Published online by Cambridge University Press: 04 December 2018
The scholarly discourse on social norms in the tradition of Thomas Schelling (1960) often makes a sharp distinction between social norms and social conventions. In attempting to apply that distinction to actual practices and to teach it to practitioners and students I encountered frequent difficulties and confusions, and finally concluded that it is untenable. I recommend a return to some version of Ullman-Margalit’s (1977) distinction between social norms of cooperation and social norms of coordination. Social norms, I say, are distinguished by beliefs in a relevant group that the rule is typical among them and approved of among them. I describe four ways that social norms of coordination, including conventions of social meaning, are influenced by social approval and disapproval. I contend that the effort by Southwood and Eriksson (2011) to show that social conventions and social norms are essentially different breaks down because their conception of social norms is overly moralized. I present a more social conception of social norms that does without the regnant distinction between “social norm” and “social convention” and instead allows for social norms of cooperation, social norms of coordination, and other kinds of social norms.
1 Schelling, Thomas C., The Strategy of Conflict (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1960).Google Scholar
2 Bicchieri, Cristina, The Grammar of Society: The Nature and Dynamics of Social Norms (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006);Google Scholar Coleman, James S., Foundations of Social Theory (Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press, 1988);Google Scholar Elster, Jon, The Cement of Society: A Survey of Social Order (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989);CrossRefGoogle Scholar McAdams, Richard H., “The Origin, Development, and Regulation of Norms,” Michigan Law Review 96 (1997): 338–433;CrossRefGoogle Scholar Southwood, Nicholas and Eriksson, Lina, “Norms and Conventions,” Philosophical Explorations 14, no. 2 (2011): 195–217;CrossRefGoogle Scholar Sugden, Robert, The Economics of Rights, Co-operation and Welfare (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1986).Google Scholar
3 Ostrom, Elinor, Governing the Commons: The Evolution of Institutions for Collective Action (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
4 Hume, David, A Treatise of Human Nature (Mineola: Dover Press, 2003 [1738]).Google Scholar
5 Mackie, Gerry, “Ending Footbinding and Infibulation: A Convention Account,” American Sociological Review (1996): 999–1017.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
6 Fox, Kate, Watching the English (London: Hodder, 2004).Google Scholar
7 Ullman-Margalit, Edna, The Emergence of Norms (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1977).Google Scholar
8 Southwood and Eriksson, Norms and Conventions.
9 Burke, Mary A. and Peyton Young, H., “Social Norms,” in Benhabib, Jess, Bisin, Alberto, and Jackson, Matthew O., eds., The Handbook of Social Economics (Amsterdam: Elsevier, 2011), 311–38.Google Scholar
10 Gerry Mackie, Francesca Moneti, Holly Shakya, and Elaine Denny, What Are Social Norms? How Are They Measured? (New York: UNICEF, 2016). tinyurl.com/measurenorms
11 Modified from Mackie et al., What Are Social Norms, which was adapted in part from Bicchieri, The Grammar of Society and from Martin Fishbein and Icek Ajzen, Predicting and Changing Behavior: The Reasoned Action Approach (New York: Psychology Press, 2010).
12 Levy Paluck, Elizabeth and Ball, Laurie, Social Norms Marketing Aimed at Gender Based Violence: A Literature Review and Critical Assessment (New York: International Rescue Committee, 2010).Google Scholar
13 Moreover, important developments requiring only minor departures from Lewis’s framework show how conventions can arise from structures that are not coordination games in his strict sense. These moves are based on the solution concept of correlated equilibrium that may yield a better and more unified account of the game-theoretic structures underlying social norms, and resolve some of the issues I have raised here in a different way. See, e.g., Peter Vanderschraaf, “Knowledge, Equilibrium, and Convention,” Erkenntnis, 49 (1998): 337–69; and Francesco Guala, Understanding Institutions: The Science and Philosophy of Living Together (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2016).
14 This is my adaptation of ideas from Geoffrey Brennan and Philip Pettit, The Economy of Esteem: An Essay on Civil and Political Society (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004); and McAdams, The Origin, Development, and Regulation of Norms.
15 Ullman-Margalit, The Emergence of Norms.
16 Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature, 354.
17 Schelling, The Strategy of Conflict.
18 Lewis, David K., Convention: A Philosophical Study, (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1969).Google Scholar
19 Lewis, Convention, 97–100.
20 Francesco Guala, “The Normativity of Lewis Conventions,” Synthese 190, no. 15 (2013): 3107–3122.
21 Lewis, Convention, 76.
22 Ibid., 78.
23 Ibid., 77.
24 Bicchieri, The Grammar of Society, 38.
25 Ross, W. D., The Oxford Translation of Aristotle, Vol. IX: The Nichomachean Ethics (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1925).Google Scholar
26 Giovanna Devetag and Andreas Ortmann, “Solving Coordination Problems Experimentally,” in Murray Webster and Jane Sell, eds., Laboratory Experiments in the Social Sciences (Cambridge, MA: Academic Press, 2007).
27 Mackie, “Ending Footbinding and Infibulation.”
28 Michael Rescola, “Convention,” Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2011.
29 Fox, Watching the English.
30 Page Fiske, Alan, “Four Modes of Constituting Relationships,” in Haslam, Nick, ed., Relational Models Theory (Mahwah, New Jersey: Lawrence Erlbaum and Associates, 2004).Google Scholar
31 Goffman, Erving, “The Nature of Deference and Demeanor,” American Anthropologist 58, no. 3 (1956): 473–502.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
32 Ackerman, Felicia, “A Man by Nothing Is So Well Betrayed as by His Manners? Politeness as a Virtue,” Midwest Studies in Philosophy 13, no. 7 (1988): 250–58.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
33 Culpeper, Jonathan, Impoliteness (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2011).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
34 Lessig, Lawrence, “The Regulation of Social Meaning,” University of Chicago Law Review 62 (1995): 943.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
35 Southwood and Eriksson, Norms and Conventions.
36 Ullman-Margalit, The Emergence of Norms, 124.
37 Southwood and Eriksson, Norms and Conventions, 199.
38 Haffner, Sebastion, Defying Hitler: A Memoir (New York: Macmillan, 2003).Google Scholar
39 Prentice, Deborah A. and Miller, Dale T., “Pluralistic Ignorance and Alcohol Use on Campus: Some Consequences of Misperceiving the Social Norm,” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 64, no. 2 (1993): 243–56.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
40 Coleman, Foundations of Social Theory.
Please note a has been issued for this article.