29 and onward). In these cases, $\Pi _n$ -completeness of $\mathrm {T}$ ensures that every model $\mathcal {M}$ of $\mathrm {T}$ is a $\Sigma _n$ -elementary extension of the standard model, which in the presence of $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -induction suffices for $\mathrm {T}$ to be $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -definable in $\mathcal {M}$ by using Craig’s trick. $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -induction is also used to prove the arithmetized completeness theorem for $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -definable theories, which is indispensable for constructing the $\Sigma _n$ -elementary extensions.

The facts listed in Section 3 should be enough to derive hierarchical generalizations for arithmetically definable extensions of fragments of $\mathrm {PA}$ of many of the theorems in, e.g., Lindström’s classic Aspects of Incompleteness [Reference Lindström29]. As suggested by the results in the present paper, some of these generalizations would apply only to $\Pi _n$ -complete theories, while in other cases mere $\Sigma _n$ -soundness would do. Others might not be prone to such generalizations at all, as shown by Kurahashi [Reference Kurahashi27, theorem 11] and pointed out to me by one of the referees. In fact, it would be interesting to see which of the results in, say, the first five chapters of Aspects (where the results do not depend on $\mathrm {T}$ being essentially reflexive) that are prone to such generalizations, using these principles.

Acknowledgments

This paper is based in part on some ideas that were left half-baked in the author’s doctoral thesis [Reference Blanck3], written under the supervision of Ali Enayat. In particular, not entirely correct claims similar to Corollary 4.28 and Theorem 4.29 have appeared there. I am grateful to Ali Enayat, Fredrik Engström, Joel David Hamkins, Aleksandre Maskharashvili, and Volodya Shavrukov for inspiration, discussion, and guidance. The comments of two excellent anonymous referees have greatly helped improve the paper by suggesting the correct statements of some of the theorems, and by weeding out a number of false claims in an earlier version of this paper.

Footnotes

1 The literature is not in total agreement about this convention. We follow Hájek and Pudlák [Reference Hájek and Pudlák17], while for example Lindström [Reference Lindström29] has it the other way around. The mnemonic here is that the superscript $1$ signals that $\phi $ occurs positively.

2 One of the referees pointed out that even $\Pi _n$ -completeness is sometimes not enough for a straightforward hierarchical generalization to hold: see, e.g., Theorem 11 of [Reference Kurahashi27] for an example.

3 As is well known, $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _1$ proves the totality of the exponential function, so the additional axiom $\mathrm {exp}$ is only required in the case $n=0$ to make sure that the partial satisfaction predicates used to establish the particularly nice properties are well-behaved. A similar remark applies also to many of the following facts, and to the statements of some of the theorems in Section 4.

4 For $n=0$ , it is known that $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _1$ suffices to show that the Craigified theory is deductively equivalent to the original one [Reference Hájek and Pudlák17, remark III.2.30]. By contrast, this is not true of $\mathrm {I}\Sigma _0 + \mathrm {exp}$ [Reference Visser, Gosh and Szymanik47].

5 In fact, only the weaker principle of $\Sigma _n$ -collection is required for this first item. However, collection plays no prominent role elsewhere in this paper.

6 Similar provability predicates, $\Pr _{\mathrm {T},\Pi _n}(x)$ appear in the literature under the name strong provability, n-provability, and oracle provability [Reference Beklemishev1, Reference Ignatiev20, Reference Kolmakov and Beklemishev25, Reference Visser, Gosh and Szymanik47]. The difference is usually only a matter of taste, since the theories $\mathrm {T} + \mathrm {Th}_{\Pi _n}(\mathbb {N})$ and $\mathrm {T} + \mathrm {Th}_{\Sigma _{n+1}}(\mathbb {N})$ are deductively equivalent, and under reasonable assumptions this is reflected also in the formalized notions $\mathrm {Pr}_{\mathrm {T},\Pi _{n}}(x)$ and $\mathrm {Pr}_{\mathrm {T},\Sigma _{n+1}}(x)$ . However, the relationship between the related notions $\mathrm {Pr}^k_{\mathrm {T},\Pi _{n}}(x)$ and $\mathrm {Pr}^k_{\mathrm {T},\Sigma _{n+1}}(x)$ (introduced below) is not as immediate, since there k bounds the length of the proof of x and the Gödel number of the additional true $\Pi _n$ or $\Sigma _{n+1}$ sentence used in the proof. Even though every $\Sigma _{n+1}$ -provable sentence has a $\Pi _n$ -proof, this proof might be much longer than the original one. We opt for the $\Sigma _{n+1}$ versions, since it helps in the proof of Fact 3.23 below, and since it makes (some of) the indices align nicely.

7 In the notation of, e.g., [Reference Lindström and Shavrukov30], $\mathrm {Pr}^k_{\mathrm {T},\Sigma _{n+1}}(x)$ would be written $k : \mathrm {Pr}_{\mathrm {T},\Sigma _{n+1}}(x)$ .

8 The additional axiom $\mathrm {exp}$ is again only required for $n=0$ , to handle the partial truth definition occurring in $\mathrm {Pr}_{\mathrm {T},\Sigma _{n+1}}$ . Remarks of this type will hereafter be omitted.

9 Here $\infty $ is a formal symbol that by definition is greater than all the natural numbers.

10 As pointed out by one of the referees, adapting Kreisel’s original proof of the $\Pi _1$ -conservativity of $\lnot \mathrm {Con}_{\mathrm {T}}$ over $\mathrm {T}$ is a simpler way to establish Corollary 4.32 than going via Theorem 4.31.

References

REFERENCES

Beklemishev, L. D. (2005). Reflection principles and provability algebras in formal arithmetic. Russian Mathematical Surveys, 60(2), 197268.10.1070/RM2005v060n02ABEH000823CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Berarducci, A. (1990). The interpretability logic of Peano arithmetic. The Journal of Symbolic Logic, 55(3), 10591089.10.2307/2274474CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Blanck, R. (2017). Contributions to the Metamathematics of Arithmetic: Fixed Points, Independence, and Flexibility. Ph.D. Thesis, University of Gothenburg, Gothenburg.Google Scholar
Blanck, R., & Enayat, A. (2017). Marginalia on a theorem of Woodin. The Journal of Symbolic Logic, 82(1), 359374.10.1017/jsl.2016.8CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chao, C., & Seraji, P. (2018). Gödel's second incompleteness theorem for ${\Sigma}_n$ -definable theories. Logic Journal of the IGPL, 26(2), 255257.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cornaros, C. (20XX). Versions of Friedman's theorem for fragments of PA. Unpublished manuscript.Google Scholar
Craig, W. (1953). On axiomatizability within a system. The Journal of Symbolic Logic, 18(1), 3032.10.2307/2266324CrossRefGoogle Scholar
D'Aquino, P. (1993). A sharpened version of McAloon's theorem on initial segments of models of IΔ0 . Annals of Pure and Applied Logic, 61, 4962.10.1016/0168-0072(93)90197-LCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dimitracopoulos, C., & Paris, J. (1988). A note on a theorem of H. Friedman. Zeitschrift für mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik, 34, 1317.10.1002/malq.19880340103CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ehrenfeucht, A., & Feferman, S. (1960). Representability of recursively enumerable sets in formal theories. Archiv für mathematische Logik und Grundlagenforschung, 5(1–2), 3741.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Feferman, S. (1960). Arithmetization of metamathematics in a general setting. Fundamenta Mathematicae, 49, 3592.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Feferman, S., (1962). Transfinite recursive progressions of axiomatic theories. The Journal of Symbolic Logic, 27(3), 259316.10.2307/2964649CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Friedman, H. (1973). Countable models of set theories. InMathias, A. R. D. andRogers, H., editors. Cambridge Summer School in Mathematical Logic 1971. Springer Lecture Notes in Mathematics, Vol. 337. New York: Springer, pp. 539573.10.1007/BFb0066789CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grzegorczyk, A., Mostowski, A., & Ryll-Nardzewski, C. (1958). The classical and the $\omega$ -complete arithmetic. The Journal of Symbolic Logic, 23(2), 188206.10.2307/2964398CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Guaspari, D. (1979). Partially conservative extensions of arithmetic. Transactions of the American Mathematical Society, 254, 4768.10.1090/S0002-9947-1979-0539907-7CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hájek, P. (1977). Experimental logics and ${\Pi}_3^0$ theories. The Journal of Symbolic Logic, 42(4), 515522.10.2307/2271872CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hájek, P., & Pudlák, P. (1993). Metamathematics of First-Order Arithmetic. Perspectives in Mathematical Logic. Berlin, Germany: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hamkins, J. D. (2018). The modal logic of arithmetic potentialism and the universal algorithm. Preprint, arXiv:1801.04599.Google Scholar
Hilbert, D., & Bernays, P. (1934–1939). Grundlagen der Mathematik, Vols. 1–2. Berlin, Germany: Springer.Google Scholar
Ignatiev, K. N. (1993). On strong provability predicates and the associated modal logics. The Journal of Symbolic Logic, 58(1), 249290.10.2307/2275337CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Japaridze, G. (1994). A simple proof of arithmetical completeness for ${\Pi}_1$ -conservativity logic. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 35(3), 346354.10.1305/ndjfl/1040511342CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kaye, R. (1991). Models of Peano Arithmetic. Oxford Logic Guides, Vol. 15. Oxford, UK: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Kikuchi, M., & Kurahashi, T. (2017). Generalizations of Gödel's incompleteness theorems for ${\Sigma}_n$ -definable theories of arithmetic. The Review of Symbolic Logic, 10(4), 603616.10.1017/S1755020317000235CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kleene, S. C. (1952). Introduction to Metamathematics. Amsterdam, Netherlands: North-Holland.Google Scholar
Kolmakov, E., & Beklemishev, L. (2019). Axiomatization of provable $n$ -provability. The Journal of Symbolic Logic, 84(2), 849869.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kripke, S. A. (1962). “Flexible” predicates of formal number theory. Proceedings of the American Mathematical Society, 13(4), 647650.Google Scholar
Kurahashi, T. (2018). On partial disjunction properties of theories containing Peano arithmetic. Archive for Mathematical Logic, 57(7), 953980.10.1007/s00153-018-0618-3CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lindström, P. (1984). A note on independent formulas. In Notes on Formulas with Prescribed Properties in Arithmetical Theories. Philosophical Communications, Red Series, Vol. 25. Gothenburg: Göteborgs Universitet, pp. 15.Google Scholar
Lindström, P., (2003). Aspects of Incompleteness (second edition). Lecture Notes in Logic, Vol. 10. Natick, MA: A. K. Peters.Google Scholar
Lindström, P., & Shavrukov, V. Yu. (2008). The $\forall \exists$ theory of Peano ${\Sigma}_1$ sentences. Journal of Mathematical Logic, 8(2), 251280.10.1142/S0219061308000774CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McAloon, K. (1978). Completeness theorems, incompleteness theorems and models of arithmetic. Transactions of the American Mathematical Society, 239, 253277.10.1090/S0002-9947-1978-0487048-9CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McAloon, K, (1982). On the complexity of models of arithmetic. The Journal of Symbolic Logic, 47(2), 403415.10.2307/2273150CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Montague, R. (1962). Theories incomparable with respect to relative interpretability. The Journal of Symbolic Logic, 27(2), 195211.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mostowski, A. (1961). A generalization of the incompleteness theorem. Fundamenta Mathematicae, 49(2), 205232.10.4064/fm-49-2-205-232CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Poizat, B. (2000). A Course in Model Theory. New York: Springer.10.1007/978-1-4419-8622-1CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Post, E. L. (1948). Degrees of recursive unsolvability. Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society, 54(7), 641642.Google Scholar
Ressayre, J.-P. (1987). Nonstandard universes with strong embeddings, and their finite approximations. In Simpson, S., editor. Logic and Combinatorics. Contemporary Mathematics, Vol. 65. Providence, RI: American Mathematical Society, pp. 333358.10.1090/conm/065/891257CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Robinson, A. (1963). On languages which are based on non-standard arithmetic. Nagoya Mathematical Journal, 22, 83117.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rogers, H. Jr. (1967). Theory of Recursive Functions and Effective Computability. New York: McGraw-Hill.Google Scholar
Salehi, S., & Seraji, P. (2017). Gödel–Rosser's incompleteness theorem, generalized and optimized for definable theories. Journal of Logic and Computation, 27(5), 13911397.Google Scholar
Scott, D. (1962). Algebras of sets binumerable in complete extensions of arithmetic. InDekker, J. C. E., editor. Recursive Function Theory. Proceedings of Symposia in Pure Mathematics, Vol. 5. Providence, RI: American Mathematical Society, pp. 117121.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shepherdson, J. C. (1961). Representability of recursively enumerable sets in formal theories. Archiv für mathematische Logik und Grundlagenforschung, 5(3), 119127.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smoryński, C. (1977). ω-consistency and reflection. In Colloque International de Logique: Clermont-Ferrand, 18–25 Juillet 1975. Colloques internationaux du Centre National de la Recherche Scientifique, Vol. 249. Paris: Editions du C.N.R.S, pp. 167181.Google Scholar
Smoryński, C., (1981). Fifty years of self-reference in arithmetic. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 22(4), 357375.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smoryński, C., (1985). Self-Reference and Modal Logic. New York: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Verbrugge, R., & Visser, A. (1994). A small reflection principle for bounded arithmetic. The Journal of Symbolic Logic, 59(3), 785812.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Visser, A. (2015). Oracle bites theory. In Gosh, S, and Szymanik, J., editors. The Facts Matter. Essays on Logic and Cognition in Honour of Rineke Verbrugge. London, UK: College Publications, pp. 133147.Google Scholar
Woodin, W. H. (2011). A potential subtlety concerning the distinction between determinism and nondeterminism. In Heller, M., and Woodin, W. H., editors. Infinity: New Research Frontiers. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 119129.10.1017/CBO9780511976889.007CrossRefGoogle Scholar