Hostname: page-component-f554764f5-246sw Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-04-16T17:00:01.792Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

An Abductive Defence of Truthmaker Realism

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  18 March 2025

Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

This paper presents an abductive argument for realism and truthmaker realism as follows. A metaphysical theory is better if it ontologically accounts for truths better than its rivals (the Abductive Principle). Truthmaker realism gives us a better ontological account for truths than its antirealist truthmaker rivals (Abductive Step). So, truthmaker realism is better than antirealist rivals. It presents the truthmaker project as an abductive project which asks us what accounts best ontologically for our truths. Antirealisms, especially idealisms, fail against their realist rivals on various abductive criteria.

Truthmaker realism is plagued by three main objections. Presenting an abductive argument for realism does two important things. First, it dissolves the standard objections. Second, it shows how truthmaker realism is overall better motivated than antirealist, pluralist, and neutralist rivals. Simple truthmaker principles added to a plausible abductive package of principles give us a straightforward argument for realism and against antirealism or any neutralist middle ground.

Type
Research Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2025. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of The Royal Institute of Philosophy

1. Introduction

Truthmaker theory is a family of accounts about a relation between bearers of truth and veridicality (e.g., sentences, experiences, judgements) and the reality their veridicality asymmetrically depends on. Given the asymmetry, the truthmaking reality on which truths depend doesn't generally depend on these truths for their reality. The result: truthmaker theorists have assumed what I call ‘truthmaker-realism’, that they should be realists (rather than antirealists, especially idealists) about truthmakers (i.e., what make truthbearers true), holding, minimally, that there are mind-and-language-independent truthmakers, or stronger: that truthmakers should generally be mind-and-language-independent.Footnote 1 For instance, ‘Willows exist’ is made true by mind-and-language-independent willows, which don't depend for their existence on this truth. Early 21st century challenges (e.g., Beebee and Dodd, Reference Beebee and Dodd2005) to this truthmaking-realism coupling were assumed to challenge truthmaker theory itself. These challenges argued that because truthmaking is neither (a) necessary nor (b) sufficient for realism, and that (c) insisting on truthmaker-realism is question-begging against antirealist alternatives, truthmaker theory itself is unmotivated. This paper dissolves these challenges by presenting a novel abductive defence of ‘truthmaker-realism’ against truthmaker-antirealist rivals. It shifts the debate from requiring, as truthmaking-critics have, that truthmaker-realists should establish truthmaking's necessity and sufficiency for realism to exhorting that truthmaker-realists should defend themselves abductively against rivals. Thereby both truthmaker-realism and truthmaker theory itself are defended.

First, §2 sketches the abductive argument for truthmaker-realism and properly introduces the three challenges (a)–(c). §3 and §4 address (a) and (b) by arguing that even if truthmaking is neither necessary nor sufficient for realism, truthmaking and realism's close tie is maintained on abductive terms. §5 argues against (c), briefly arguing against a rival stance which underlies it: truthmaker-neutralism, that is, either agnosticism or principled neutrality about truthmakers’ metaphysical status (e.g., mind-independence). §6 presents two abductive arguments against truthmaker-realism's main antirealist rival: truthmaker-idealism. Together, §§2–6 introduce a new strategy for defending truthmaking and realism's close connection, truthmaker-realism, against its main rivals.

2. The Abductive Strategy for Truthmaker-Realism

The following are abductively important maxims which any theory should follow:

explanatory power: minimise brute truths, that is, leave as little truth unexplained as possible.

anti-ad-hoc-ery: do not make ad hoc additions to one's theory.

common knowledge consistency: maximise consistency with one's knowledge and our common knowledge.

All three are important maxims of theory choice. According to explanatory power, if theory T1 accounts for more truths than rival theory T2, then T1 is a better theory overall than T2; T1 leaves less truth unaccounted for or unexplained, that is, leaves us with fewer brute truths.Footnote 2 anti-ad-hoc-ery is important for it gives us a clear decision procedure: if T2 makes certain additions merely to deal with some problem or to satisfy a theoretical demand while T1 does not have to make additions to deal with the problems and theoretical demands, then T1 is preferable. It is also related to another key virtue:

independent motivations: the more independent reasons for an addition to a theory, the better motivated the addition.

By contrast, if an addition has no independent motivations, it is not properly motivated. anti-ad-hoc-ery and independent motivations go hand in hand.

common knowledge consistency is clearly important: clashing with common knowledge (or one's own knowledge) entails that something in the theory in question is false and there is strong evidence against it. So, a theory should aim to minimise clashes and maximise consistency. Following these maxims is key to the abductive defence of any theory in the face of its various explanatory tasks and in the face of theoretical rivals.

There has been much debate about the truthmaker-project's nature. I propose that it is an abductive project which adds an extra maxim to the abductively important maxims:

truthmaker-maxim: minimise ontologically brute truths, that is, provide a sufficient ontological basis for all relevant truths.

Since not all theories are theories of everything, that a theory leaves some truths without an ontological basis is not a problem for a theory, unless those truths are relevant to the theory. For instance, if it is part of a theory T that s is true, then s should ultimately be given a sufficient ontological basis according to T.Footnote 3 The truthmaker-maxim is related to explanatory power above. While the latter requires that a theory minimise brute truths by giving an explanation for as much truth as possible, the former is more demanding, asking for an ontological basis for all relevant truths.

Truthmakers are those entities which ontologically explain or account for truths. Asay (Reference Asay2020, §2.1), for instance, divides truthmaking into two rival approaches: explanatory truthmaking and truthmaking-as-ontological-accounting. He defends the latter but argues that even ontological truthmaker theorists can say that truthmaking explains truth (ibid., p. 44). Metaphysical theories are tested on how well they can account for truths: if theory T1 accounts for truths better than theory T2, then T1 is a better theory overall than T2.

Famously, earlier truthmaker theorists such as Bigelow (Reference Bigelow1988, p. 123), Armstrong (Reference Armstrong2004, p. 5), and Heil (Reference Heil2003, p. 61) explicitly tied truthmaking closely to realism, a general metaphysical view according to which there are mind-independent entities. What has worried critics especially is that they never actually argued for this connection. If we understand the project abductively, however, we can construct a novel, abductive way of understanding the famous statements and of arguing for truthmaker-realism and hence realism:

Premise 1: A metaphysical theory is better if it ontologically accounts for truths better than its rivals (the Abductive Principle).

Premise 2: Truthmaker-realism gives us a better ontological account for truths than its antirealist truthmaker rivals (the Abductive Step).

Therefore,

Conclusion: Truthmaker-realism is a metaphysically better theory than antirealist rivals.

Truthmaker-realism is the view that there are mind-independent truthmakers and that truthmakers are on the whole, exceptions aside, mind-independent in the relevant way. Some clarifications: (1) tables, for instance, are ‘mind-independent in the relevant way’ for realism, even though their existence depends on people designing them.Footnote 4 (2) The relevant realism here is general, not for instance relative to a ‘discourse’ (Cameron, Reference Cameron2008, p. 122) or ‘set of claims’ (Asay, Reference Asay2020, p. 159; Reference Asay2012, p. 389).Footnote 5 General forms of realism are contrasted with general antirealisms, which aren't discourse-relative but global. For instance, idealism claims that all things are mind-dependent in the relevant way, and globally deflationary neutralisms eschew metaphysics altogether. Defending general realism and articulating truthmaker-realism this way are important because of the recent resurgence of antirealisms, especially idealism.Footnote 6 (3) Truthmaker-realists think that some truths are made true by mind-independent truthmakers (e.g., truthmakers for ‘Some willows are shrubs’), or stronger: truthmakers are generally mind-independent; clear exceptions include truth about mind-dependent reality (e.g., ‘Fear exists’) and truthmaker-free truths (potentially, e.g., negative truths, see Schipper, Reference Schipper2018). Truthmaker-antirealists accept truthmakers but claim they're all mind-or-language-dependent: e.g., truthmaker-idealism takes truthmakers to be ideas. Truthmaker-antirealisms about specific domains (e.g., truths about morals, social constructions, mathematics) take their truthmakers to be mind-or-language-dependent; they are compatible with general truthmaker-realism: some truths may still have mind-independent truthmakers.

Critics of truthmaking, such as Dodd (Reference Dodd2002), Beebee (with Dodd) (Reference Beebee and Dodd2005) and MacBride (Reference MacBride, Beebee and Dodd2005, Reference MacBride and Zalta2020), argued that truthmaker-realism lacks motivation with three main objections: truthmaking is neither (a) necessary nor (b) sufficient for realism, and (c) insisting on truthmaker-realism is question-begging against antirealist-truthmaking. (a)–(c) are supported with simple, straightforward considerations.

Objection-a

realism without truthmaking: accepting any kind of truthmaker principle is, as Dodd (Reference Dodd2002, p. 83) has famously argued, a ‘hugely uncompulsory additional step’ for avoiding idealism or other non-realist views truthmaker theorists have attempted to undermine (e.g., phenomenalism, see Martin, Reference Martin1984). All we need to accept, Dodd (ibid.) explains, is that ‘the items to which we are ontologically committed by the things we say (viz. objects, events and–arguably–properties) are mind-independent [to] have a version of realism’; Tahko argues that ‘Realism can stand on its own [without truthmaking]’ (Reference Tahko and Calemi2015, p. 218);

Objection-b

antirealist truthmakers: the availability of alternative antirealist and neutral versions of truthmaking; as Cameron (Reference Cameron2008, pp. 116ff.) writes, ‘it's definitely not sufficient to be a realist that one be a truthmaker theorist, since one can simply be anti-realist about the truthmakers’, or Tahko: ‘truthmaking is a way to account for truth regardless of one's ontology’ as it can ‘offer an ontologically neutral way to account for truth’ (Reference Tahko and Calemi2015, p. 217, added emphasis); and

Objection-c

question-begging: using a truthmaker-realist-principle, or a truthmaker-principle that is congenial to realism, in arguing against versions of antirealism, is to beg the question against such views.

Presenting the truthmaker argument for realism as abductive, however, does two important things: it dissolves these standard objections, in the sense that (1) even if truthmaking is neither necessary nor sufficient for realism, it neither follows that truthmaker theory as a whole nor truthmaker-realism is unmotivated; and (2) it isn't question-begging: it provides independent reasons to prefer realist over antirealist truthmaking. I shall argue for (1) in §3 (realism without truthmaking) and §4 (antirealist truthmakers); and (2) in §5 (question-begging) and §6 where I illustrate the strategy with two anti-idealist abductive arguments. Doing (2), further, responds to the critics’ anti-truthmaking arguments that use the possibility of truthmaker-idealism against truthmaker-realism and truthmaking generally: truthmaker-idealism's mere possibility doesn't undermine truthmaker-realism, if truthmaker-realism is still abductively stronger. We thus respond to both truthmaker-idealists and anti-truthmaker-theorists.

A final point: truthmaker theorists and those sympathetic to the project have responded to these objections (a)–(c) not by addressing the objections head-on but by retreating to minimal, ‘ontologically neutral’ (Tahko, Reference Tahko and Calemi2015, §3, pp. 207–11) or pluralist, ecumenical versions of truthmaking (Asay, Reference Asay2022, passim; Reference Asay2020, pp. 22ff., §4; Schipper, Reference Schipper2016, §1.6–1.7), explicitly stating that truthmaking is compatible both with realism and antirealism. Since truthmaker theory itself is committed to neither realism nor antirealism, it is argued, truthmaker theorists should in fact be neutral about the nature of any given truthmakers. This is, plausibly, also behind the truthmaker-semantic strategies of Yablo (Reference Yablo2014), Fine (Reference Fine, Hale, Wright and Miller2017a), and others. Truthmaker-neutralism is another potential truthmaker-antirealist challenge to which I shall respond, in §5, in defence of truthmaker-realism on abductive grounds.

3. Objection-a: Realism without Truthmaking?

Against objection-a: even if critics such as Dodd are right that realism can be expressed independently of truthmaking, one cannot conclude then that truthmaker theory is not well motivated or that truthmaker-realism is false or not attractive. For an important question remains for any realist metaphysical theory: ‘What ontologically accounts for truth?’ If the theory does not identify the objects in its realist ontology as truthmakers, the ontological grounds, of truths, then what, according to the theory, does ontologically account for truths? Realists who do not also accept truthmaker-realism would leave much unaccounted for. Without such an account, they would score poorly on an important abductive measure for any good metaphysical theory: any ontologist needs ultimately to account ontologically for truths. Further, apple-realists who are not truthmaker-realists accept that there are apples but not that apples make claims such as ‘there are apples’ true. They would (i) need to account for the relationship between ‘there are apples’ and reality in another way, and (ii) explain why their account is better than those who say that apples make such claims true, especially given that their own account already accepts their existence.

They would then also fall short on abductive measures such as simplicity, elegance, and, importantly, relevance. The apple-realist truthmaker view, by contrast, scores high especially on relevance, but also simplicity and elegance (see Forster and Sober, Reference Forster and Sober1994, for a defence of simplicity and its relation to anti-ad-hoc-ery). For apples are clearly the most relevant worldly entities to account for the truth of ‘apples exist’, and appealing to apples as the truthmakers is elegantly simple compared to a complicated story, say, about sense-data or ideas in the minds of deities, especially when apples are available (see §6).

One might respond that this is a shallow response against critics such as Dodd, who accept that ‘apples exist’ is ontologically committed to apples but no truthmaker-ideology. However, this section argues that even if realism doesn't require truthmaking, truthmaker-realism is the abductively better realist position. A realist can reject truthmaker theory (e.g., Dodd), but unless for instance one's realist theory of ontological commitment is tied with a realist truthmaker theory, one still needs to say what accounts for the truths. Rejecting this question altogether seems abductively non-ideal, especially if one already has an ontology which one can use to answer the question ‘What accounts for truths such as “apples exist” or “this apple is spherical”?’. The alternative is to answer this question, saying what accounts for truths, for instance saying why only including spherical apples in one's ontology (as Dodd does) allows us to account for truths such as ‘this apple is spherical’. In the latter case, one is giving a truthmaker theory, despite likely rejecting necessitation and the standard truthmaker-ontology of states-of-affairs (Armstrong, Reference Armstrong1997) or particularised properties (Martin and Heil, Reference Martin and Heil1999, p. 45). Say one is realist about spherical apples: they are mind-independent. Then a realist view of spherical apples as truthmakers seems preferable both to rejecting the task of ontological accounting and to an antirealist view about what accounts for such truths. Note, I assume that it's controversial nowadays to insist that truthmaker-ideology essentially involves thinking that truthmakers must be non-mereological unities of objects and their properties – not even Armstrong held this for all truths, and Parsons (Reference Parsons1999) and Schipper (Reference Schipper2020, §1.1) argue that this view of truthmakers’ ontological category is non-compulsory (though see Dodd, Reference Dodd2002, pp. 74–75 against Parsons). This doesn't affect my defence of truthmaker-realism.

4. Objection-b: Non-realist Truthmakers?

Critics have made clear that precise formulations of the truthmaking relation itself, whether in terms of necessitation (viz., Armstrong) or supervenience (e.g., Bigelow and Lewis), are compatible with some forms of non-realism. According to

necessitation (nec): x makes p true if, and only if, in all the worlds in which p and x exist, p is true (see Merricks, Reference Merricks2007, p. 7).

Most now, except Asay (Reference Asay2020, ch. 3), would take necessitation only to be necessary (e.g., Schipper, Reference Schipper2021, §2; Reference Schipper2022a, p. 997). Supervenience accounts claim that

supervenience-t (sup): truths, the Ts, supervene on reality: so any change in the truths in terms of truth-value entails some change in reality (Bigelow, Reference Bigelow1988, pp. 133ff., 158ff.; Lewis, Reference Lewis1992, p. 218).

Antirealists can accept both nec and sup and just claim that all the x's which necessitate truths, and the reality on which truths supervene, are mind-, evidence-, or language-dependent entities.

Some antirealists, in fact, explicitly use the language of truthmaking to articulate their views; for instance, intuitionists following Brouwer and Heyting, such as Göran Sundholm (Reference Sundholm1994a, pp. 121–22; Reference Sundholm, Niiniluoto, Sintonen and Wolenski2004, pp. 449–51), think that the truthmakers for mathematical claims are proof-constructions.Footnote 7 One might generalise: all claims, also those about chairs and quarks, are made true by constructions, proof-like systems of evidence. Put idealistically: all truths supervene on or are necessitated only by minds and other mind-dependent truthmakers. I shall often focus on the relationship between truthmaking and idealism as the main antirealist rival in this paper, about which Bergmann famously writes: ‘the truth of S must be grounded ontologically. On this first move idealists and realists agree’ (Reference Bergmann1961, p. 229; see also Dodd, Reference Dodd2002, pp. 83–84; and Daly, Reference Daly, Beebee and Dodd2005, pp.95–97). Note, however, that when this is brought up in the literature (e.g., MacBride, Reference MacBride and Zalta2020, §3.1), it is never mentioned that Bergmann will argue strongly that the further moves favour realism (see Reference Bergmann1964, passim; for discussion, see Allaire, Reference Allaire1974, pp. 60–61; Heald, Reference Heald1992, pp. 40–43). Fumerton (Reference Fumerton2002, pp. 5–6) points out that truthmaker theory and alethic realism are compatible with ‘radical metaphysical idealism’. Fumerton (Reference Fumerton, Pedersen and Wright2013, p. 200) also points out that even Berkeley (Reference Berkeley and Dancy1713) was ‘a robust realist’ about truth while holding the view that ‘the only truth makers for Berkeley were facts about minds and ideas’ (ibid.). Thus, according to him, Berkeley is a truthmaker-idealist.

It is obvious that just saying that truth depends asymmetrically on, is necessitated by, or supervenes on, reality isn't sufficient for realism. A basic asymmetry principle clearly doesn't rule out that reality is mind-or-interest dependent. Figures such as Berkeley, other idealists, and antirealists of various sorts, have not been unsympathetic to correspondence intuitions. Dummett (Reference Dummett1976, pp. 51–55), famously a supporter of antirealism, accepts Principle C (if a statement is true, there must be something in virtue of which it is true, 1976, p. 53), which the intuitionist Sundholm describes as ‘clearly nothing but a formulation of a truth-maker condition on truth’ (Reference Sundholm1994a, pp. 123–24). See also Daly (Reference Daly, Beebee and Dodd2005, p. 96) who argues that the correspondence intuition (that ‘<p> is true if and only if things are as <p> says they are') is compatible with any theory of truth and is ontologically neutral. He (ibid., p. 97) even argues that combining this with the truthmaker principle and Armstrong's states-of-affairs ontology gives us principles which are compatible with pragmatist and coherentist theories of truth.

How should truthmaker-realists (e.g., Bigelow, Reference Bigelow1988, p. 123; Armstrong, Reference Armstrong2004, p. 5; and Heil, Reference Heil2003, p. 61), who insist on a strong connection between realism and truthmaking, respond? The paper's novel claim is that accepting truthmaker-principles as part of the best abductive package of principles provides a strong argument for realism as the favoured view. An important part of the way to do this is to be explicit and emphatic about one's underlying metaphysical commitments,Footnote 8 and not just to retreat to a sort of neutralism about one's truthmaking commitments, as some recommend in the face of Beebee and Dodd's (Reference Beebee and Dodd2005, p. 16) criticisms.Footnote 9 Truthmaker-neutralists, who are moved by the critics, will answer the question, ‘What are the natures of truthmakers?’ with ‘We must stay neutral about this, not to beg the question against alternative theories’. Another way to look at such ecumenicality is that it is ultimately question-avoidance.Footnote 10 Realists, by contrast, can abductively argue that realism about truthmakers is part of the best version of truthmaker theory. This leaves less brute and unanswered and is, thus, ceteris paribus, more virtuous.

As I argue in the next section, this is not to beg the question against antirealism, to preclude antirealist truthmakers, or to deny that one can have a theory of truthmakers as all mind-dependent. Instead, it is to argue that truthmaker-realism is the best of a variety of alternative theories of truthmaking.Footnote 11 One is arguing that such antirealists and truthmaker theorists alike do not have the best motivated theory on abductive grounds such as relevance and explanatory power.

In sum, critics of truthmaker theory have argued that truthmaking is neither sufficient nor necessary for realism and thereby rejected truthmaker-realism and truthmaker theory. They aren't arguing that truthmaker-antirealism is better than truthmaker-realism. They assume that the mere possibility of truthmaker-antirealism undermines truthmaker-realism and the realism-truthmaking connection. It was never clear, though, that their targets (e.g., Heil, Bigelow, Armstrong) thought truthmaking was necessary or sufficient for realism. Overall, this paper argues that the critics haven't achieved a rejection of truthmaker-realism. One can either accept truthmaker-realism, truthmaker-antirealism (including truthmaker-idealism or truthmaker-neutralism) or reject accounting for truth altogether. Generally plausible abductive reasons support truthmaker-realism over any of these other alternatives: realism and truthmaking go hand in hand as an abductively better package, or so I continue to argue.

To be clear: I haven't objected to the view that truthmaker theory is neither necessary nor sufficient for realism, but to the view that if truthmaker theory is neither necessary nor sufficient for realism, we shouldn't be truthmaker theorists or truthmaker-realists. I haven't argued that the arguments for truthmaker theory's being neither necessary nor sufficient for realism aren't sound. Rather, as arguments against truthmaker theory and truthmaker-realism the objections are invalid, given the abductive defence of truthmaker-realism. Next, I defend truthmaker-realism further – it doesn't beg the question against, but is instead abductively better than, its truthmaker-antirealist rivals: truthmaker-neutralism (§5.1) and truthmaker-idealism (§6). The abductive defence of truthmaker-realism thus responds both to truthmaking's critics and truthmaker-realism's rivals.

5. Objection-c: Begging the Question against Antirealist Truthmaking

Is an explicit commitment to realism really, as Beebee and Dodd (Reference Beebee and Dodd2005, p. 16) have pointed out and Tahko (Reference Tahko and Calemi2015, p. 211) has repeated, just begging the question against antirealisms and non-realisms?

In response: first, if truthmaker-principles and antirealism are compatible as critics emphasise in objection-b, then truthmaker-realism isn't question-begging. It takes additional argumentation and steps in reasoning to see that realism comes out as the most virtuous – a bias in favour of realism is not merely built into the principle, as one could legitimately argue if the argument were deductive and if antirealist truthmaking were made impossible. Within an abductive strategy, furthermore, truthmaker-realists need not directly rule out non-realist truthmaker theories. Instead, they can propose and defend their alternative as better. This section and the following sections argue for this in detail. Second, they need not appeal to independently plausible accounts of truth and truthmaking, as critics demand, to avoid the charge of begging the question (see Beebee and Dodd, Reference Beebee and Dodd2005, p. 16; Tahko, Reference Tahko and Calemi2015, p. 211; and Cameron, Reference Cameron2008, pp. 116ff.). Rather, if one is a realist and comprehensive, comprehensiveness being another theoretical virtue, one will propose an appropriately realist theory of truth and truthmaking (see e.g. Martin, Reference Martin1984).

Cameron (Reference Cameron2008, pp. 121ff.) responds to this problem which he also raised for truthmaker theorists by saying that they need to accept a further theory of fundamentality which they can then combine with their theory of truthmaking to rule out antirealist truthmakers. According to him, it is not the role of truthmaker theories but the role of theories of fundamentality to provide the world's truthmakers. This, however, is not the only attractive option for truthmaker-realists. They have at least two other options:

  1. (a) provide a realist ontology, a domain of mind-independent entities, and reasons for identifying truthmakers in that domain (e.g., Bigelow, Reference Bigelow1988, p. 123; Armstrong, Reference Armstrong2004, p. 5; and Asay, Reference Asay2020, §8 seem to take this option, though see below); or

  2. (b) build into their views of truth and truthmaking a general commitment to realist, mind-independent truthmakers (Russell, Reference Russell1912, pp. 119–30 clearly takes this route).

By doing either (a) or (b) one provides an account of what truthmakers are as a crucial part of one's truthmaker theory itself, not merely as a supplement – for surely an account of which entities are truthmakers for which truths is part of a truthmaker theory. (Even though he is a critic, MacBride (Reference MacBride and Zalta2020, §0) identifies this as one of truthmaker theory's central tasks, one interconnected with its other tasks.)

Providing a theory of fundamentality is just one route, but it doesn't work in the way that Cameron envisages (see also Schaffer, Reference Schaffer2008; Rettler, Reference Rettler2016; and Heil, Reference Heil2003; for criticisms, see Schipper, Reference Schipper2021; Audi, Reference Audi2020). The problem with Cameron's view is that even if one provided a separate theory of fundamentality, one would not yet have a theory of truthmakers. This requires in addition a crucial step which is part of truthmaker theory: to say which fundamental entities are truthmakers for which truths (§5.1 defends this in detail).

Importantly, none of these routes is question-begging, including route-(b), if part of an abductive package. Non-realists can provide their own alternatives. Realists provide theirs. The field is then open to argue which theory is abductively stronger.

It is reasonable for realists to give realist accounts of truth and truthmaking. By adopting an overall realist position, one is committing oneself to accepting a systematic account of everything from a realist perspective. This plausibly includes, when providing a theory of truth, pointing to truth-independent objects as the reasons why what we say about them is true. This isn't question-begging. It's a natural consequence of being realist about one's commitments. One who takes everything to be language-dependent (e.g., Goodman, Reference Goodman1978), say, will be committed to answering philosophical questions and problems by analysing language or looking only to linguistic entities. Realists, by contrast, will solve philosophical problems and explain philosophically relevant concepts such as truth by pointing to mind-and-language-independent objects. One can articulate the truthmaking relation as above in terms of nec or sup, but it would be unreasonable to demand that truthmaker-realists should only be committed to something that antirealists can also accept, such as nec or sup, in their account of the truthmaking relation. For instance, one might add:

externality: the truthmakers, those entities on one side of the relation, are, except in exceptional cases,Footnote 12 outside of those truths that they make true.Footnote 13

This is a claim about truthmaking being an external relation to outside entities. It is consistent with truthmaking being an internal relation in Heil's (Reference Heil2012, pp. 158–61) sense, on which all it takes for the relation to hold is for the truthmaker, e, and the truthbearer, s, to exist, for even though e is external to s, when they both exist, e makes s true. Externality in our sense is directly relevant to the realism debate – and has to do with relations, e.g., spatial, mereological, or instantiative. If x is external to y, then x does not occupy the same space as y, is not a proper part of y, and is not an intrinsic property of y. Idealists, pragmatists, linguistic constructivists, and other antirealists might not accept this additional principle, for they might accept principles on which only either s, a part of s, or some property of s (such as its expediency) makes s true. This principle is not just consistent with realism but reasonable for realists to accept.

The charge against realists of begging-the-question made by supposedly neutral, neutralist critics seems motivated by something like the following principle:

fair play: when giving an account of some subject-matter m, one must put one's account of m and the principles regulating m in such terms with which all parties in the debate can agree, including one's opponents and those who are yet undecided, or else one is begging the question against those opponents, that is, or else one isn't playing fair. We must all play fair!Footnote 14

Critics seem to apply this supposed principle of philosophical disputes to the debate about truthmaking and charge realists with playing unfairly by begging the question against truthmaker-antirealists. Realists demand, minimally, that some truthmakers are mind-independent. Pluralists, such as Asay (Reference Asay2020) and Schipper (Reference Schipper2016), can accept this. But not all parties in the debate can accept even this. Beebee and Dodd (Reference Beebee and Dodd2005, p. 16) put it starkly when they say that antirealists can successfully respond to realist arguments thus:

If truthmaker theory enshrines a commitment to realism, then presumably the appropriate anti-realist reaction to such an argument is simply to deny whatever truthmaker principle is being used as a premise in that argument.

However, is it reasonable to demand that realists follow fair play and to demand that antirealists can just respond by denying realists’ truthmaker-principles? What account of truthmakers should they give that allows them to play fair?

It would be equally unfair and unreasonable to demand that all truthmakers must be idealist and antirealist. The only alternative is some neutral, middle-ground conception of truthmakers potentially acceptable to everyone. But is such a conception a feasible alternative? I now briefly argue that neutralism is not an attractive alternative, especially if one needs to play fair against realism or, more generally, if one is moved by considerations of begging the question.

5.1 The Feasibility of Neutralism

To flesh out a middle ground, neutralist conception of truthmakers, one might draw on Cameron's (Reference Cameron2008, pp. 115–16) other famous suggestion that we should separate (i) questions about whether truths have truthmakers from (ii) questions about what the right ontology is. Any commitments about the nature of entities would come at the level of ontology, leaving one's truthmaker theory neutral about the nature of truthmakers (e.g., Fine, Reference Fine2017b, §2). Realists and antirealists can, then, both accept that some truth, T, is made true by reality. They might even agree on what entity, e, in reality makes T true. Where they disagree is on the nature of e. The existence and truthmaking role of e, as long as we are neutral about the nature of e (as the suggestion goes), is something about which both sides can agree. For instance, apples make ‘apples exist’ true. But according to neutralists, we can stay neutral about the nature of apples. To avoid begging the question against even truthmaker-antirealists and non-necessitarians, we should be maximally neutral about the natures of truthmakers, including whether they are mind-independent: truthmaking apples’ natures need merely allow them to be truthmakers – most minimally, they just need to exist. Both realists and antirealists can accept this maximally neutral truthmaker-principle:

tmp: truths T are made true by truthmakers e, except in exceptional circumstances.

Compare tmp with Tahko's (Reference Tahko and Calemi2015, p. 216) proposed ‘ontologically neutral’ truthmaker-principle:

tm*: Necessarily, if a proposition <p> is true and has a truthmaker, then there is some α in virtue of which it is true.

tmp has, by contrast, no commitment to propositions or to necessitation, which arguably, leads one to a theory of universals, acceptable to Armstrong but not to nominalists (see Tahko, Reference Tahko and Calemi2015, p. 217). tmp allows for rejecting truthmaker-maximalism, on which all truths require truthmakers. tmp is perhaps neutrality-maximalised. Most importantly for our purposes, tmp has no commitment to realism.

No one need endorse tmp as enough for truthmaking. Its relevance here is that it takes the reasoning regarding the charge of begging the question to its natural conclusion: leaving us with a maximally neutral truthmaker-principle, which begs no questions against any potential truthmaker theory (including antirealist, non-maximalist, and non-necessitarian truthmaking). Similarly, truth-minimalists (e.g., Horwich, Reference Horwich1998) strip the truth-property of all metaphysical substance: ‘<p> is true iff p’ captures everything about truth. tmp is a minimalist truthmaker-principle, and truthmaker-neutralism is minimalist-truthmaking, stripped of all metaphysics.

Cameron's suggestion and this excision of metaphysical commitments from one's truthmaker-principle miss the point of providing a theory of truthmakers in the first place for at least two interrelated reasons. These reasons support the realist approach of option-(b) above, e.g., of Russell, rather than option-(a), chosen, e.g., by Armstrong and Bigelow.

Reason-1: contrary to what Cameron and Asay (Reference Asay2020; see below) argue, defending some ontology O as the right ontology is not the same as giving an account of truthmakers. Realists defend the view that at least some of reality is mind-and-language-independent (see what Brock and Mares (Reference Brock and Mares2007, ch. 1) call the existence and independence theses). But one can consistently be a realist while also arguing that because of the nature of truth, that is, because of something to do with what truths mean and how truthbearers can come to have the property being true, all truths can only be made true by mind-and-culture dependent practices. In this case, one will still be a realist since one defends the view that there are mind-independent entities; they just are not among the truthmakers. Also, one can be a thorough-going idealist and think that everything is mind-dependent but think that truth requires mind-independent entities. Depending on the full story of truthmaking one provides, one might then be an error theorist about most of what we say and believe (see Unger, Reference Unger2006, ch. 7).Footnote 15 Again, there is no guarantee that defending any ontology, or account of what is fundamental, entails any account of truthmakers or the truthmaking relation. Pace Cameron, and others such as Asay (Reference Asay2020, §1.3), one's ontology doesn't automatically give one one's account of truthmakers. More work is needed to connect one's theory of what there is (or one's theory of what's fundamental) with one's theory of truthmakers.

According to Asay's ‘conception of truthmaking as fundamentally an exercise in ontology’ (Reference Asay2020, cover blurb), ‘to be is to be a truthmaker’ (2020, §1.3). Asay is here clearly echoing Quine's (Reference Quine1948) famous criterion of ontological commitment and giving his own truthmaker-based criterion; since the equivalence goes both ways, he is also giving us a criterion of truthmaker-commitment, that is, to identify the truthmakers, identify what exists. Asay (Reference Asay2020, pp. 22–23) rejects truthmaker-fundamentalism (unlike Cameron),Footnote 16 but accepts a similar relationship between truthmakers and ontology; he argues: ‘one doesn't “complete” the task of truthmaker theory – i.e., specifying what all the truthmakers are – until one has a completed ontological inventory. Since the truthmakers aren't a proper subset of what exists, they cannot be thought of as some special ontological category’ (ibid., p. 23). When one has a complete ontological inventory, one has a complete list of truthmakers, and vice versa.

But this conception of the relation between truthmakers and ontology is not necessarily correct, for instance if there are ineffable entities, about which one cannot articulate any truths and which thus cannot be truthmakers,Footnote 17 or if truthmakers need not be entities (e.g., Melia, Reference Melia, Beebee and Dodd2005, pp. 67ff.; Schipper, Reference Schipper2020, §1.1). Either way, having a complete ontological inventory or an inventory of all the fundamental entities, pace Cameron and Asay, doesn't allow us to conclude yet that these are all the truthmakers, the only truthmakers, or even any of the truthmakers. This requires further argumentation specifically linking what we can say and think truly and one's metaphysics. And one definitely needs further argumentation to establish that the truthmakers are the only entities in the inventory. These arguments depend on the resolution of difficult questions, for instance, about the limits of thought. Ultimately, I suspect that Asay's overall metaphysical view is realist (see also his useful account of realism in terms of truthmakers, Reference Schipper2020, §8.3) – my point is that theirs is not a view of the relation between truthmaking and ontology that truthmaker theorists must hold.Footnote 18

The upshot is that to defend truthmaker-realism one needs a more direct argument within truthmaker theory. It is not enough merely to defend a realist ontology. Demanding that all truthmaker theorists must embrace an independent neutral principle such as tmp is just not feasible. This would, further, problematically rule out even other natural specifications of the truthmaker-principle, e.g., necessitation's necessity for truthmaking. Although this doesn't without further argumentation entail truthmaker-realism, it does have consequences for truthmaking's categorial ontology, e.g., a states-of-affairs or trope ontology. Just because accepting principles like necessitation would (potentially) beg the question against rival views about ontological categories (e.g., individuals-only ontologies, see Parsons, Reference Parsons1999), this doesn't mean that truthmaking itself is not a substantial relation, like necessitation. Taking the begging-the-question objection to its natural conclusion yields non-committal, tmp-like principles, but is not something truthmaker theorists should accept. Worse, it stacks the cards against truthmaker-realists and -antirealists alike, whose truthmaker accounts rely not just on proposing the right ontology but on an account of the relation between this ontology and truth, namely truthmaker theory. Doing ontology is part of doing truthmaker theory, but they are not the same – truthmaker-realists should do the latter: present a realist truthmaker theory – and this involves presenting a realist truthmaker-principle.

Also, Reason-2, although tmp is acceptable to the various sides of the discussion, it constitutes no account of truthmakers. It just says that some truths have truthmakers without saying anything about what they are. However, if one is a realist, why would one stop at tmp in one's account of truthmaking? A realist shouldn't shy away from giving an all-encompassing, comprehensive account from a realist perspective, as long as it remains theoretically virtuous; this includes giving realist accounts of truthmaking and of the nature of truthmakers. It is a natural extension of the aims of realists, when giving an account of truth and the truthmaking relation itself, to add that truthmakers are, exceptional cases aside, external to and independent of truthbearers and to minds.

This seems to follow too when one adds an abductively attractive relevance or aboutness-constraint on the truthmaking relation itself, as Smith (Reference Smith1999), Merricks (Reference Merricks2007, ch. 2), Griffith (Reference Griffith2015, pp. 326–27), and Schipper (Reference Schipper2018, §4; Reference Schipper2022a, p. 998; Reference Schipper2022b, pp. 4–7; Reference Schipper2022c, §2) do, thereby moving beyond tmp in minimal abductively well-motivated ways. It is not just via one's account of one's ontology that one demands that the truthmakers must be mind-independent. When we talk about mind-independent entities, it is most plausible that only mind-independent entities make what we say true. But, in the exceptional circumstances that one is talking about mind-dependent cases, say if one is a psychologist who often talks about psychological states, then much of what one says is made true by mind-dependent reality. Similar points apply to linguists and language-dependent reality. One's commitment to realism can be part of one's account of truthmakers not only via one's realist ontology, but it can be introduced in one's account of the truthmaking relation itself, for instance, when one demands that it is constrained by what the truthbearers are about. In the cases where we are trying to say or believe truths about mind-independent reality, no truthmaking relation applies to those truthbearers unless realism is true.

Also, realists would be giving a more unified overall theory of everything if they were to use realist truthmakers to account for what makes a truthbearer true. The other possible options, recall, are:

  1. (a) to give an antirealist account of truthmakers,

  2. (b) to give some neutral account of truthmakers, or

  3. (c) not to account for truthmakers at all.

We can rule (c) out as theoretically not virtuous for truthmaker theorists.Footnote 19 If (a), then truthmakers are not mind-independent. If (b), then the (neutral) truthmakers are neither mind-independent nor mind-dependent. In this case, they are not mind-independent. In both cases, (a) and (b), realists would be accepting an account on which truthmakers are not mind-independent. Both are possible accounts even for a realist to accept, given the reasoning in Reason-1 above. However, neither is congenial to realists, who, once they go in for truthmakers, should aim for a unified account of reality and truthmakers.Footnote 20 Realists should not agree to either. Therefore, neither option is playing fair.

Another neutralist (b)-option would be to demand that all parties be non-commital or agnostic about the nature of truthmakers. But this merely kicks the can down the road. Ultimately truthmaker theorists must commit, otherwise they fail on comprehensiveness. Comprehensive neutralists aim to remain neutral about all ontological matters.Footnote 21 But realist accounts would score poorly abductively if they had a realist ontology but ontologically neutral truthmakers, e.g., by claiming that all truthmakers are abstract, semantic posits (Fine Reference Fine, Hale, Wright and Miller2017a, p. 561). For then one may ask whether the semantic posits are mind-and-language-dependent or -independent. If the former, neutralism collapses into truthmaker-antirealism, and if the latter, truthmaker-realism. Even if some form of neutralism doesn't so collapse, metaphysical realists would need good reasons why one's available realist ontology does not provide the truthmakers.Footnote 22 One's realist theory would be simpler and more comprehensive if one provided a realist account of truthmakers. It is not question-begging for one to defend a unified view which is more congenial to one's overall philosophical outlook and makes stronger, more informative claims, actually telling us something positive about truthmakers. Therefore, it is not question-begging for realists about ontology also to be realists about truthmakers, even though weaker claims, in option-(b), are available to them. Realisms about truthmakers are not compatible with either neutralism about the nature of all truthmakers or the existence of all truthmakers: they need at least to say that some truthmakers exist and are mind-independent. In fact, beyond this, they could remain neutral about both the existence and natures of truthmakers, though on abductive grounds, a more definitive and precise answer would on the whole be preferable.

In fact, one should be sceptical about principles such as tmp without further explication of what all the terms are about and, crucially, what truthmakers are. tmp captures a core commitment of truthmaker theory but it is also vague and open-ended; so why think that it is at all satisfactory as even part of one's account? For instance, the (commonsense) realist answer to the question ‘What are truthmakers?’ is: truthmakers are just the ordinary mind-independent entities which we all thought we were talking about,Footnote 23 except potentially where matters are more complicated (e.g., talk about mathematical objects and science's theoretical entities) or specifically psychological (e.g., talk about emotions). This, then, gives us an answer to a question that must be forthcoming. Not to answer the question, as neutralism suggests (b and c), is to prevaricate and to leave one's truthmaker theory incomplete (and vague). Of course, one may take a more piecemeal approach and build one's theory by giving answers truth-by-truth or by leaving the ontological work to others.Footnote 24 But, ultimately one should opt for as much completeness as one can get. The realist answers are not so much question-begging as giving some of the more plausible, informative, general answers to pressing questions.

The neutralist alternative is not abductively feasible. Now, we have a defence of truthmaker-realism specifically in the face of antirealist and neutralist alternatives which addresses the classic objections head-on.

6. Two Abductive Arguments for Truthmaker-Realism against Idealist Rivals

As we saw, antirealists, including idealists, can accept tmp and build their own truthmaker theory. Truthmaker-idealists might accept tmp and add that all truthmakers are mental states such as beliefs, ideas, and experiences, and their properties.

However, in this section, I shall argue that:

  1. (1) if one is an idealist, developing such an account of truth in terms of truthmakers is not attractive, and, specifically,

  2. (2) on closer inspection, such antirealist truthmaker views, in particular the best forms of idealism, are not the abductively most attractive views to hold.Footnote 25

Although realism also doesn't entail tmp (or vice versa), I argue here that even a neutral principle such as tmp, ultimately, abductively favours truthmaker-realism. So, whether or not we are forced to accept a principle such as tmp, truthmaker-realism comes out better motivated. Even though idealism is prima facie compatible with tmp, closer examination reveals the unattractiveness of truthmaker-idealism. To show this, I present two abductive arguments against truthmaker-idealism: (a) the Perceptual Argument (against Berkeleyan truthmaker-idealism), and (b) the Argument from Unobserved Entities (against truthmaker-phenomenalism). These anti-idealist abductive arguments illustrate how the abductive defence gives us arguments for truthmaker-realism and against specific antirealisms, giving models for future arguments against other specific antirealisms.

6.1 The Perceptual Argument

First, Berkeleyan truthmaker-idealism is problematic because it fails to distinguish between the objects of perception and the perceiving of these objects, that is, the perceptual experiences themselves.Footnote 26 This is especially pressing for truthmaker theorists, for it is natural to try to use truthmaking as an account of the veridicality of perception – and the wider a theory's explanatory strength, the better.

But the structure of perception according to Berkeleyan idealists is not congenial to truthmaker theory, which needs minimally to distinguish between truthbearers, or more precisely veridicality-bearers,Footnote 27 here the perceptual experiences and what the truthbearers are about, the objects, that is, the truthmakers. If there is no distinction between perceptual experiences and the objects of perceptions, then one must give an account of the veridicality (i.e., truth) of perceptions differently. One option is to account for veridicality not in terms of the existence of a perception's objects. But this severs the link between perceptions and what they are about, opening their truthmakers to the charge of irrelevance and their theory to ad-hoc-ery. Truthmaker-realism, by contrast, can easily be applied to the standard accounts of perception, which are either directly or indirectly realist, by saying that the objects of perception make the perceptual experiences (or their contents) true – see Snowdon, Reference Snowdon1981, p. 186; Johnston, Reference Johnston, Gendler and Hawthorne2006, pp. 278–79; and Brewer, Reference Brewer2011, p. 143, who employ making true and truthmakers in their favoured account of (veridical) perceptual experience.

When we look closely at the structure of the most plausible form of Berkeleyan idealism, a clear, more radical option emerges: we see that it should instead accept one of truthmaker theory's rivals, namely the identity theory or approach (e.g., Hornsby, Reference Hornsby1997; Dodd, Reference Dodd2000; Johnston, Reference Johnston2013), on which experiences are veridical (true) when they are identical to their objects.Footnote 28 This fits the structure of perception according to Berkeleyan idealists perfectly. Truthmaking's asymmetric dependence relation is in fact not compatible with such idealisms. Therefore, Berkeleyans will have to account for the veridicality of perception in some other way within the resources of their view but without truthmaking, making at least Berkeleyan truthmaker theory inconsistent or unattractive.

There may be possible responses to this problem and the next, but these explanatory challenges clearly lead to complications that make the accounts potentially, unnecessarily complex and, thus, abductively weaker than their realist rivals.Footnote 29

6.2 The Argument from Unobserved Entities

Now, the (Abductive) Argument from Unobserved Entities.Footnote 30 Phenomenalism is faced with the following problem about unobserved entities: (a) according to phenomenalism, all objects, including ordinary objects such as watermelons and tins-of-beans are constituted by mental states – normally perceptions or experiences, of such objects; (b) phenomenalism needs to account for objects that are not perceived; but (c) it would be counterintuitive and against the common knowledge virtue (§2) just to reject that there is anything to be accounted for.

The standard non-theistic, non-Berkeleyan phenomenalist (most famously, Ayer's Reference Ayer1954) response to the problem is to say that an unobserved tin-of-beans's reality consists in something like this counterfactual being true: if a perceiver were in the right conditions, for instance, properly situated in relation to the kitchen cupboard, then the perceiver would experience tins-of-beans-like sensations. However, what accounts for the truth of these phenomenalist-enabling conditionals? They are contingent truths, so not true by logic alone. Therefore, there must be something in the world in virtue of which they are true – something that accounts for their truth.Footnote 31 Normally, the tin-of-beans itself, if available, is what most plausibly accounts for our experience of the tin-of-beans, specifically the tin-of-beans being in the right conditions for being perceived. According to phenomenalists, however, the tin-of-beans doesn't just exist only when one has tins-of-beans-like experiences, but the tin-of-beans is nothing more than such experiences. Without there being an experience-independent tin-of-beans, however, one is hard-pressed to find what makes the conditional true. By stipulation, there just aren't any tin-of-beans-experiences now. Therefore, currently, there is no tin-of-beans yet, according to phenomenalism. Phenomenalism, then, given the resources of its theory of the world, is hard-pressed and seemingly unable to give further explanations and an ontological account when they need to be given. Phenomenalists cannot explain the truths that they posit to account for the intuition and datum about unobserved tins-of-beans.

Realism (about tins-of-beans), on the other hand, can easily say what in the world accounts for the truth of the counterfactuals: the tin-of-beans, its dispositions, and the dispositions of perceivers. Phenomenalism, thus, posits at least one series of truths as brute that realists need not posit as brute. Therefore, by abductive principles such as explanatory power, the truthmaker-maxim, and common knowledge, realism is abductively stronger than phenomenalism, at least on this point.

Rejecting the truthmaker-principle or the need to explain this truth won't help phenomenalists. Doing so (i) still leaves the truth unaccounted for, which, in the wider debate held on abductive grounds, leaves realists on firmer explanatory ground. And, (ii), denying that it is a problem that phenomenalism accepts more brute truths than other theories is not plausible, for it is a central abductive principle that theories are more virtuous if they posit fewer brute truths. Even if Bueno and Shalkowski (Reference Bueno and Shalkowski2020, p. 458) are right that this doesn't guarantee that the theories are true, at least they are more likely to be true based on all the relevant information that we have.

Phenomenalists might, instead, reject the datum about unobserved objects. They would, then, still have further explaining to do, which the realist does not: that is, phenomenalists would need to give a compelling explanation of why we think that objects don't just disappear when no one is perceiving them and that there are objects that exist unperceived, even though, according to their rejection of the datum, there aren't any such objects.Footnote 32 Both options leave phenomenalists on abductively weaker grounds than realists.

This abductive argument for realism can also be extended to similar non-realist views which accept the truth of counterfactuals without having the resources internal to their theories to say what in the world accounts for their truth. Such theories are less attractive than those that have such resources. Although I won't spell this out here, this abductive strategy should also apply to truthmaker arguments against non-realisms about the past (see Parsons, Reference Parsons, Beebee and Dodd2005), against behaviourism (Liggins, Reference Liggins, Beebee and Dodd2005), against Rylean (Ryle, Reference Ryle1949, p.120), counterfactual accounts of dispositions (Martin, Reference Martin1994/2008, p.19; Armstrong, Reference Armstrong1969, p.23; Reference Armstrong and Heil1989) and against various other similar views which posit brute counterfactuals to account for the data of ordinary experience (Armstrong, Reference Armstrong1997, Reference Armstrong2004).

7. Conclusion

If Williamson (Reference Williamson2016, passim) is right that the argumentative approach of all philosophy is ultimately abductive, even if philosophers think otherwise about what they are doing, then philosophical disputes are not resolved by piecemeal argumentation. Rather, whole pictures need to be compared and weighed up for their virtues, not just piecemeal definitions (see also Quine, Reference Quine1951). Abductive strategies have prominent advocates in metaphysics (see, e.g., Lewis, Reference Lewis1986, p. 4; Sider, Hawthorne, and Zimmerman, Reference Sider, Hawthorne and Zimmerman2008, p. 6; Paul, Reference Paul2011). Critics such as Bueno and Shalkowski (Reference Bueno and Shalkowski2020, passim) have argued that theoretical virtues are not truth-conducive, thus providing no reason to believe a theory. However, not even they deny that virtues provide reasons to accept the virtuous over their less virtuous rivals (ibid., p. 465).Footnote 33 Such strategies in defence of some theory T about m would minimally involve

  1. (a) proposing a theory T of m, and

  2. (b) defending T by arguing that it has explanatory and theoretical virtues over its rivals, such as parsimony, modesty, simplicity, elegance, relevance, and completeness.

Realist truthmaker theorists are, then, not begging the question against antirealists, nor is rejecting truthmaker-principles, as Beebee and Dodd (Reference Beebee and Dodd2005, p. 16) suggest, then, enough to nullify the challenge to non-realisms. Understood as an abductive challenge, truthmaker-realists, as Beebee and Dodd also demand, will ‘have reasons, independently of [their] commitment to realism, for believing that the principle is true’ (ibid.). Rejecting any of these generally attractive abductive principles and virtues would need to be well motivated and comply with further principles such as anti-ad-hoc-ery.Footnote 34 The main reason, I have argued, for accepting an explicitly realist principle that can be wielded in arguments against antirealism is this: realist truthmaker-principles have more theoretical virtues than antirealist ones. The relevant virtues are not merely that truthmakers explain truths, as many – for instance, Daly (Reference Daly, Beebee and Dodd2005) – have assumed is the only theoretical role that truthmakers play according to truthmaker theory.Footnote 35 Truthmaker-realism has a wider theoretical role and has more theoretical virtues that are relevant to its success. For instance, as I've argued, it gives relevant ontological accounts and leaves less unexplained than phenomenalism and other similar non-realist views do. So, truthmaker-realism is more plausible than these alternatives.

Indeed, if one utilises an abductive strategy to argue for truthmaker-realism and against -antirealist rivals, then one can see that there is no particular truthmaker-principle that antirealists and other, perhaps more neutral, critics may point to as question-begging. Understood in this light, one now has a response to the critics and a new argumentative strategy in defence of truthmaker-realism.

Acknowledgements

Special thanks are due to Paul Snowdon, Tim Crane, Peter Unger, Julius Schönherr, Christoph Schuringa, Göran Sundholm, and Konglu Zhong; Timothy Williamson, to whose lecture on abductive philosophy I officially responded for his 2020 lecture series on Philosophical Methods, now published as a book with my response; Naomi Osorio-Kupferblum, Matteo Plebani, and Stephen Yablo, my fellow symposiasts at the 10th European Congress of Analytic Philosophy's symposium ‘Conceptualising Subject Matter and Aboutness’ (Utrecht, August 2020); the organisers of a centenary celebration of Russell's 1920 Beijing lectures where I presented an early version; and two excellent, anonymous reviewers.

Footnotes

1 If one's theory takes Xs generally to be F, any exceptions in the theory must be well motivated.

2 Some idealists might take reality to depend on truths, recommending another maxim: minimise brute existents, not brute truths. One might, then, wonder whether we are playing a realist game already. Two responses: (1) explanatory power and truthmaker principles go hand in hand. Indeed, the paper argues that the truthmaker-game is realist: truthmaker-supporting abductive principles favour realism over alternatives (e.g., truthmaker-idealism). Also, (2), explanatory power is generally plausible; realism may even be a current ‘absolute presupposition’ (Collingwood, Reference Collingwood1948, ch. 5; Sundholm, Reference Sundholm2019; also Reference Sundholm, Prawitz and Westerståhl1994b, p. 381; and Reference Sundholm, Niiniluoto, Sintonen and Wolenski2004, p. 437). Idealists may attempt to challenge this theoretical virtue. But its general plausibility makes this challenging.

3 This is sometimes called ‘ontological seriousness’ (Martin and Heil, Reference Martin and Heil1999, p. 35). It's compatible with a philosophical division-of-labour illustratable thus: ethicists argue for which truths are true; metaethicists and ontologists search for the right truthmakers. Their work can inform each other, each forming important, essential parts of a complete theory. Mackie (Reference Mackie1977, pp. 36–49) combines them, rejecting the truth of ethical truthbearers after considering their possible truthmakers (for discussion, see Taylor, Reference Taylor2020, §2). Martin and Heil (Reference Martin and Heil1999, §1) argue that even antirealists cannot shirk their ontological responsibilities: ontology is inescapable (see also Heil, Reference Heil2021).

4 When defining realism, Asay also uses the words ‘an ontology of the relevant kind’ and ‘ontology in a relevant fashion’ (Reference Asay2020, p. 159). He argues that he cannot present a more ‘general and comprehensive account of just what character these realism-relevant truthmakers need to have in every case [… because…] [w]hether there is anything more specific that is essential to all the views we label “realist” is a matter that cannot be settled independently of looking at each and every individual realism debate’ (ibid., pp. 159–60). Asay worries about the cohesiveness of the general realism-vs-antirealism debate. I assume coherence.

5 An anonymous reviewer calls their views ‘fine-grained’.

7 For discussion, see Mulligan, Reference Mulligan, Lowe and Rami2009, pp. 56ff. Note, Sundholm himself is a truthmaker theorist and generally a metaphysical realist, thus a truthmaker-realist, just not about mathematics. See, e.g., Sundholm, Reference Sundholm, Niiniluoto, Sintonen and Wolenski2004, p. 453 on fallibility, though for complications, see also Reference Sundholm, Prawitz and Westerståhl1994b, p. 383.

8 Armstrong, for instance, explicitly and repeatedly writes that he's a naturalist and draws consequences for his accounts of truthmaking, truthbearers (see Reference Armstrong2004, p. 12) and truthmakers, based on these underlying commitments. His naturalism constrains his theory of truthmaking. He's not a naturalist because he's a truthmaker theorist; rather, he's a truthmaker theorist who fleshes out his version of truthmaking based on his naturalist and realist assumptions. He, just like Russell (Reference Russell1919, p. 25), builds his realism into his account of truthmaking (though MacBride (Reference MacBride and Zalta2020, §0) disagrees with my reading of Russell). For our purposes it doesn't matter if any truthmaker-realist has presented an abductive argument before. I argue that an abductive defence is available to truthmaker-realists.

9 See, e.g., Tahko (Reference Tahko and Calemi2015, pp. 207–208, §3, p.218), who explicitly discusses thinking of ‘truthmaker theory [as] offer[ing] an ontologically neutral way to account for truth’, Schipper's (Reference Schipper2016, chs. 1 & 7; Reference Schipper2020, §§1.1 & 2.3) ‘modest’ view (Schipper Reference Schipper2023 even advocates neutral quantification), and Yablo (Reference Yablo2014, ch. 4) and Fine (Reference Fine2017b, §2) (the latter explicitly strip truthmaker theory of metaphysical commitments, without discussing Beebee and Dodd). Their detailed neutralism-advocating meta-ontological arguments are beyond this paper's scope.

10 An anonymous reviewer helpfully suggests an appropriate form of question-avoidance: when answering the question is not relevant to one's tasks. When it is relevant, e.g., here, it is a ‘non-starter’ to stay neutral. See also §5.1.

11 This discussion avoids the problem that Cameron (Reference Cameron2008, p. 117) raises, when he states that by emphatically insisting that truthmakers must generally be mind-independent, truthmaker-realists merely ‘shout’ at antirealist truthmaker theorists, ‘No! – you must be a realist about truthmakers!’. The abductive strategy, instead, gives us strong reasons for realism about truthmakers.

12 See also Russell (Reference Russell1912, pp. 128–29, 130). Exceptional cases include self-referential truths such as ‘This sentence starts with the letter “T”’.

13 See also Russell (Reference Russell1912, pp. 119–25, esp. 121).

14 Hirsch's (Reference Hirsch2011, pp. 98ff.) meta-ontological principle of charity inspired fair play. However, Hirsch, quoting Wittgenstein (Reference Wittgenstein1953, I.38), argues that non-realists take language on holiday (2011, p. 81). He argues that commonsense-realism is true (ibid., ch. 5, p. 187), and, in short, that despite thinking otherwise, non-realists don't even disagree with commonsense-realists: they fail even to present serious alternatives (according to my reading of Hirsch). Hirsch's charity principle and fair play thus differ in that fair play assumes genuine disagreement. With fair play, I diagnose the principle behind the charge of question-begging. I argue that both the charge and its principle are confused.

15 Early Unger (Reference Unger1979, §5) endorses such a position without endorsing idealism – Unger (ibid., p. 33) helpfully contrasts this with the Berkeleyan position, which holds that ordinary truths’ truthmakers are ideas. Unger uses the same nihilistic arguments later (Reference Unger2006, ch. 7) to argue for a position that favours idealism, though one which rejects ‘the watermelon is round’ as false either because there is no watermelon or because there are always many watermelons, never just one. Unger (Reference Unger2006) is sympathetic to an idealist position which is error-theoretic about many ordinary truths. However, he has no explicit view of truth.

16 See also Schipper, Reference Schipper2021, passim.

17 Zhong (Reference Zhong2022) defends the thesis that there are ineffable entities. Hofweber (Reference Hofweber, Bennett and Zimmerman2017) argues that there are no ineffable facts.

18 Asay's actual views are more complex than the quotations here suggest. Unfortunately, space restrictions prevent going into further detail. My main point: what he says can be interpreted as expressing neutralism about truthmaker theory's contribution.

19 An anonymous reviewer helpfully and approvingly calls this option ‘a non-starter’.

20 Famously, some realists claim that realism is not bound to any theory of truth (Devitt, Reference Devitt1991), or instead to non-correspondence views such as truth-pragmatism (Ellis, Reference Ellis1988, Reference Ellis1990). Devitt (Reference Devitt1991, Reference Devitt2010) argues thereby that realism is immune to attacks on theories of truth. Even so, truthmaker theorists should aim for the unification of reality and truthmakers. Abductively, unity is better than disunity (though, see Schipper, Reference Schipper2018, §6.2.3). See Jago (Reference Jago2018, passim, pp. 3ff.) for maximum unity: to be true is to be made true.

21 Compare: constructive empiricists (van Fraassen, Reference van Fraassen1980) aim to remain ontologically neutral about the unobservable parts of scientific theories, to some, metaphysics’ very subject matter, but aren't neutral about the empirical parts. This however collapses into realism or antirealism, depending on empirical reality's ontology. Neutralist empiricists would be ontologically neutral even about the empirical portions.

22 Truthmaker-semanticists who aim to remain ontologically neutral in their truthmaker theory have not actually given any systematic reasons for this (Fine Reference Fine, Hale, Wright and Miller2017a, p. 561; Yablo Reference Yablo2014, ch. 4). Detailed engagement is beyond the paper's scope.

23 Most truthmaker theorists, even Armstrong, believe this, at least for existential truths. Two ontological disputes can be distinguished: (a) whether states-of-affairs, facts, tropes, or objects-under-counterpart-relations are ordinary entities; and (b) whether the relevant entities are mind-independent. Since the current debate is about realism vs non-realisms, the relevant ordinary view includes ordinary mind-independent round watermelons and apples, whatever their ontological category in the (a)-sense. The relevant ordinary view, for our purposes, remains undecided about (a), but rules out their being ideas in divine or human minds.

24 Schipper (Reference Schipper2018, pp. 3685, 3705, §6.2.1), e.g., advocates piecemeal truthmaker theory. By contrast, Asay: ‘By recognizing the inherent holistic nature of ontological accounting, we obviate the need to offer a specific piecemeal account of what each truth's specific and particular ontological commitments are’ (Reference Asay2020, p. 63).

25 Tahko (Reference Tahko and Calemi2015, p. 216) writes, ‘As for idealists, they could presumably interpret existence so that it does not require material existence, although I am not aware of any idealist which would employ truthmaking explicitly’ (second emphasis added). All the critics needed was the logical compatibility of truthmaking and idealism, and no actual truthmaker-idealists. I argue that the combination of truthmaking and serious versions of idealism, even if compatible, is not abductively attractive, especially compared to truthmaker-realism.

26 See also Russell (Reference Russell1912, pp. 38–43), who presents the Berkeleyan view thus, and Stove (Reference Stove1991, pp. 123–31,139–48) on Berkeley's arguments, identity's centrality for idealism, and idealism's varieties.

27 Perceptual experiences, as with sentences, are either veridical or non-veridical. This is compatible with intentionalism (Crane, Reference Crane2009, passim), propositionalism (Searle, Reference Searle1983, ch. 3), and even naïve realism, which adds that veridical and non-veridical experiences form no common kind (Snowdon, Reference Snowdon1981). Similarly, truthmaker theory doesn't require truths and falsehoods to involve common truthbearers (e.g., propositions).

28 Truthmaker theory and identity ‘theory’ are rival views about the relations between truth and reality. Some identity rivals claim the relation is identity, others reject providing a theory altogether. See Hornsby's (Reference Hornsby1997, §III.4) identity-theoretical answers to ‘questions about the relation between language and the world’ which she claims constitute ‘no new theory’.

29 See also Price (Reference Price1940, p. 188) on overcomplexity being a defect of phenomenalism.

30 The argument is inspired by Martin's (Reference Martin1984, pp. 18–19) classic argument, though his is not clearly abductive, so importantly different.

31 Bergmann (Reference Bergmann1964, p. vii) argues that even truths true by logic alone need a truthmaker, ‘the formal features of reality’ (Heald, Reference Heald1992, p. 44).

32 See Price (Reference Price1940, p. 20) on Hume's (Reference Hume1739, p. 188) discussion of what accounts for the continued existence of unobserved objects. See also Schipper and Snowdon (Reference Schipper, Snowdon, Zalta and Nodelman2023, §4.2).

33 For our purposes, it is enough if truthmaker-realism's being better than its rivals (given the theoretical reasons provided) gives us good reasons to accept realism over rivals, even if they fall short of reasons to believe the theory over its rivals, if Bueno and Shalkowski are right. Acceptance is a first step towards belief. Also, they (ibid., §5) argue that an abductive argument for T presupposes the truth of T, thus begging the question against rivals. §5's arguments should go some way to addressing such objections.

34 For further discussion, see the debate surrounding meta-incommensurability, e.g., Oberheim and Hoyningen-Huene (Reference Oberheim1997, §3) who introduce the notion; Devitt (Reference Devitt, Hoyningen-Huene and Sankey2001, §8) for a realist-defending response.

35 See Lewis (Reference Lewis2001, pp. 611–12), who denies that truthmakers or truths’ supervenience-base play any explanatory role in truthmaking. See also Asay (Reference Asay2020, §2.2) for arguments against explanatory-first truthmaking (for discussion, see Schipper, Reference Schipper2022b, pp. 3ff.). Daly (Reference Daly, Beebee and Dodd2005, passim) sketches three strategies for the explanatory work that truthmaking might be put to do, including that truthmaking gives an inference-to-the-best-explanation way to explain our realist intuitions. He does not consider, however, that the defence itself of truthmaker-realism can be abductive, as I am arguing.

References

Adams, Robert, ‘Idealism Vindicated’, in van Inwagen, P., Zimmerman, D. (eds.), Persons (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007), 3554.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Allaire, Edwin, ‘Bergmann's Ontologies’, in The Ontological Turn (Iowa City: University of Iowa Press, 1974), 3864.Google Scholar
Armstrong, David, ‘Dispositions Are Causes’, Analysis, 30:1 (1969), 2326.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Armstrong, David, ‘C.B. Martin, Counterfactuals, Causality, and Conditionals’, in Heil, J. (ed.), Cause, Mind, and Reality (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1989), 715.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Armstrong, David, A World of States of Affairs (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Armstrong, David, Truth and Truthmakers (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Asay, Jamin, ‘A Truthmaking Account of Realism and Anti-Realism’, Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 93:3 (2012), 373–94.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Asay, Jamin, A Theory of Truthmaking (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2020).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Asay, Jamin, ‘Ecumenical Truthmaking’, Asian Journal of Philosophy, 1:3 (2022), 15.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Audi, Paul, ‘Why Truthmaking Is Not a Case of Grounding’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 51:3 (2020), 567–90.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ayer, A.J., ‘Phenomenalism’, in Philosophical Essays (London: Macmillan, 1954).Google Scholar
Beebee, Helen and Dodd, Julian, ‘Introduction’, in Truthmakers (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2005), 116.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bergmann, Gustav, ‘The Glory and the Misery of Ludwig Wittgenstein’, in Logic and Reality (Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 1961/1964), 225–41.Google Scholar
Bergmann, Gustav, Logic and Reality (Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 1964).Google Scholar
Berkeley, George, Three Dialogues Between Hylas and Philonous, with his Principles of Human Knowledge, Dancy, J. (ed.), (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1713/1998).Google Scholar
Bigelow, John, The Reality of Numbers (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1988).Google Scholar
Bolender, John, ‘An Argument for Idealism’, Journal of Consciousness Studies, 8:4 (2001), 3761Google Scholar
Brewer, Bill, Perception and Its Objects (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brock, S. and Mares, Edwin, Realism and Anti-realism (Stocksfield: Acumen, 2007).Google Scholar
Bueno, Otávio and Shalkowski, S.A., ‘Troubles with Theoretical Virtues’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 101:2 (2020), 456–69.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cameron, Ross, ‘Truthmakers, Realism and Ontology’, Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement, 62 (2008), 107–28.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chalmers, D.J., ‘Idealism and the Mind-Body Problem’, in Seager, William (ed.), The Routledge Handbook of Panpsychism (London: Routledge, 2019), 353–73.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
R. Collingwood, J., An Essay in Metaphysics (Oxford: Clarendon, 1948).Google Scholar
Crane, Tim, ‘Is Perception a Propositional Attitude?’, The Philosophical Quarterly, 59:236 (2009), 452–69.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Daly, Chris, ‘So Where's the Explanation?’, in Beebee, H. and Dodd, J. (eds.), Truthmakers (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005), 85103.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Devitt, Michael, Realism and Truth, 2nd ed. (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1991).Google Scholar
Devitt, Michael, ‘Incommensurability and the Priority of Metaphysics’, in Hoyningen-Huene, P. and Sankey, H. (eds.), Incommensurability and Related Matters (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 2001), 143–57.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Devitt, Michael, Putting Metaphysics First (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2010).Google Scholar
Dodd, Julian, ‘Is Truth Supervenient on Being?’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 102:1 (2002), 6985.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dodd, Julian, An Identity Theory of Truth (London: Palgrave, 2000).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dummett, Michael, ‘What is a Theory of Meaning? (II)’, in The Seas of Language (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1976/1993), 3493.Google Scholar
Ellis, Brian, Truth and Objectivity (Oxford: Blackwell, 1990).Google Scholar
Ellis, Brian, ‘Internal Realism’, Synthese, 76:3 (1988), 409–34.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fine, Kit, ‘Truthmaker Semantics’, in Hale, B., Wright, C., Miller, A. (eds.), A Companion to the Philosophy of Language (Oxford: Blackwell, 2017a), 556–77.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fine, Kit, ‘Naive Metaphysics’, Philosophical Issues, 27:1 (2017b), 98113.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Foster, John, A World for Us (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Forster, Malcolm and Sober, Elliot, ‘How to Tell When Simpler, More Unified, or Less Ad Hoc Theories Will Provide More Accurate Predictions’, The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 45:1 (1994), 135.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
van Fraassen, Bas, The Scientific Image (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1980).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fumerton, Richard, Realism and the Correspondence Theory of Truth (Oxford: Rowman and Littlefield, 2002).Google Scholar
Fumerton, Richard, ‘Alethic Pluralism and the Correspondence Theory of Truth’, in Pedersen, N.J.L.L. and Wright, C.D. (eds.), Truth and Pluralism (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2013), 197212.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goodman, Nelson, Ways of World-making (Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company, 1978).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Griffith, Aaron, ‘How Negative Truths are Made True’, Synthese, 192:1 (2015), 317–35.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Heald, William, ‘From Positivism to Realism’, Books at Iowa, 56:1 (1992), 2546.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Heil, John, ‘Truth Making and Entailment’, Logique et Analyse, 43:169–170 (2000), 231–42.Google Scholar
Heil, John, From an Ontological Point of View (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2003).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Heil, John, The Universe As We Find It (Oxford: Clarendon, 2012).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Heil, John, Appearance & Reality (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2021).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hirsch, Eli, Quantifier Variance and Realism (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hofweber, Thomas, ‘Are There Ineffable Aspects of Reality?’, in Bennett, K. and Zimmerman, D. (eds.), Oxford Studies in Metaphysics, Volume 10 (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2017), 124–70.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hofweber, Thomas, ‘Idealism and the Harmony of Thought and Reality’, Mind, 128:511 (2015), 699734.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hornsby, Jennifer, ‘Truth’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 97:1 (1997), 124.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Horwich, Paul, Truth, 2nd ed. (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1998).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hume, David, A Treatise of Human Nature (London: White-Hart, John Noon, 1739).Google Scholar
Jago, Mark, What Truth Is (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2018).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Johnston, Mark, ‘Better Than Mere Knowledge?’, in Gendler, T.S. and Hawthorne, J. (eds.), Perceptual Experience (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006), 260–90.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Johnston, Colin, ‘Judgment and the Identity Theory of Truth’, Philosophical Studies, 166:2 (2013), 381–97.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, David, ‘Truthmaking and Difference-Making’, Noûs, 35:4 (2001), 602–15.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, David, ‘Critical Notice of D.M. Armstrong's A Combinatorial Theory of Possibility’, Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 70:2 (1992), 211–24.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, David, On the Plurality of Worlds (Oxford: Blackwell, 1986).Google Scholar
Liggins, David, ‘Truthmakers and Explanation’, in Beebee, H. and Dodd, J. (eds.), Truthmakers (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005), 105–16.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
MacBride, Fraser, ‘Lewis's Animadversions on the Truthmaker Principle’, in Beebee, H. and Dodd, J. (eds.), Truthmakers (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005), 117–40.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
MacBride, Fraser, ‘Truthmakers’, in Zalta, Edward (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2020 Edition), accessed February 23, 2013 and February 13, 2019 at http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2020/entries/truthmakers/.Google Scholar
Mackie, John Leslie, Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong (New York: Penguin Books, 1977).Google Scholar
Martin, C.B., ‘Anti-Realism and the World's Undoing’, Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 65:1 (1984), 320.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Martin, C.B., ‘Dispositions and Conditionals’, in The Mind in Nature (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1994/2008), 1220.Google Scholar
Martin, C.B. and Heil, John, ‘The Ontological Turn’, Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 23:1 (1999), 3460.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Meixner, Uwe, ‘Idealism and Panpsychism’, in Bruntrip, G. and Joskolla, L. (eds.) Panpsychism (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2017), 387406.Google Scholar
Melia, Joseph, ‘Truthmaking without Truthmakers’, in Beebee, H. and Dodd, J. (eds.), Truthmakers (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005), 6784.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Merricks, Trenton, Truth & Ontology (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mulligan, Kevin, ‘Truth and the Truth-Maker Principle in 1921’, in Lowe, E.J. and Rami, A. (eds.), Truth and Truth-Making (Stocksfield: Acumen, 2009), 3958.Google Scholar
Oberheim, Eric, ‘Incommensurability, Realism and Meta-Incommensurability’, Theoria, 12:3 (1997), 447–65.Google Scholar
Parsons, Josh, ‘There is no ‘truthmaker’ argument against nominalismAustralasian Journal of Philosophy, 77(3) (1999), 325334.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Parsons, Josh, ‘Truthmakers, the Past, and the Future’, in Beebee, H. and Dodd, J. (eds.), Truthmakers (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005), 161–74.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Paul, L.A., ‘Metaphysics as Modeling’, Philosophical Studies, 160:1 (2011), 129.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pelczar, Michael, Phenomenalism (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2022).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Price, H.H., Hume's Theory of the External World (Oxford: Clarendon, 1940).Google Scholar
Quine, W.V., ‘Two Dogmas of Empiricism’, Philosophical Review, 60:1 (1951), 2042.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Quine, W.V., ‘On What There Is’, Review of Metaphysics, 33:3 (1948), 2138.Google Scholar
Rettler, Bradley, ‘The General Truthmaker View of Ontological Commitment’, Philosophical Studies, 173:5 (2016), 1405–25.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Russell, Bertrand, The Problems of Philosophy (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1912).Google Scholar
Russell, Bertrand, ‘On Propositions’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volumes, 2:1 (1919), 143.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ryle, Gilbert, The Concept of Mind (London: Hutchinson, 1949).Google Scholar
Schaffer, Jonathan, ‘Truthmakers and Fundamentality’, Philosophical Books, 49:4 (2008), 302316.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schipper, Arthur, Truth and Reality (PhD Dissertation, UCL, 2016).Google Scholar
Schipper, Arthur, ‘Aboutness and Negative Truths’, Synthese, 195:8 (2018), 3685–722.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schipper, Arthur, ‘Aboutness and Ontology’, Philosophical Studies, 177:2 (2020), 503–33.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schipper, Arthur, ‘Fundamental Truthmakers and Non-Fundamental Truths’, Synthese, 198:4 (2021), 3073–98.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schipper, Arthur, ‘Necessitation and the Changing Past’, Theoria, 88:5 (2022a), 9971013.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schipper, Arthur, ‘Ontological Accounting and Aboutness’, Asian Journal of Philosophy, 1:1 (2022b), 18.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schipper, Arthur, ‘Inquiry & Ordinary Truthmakers’, Metaphysica, 23:2 (2022c), 247–73.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schipper, Arthur, ‘Singular Terms and Ontological Seriousness’, Journal of the American Philosophical Association, 9:3 (2023), 574–95.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schipper, Arthur and Snowdon, Paul, ‘Henry Habberley Price’, in Zalta, E. and Nodelman, U. (eds.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2023 Edition), https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/price/.Google Scholar
Searle, John, Intentionality (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1983).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sider, Theodore, Hawthorne, John, and Zimmerman, Dean (eds.), Contemporary Debates in Metaphysics (Oxford: Blackwell, 2008).Google Scholar
Smith, Barry, ‘Truthmaker Realism’, Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 77:3 (1999), 274–91.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Snowdon, Paul, ‘Perception, Vision and Causation’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 81:1 (1981), 175–92.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stove, David, The Plato Cult (Oxford: Blackwell, 1991).Google Scholar
Sundholm, Göran, ‘Existence, Proof and Truth-Making’, Topoi, 13:2 (1994a), 117–26.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sundholm, Göran, ‘Ontologic versus Epistemologic’, in Prawitz, D. and Westerståhl, D. (eds.), Logic and Philosophy of Science in Uppsala (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1994b), 373–83.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sundholm, Göran, ‘Antirealism and the Roles of Truth’, in Niiniluoto, I., Sintonen, M., and Wolenski, J. (eds.), Handbook of Epistemology (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 2004), 437–66.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sundholm, Göran, ‘Ontological Descriptivism’, lecture given at the Workshop Assertion and Proof in Lecce on 12 September 2019.Google Scholar
Tahko, Tuomas, ‘Armstrong on Truthmaking and Realism’, in Calemi, F.F. (ed.), Metaphysics and Scientific Realism (Berlin: De Gruyter, 2015), 207–18.Google Scholar
Taylor, Luke, ‘What's So Queer About Morality?’, The Journal of Ethics, 24 (2020), 1129.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Unger, Peter, All the Power in the World (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Unger, Peter, ‘There Are No Ordinary Things’, in Philosophical Papers Volume 2 (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1979/2006), 336.Google Scholar
Williamson, Timothy, ‘Abductive Philosophy’, Philosophical Forum, 47:3–4 (2016), 263–80.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wittgenstein, Ludwig, Philosophical Investigations (New York: Macmillan, 1953).Google Scholar
Yablo, Stephen, Aboutness (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2014).Google Scholar
Zhong, Konglu, Are There Ineffable Facts? (Master's Thesis, Peking University, Department of Philosophy & Religious Studies, 2022).Google Scholar