Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-8ctnn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-28T11:05:03.320Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Values-Based Practice: A Theory-Practice Dynamic for Navigating Values and Difference in Health Care

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 September 2023

Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

This chapter introduces values-based practice as a resource for working with individually diverse values in health and social care, and describes its origins in an on-going development through the resources of philosophy. The chapter is in two main sections. Section I, Values-Based Practice, builds on two brief interactive exercises to introduce and explain the key features of values-based practice. As a relatively recent addition to the range of resources for working with values in health and social care, values-based practice is distinctive in focussing on the diversity of values comprising individual lived experience. Like evidence-based practice, values-based practice is a process-driven rather than an outcome-driven methodology. That is to say, rather than offering prescribed answers, both approaches offer processes that support decision-makers in coming to answers for themselves based on the particular circumstances presented by the situation in question. Although entirely complementary, the processes involved are of course different. Where evidence-based practice relies on meta-analyses of the results of high-quality clinical trials to inform a consensual model of decision-making, values-based practice builds on learnable clinical skills and other process elements to inform a dissensual model of decision-making rather than seeking to overcome value-conflicts in reaching consensus. Working within a premise of mutual respect for differences of values, and guided by three key principles linking values and evidence, values-based practice, as described in the chapter, supports dissensual decision-making, balanced according to the circumstances presented by the decision in question, within frameworks of locally-set frameworks of shared values. Section II, The Theory-Practice Dynamic, then outlines the theory-practice dynamic on which values-based practice is based. The origins of values-based practice in mid-twentieth century ordinary language philosophy of the Oxford School are outlined. As the chapter illustrates, although a limited area of analytic philosophy, many aspects of values-based practice are informed by ordinary language philosophy, ranging from its premise, through the training exercises and other process elements described in Section I, to its role in hybrid empirical studies supporting its model of service delivery. The development of values-based practice, furthermore, as section II goes on to describe, is ongoing, with key initiatives drawing not only on both analytic and Continental traditions of European philosophy, but also on non-European philosophies such as those of Africa and the Caribbean.

Type
Paper
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of The Royal Institute of Philosophy

Introduction

Dancing with AngelsFootnote 1

Natalie (not her real name) was accompanied by angels. They used to sing to her and she to them. Natalie would often dance with her angels and though she caused no problems she was regularly taken to hospital and prescribed antipsychotic medication. Natalie refused to take medication because she believed that it killed her angels. In her mid-twenties she was detained on an involuntary basis and put on depot medication without her consent. Natalie subsequently took her own life. She left a note saying she couldn't face living without her angels.

Natalie's tragic story captures much that is important about values-based practice in health and social care. Below in this chapter we describe values-based practice in detail. But Natalie's story anticipates a number of key points about values and values-based practice that we should bear in mind throughout:

  • Values as what matters to the individual person: health-related values include anything that matters or is important to those directly involved in a given situation; Natalie's voices mattered more to her than anything else in her life.

  • Values beyond moral judgement: health-related values thus include but are wider than ethical and legal values; those concerned with Natalie's care genuinely thought they were doing ‘right’ by her and they used their powers of involuntary (i.e., compulsory) treatment entirely within the legal rules; yet, it was the failure to take seriously what mattered to Natalie that led in this story to tragedy.

  • Health-related values include centrally (but are not limited to) those of the service user concerned; this is why the story makes a point of noting that Natalie's dancing with her angels caused no problems for other people. Had her voices been, for example, urging her to harm someone, the balance of values would have been less unequivocal.

  • Health-related values require a process for balanced decision-making where values conflict: Natalie's story is very individual to her and (beyond the importance of the individual uniqueness of values) implies no general rule about voice hearing; as just noted, had her angels told her to harm other people, her story would have been a different story requiring different decision-making.

  • A process-based model of balanced decision-making is provided by values-based practice: it starts from a recognition of the diversity of individual values as they impact on health care (some people who hear voices want to get rid of them; Natalie's voices mattered so much to her that she couldn't live without them); and rather than seeking a rule defining pre-set ‘right’ outcomes, values-based practice relies on clinical skills and other process elements (described below) for balanced decision-making in the situation in question.

  • As a decision-support tool, values-based practice is a partner to evidence-based practice: there is good evidence that a recovery-oriented person-centred approach to supporting Natalie with her voices would have had a positive outcome for everyone.

So described, values and values-based practice raise a whole series of long-standing philosophical issues, not least in the long-running ‘is-ought'debate about the relationship between facts and values (or descriptive and evaluative meanings). This is why values-based practice remains a product of an ongoing theory-practice dynamic. Practical implementation is not contingent on the underlying theoretical issues being resolved. But engaging with these issues both enhances philosophical work in relevant areas while at the same time ensuring that values-based practice continues to develop as a research-led discipline rather than collapsing into pragmatically-driven received simplifications.

In this chapter, we will first describe values-based practice as it is used in contemporary health and social care, and then indicate a number of future developments arising from the continued operation of the theory-practice dynamic on which it is based.

Section I: Values-Based Practice

As a practical discipline, values-based practice is best understood by ‘doing not saying’, that is to say, being a skills-based approach it is most effectively learned through practical engagement with the issues rather than from merely reading about them. Hence, we will introduce it here with two of the interactive exercises we have developed for medical students and other healthcare workers as part of their training for front-line clinical and social care. We will describe these exercises and their usual outcomes so there is no need to do them for yourself. But they take only a few moments each, and you may find doing them for real illuminating.

Exercise 1: The Three Words ExerciseFootnote 2

Although based on the philosophical principles outlined below, the ‘three words’ exercise works as an exercise in word association.

The exercise is simply to ‘write down three words (or very short phrases) that mean ‘values’ to you .

If you try this for yourself, take a few moments to actually write down your own ‘three words’ before reading on – in training exercises we find writing your answers down rather than just doing the exercise ‘in your head’ makes a big difference to learning (remember, this is about ‘doing not saying’!).

Figure 1 (over page) shows the answers given in one of our training exercises – how did your three words compare with these? What strikes you about Figure 1?

Figure 1 A sample of the triplets of words given by participants in a training session in values-based practice.

There are two key learning points to take from this exercise:

1) The diversity of values – this is reflected in the variety of triplets people come up with. There are repeat words, certainly (‘principles’, for example, and ‘best interests’) but even running this exercise with up to 200 students we have never yet had two respondents come up with exactly the same three words.

If you are not surprised by this perhaps you should be. After all, ‘values’ is not an unfamiliar word. In a sense we all know what it means. But when it comes to a challenge of this sort, it appears we all mean something slightly different by this term! On the other hand, once we identify ‘values’ as the non-technical and pre-reflective notion to simply mean ‘what matters to you’, the diversity of individual values should perhaps not come as a surprise.

In the next exercise we will see how the diversity of meanings we attach to the word ‘values’ is reflected in the diversity of the personal values that drive our choices in health and social care.

2) Values and ‘what matters to you’ – if we look again at Figure 1, we notice something else – yes, everyone's triplet is different; but there is nothing in the triplets of words people come up with that seems simply nothing to do with values.

So, we can think of the results of this exercise as picking out different aspects of what – despite the everyday familiarity of the word ‘values’ – is a complex multifaceted notion. We will return to this point in the second half of the chapter when we look at the theory underpinning values-based practice. For now, one way of drawing together these different meanings, is to say that for clinical purposes, ‘values’ include …

  • anything that matters or is important to those concerned in the situation in question.

This (admittedly tautological) definition may perhaps be lacking philosophically in clarity and depth as much as in content. But it works well in clinical contexts to emphasise the breadth and diversity of relevant issues. It also provides a helpful nominal link between values-based practice and the growing international ‘what matters to you?’ movement, which as its name suggests, promotes the importance of finding out ‘what matters to you?’.Footnote 3 The next exercise shows why this is significant, why it is that (as in values-based practice) clinical decision-making should be based on asking not only ‘what is the matter with you?’ but also ‘what matters to you?’.

Exercise 2: A Forced Choice Exercise

Where the three words exercise is an exercise in word association, the ‘forced choice’ exercise requires an effort of the imagination.

Imagine you have developed early symptoms of a potentially fatal disease.

There are two possible evidence-based treatments available, both of which offer advantages but neither of which is perfect:

  • TREATMENT A – gives you a guaranteed period of remission but no cure

  • TREATMENT B – gives you a 50:50 chance of ‘kill or cure’

It's your decision – what is the minimum period of remission you would want from Treatment A to choose that treatment rather than choosing the 50:50 ‘kill or cure’ option offered by Treatment B?

Write down, 1) your minimum period, and then, 2) your reasons for choosing the period that you did.

Figure 2 illustrates the wide range of minimum figures people come up with when they do this exercise. This is nothing to do with differences in the evidence-base of the decision: everyone had the same evidence base (an artificially constrained evidence base at that). Nor has it to do with diversity in the target group: the range of responses in Figure 1 happens to be from a group of medical students, roughly 50:50 men and women, though otherwise with similar backgrounds and ages; but we find a similar range is the norm with whatever group the exercise is used.

Figure 2 A typical range of responses in the forced choice exercise.

The second part of the exercise then shows us that we get this wide range because, despite their apparent similarities, individuals bring very different personal values to the choices they make. This is the message of the ‘what matters to you?’ movement – different things matter or are important to different people. In this exercise, one person may choose perhaps 20 years because he or she has a young family and wants enough time to see them safely grown up; another may choose only a year because that person is finishing a project that he or she feels passionate about and that will take a year to complete; and so on.

Again, if you did this exercise for real, revisit your minimum figure and the reasons behind it – what mattered or was important to you in this imaginary situation?

Learning Points from the Forced Choice Exercise

The key learning point from the forced choice exercise is the link between diversity of individual values and clinical decision-making. We can sum this up as:

  • same evidence + different values = different decisions

This in turn carries other important learning points:

  • The importance of shared decision-making based on evidence and values

As clinicians we are familiar with the importance of the evidence-base for decision-making. The forced choice exercise reminds us that it is also important to take the values-base of decision making into account.

In the context of a training exercise this may seem obvious. That it is however far from obvious in practice is shown by the need for a whole international movement (noted above) pushing the importance of asking ‘what matters to you?’. The need for such a movement, furthermore, continues despite growing emphasis on the importance in clinical care of shared decision-making – that is, decision-making that is shared between clinicians (as experts on the evidence) and patients (as experts on what matters to them) within contemporary models of patient-centred care. In the United Kingdom, for example, professional guidance for doctors has made shared decision-making of this kind the basis of consent to treatment for at least the last two decades (see General Medical Council, Reference Council2008). This guidance was reinforced by a decision of the UK Supreme Court in 2015 (the Montgomery ruling, Montgomery v Lanarkshire Health Board, 2015; see also, Herring et al., Reference Herring, Fulford, Dunn and Handa2017), and it has been further reinforced by evidence-based guidelines from NICE, the UK's National Institute for Health and Care ExcellenceFootnote 4 (NICE, 2021).

So shared decision-making, it would seem, is harder than it appears. Once again, the forced choice exercise helps to explain why this should be so. We here draw attention to three salient considerations.

  • It is hard for patients

One reason shared decision-making is difficult is that it is hard for patients. If you did the forced choice exercise for real you probably found it more challenging than exercise 1 (the ‘three words’ exercise). This is partly because the situation it asks you to imagine is not a pleasant one: though of course it is not unrealistic – it may indeed be a situation similar to one with which you have personal experience. But either way, the challenge most people find is to answer it for yourself. It is easy enough to say what ‘most people’ would choose as a minimum period; or what the ‘rational choice’ would be; but answering the question in the form of your own personal decision, taken for yourself as you are currently placed (at your own age and in your own situation), is, most people find, surprisingly challenging.

This is in itself an important learning point from the exercise – that answering the forced choice question (and its cognates) even in the relatively safe environment of a training session is surprisingly hard. How much harder therefore must it be for someone faced with this or an equivalent choice in circumstances of personal existential threat in choosing one's personal treatment outcome.

  • It is also hard for clinicians

Understanding what matters to a given patient is also hard for clinicians. This is because as clinicians we are trained to understand ‘what is the matter with you’ and (wrongly) extrapolate this to understanding ‘what matters to you’. This is well illustrated by the experience of Zoe Barber, one of the pathfinders for training in values-based practice in Oxford, of her first experience as a participant in the forced choice exercise. Mindful of her impending marriage and wish to start a family, Zoe chose twenty years as her minimum period; but was shocked when she found her partner, Tom, chose eighteen months. When he explained his reasoning (this was the time he needed to finish his PhD), she understood, but as she wrote later, it was a ‘light bulb moment – If I could so misjudge the values of the man I share my life with, just how wrong might I be in assuming that I know what is important to the patient I met perhaps only five minutes ago!’ (in Handa et al., Reference Handa, Fulford-Smith, Barber, Dobbs, Fulford and Peile2016, pp. 20–7).

  • Shared decision-making and recovery in person-centred mental health

Shared decision-making is especially important in person-centred mental health care as the basis of recovery. ‘Recovery’ in this context means recovering a good quality of life as defined by the values of – by what matters or is important to – the person concerned (Slade et al., Reference Slade, Amering, Farkas, Hamilton, O'Hagan, Panther, Perkins, Shepherd, Tse and Whitley2014; Hughes et al., Reference Hughes, Crepaz-Keay, Emmett and Fulford2018). This is challenging in several ways. First, as Natalie's story at the start of this chapter illustrates, recovery, so defined, may but in other cases it may not coincide with traditional professional concerns such as symptom control. It is challenging, second, because the operative values in a number of mental health conditions may present particular difficulties of understanding (we return to the philosophical resources supporting understanding in the second half of the chapter). It is challenging, third, because in mental health, what matters to the patient may be in conflict with what matters to everyone else (which is where the resources of values-based practice for balanced decision-making that we describe immediately below, come into play). But for all these challenges, without an understanding of what matters to the individual concerned, recovery in mental health cannot even get started.

The Process Elements of Values-Based Practice

We do not have space here to describe the process elements of values-based practice in detail (but see for example, Fulford, Peile and Carroll, Reference Fulford, Peile and Carrol2015, and other Resources on the website for the Collaborating Centre for Values-based Practice in Oxford at: valuesbasedpractice.org).

The process of values-based practice is shown in the form of a summary flow diagram in Figure 3 and brief definitions of its constituent process elements are given in Figure 4. As these indicate, values-based practice is premised on mutual respect for differences of values. This does not mean that in values-based practice ‘anything goes’; on the contrary, any form of racism or other discriminatory values are by definition excluded by the requirement for mutuality (we return to the philosophical origins of this premise in the second half of the chapter).

Figure 3 A Flow Diagram of Values-based Practice.

Figure 4 Brief Definitions of the Process Elements of Values-Based Practice.

Within the premise of mutual respect, values-based practice then builds on four key areas of learnable clinical skills (awareness, knowledge, reasoning, and communication) within a particular model of service delivery (one that is person-centred and multidisciplinary) and guided by three key principles linking evidence and values (namely, the Two Feet principle, the Squeaky Wheel principle, and the Science-Driven principle). Together, these support balanced decision-making on questions of values through a particular model of partnership (dissensual partnership) operating within (locally set) frameworks of shared values.

You will see how the above two exercises provide an introduction to values-based practice. In any actual training session, a focus on individual lived experience (as a service user or service provider) is of course essential. But with this caveat, the three words exercise sets the scene for training by making participants aware of the diversity of values. Hopefully, participants come to recognise for themselves that there is more to ‘what matters to you?’ than can be captured in ethical and legal guidelines. The forced choice exercise then builds on this, acting as a focus for discussion of almost any aspect of values-based practice. This is a guided discussion aimed at understanding the practical importance of shared decision-making based on values (‘what matters to you?’) as well as evidence (of what works in dealing with ‘what's the matter with you’).

Section II: The Theory-Practice Dynamic

The importance of ensuring that values-based practice remains driven by an ongoing dynamic between theory and practice received early endorsement from what at first glance might appear an unlikely source, namely a Senior Advisory Board of experienced clinicians, managers, and politicians, who generously took on the task of guiding the VBP Centre in Oxford through its early days of developing its impact within the UK health service.Footnote 5

The background to this endorsement is worth brief reprise. Values-based practice was developed originally as a practical discipline mainly within mental health. As described further below, it was based originally on theoretical principles derived primarily from mid-twentieth century ordinary language analytic philosophy; but the philosophy as such had largely fallen out of view as the discipline started to take root in practice. For example, although the underlying philosophy had been instrumental in the development of a number of training exercises (see above), explicitly philosophical material was entirely absent from the first practical training manual for values-based practice (Woodbridge and Fulford, Reference Woodbridge and Fulford2004).

It was perhaps understandable, therefore, that when we set up The Collaborating Centre in OxfordFootnote 6 with the aim of extending values-based practice from mental health to other areas of health care, our focus at the time should have been on practice rather than theory. At the first meeting of our Advisory Board, correspondingly, we described how rather than developing the theory of values-based practice, we had identified three key areas of practice on which we would focus – training, regulation, and teamwork. Yes, good thinking, our Advisory Board commented, drawing on their considerable experience; but not, they continued, if this is at the expense of theory. There should instead be an ongoing partnership between theory and practice underpinning the work of the Centre as a whole. Theory, the Board explained, was vitally important if values-based practice was to avoid the fate of so many other initially promising initiatives, in becoming ‘dumbed down’ under the bureaucratic and other inevitable pressures of day-to-day clinical and managerial concerns. Remember, they said, the American humourist, J.L. Mencken's aphorism, variously cited along the lines of, ‘For every complex problem, there is always at least one solution that is clear, plausible – and wrong!’ (Mencken, Reference Mencken1920).

This made sense in our circumstances. Through an exchange in the early days of the Centre with (the now late) David Sackett, we were aware of his disappointment that his originally rich model of evidence-based practice, developed in his role as the Founder Director of Oxford's Centre for Evidence-based Medicine, had been, precisely as our Advisory Board warned, dumbed down. Sackett's original model of Evidence Based Medicine had three elements: it combined evidence of various kinds (appropriate to the question of concern) with clinical experience, and, yes, patients’ individual values (Sackett et al., Reference Sackett2000, p. 1) – a far cry then from much of today's evidence-based medicine in which evidence, and indeed evidence of only one kind (prototypically from randomised controlled trials), is considered relevant.Footnote 7

Thus forewarned, the work of the Centre for Values-based Practice has been pursued explicitly within an ongoing dynamic between theory (primarily but not only philosophical theory) and practice. The dynamic, we should add, is indeed ‘ongoing’: there is much of theory that remains untouched let alone explored. But by way of illustration, we will outline two areas showing the power of the theory-practice dynamic to which our Advisory Board pointed us – first, the origins of values-based practice in ordinary language philosophy; second, its ongoing development by way of a now growing range of other philosophies, both European and non-European in inspiration.

Origins in Ordinary Language Philosophy

The poster child of mid-century ordinary language philosophy of the ‘Oxford school’ was J.L. (John Langshaw) Austin, at the time White's Professor of Moral Philosophy and a Fellow of Corpus Christi College. In developing his philosophy, Austin built on the observation that we are in general better at using everyday concepts (including many of the concepts with which philosophers struggle) than we are at defining them. Something similar had been pointed out several centuries previously by the early Neo-Platonist philosopher and Bishop of Hippo, St Augustine, in his Confessions (Book 11, Chapter 14, No. 17): ‘What then is time?’, Augustine wrote, ‘Provided that no one asks me, I know. If I want to explain it to an enquirer, I do not know’ (Chadwick, Reference Chadwick1992). Why not, therefore, Austin and others argued, explore the way concepts are actually used in ordinary (i.e. non-reflective) contexts rather than (as philosophers have traditionally done) getting out of our depth with trying to define them.

Ordinary language philosophy, so defined, has been subject to much criticism, some for what it is, some for what it is not (see for example various essays in the collection by K.T. Fann, Reference Fann1969). Rather than exploring its pros and cons in general we will focus here on four aspects of the resources it brings to the development of values-based practice.

1) Focusing where practice ‘is at’

As a method, ordinary language philosophy is highly compatible with the challenges of practice in that it focuses on where the conceptual problems of practice are ‘at’, i.e., in ordinary everyday usage. Much of clinical care (at least in acute hospital medicine) can proceed up to a point effectively with little regard to conceptual problems; there are after all in such contexts sufficient empirical problems with which to engage. But where conceptual issues arise in health care (notably, as we describe further below, in mental health care), they arise as problems in everyday practice and are framed in the language of practice.

The language of practice, moreover, as Austin himself pointed out, is particularly well displayed, again consistently with clinical experience, through case studies. Towards the end of one of Austin's most explicitly methodological papers, A Plea for Excuses, having worked from legal case reports, he directs philosophers to the (as he believes) richer resources of case material in (what he calls) ‘abnormal psychology’: ‘There is’, he says, anticipating by some forty years the development of values-based practice in mental health (described below), ‘gold in them thar hills’ (Austin, Reference Austin1956/7, p. 24).

2a) A more complete view: the three words training exercise

Austin had a very modest view of his proposals for ordinary language philosophy. Indeed, he repeatedly caveated its potential. One such caveat was the extent of its outputs: it gave us, at most, and only with concepts of the kind for which it was suited, a ‘more complete view’ of their meanings. When we try to define a complex concept, so Austin argued, we tend to focus on one or other aspect of its meaning; exploring ordinary usage, on the other hand, expands our view to encompass a more complete view of its meaning. Exploring ordinary usage thus gives us what another philosopher working in this tradition, Gilbert Ryle, called the ‘logical geography’ (Ryle, 1949, Reference Ryle1963 edition, p. 10).

The Austin/Ryle ‘more complete view’ is directly reflected in the three words training exercise for values-based practice described above. Merely asking participants to ‘define’ what they mean by ‘values’ would leave them at best bemused. As a word association exercise, by contrast, participants see for themselves the diverse aspects of the meaning of this complex concept: that it is broader than ethics, highly individual, and so on (though not inchoate); and through guided discussion they come to embrace a shared summary of these meanings for practical use as ‘anything that matters or is important to the individual concerned’.

2b) A more complete view: the fact/value distinction in health care

The Austin/Ryle ‘more complete view’ also has substantive implications for our understanding of the concepts (disease, illness, etc.) defining health care. Indeed, the guiding model of values-based practice – as a partner to evidence-based practice supporting clinical decision-making in all areas of healthcare – is itself an aspect of this more complete view.

Again, we will not have space to develop this aspect of the theory underpinning values-based practice in detail (but see the More about Values-based Practice at: values-basedpractice.org). The model starts from an observation of another of Austin's pupils, and a successor as White's Professor, R.M. Hare, that we can sum up as ‘diverse values become visible values’ (Hare, Reference Hare1952, p. 123 et seq.; Hare, Reference Hare1963; this idea is incorporated in the process elements of values-based practice as the Squeaky Wheel Principle, see Figure 4). Combining this with the work of the American philosopher Hilary Putnam on facts and values being distinct but not dichotomous (Putnam, Reference Putnam2002)Footnote 8 suggests that health concepts are always hybrid, i.e. part-fact/part-value (Fulford, Reference Fulford1989). We see this, notably, in the overtly value-laden concepts of mental disorder (discussed further below); but health concepts may appear to be value free where (as in the context of life-threatening acute hospital care) the operative values (such as, in this case, relief of pain and saving life) are widely shared.

It is this hybrid model, in essence, by which values-based practice has been guided throughout: from its original theoretical formulation and development in mental health, through its wider partnership with evidence-based medicine, to contemporary applications such as the shared decision-making based on evidence and values that (as described above) is at the heart of today's person-centred clinical care.

3) A collaborative approach

Integral to Austin's modest conception of ordinary language philosophy is his idea that philosophers should model themselves on empirical scientists by collaborating in teams rather than (as they have traditionally done) working alone as ‘sole traders’. Austin's inspiration for this idea was his experience as an intelligence officer in the Second World War: he had been impressed by the way teams could solve complex problems by tackling them piecemeal.

In the development of values-based practice we combined Austin's ideas on team work with the quasi-empirical nature of ordinary language philosophy (he calls it at one point, philosophical ‘fieldwork’, Austin, Reference Austin1979, p. 25), to employ a hybrid philosophical/social science methodology to explore differences of implicit values within multi-disciplinary teams (Colombo et al., Reference Colombo, Bendelow, Fulford and Williams2003; and Fulford and Colombo, Reference Fulford and Colombo2004). The key result from this work – that the range of implicit values exhibited by team members matched the range of implicit values exhibited by patients – became the basis for the ‘extended’ multidisciplinary team of values-based Practice (see Figure 4).

4) A starting point – sometimes the first word, never the last

Ordinary language philosophy comes with a further important caveat, again, repeatedly emphasised by Austin, namely that he was not proposing anything in the way of a philosophical sinecure. One of Austin's pupils, and later biographical editor, Sir Geoffrey Warnock, reports Austin as opening a seminar on ordinary language philosophy with ‘I want to say something today about one way of possibly getting started with some kinds of philosophical problem’ (Warnock, Reference Warnock1989, p. 6). Elsewhere Austin himself writes in similar vein to the effect that ordinary language philosophy may sometimes be ‘the first word (but) never the last’ (cited by Warnock, Reference Warnock1989, p. xx).

This caveat, so often ignored by the critics of ordinary language philosophy, has many important consequences for values-based practice, not the least of which is its recent flowering into other areas of philosophy. Ordinary language philosophy has proven highly effective in getting values-based practice started. In Austin's terms it has been a fruitful ‘first word’; but as Austin himself anticipated, and as we illustrate in the next section, it is far from being the ‘last word’.

Ongoing Development and Other Philosophies

As several times noted, values-based practice was developed first in mental health. This might seem surprising given the widely perceived ‘second-class’ status of mental health among health disciplines. It reflects, however, another of Austin's insights, namely that the most productive areas for ordinary language philosophy are often just those areas where the concepts of interest appear to break down or in other ways cause difficulties. This is not unlike the medical example of diabetes (where the pancreas stops working properly) leading to the eventual discovery of insulin. Austin used the metaphor of a ‘blinding veil of ease and obviousness’ to capture the idea that the full meanings of complex concepts may be hidden from us by the facility with which we use them in unproblematic contexts (Austin, Reference Austin1956/57, p. 23).

Following Austin's lead, the conceptual challenges presented by mental health are thus opportunities for breaking through the ‘blinding veil’ to a more complete view of the meanings of the health concepts as a whole. This is indeed what we find. If the conceptual insights summarised above are correct, the overtly value-laden concepts of mental disorder are not an indication, somehow, of deficiencies in the mental health disciplines, but a sign rather that the health concepts as a whole are (in part and albeit often covertly) evaluative in nature.

This is of course an arguable claim (though the argument, as recent commentators have pointed out, has moved on from whether the health concepts are in part evaluative in nature to where the line between fact and value should be drawn, see Stein et al., Reference Stein, Nielsen, Hartford, Gagné-Julien, Glackin, Friston, Maj, Zachar and Aftabforthcoming, 2023). But even if it is correct, we should anticipate (again, following Austin, point 4 above) that this will not be the last word on the subject. This indeed has been our experience in developing values-based practice. We noted above the results of combining ordinary language philosophy with methods derived from the social sciences. We will focus in the rest of this section on the results of extending the theoretical base of values-based practice to other areas of philosophy in the context, first of mental health, then of health care as a whole.

Philosophy, Values-Based Practice and Mental Health

As noted above, values-based practice, reflecting the overtly value-laden nature of concepts of mental health, was developed first for use in this area of health care. And it is the challenges presented by the values operative in mental health that continue to drive the development of values-based practice in mental health.

To be clear, there is much in mental health (as of course there is in bodily health) that is susceptible to values-based interventions based only on its original formulation in ordinary language philosophy. The outcome of Natalie's story at the start of this chapter, of ‘Dancing with Angels’, was a tragedy precisely because it could have been avoided if her self-evident values had been listened to. Indeed, the very concept of ‘recovery’ in mental health is values-driven in that, as noted above, recovery means recovering a good quality of life as defined by the values of (by what is important to) the person concerned. Which makes it all the more important to recognise that the operative values may be considerably more obscure than in Natalie's story. How, for example, should we understand people with anorexia who make clear, just as explicitly as Natalie made her values clear, that they value fasting and weight loss even more than their own death? Or how should we understand people with addictive disorders who both wish and do not wish to continue their addictive behaviour?

Developments in phenomenologically-enriched values-based practice are proving effective in areas such as these, where the operative values are obscure to ordinary empathic understanding. Thus, the Italian philosopher and psychiatrist, Giovanni Stanghellini, has developed a range of insights based on Jean Paul Sartre's three-way phenomenology of the body, into the pre-conscious (or pre-reflective) life world of people with anorexia (Stanghellini, Reference Stanghellini2017). Combining this with empirical methods he has developed both therapeutic (Stanghellini, Reference Stanghellini2019) and research interventions (Stanghellini et al., Reference Stanghellini, Castellini, Brogna, Faravelli and Ricca2012). Similar phenomenologically-inspired work on addictive disorders, drawing in this instance on dialectical methods and extending to policy-level interventions, has been developed by the Brazilian phenomenologist and psychiatrist, Guilherme Messas (Messas, Reference Messas2021; Messas and Fulford, Reference Messas and Fulford2021a and Reference Messas and Fulford2021b).

In this and other areas, then, we have seen a coming together in values-based practice of two traditionally separate strands of European philosophy, respectively analytic philosophy and phenomenology. Analytic philosophy has much to offer still, it should be said. Take, for example, Anna Bergqvist's work on the relationality of values in psychiatric ethics and shared decision-making (described below). And in a contrasting area, the mathematician and philosopher, Philipp Koralus, has developed a computable model of rationality based on semiotic logic (his ‘erotetic theory’ of rationality, see Koralus and Mascarenhas, Reference Koralus and Mascarenhas2013) with potentially important implications for understanding and intervening in severe mental disorders such as schizophrenia (Parrott and Koralus, Reference Parrott and Koralus2015).

A further and quite different area of development has drawn on philosophies that are non-European in origin. Such philosophies have found important applications for example in relation to the much-contested area of race relations in mental health. Leading the field in this has been the activist and expert-by-experience, Colin King, drawing notably on the work of the French Caribbean philosopher and psychiatrist, Franz Fanon (King et al., Reference King, Clarke, Gillard, Fulford, Stoyanov, Stanghellini, Staden, Wong and Fulford2021; Fulford, King, and Bergqvist, Reference Fulford, King and Bergqvist2023). King's work identifies the origins of racial bias in psychiatry in unacknowledged values of whiteness operating through judgements of rationality implicit in psychiatric diagnostic categories. This has implications for a remedial approach based on values-based principles of co-production across lines of colour.Footnote 9 This work is important in its own right and in addition has wider implications for reducing the notorious vulnerability of psychiatry to abusive uses for political (rather than legitimately medical) ends.

Philosophy, Values-Based Practice, and Health Care

Given Austin's mental health first message, we should not be surprised to find theoretical developments in the rest of healthcare following the lead set by mental health, drawing that is to say on both European and non-European philosophical sources. The driver though in the context of bodily health is not (in general) empathically obscure values but the need to expand the horizons of values-based practice from individual to social values.

The need for such an expansion was pointed out originally by the Indian analytic moral philosopher Shridhar Venkatapuram (Reference Venkatapuram and Loughlin2014). Pointing to the findings of the epidemiologist Sir Michael Marmot, with whom he had been working, Venkatapuram argued that in focussing on individual values, values-based practice was misaligned with current evidence suggesting that the main drivers of pathology in most areas of bodily health were not individual and biological but social and political.

Our response to this has been, in part, an open access collection of case studies in social values and health care edited by the Bulgarian psychiatrist and philosopher Drozdstoj Stojanov (Stojanov et al., Reference Stoyanov, Stanghellini, Van Staden, Wong and Fulford2021). This includes case studies from the South African philosopher and psychiatrist Werdie van Staden on what he has called Batho Pele, a distinct form of values-based practice based on African philosophical concepts that, uniquely, transcend the individual/social divide: van Staden's contributions to Stoyanov's volume illustrate the impact of Batho Pele in both clinical (Van Staden, Reference Van Staden, Stoyanov, Stanghellini, Van Staden, Wong and Fulford2021) and policy (Ujewe and Van Staden, Reference Van Staden, Stoyanov, Stanghellini, Van Staden, Wong and Fulford2021) contexts.

A second philosophical response to Venkatapuram's challenge has been work by the the analytic philosopher Anna Bergqvist (who is Theory Lead for the Collaborating Centre), based on Iris Murdoch's work on the relationality of values in psychiatric ethics (Bergqvist, Reference Bergqvist, Panizza and Hopwood2022), moral philosophy (Bergqvist, Reference Bergqvist, Werkhoven and Dennis2018a, Reference Bergqvist, Bergqvist and Cowan2018b), and shared decision-making (Bergqvist, Reference Bergqvist2020). According to this work, we should understand values in general, whether expressed individually or socially, as arising not as it were ‘within one's head’, but discursively in the interactions between people. The analytic philosophy driving this conclusion has wide-ranging implications for all areas of health care. In Bergqvist's own work, it has been guiding her development of closer collaboration between experts-by-experience and experts-by-training in multiple areas ranging from the shared clinical decision-making, outlined above, through to policy based on new models of public mental health.Footnote 10

Conclusions

In this chapter we have introduced by way of two interactive exercises the key features of values-based practice and then outlined the importance of philosophy both in its origins and its ongoing development.

A couple of caveats – one practical, the other philosophical – are necessary. The practical caveat is that values-based practice is only one tool in an increasingly rich toolbox of resources available to health and social care for working with values. Besides ethics and medical law, other tools in the values toolbox include decision analysis (the basis of online and other clinical decision aids) and health economics. Values-based practice as we have described adds to the toolbox a resource for working particularly with individual values (whether or not relationally derived) in the context of shared clinical decision-making. Values-based practice, so understood, is in this respect, again as we have indicated, a partner to evidence-based practice in supporting shared clinical decision-making. In its partnership with evidence-based practice, however, values-based practice is most effectively deployed alongside other tools in the values toolbox.

Our philosophical caveat is that the theory-practice dynamic described in the second half of the chapter should be understood as a two-way dynamic, with philosophy benefitting as much from its exposure to practice, as practice benefits from its exposure to philosophy. Both sides of the dynamic are important. So important has been the contribution of philosophy to practice that there is a sense in which values-based practice could be regarded as a philosophy-into-practice offshoot of the wider resurgence of interdisciplinary work between philosophy and psychiatry that emerged in the 1990s (Fulford et al., Reference Fulford, Morris, Sadler and Stanghellini2003). There are of course many relevant areas of philosophy that have still to pick up the opportunities offered by values-based practice (the philosophy of science, for example, and political philosophy). But from the start there have been clear examples of the benefits the other way, of interdisciplinary work in philosophy and psychiatry being of as much benefit to philosophy as to practice.Footnote 11

The opening story in this chapter, of the tragic outcome of Natalie being denied her dancing with angels, was intended to root the chapter in the realities of day-to-day clinical care. As a story from mental health, the ‘mental health second’ stereotype still so widely prevalent in health care, may make the story appear less relevant to other ‘more scientific’ areas. This is perhaps why, it may be thought, so much of the recent practical development of values-based practice noted in the first half of the chapter has been in areas of bodily medicine such as surgery. But Austin's observation guiding the philosophical development of values-based practice shows the opposite to be the case. Recall that in ordinary language philosophy, Austin argued, we have most to learn from where things go wrong. This then suggests a quite different – a ‘mental health first’ – bottom line from Natalie's story: that mental health in leading the development of philosophically-informed values-based practice, far from being in second place, is showing the way forward for person-centred health care as a whole.

Footnotes

1 Based on real events but with identifying details altered – from Crepaz-Keay and Fulford (Reference Crepaz-Keay, Fulford, Parker, Schnackenberg and Hopfenbeck2021).

2 This exercise was devised originally by Kim Woodbridge, a nurse trainer at the Sainsbury Centre for Mental Health, who worked with Bill Fulford to develop the first training manual for values-based practice (see Woodbridge and Fulford, Reference Woodbridge and Fulford2004).

3 See https://wmty.world. Many organisations have their own websites dedicated to WMTY – see for example, The Institute for Healthcare Improvement website at: https://www.ihi.org/Topics/WhatMatters/Pages/default.aspx.

4 NICE is responsible for providing evidence-based guidelines for the interventions that can and cannot be provided within the UK's National Health Service.

5 For details of our Founder Advisory Board, see https://valuesbasedpractice.org/who-are-we/advisory-board/.

6 Its full title is The Collaborating Centre for Values-based Practice in Health and Social Care, St Catherine's College, Oxford, see https://valuesbasedpractice.org.

7 The relevance hierarchy is upended for values-based practice in which lived experience comes out at the apex (see Fulford, Reference Fulford2020).

8 Read as arguing that the distinction between fact and value (or description and evaluation) is necessary to ordinary usage even though it cannot be traced all the way back to individual examples of pure forms of either.

11 For an early example, see Hoerl (2001).

13 Original date of publication, 1949.

14 Portuguese translation: Arthur Maciel, 2012. Also available as a free download at: https://valuesbasedpractice.org/more-about-vbp/full-text-downloads/ (and scroll down to Whose Values: A Workbook).

References

Austin, John, ‘A Plea for Excuses’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 57 (1956/7), 130. Reprinted in A.R. White (ed.), The Philosophy of Action (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1968).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Austin, John, Philosophical Papers, 3rd edition, (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1979).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bergqvist, Anna, ‘Moral Perception and Relational Self-Cultivation: Reassessing Attunement as a Virtue’, in Werkhoven, S. and Dennis, M. (eds.), Ethics and Self-Cultivation: Historical and Contemporary Perspectives (London: Routledge, 2018a), 197221.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bergqvist, Anna, ‘Moral Perception, Thick Concepts and Perspectivalism’, in Bergqvist, Anna and Cowan, R. (eds.), Evaluative Perception (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2018b), 258–81.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bergqvist, Anna, ‘Narrative Understanding, Value and Diagnosis: A Particularist Account of Clinical Formulations and Shared Decision-Making in Mental Health’, Philosophy, Psychology & Psychiatry, 27:2 (2020), 149–67.Google Scholar
Bergqvist, Anna, ‘Psychiatric Ethics’, in Panizza, Silvia Caprioglio and Hopwood, Mark (eds.), The Murdochian Mind (London: Routledge, 2022), 479–92.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chadwick, Henry (trans.), St Augustine Confessions (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1992).Google Scholar
Colombo, Anthiny, Bendelow, Gillian, Fulford, Kenneth, and Williams, Simon, ‘Evaluating the Influence of Implicit Models of Mental Disorder on Processes of Shared Decision Making within Community-Based Multidisciplinary Teams’, Social Science & Medicine, 56 (2003), 1557–70.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Crepaz-Keay, David and Fulford, Kenneth, ‘Voices, Values and Values-Based Practice: Engaging with What Matters in Voice Hearing’, in Parker, I., Schnackenberg, J., and Hopfenbeck, Mark (eds.), The Practical Handbook of Hearing Voices: Therapeutic and Creative Approaches (Monmouth, UK: PCCS Books, 2021), 113–22.Google Scholar
Fann, K.T. (ed.), Symposium on J.L. Austin (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1969).Google Scholar
Fulford, Kenneth, Moral Theory and Medical Practice (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989, reprinted 1995 and 1999).Google Scholar
Fulford, Kenneth, ‘Editorial’, JNDS (Journal of the Nuffield Department of Surgical Sciences), 1:4 (2020), available at: https://journal.nds.ox.ac.uk/index.php/JNDS/article/view/125.Google Scholar
Fulford, Kenneth, Morris, Katherine, Sadler, John, and Stanghellini, Giovanni (eds.), Nature and Narrative: An Introduction to the New Philosophy of Psychiatry (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2003).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fulford, Kenneth and Colombo, Anthony, ‘Six Models of Mental Disorder: A Study Combining Linguistic-Analytic and Empirical Methods’, Philosophy, Psychiatry & Psychology, 11:2 (2004), 129–44.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fulford, K.W.M (Bill), Peile, Ed, and Carrol, Heidi, Essential Values-Based Practice: Clinical Stories Linking Science with People (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2012).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fulford, Kenneth, King, Colin, and Bergqvist, Anna, ‘The Inter-Personal Lived World of Values and Race Equality in Mental Health’, PSN (Psychiatrie. Sciences Humaines and Neuroscience), 21:1 (2023), 3146.Google Scholar
Council, General Medical, Consent: Patients and Doctors Making Decisions Together (London: The Genral Medical Council, 2008).12Google Scholar
Handa, Ashok, Fulford-Smith, Lucy, Barber, Zoe, Dobbs, Thomas, Fulford, Kenneth, and Peile, Edward, ‘The Importance of Seeing Things from Someone Else's Point of View’, BMJ Careers online journal (2016), available at: http://careers.bmj.com/careers/advice/The_importance_of_seeing_things_from_someone_else's_point_of_view.Google Scholar
Hare, Richard, The Language of Morals (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1952).Google Scholar
Hare, Richard, ‘Descriptivism’, Proceedings of the British Academy, 49 (1963), 115–34. Reprinted in R.M. Hare, Essays on the Moral Concepts (London: Macmillan, 1972).Google Scholar
Herring, Jonathan, Fulford, Kenneth, Dunn, Michael, and Handa, Ashok, ‘Elbow Room for Best Practice? Montgomery, Patients’ values, and Balanced Decision-Making in Person-Centred Care’, Medical Law Review, 25:4 (2017), 582603.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hoerl, Christoph, ‘Understanding, Explaining, and Intersubjectivity in Schizophrenia’, Philosophy, Psychiatry & Psychology, 8:2 (2017), 83–8.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hughes, Julian, Crepaz-Keay, David, Emmett, Charlotte, and Fulford, Kenneth, ‘The Montgomery Ruling, Individual Values and Shared Decision-Making in Psychiatry’, British Journal of Psychiatry Advances, 24 (2018), 93100.Google Scholar
King, Colin, Clarke, Simon, Gillard, Steven, and Fulford, Kenneth, ‘Beyond the Color Bar: Sharing Narratives in Order to Promote a Clearer Understanding of Mental Health Issues across Cultural and Racial Boundaries’, in Stoyanov, Drozdstoj, Stanghellini, Giovanni, Staden, Werdie Van, Wong, Michael, and Fulford, Kenneth (eds.), International Perspectives in Values-Based Mental Health Practice: Case Studies and Commentaries (Berlin: Springer Nature, 2021), 403–9.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Koralus, Philipp and Mascarenhas, Salvador, ‘The Erotetic Theory of Reasoning: Bridges between Formal Semantics and the Psychology of Deductive Inference’, Philosophical Perspectives, 27:1 (2013), 312–65.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mencken, H.L., Prejudices: Second Series (Whitefish, Montana: Kessinger Publishing, 1920, reprinted 2006).Google Scholar
Messas, Guilherme, The Existential Structure of Substance Disorders: A Psychopathological Study (Berlin: Springer Nature, 2021).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Messas, Guilherme and Fulford, Kenneth, ‘Three Dialectics of Disorder: Refocusing Phenomenology For 21st Century Psychiatry’, Lancet Psychiatry, 8:10 (2021a), 855–7.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Messas, Guilherme and Fulford, Kenneth, ‘A Values-Based Phenomenology for Substance Use Disorder: A New Approach for Clinical Decision-Making’, Estudos de Psicologia (Campinas), 38 (2021b), 111.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Montgomery v Lanarkshire Health Board (judgement delivered 11 March 11 2015): https://www.supremecourt.uk/cases/uksc-2013-0136.html.Google Scholar
NICE, Shared Decision Making NICE Guideline (London: National Institute for Health and care Excellence, 2021).Google Scholar
Parrott, Matthew and Koralus, Philipp, ‘The Erotetic Theory of Delusional Thinking’, Journal of Cognitive Neuropsychiatry, 20:5 (2015), 398415.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Putnam, Hilary, The Collapse of the Fact/Value Dichotomy and other Essays (Cambridge, MA, and London, England: Harvard University Press, 2002).Google Scholar
Ryle, Gilbert, The Concept of Mind (London and New York: Penguin Books, 1963).13Google Scholar
Sackett, David, S.E. Straus, Scott Richardson, William Rosenberg, and R.B. Haynes, Evidence-Based Medicine: How to Practice and Teach EBM, 2nd edition, (Edinburgh and London: Churchill Livingstone, 2000).Google Scholar
Slade, Michael, Amering, Michaela, Farkas, M., Hamilton, B., O'Hagan, M., Panther, G., Perkins, Rachel, Shepherd, G., Tse, S., and Whitley, R., ‘Uses and Abuses of Recovery: Implementing Recovery-Oriented Practices in mental Health Systems’, World Psychiatry, 13 (2014), 1220.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Stanghellini, Giovanni, Lost in Dialogue: Anthropology, Psychopathology, and Care (Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press, 2017).Google Scholar
Stanghellini, Giovanni, ‘The PHD Method for Psychotherapy: Integrating Phenomenology, Hermeneutics, and Psychodynamics’, Psychopathology, 52:2 (2019), 7584.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Stanghellini, Giovanni, Castellini, G., Brogna, P., Faravelli, C., and Ricca, V., ‘Identity and Eating Disorders (IDEA): A Questionnaire Evaluating Identity and Embodiment in Eating Disorder Patients’, Psychopathology, 45:3 (2012), 147–58.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Stein, Dan J., Nielsen, Kris, Hartford, Anna, Gagné-Julien, Anne-Marie, Glackin, Shane, Friston, Karl, Maj, Mario, Zachar, Peter and Aftab, Awais, ‘Philosophy of Psychiatry: Theoretical Advances and Clinical Implications’, World Psychiatry (forthcoming, 2023).Google Scholar
Stoyanov, Drozdstoj, Stanghellini, Giovanni, Van Staden, Werdie, Wong, Michael, and Fulford, Kenneth (eds.), International Perspectives in Values-Based Mental Health Practice: Case Studies and Commentaries (Berlin: Springer Nature, 2021).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ujewe, Sanuel and Van Staden, Werdie, ‘Policy-Making Indabas to Prevent “Not Listening”: An Added Recommendation from the Life Esidimeni Tragedy’, in Stoyanov, Drozdstoj, Stanghellini, Giovanni, Staden, Werdie Van, Wong, Michael, and Fulford, Kenneth, (eds.), International Perspectives in Values-Based Mental Health Practice: Case Studies and Commentaries (Berlin: Springer Nature, 2021), 257–62.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Van Staden, Werdie, ‘“Thinking Too Much”: A Clash of Legitimate Values in Clinical Practice Calls for an Indaba Guided by African Values-Based Practice’, in Stoyanov, Drozdstoj, Stanghellini, Giovanni, Van Staden, Werdie, Wong, Michael, and Fulford, Kenneth (eds), International Perspectives in Values-Based Mental Health Practice: Case Studies and Commentaries (Berlin: Springer Nature, 2021), 179–87.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Venkatapuram, Sridhar, ‘Values-Based Practice and Global Health’, in Loughlin, M. (ed.), Debates in Values-Based Practice: Arguments For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2014), 131–41.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Warnock, Geoffrey, J.L. Austin (London: Routledge, 1989).Google Scholar
Woodbridge, Kim and Fulford, Kenneth, Whose Values? A Workbook for Values-Based Practice in Mental Health Care (London: Sainsbury Centre for Mental Health, 2004).14Google Scholar
Figure 0

Figure 1 A sample of the triplets of words given by participants in a training session in values-based practice.

Figure 1

Figure 2 A typical range of responses in the forced choice exercise.

Figure 2

Figure 3 A Flow Diagram of Values-based Practice.

Figure 3

Figure 4 Brief Definitions of the Process Elements of Values-Based Practice.