Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-dsjbd Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-23T17:20:14.790Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Death by Analogy: Identity Crises on a Roman Sarcophagus

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  24 March 2023

Emily Clifford*
Affiliation:
Christ Church College, University of Oxford
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

This article examines how images on a sarcophagus involved Roman viewers in processes of thinking by analogy and so invited them to engage in meditation on death. This more thanatological slant is sidelined in current approaches that emphasise how exemplary figures on sarcophagi consoled the bereaved and praised the dead. Building on these approaches, together with work on the mediating role played by artefacts in thought, this article proposes that analogies on sarcophagi also invited the living to think about their own death and the possibilities and limitations of analogy for thanatological reflection. It argues, further, that sarcophagi should be read more expansively, allowing for figures and scenes to have more than one identity rather than collapsing them into one: this multiplicity reinforces meditation on death. The article focuses on Roman sarcophagi that feature Adonis, with emphasis on the Rinuccini sarcophagus; this unusual sarcophagus explicitly juxtaposes real-life and mythological scenes.

Type
Articles
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of The Society for the Promotion of Roman Studies

Thus die I, thus, thus, thus.

Bottom as Pyramus in Shakespeare, A Midsummer Night's Dream, act 5, scene 1

When Shakespeare's Bottom dies as Pyramus, he dies in his own way and like a tragic hero. The combination generates a parody and prompts reflection on the theatricality of death. Pyramus's problem is one of originality: he dies too self-consciously, too much like a lion-hearted lover. But he also faces a challenge common to all would-be artists-of-dying: ignorance. No one knows what it is like to die. When it comes to imagining what it is like to die, the art of analogy can propose a bridge between an object of study and future subjective experience. As a result, ideas about dying are often underpinned and overshadowed by examples; they are shaped by other people's deaths and by models of dying proposed by art. Either way, being an outsider poses challenges.Footnote 1 How far can we extrapolate a generalised idea about dying from examples?Footnote 2 Can we compare one death with another?Footnote 3 In this article, I explore how one category of ancient objects — Roman sarcophagi — mediated reflection on the possibilities and limitations of analogy for meditation on death.Footnote 4 As I discuss in my conclusion, this sort of image-mediated conceptualisation can be emically situated within a specifically Roman cultural regime.

I focus on Roman sarcophagi that have been categorised as featuring the mythological death of Adonis.Footnote 5 These offer a productive case study because, as burial containers, sarcophagi are associated with death. But the life history of scholarship on sarcophagi and death has been turbulent. In the 1940s, those interested in classical archaeology and mythological representations (which is to say, non-Christian images and ideas) moved away from looking for ancient beliefs about the afterlife in sarcophagi.Footnote 6 More recently, approaches have found a middle ground between classicism and eschatology by emphasising the perspectives of the living: images on sarcophagi console the bereaved and praise the dead by offering analogies with exemplary figures from mythology or Roman life.Footnote 7 Sarcophagi have thus been positioned within a Roman phenomenon of exemplarity, a key feature of cultural, especially rhetorical, discourse.Footnote 8 There is also a growing body of literature that pursues a thanatological, or death-focused, approach by exploring how the formal features of a sarcophagus — its shape, ornamentation, framing devices, figures and portraits — prompt meditation on death and the dead.Footnote 9 This work somewhat closes the rift between the study of classical and early Christian material. It also contributes to a field interested in sensory and embodied experience, materiality and object-oriented approaches to the relationship between Graeco-Roman art and ideas about death.Footnote 10 In this paper on analogical viewing and thanatological thinking I build on both current approaches. I dig deeper into how analogies on sarcophagi work, while also considering formal features and the ways in which these features negotiate the challenges of imagining what it is like to die. My point is that analogies on sarcophagi did not just interact with the living as the bereaved and the dead as the deceased, but also invited the living to engage in meditations on death.Footnote 11

My emphasis, throughout this article, on close looking — and on the generative relationship between a visual object and its viewers — raises a practical question of visibility: to what extent, and under what conditions, can we speak of ‘viewers’ of Roman sarcophagi? This is a difficult question, not least because for any given example (including most of the sarcophagi that I discuss here) precise contextual information has often been lost. In general, as regards ‘viewing’, sarcophagi were displayed or concealed in a range of contexts: though some continued to be visible either publicly or privately (at least in principle),Footnote 12 others were unlikely to be seen after interment.Footnote 13 The sort of viewing that I pursue here might, then, best be imagined as taking place during a funeral,Footnote 14 or else before it, perhaps even by its future occupant — an intriguing possibility in the context of this paper.Footnote 15

Sarcophagus studies have often been characterised by a desire to translate and organise, to identify images as specific and to group them as a generalisable and thus recognisable category — ‘an image of’ or ‘images of’ Adonis.Footnote 16 But Roman sarcophagi resist this approach.Footnote 17 The abundance of analogical possibilities presented by sarcophagi invites, even thematises, a more expansive mode of viewing.Footnote 18 Others have emphasised the survival of a diverse cultural heritage in sarcophagi images and deliberate variation of motifs to suit different contexts.Footnote 19 I would add that intimations of multiple stories within one image produce a scene with a plural identity or a fluid, elusive identity.Footnote 20 The ‘identity crises’ part of my title thus refers to problems of specificity and generality in methodologies historically present in the discipline of classical art and archaeology as well as example-based meditation on death.

Indeed, example-based meditation is a running theme in this article in approach as much as content. Though the sarcophagi that I discuss here are comparable with one another (they are similar objects with similar functions and contexts, originating from a relatively brief time-period), the exercise of constructing a general argument from specific examples stages, in a more extreme fashion, the assumptions that necessarily underpin extrapolation of a cultural-historical story from fragmentary evidence.Footnote 21 My examples purport to represent a corpus and a cultural phenomenon. Moreover, the possibilities and limitations of the case studies in this article mirror the promise and deficiency of images of Adonis as exemplars of what it is like to die. Analogies, examples and their shortcomings thus carry and compromise the form and the content of my argument.

Why Adonis? Adonis, beloved of Venus, died after being wounded in the thigh by a boar during a hunting expedition. The myth is a tale of love and loss, death and grief.Footnote 22 In ancient Greek tradition, the story had a cyclical dimension, with Adonis dying and returning annually in rhythm with the seasons.Footnote 23 Adonis also comes with a scholarly tradition, a history of views deriving existential beliefs about mortality, immortality and resurrection or rebirth from the cult of Adonis and his representations in Graeco-Roman culture.Footnote 24 So even when not on a sarcophagus, Adonis's death has a claim to exemplarity. He is a natural subject for example-based meditation on death.

Though I refer to several sarcophagi, I focus on the Rinuccini sarcophagus (Figs 1–6).Footnote 25 I consider first how resemblances within the sarcophagus's rectangular field invite a mode of viewing and thinking based on equivalence. Then, I discuss the numerous identities that might inhere in representations of Adonis himself and what this multiplicity does in the context of death. In my conclusion, I turn to more reflexive ways in which sarcophagi make the process of meditation by analogy an object of discourse. I suggest, finally, that the way of conceptualisation explored in this paper is recognisably Roman.

FIG. 1. Rinuccini sarcophagus front panel, c. 200 c.e., marble, length 212–15 cm, height 101 cm. Berlin State Museums, Berlin, 1987.2. (Artwork in the public domain; photograph by the author)

FIG. 2. Rinuccini sarcophagus front panel (Fig. 1), detail of the left-hand side. (Artwork in the public domain; photograph by the author)

FIG. 3. Rinuccini sarcophagus front panel (Fig. 1), detail of the right-hand side. (Artwork in the public domain; photograph by the author)

FIG. 4. Rinuccini sarcophagus front panel (Fig. 1), detail of the centre. (Artwork in the public domain; photograph by the author)

FIG. 5. Rinuccini sarcophagus left-end panel, marble, depth 94 cm. Berlin State Museums, Berlin, 1987.2. (Artwork in the public domain; photograph by the author)

FIG. 6. Rinuccini sarcophagus right-end panel, marble, depth 99 cm. Berlin State Museums, Berlin, 1987.2. (Artwork in the public domain; photograph by the author)

I Death By Analogy

The front face of the Rinuccini sarcophagus presents two spaces divided by a pier that swoops outwards at the top; the illusion is that the pier supports an open archway that connects and demarcates two areas (Fig. 1).Footnote 26 Viewers of the sarcophagus relief are situated, as it were, in an imaginary vaulted space that is created by the sarcophagus relief, and are provided with views in either direction from beneath the arch, one looking into the left-hand space, one to the right. These spaces are filled with figures carved in high relief that seem to inhabit two different realms, real and mythological.Footnote 27

In the left-hand scene (drawn from Roman life, a vita Romana scene), figures are clothed, women accompany men and most figures stand upright (Fig. 2). This is a domain of layers and folds, with bodies wrapped in fabric and figures in the foreground partially concealing those behind. The bodies of two male figures on the group's fringes form other partitions, their heads turning towards the space between them, an interior space shielded by their bodies and inhabited by a woman, a smaller kneeling figure and a domestic animal, a bull. By contrast, the right-hand scene is a display of macho nudity, with bodies twisting and sprawling (Fig. 3). While, on the left, up-standing bodies and the deep folds of their garments emphasise verticals, figures on the right ride and lunge above the arch of the cave, or loll and crouch below, upon the ground: the arc composed by their bodies reinforces the cave's curvature to encircle the boar, producing a vigorous space of circles, spy-holes and traps. Indeed, the halo of smooth, sculpted flesh around rough pitted textures — bulbous crannies in the rock and craggy waves that ripple about the boar's chest and neck — revels in surface, a riposte to the left-hand insistence on depth. Though the three figures in the top right of the mythological scene are usually interpreted as Adonis's companions (and so human not divine), their position in the upper field alongside two horsemen complicates their ontological status, because the latter are usually read as the Dioscuri, the twins Castor and Pollux, mortal and divine respectively. On the left, then, we have an ordinary realm with people arranged in layers and figures’ feet planted firmly on the ground (even, it seems, the feet of the two figures usually identified as personifications of harmony and duty). On the right we have an alternate one, where human, divinity and hero intermingle in a flatter but sky-high plane.Footnote 28 The sculptor has distinguished two zones.

The demarcation is, however, ruptured by a nude, sprawling male body, usually interpreted as Adonis since he is injured and alongside a boar (Fig. 1). This figure (and the animal beneath him) connects the two spaces by slumping through the arch, which works, effectively, as a gateway between the spaces.Footnote 29 He encourages viewers to link one scene with another, to view two halves as one, to think by analogy. One possibility is that he connects two scenes of harmony and duty with a third scene of courage: he links a marriage symbolised by joined right hands and a sacrifice and libation, probably before battle,Footnote 30 with a wounded hunter's parting shot, spearing the boar that gored him.Footnote 31 Or perhaps he glosses two exemplary scenes from a Roman man's life (marriage and sacrifice) with the universal message that all men must die.Footnote 32 Both these interpretations fit with a principle (widely endorsed in scholarship) that mythological scenes enact consolation rhetoric by introducing, in a loosely analogous way, solace for the bereaved and praise for the dead. But the reflections that are prompted by this scene are also thanatological and epistemological. The slumped male figure puts dying centre-stage and, by establishing a way of viewing predicated upon making connections and comparisons, turns attention upon the process of thinking about death by analogy.

There is nothing simple about drawing analogies with the images on this sarcophagus.Footnote 33 Repetitions and correspondences accumulate to thematise figurative viewing, its problems and its possibilities. The relief is a collection of groups and pairs: moving from the left, a husband and wife join hands; a soldier pours a libation beside a sacrificial victim; the injured figure of Adonis faces the boar; the Dioscuri ride; Adonis's three companions lunge; two dogs frame Adonis; two attack the boar. In some ways these groups are mirror images, in others alternatives. We see a reflection of marital harmony in the partnership between hunters and Dioscuri and its inversion in the struggle between hunters, gods and boar. The Dioscuri are nude with a short cloak and ride rightwards, their motion bringing them towards, even against, Adonis's unmounted companions, who are similarly dressed but unmounted. The groups are matched and distinguished: on horse, on foot; bodies in profile, bodies in front and rear view; two (or four with the horses) moving as one, two converging in a triangle; heads turn apart, faces look in the same direction. Each group is also joint and several, replicating themes of similarity and difference at a micro level. If the two mounted figures are Castor and Pollux, one is mortal, the other divine (but we cannot identify which is which), and arguably each has more in common with his horse than his brother: though their bodies seem to move in the same direction, their heads (and their horses’ heads) turn apart. The repetition distinguishes as much as it aligns.

This has implications for more generalised meditation on dying, mediated by the combination of examples. I will focus on three sets of ideas thrown together by the images: sacrifice, hunting and marriage. Let us begin with an interpretation that traces male bodies to make a general argument about Roman virtues, specifically those of the deceased (who is often presumed to be male, though this is a tenuous assumption: the identity of the deceased is unknown).Footnote 34 The male figures differ in appearance: the left is in a toga; the central figure in military dress; the third nude; the hunters and Dioscuri partially draped.Footnote 35 The combination mixes sobriety, strength and erotic appeal, but a common thread prevails: the male body is repeatedly a model of harmony, duty and courage.Footnote 36 As such, the figures might represent the deceased in admirable guises, as enshrined in his family's memory. This is a fairly standard interpretation.

We can, however, push the analogies further, such that similarities become an exercise in the figurative nature of meditating upon dying. I begin with the central scenes of sacrifice, libation and death (Fig. 4). To the left, a kneeling figure prepares to pierce a bull's throat while a butcher strikes from behind (a similar butcher to the one on the sarcophagus's left-end relief, Fig. 5).Footnote 37 In the centre, a man stands with his armoured torso in frontal view, his head turned to the left and his right arm extended to pour a libation from a bowl over the bull. To the right, Adonis falls from one realm into another, his right arm bent in a mirror reflection of the soldier's left and extended backwards to touch, or almost touch, that figure's left knee. These events are bound closer by visual parallels between Adonis's drooping head and the bowed neck of the bull, intimating, perhaps, two blood sacrifices. Mythological accounts survive in which a god (variously Mars, Diana or Apollo) drove the boar to wound Adonis,Footnote 38 so Adonis's death, and the blood he sheds, picks up on the power and violence latent in the left-hand scene of religious dying; in each scene the gods receive or take a victim.Footnote 39

Enclosed by two scenes in which bodies (bull, Adonis and boar) pour out their life's blood, or will soon do so, the figure of the soldier takes on a thanatological significance.Footnote 40 He too sheds liquid, but from a hollow vessel. In the context of the sarcophagus, his libation might, among other associations, look backwards, honouring a past death, or deaths, with a liquid memorial.Footnote 41 But his military dress also accommodates the possibility of death in battle, perhaps, like Adonis in some accounts, slain by Mars, whether Mars be god, boar, war or all three.Footnote 42 In mythology, Adonis is sometimes injured by a god-as-boar (or a god-sent boar), which is similar to how, in the Iliad, warriors are slain by gods, gods-in-men and men-like-boars.Footnote 43 Adonis's death by boar thus presents an analogy for military death, and vice versa. Indeed, the round libation dish in the soldier's hand echoes the circular perimeter of the cave that holds the gory scene between Adonis and the boar, visually reinforcing the equivalence of the scenes. One implication is that Adonis's death is exemplary insofar as his death is not extraordinary; he, like everyone else (a soldier, or any mortal creature), dies like (in the same sort of simile as) everyone else — like, for example, a boar or a bull.

What does it mean, then, for Adonis to look like a slayer as well as a victim? His body is also twinned with that of the small figure crouching beside the bull: another sacrificial slayer.Footnote 44 This draws attention to the spear (now lost) that this Adonis once directed into the boar's throat.Footnote 45 Imagine that the spear is still in Adonis's grip. Not only do both figures pierce (or will pierce) their victims with a weapon in the neck, but their positions and poses are similar. Each is set to the left of the animal they kill. In addition, though Adonis sits and the other kneels, the lines of their shoulders incline gently to the right, both left legs are bent and the upper portions of their right arms trace the same gradient. Given the possibility of analogies not just between two scenes of dying but between two scenes of killing (with boar and Adonis doubling as aggressor and victim), the circular dish in the soldier's hand offers the mythological scene as a mise en abyme of sacrificial dying and a mirror reflection, a reversal in which the exemplary death is not that of Adonis but the boar, enclosed within the darkness of the cave, opening its mouth in a voiceless scream.Footnote 46 In this respect, the arcs of sculpted masonry at the relief's centre pick up the circle of the cave (also sculpted, but sculpted to look natural) and tighten the correspondences between the soldier and the boar, two masculine figures with heads turned to the left. It is no coincidence that a sacrificial bull and a boar feature on the sarcophagus's left- and right-side friezes respectively (Figs 5 and 6). The bull is led; the boar is chased; both move away from columned archways. Are the bull and the boar central figures here?

Let us return to the interpretation that I introduced above: the repeated male figure and implications for the deceased's good character. So far, my discussion has focused on males and masculinity: dying like a soldier, Adonis, a bull or a boar. But what about the woman in the foreground at the frieze's left-hand end (Figs 1 and 2)? It has been suggested that, as one of three male figures (also including the soldier and Adonis), the man grasping her right hand (though the hands are lost) enacts one virtue for which the deceased is praised, the harmony of marital union.Footnote 47 This is an attractive interpretation, not least because the heads of the two male figures that frame the left-hand scene turn towards one another in an implicit mirror reflection; this might be the same man in two differently commendable contexts (harmony and duty). But an over-specific mapping of identity here does not account for similarities between the woman and the soldier. These two stand in a frontal pose, their weight upon their right leg, the left relaxed. Their right arms are extended, while the left bend and clasp the fabric of their cloaks, pulling it across their hips and upwards to reveal the folds of the clothing beneath. Both stomachs are accentuated, one by stretched fabric, the other by a moulded breastplate. Both heads turn to the left and the figures are similar heights. The soldier is linked visually, and thereby conceptually, with the woman.

Aside from resisting any neat organisation of who's who here, the visual analogy intensifies thanatological meditation: any ideas about dying generated by him are also shaped by her. This matters, because if the male marital figure evokes union, the female imbues that concept with additional narratives of power, consent, abduction, departure, death and loss. Traditionally a Roman woman's marriage staged a mock kidnap from her father's house, a cultural re-enactment of, among other stories, the mythical abduction of Proserpina, goddess of spring (and life), by Pluto, god of the underworld (and death).Footnote 48 This sculpted woman's split pose (body turned towards the viewer, head towards the man grasping her hand) is thus ambivalent. Does she turn towards or from him? If towards, where has she come, or been taken, from?Footnote 49 Admittedly, the female figure in the background between these two has been identified as a personification of harmony (which is the obvious emphasis of the scene).Footnote 50 But what about the figure behind the married woman's left shoulder, who tilts her face towards the sky? Might this hint at distress, desperation, an appeal to the gods?Footnote 51 A woman taken in marriage on a sarcophagus might import themes of abduction, loss and death as well as union; in fact, this was a popular association.Footnote 52 Consider one sarcophagus held in the Uffizi, which deals more explicitly with these themes in the story of Proserpina's abduction by Pluto (Fig. 7).Footnote 53 Proserpina's body is outstretched in his arms as if already deceased. Another sarcophagus shows the kidnap of two sisters, the daughters of Leucippus, by the Dioscuri and mourns in its epigraph the death of a young bride (Fig. 8).Footnote 54 The sculpted girls appear alive, but their torsos are rigid and near horizontal. These are the sorts of images and stories that formed the cultural backdrop to the Rinuccini sarcophagus, and which might well have coloured the impact of the marriage scene when viewed alongside the other more noticeably violent scenes.Footnote 55 Indeed, if anyone did remember the role played by the Dioscuri in the abduction of the daughters of Leucippus, the glance by the left-hand twin on the Rinuccini sarcophagus towards the scenes on the frieze's other end might acquire a troubling edge.Footnote 56

FIG. 7. Sarcophagus with the abduction of Proserpina, c. 160–180 c.e., marble, length 210 cm, height 75 cm, depth 63 cm. Uffizi Gallery, Florence, 1914, 86 (Photograph by Gerhard Singer, provided by the Deutsches Archäologisches Institut Rom, D-DAI-ROM-72.120, cropped by the author)

FIG. 8. Sarcophagus with the abduction of the daughters of Leucippus by the Dioscuri, c. 160–180 c.e., marble, length 220 cm, height 56 cm, depth 75 cm. Uffizi Gallery, Florence, 1914, 104. (Artwork in the public domain; photograph by Gerhard Singer, provided by the Deutsches Archäologisches Institut Rom, D-DAI-ROM-72.131, cropped by the author)

In addition, the visible presence of one woman might make another's absence more striking. Usually Venus, Adonis's bereaved lover, plays a prominent role.Footnote 57 On the Rospigliosi sarcophagus, for example, she appears four times (Fig. 9).Footnote 58 Each time, her arm connects her with Adonis, bridging the gap between them. A sarcophagus in the Vatican, Vatican 10409, has a similar impact (Fig. 10):Footnote 59 to the left, the figures turn towards each other, connected by Venus's hand; in the centre, the curtained backdrop connects them in a private space; to the right, Venus's drapery arcs above them, grouping them in another pseudo-indoor scene.

FIG. 9. Sarcophagus with Adonis, c. 200 c.e., marble, length 237 cm, height 58 cm. Casino Rospigliosi, Rome. (Artwork in the public domain; photograph by Franz Schlechter, provided by the Deutsches Archäologisches Institut Rom, D-DAI-ROM-86.48, cropped by the author)

FIG. 10. Sarcophagus with Adonis, c. 220 c.e., marble, length 215 cm, height 72 cm, depth 71 cm. Museo Gregoriano Profano, Vatican, 10409. (Artwork in the public domain; photograph by Gisela Geng, provided by the Forschungsarchiv für Antike Plastik, FA-S-GEN-5710-01a_21252, cropped by the author)

On the Rinuccini sarcophagus (Fig. 1), by contrast, Venus is absent from the hunt and possibly the whole frieze, except by analogy with the wife,Footnote 60 or perhaps the husband. The composition still conveys intimacy with its abundance of groups, but Adonis is remarkably isolated. The vault of the cave fails to bring him within its embrace: the right calves of the Dioscuri trace its curve downwards to meet his shoulder, separating him from the boar. The body that spans mythological and real zones also sits outside both. The nude male on the right and the draped female on the left therefore also work as each other's analogies:Footnote 61 the man or the god that takes a woman in his grip (and so implicitly removes her from her family) accentuates the impotence and loneliness of the bereaved, who has been taken out of the picture.

In focalising death through the eyes of the bereaved Venus, it is clear how sarcophagi such as these might have participated in consolatory rhetoric: grieving viewers may have seen themselves and their sorrow repeated in the decoration and been comforted that gods and heroes suffered the same or worse. They might have found solace in reinforcement of their status by identification with exemplary figures. They might have experienced hope of victory over death, particularly in the context of Adonis's association with cyclical renewal.Footnote 62

But my point here is that the profusion of analogies also becomes something more thanatological.Footnote 63 Indeed, within the group of objects that Dagmar Grassinger categorised as ‘Adonis’ sarcophagi, there often appear scenes in which Venus bids farewell to Adonis as he departs for the hunt (a profectio, or ‘departure’ scene) and scenes in which the lovers embrace while figures such as winged cupids tend his wound (a union that precedes another sort of departure — in death).Footnote 64 On the Rinuccini sarcophagus, the reconfiguration of the more familiar scene of two lovers separating (before the hunt) or embracing (before Adonis's death) in an image of marriage (itself conceivably, though more subtly, associated with separation — separation from the bride's family) gives the latter scene an emotional twist that chimes with the theme of departure in death that overshadows the relief as a whole.Footnote 65 The dominant emphasis of the Rinuccini marriage scene may be union, but the cultural and artistic tapestry against which the image is viewed imbues it with thanatological significance.

In these ways, resemblances across the frieze set up a mode of viewing based on association and transference of impressions. In the context of death, this shapes the processes and results of thanatological thinking.Footnote 66 But in addition, given the discrepancies as well as similarities between details, resemblances might provoke meditation on the essential but flawed role played by examples and the challenges of extrapolating from them generalised ideas about what it is like to die.Footnote 67

II DYING LIKE ADONIS (OR A. N. OTHER)

On this note, let us consider how resemblances might generate a provocative lack of specificity in the context of death. What does it mean for multiple identities to be immanent in one figure? An assumption runs through much scholarship on Roman sarcophagi that figures have an identity. They may allude to other traditions, but there is a core story to be unearthed.Footnote 68 On Michael Koortbojian's analysis, for example, the sprawling nude on the Rinuccini sarcophagus is a variant of Adonis and a vessel for the generalised idea of mortality.Footnote 69 But at what point does variation risk producing someone else entirely? When is resemblance simply reality? Ovid's playful description of Adonis in his Metamorphoses is instructive here (Met. 10.515–18):Footnote 70

laudaret faciem Liuor quoque: qualia namque
corpora nudorum tabula pinguntur Amorum,
talis erat; sed, ne faciat discrimina cultus,
aut huic adde leues aut illis deme pharetras.
Envy, too, would praise his appearance, for his body was just like
the bodies of nude Loves that are painted on a panel;
but, so that clothing does not distinguish them,
either give him light arrows or take them from them.

Ovid's visualisation of Adonis's body plays with the boundary between resemblance and identification. The image of Adonis that emerges from the text draws on images of ‘Loves’ familiar from the iconographic tradition.Footnote 71 Ovid distinguishes the textual image by the absence of the Loves’ usual attributes, arrows, but undercuts the difference by suggesting that Adonis would be better with arrows, a depiction that might render him visually indistinguishable from a Love and allow him to defend himself successfully against the boar.

This last possibility anticipates the mercurial mythological identification invited by sarcophagi. Give Adonis a weapon, allow him to defeat the boar, and he might become … Meleager.Footnote 72 Consider one sarcophagus in the Palazzo Doria Pamphilj (Fig. 11):Footnote 73 a central nude male figure is shown in a three-quarters stance, striding with his left leg forwards as he thrusts his spear into a boar's forehead. This figure is usually identified as Meleager.Footnote 74 A similar body schema, alike in pose albeit with his head tilted further forwards, appears on the Rospigliosi sarcophagus, beside the seated figure usually identified as the wounded Adonis (Fig. 9).Footnote 75 We also see hints of this man in hunter figures in the background to ‘Adonis’ sarcophagi in the Vatican and Mantua (Figs 10 and 12).Footnote 76

FIG. 11. Sarcophagus with Meleager, c. 180–200 c.e., marble, length 247 cm, height 94 cm, depth 110 cm. Palazzo Doria Pamphilj, Rome. (Artwork in the public domain; photograph by Peter Barritt, provided by Alamy, G3DJN3)

FIG. 12. Sarcophagus with Adonis, c. 190 c.e., marble, length 218 cm, height 73 cm. Palazzo Ducale, Mantua (Artwork in the public domain; photograph by Gisela Fittschen-Badura, provided by the Forschungsarchiv für Antike Plastik, Fitt77-03-01_12159, cropped by the author)

Usually, identification of these figures is subordinated to that of the male nude in the foreground, whose leg wound sets the tone (as an ‘Adonis’ scene). But what happens when that fallen figure also deals the killing blow, as on the Rinuccini and Vatican sarcophagi (Figs 1, 3 and 10)? By combining more than one body schema (for example Adonis and Meleager), these reliefs challenge attempts to specify the identity of the figure or scene.Footnote 77 On the Vatican sarcophagus, a fallen male figure, nude apart from a cloak, is shown upon his knees, his head turned towards the boar and his left hand raised palm outwards in defence (Fig. 10). His right hand, by contrast, grasps a large spear that he thrusts into the boar's throat. The balance of power is unclear. Leaning ever so slightly backwards and kneeling with his genitals exposed, the fallen nude appears in a position of erotic vulnerability. But the line of his spear, braced upon the ground, is strong and stiff, virile even, projecting from his groin. The figure subjugates and succumbs in one.

This highlights the fragility of extrapolating a story from identification of a specific figure: if a fallen man is Adonis, Meleager-like people around him become generalised hunter companions, background figures as opposed to named characters. But when defeat is mixed with victory, as on the Rinuccini and Vatican sarcophagi, it becomes more difficult to determine the figure's identity and, in turn, the identity of the wider scene. What would it take to accept that a figure alongside a boar is not specifically Adonis, and not a participant in a generic hunt scene or another mythological hunt scene, but all of them at once? We either accept that scenes include images that are variously generic ‘hunter attacks a boar’ figures and specific mythological characters (and that it is possible to distinguish the two),Footnote 78 or we must consider the possibility that figures and scenes can hold more than one identity. If the spear-wielding, nude male shown at disadvantage on the Rinuccini and Vatican sarcophagi were a literary figure, he might be ‘Adonis-Meleager’, neither an Adonis, nor a Meleager (likewise, it is Bottom-as-Pyramus who dies, not one or the other).

In fact, even as a wounded, dying hunter, Adonis still recalls Meleager. This is notable on examples in Blera and the Villa Giustiniani Massimo (Figs 13 and 14).Footnote 79 On these the semi-recumbent nude figure usually identified as Adonis looks remarkably similar to depictions of the prostrate Meleager, such as that on the narrow superior frieze of the sarcophagus in the Palazzo Doria Pamphilj (although this raises a question as to whether the latter could be Adonis) (Fig. 11). Repetition of the boar and male figure prompts viewers to recognise a specific scene (Adonis, say, rather than Hector) and opens the possibilities to include other identities such as Meleager and the deceased. Why see one story in any one scene? Given that there are not only examples such as the Rinuccini sarcophagus that encourage analogy between real and mythological scenes, but also ones that set Mars and Rhea Silvia alongside Endymion and Selene (Fig. 15),Footnote 80 for example, we should consider the possibility that images on sarcophagi work in an altogether more expansive way, becoming multiple stories and identities at once.Footnote 81

FIG. 13. Sarcophagus with Adonis, c. 200 c.e., marble, length 198 cm, height 52 cm, depth 55 cm. Chiesa Santa Maria Assunta, Blera. (Artwork in the public domain; photograph by Barry Ferst)

FIG. 14. Sarcophagus with Adonis, c. 180 c.e., marble, length 210 cm, height 49 cm. Villa Giustiniani Massimo, Rome. (Artwork in the public domain; photograph by Gerhard Singer, provided by Deutsches Archäologisches Institut Rom, D-DAI-ROM-68.5200, cropped by the author)

FIG. 15. Sarcophagus with Mars and Rhea Silvia, Selene and Endymion, c. 200–215 c.e., marble, length 225 cm, height 82 cm. Museo Gregoriano Profano, Vatican, 9558. (Artwork in the public domain; photograph by Gisela Geng, provided by the Forschungsarchiv für Antike Plastik, FA-S-GEN-5713-01_21259)

A more expansive reading is supported by the multiplicity of directional imperatives on sarcophagi friezes.Footnote 82 Carl Robert categorised Adonis sarcophagi according to whether their scenes run from left to right or right to left, but the density of analogies within a sarcophagus frieze offers numerous routes for eyes to follow,Footnote 83 and so frustrates categorisation according to one linear pattern.Footnote 84 For example, while the Rinuccini scene can be read as a left-to-right progression through an adult male Roman's life,Footnote 85 it also invites convergence on a central twin sacrifice (Fig. 1). The variety of options for exercising visual attention leaves narrative possibilities open-ended, both as a matter of sequence and content.

Moreover, latent within the image of the outstretched male nude is a long, diverse visual tradition of dead and dying figures. The sprawling nude on the Blera sarcophagus is charged with possibilities (Fig. 13). His slumped body, lifted by a companion, could be (at least) Adonis, Meleager or even Hector (Fig. 16).Footnote 86 Polymorphous identity is not an accidental result of one schema being especially aesthetically pleasing or, more prosaically, there being limited options for representation of a dying or dead body. Scenes on sarcophagi are not generic: they are specific, but abundantly, multifariously specific, pointing viewers in more than one direction at once (as on the Rinuccini sarcophagus, where the slumped pose of the figure indicates Adonis, but the presence of the Dioscuri and the killing blow indicates Meleager).Footnote 87

FIG. 16. Sarcophagus with Hector brought back from Troy, c. 200 c.e., marble, length 175 cm, height 50 cm. Louvre, Paris, Ma 353. (Artwork in the public domain; photograph by Gisela Fittschen-Badura, provided by the Forschungsarchiv für Antike Plastik, file Fitt71-24-08, cropped by the author)

Indeed, the Rinuccini sarcophagus foregrounds movement between the specific and general by combining myth and Roman life in an unexpected and conspicuous way. While analogy is implicit on other sarcophagi, a side-by-side comparison of realms is unusual.Footnote 88 However, even if most sarcophagi do not juxtapose scenes like this, they do experiment with situating the departed or bereaved explicitly within a mythological scene, moving closer towards closing the gap between representation and reality and so between one particular, the analogue, and another, the target.Footnote 89 On the Vatican sarcophagus the two central seated figures (read as Adonis and Venus) have portrait features (Fig. 10). Figures on the Rinuccini sarcophagus also had portraits (Figs 1 and 2).Footnote 90 We cannot know whether Adonis had one because all that survives of his head is a flat surface prepared for an attachment (and it is unclear whether this is an original or a later feature).Footnote 91 Other heads are also missing and the dowels and dowel holes suggest these might have been supplemented, although the existence of sarcophagi with unfinished portraits leaves open the possibility that the absence of faces was a choice.Footnote 92

There are two important points to make here about specificity and identity. First, many sarcophagi, including the Rinuccini sarcophagus, present figures with at least two specific identities simultaneously (Adonis, for example, and a real Roman person).Footnote 93 This fits within a third-century movement away from mythological narrative and towards more overt identification between Romans and characters.Footnote 94 But, secondly, the combination of specifics also highlights their distinction. On the Vatican sarcophagus the portraits and central position of the enthroned couple present them as representative figures, not participants in a fictional narrative: the portrait that belongs to Adonis, gazing out of the scene with apparent lack of concern for his wound,Footnote 95 isolates him from mythological events.Footnote 96 On the Rinuccini sarcophagus, juxtaposition of Adonis's nude wounded body alongside the portrait belonging to the armoured Roman forces viewers to acknowledge the gap between identities. It appears that the point is to notice combinations or disparities, either because portraits are left blank or because they jar in a surprising way.Footnote 97 The idea is to recognise more than one specific identity, not to collapse them into one.

This has implications for how Roman sarcophagi invite viewers to think about what it might be like to die, and what they are doing when they engage in meditation on death in response to an image. On the one hand, multifarious figures are generative: they pull together several sets of ideas and combine them to produce something new. This line of thought has been comprehensively pursued, for example by Michael Koortbojian.Footnote 98 As Koortbojian emphasises, the presence of images and motifs within the cultural tradition lingers in later variations. But what is important about his argument for my purposes is that it emphasises survival (survival of identities via the enduring influence of artistic renditions), and the generation of a new generalised — and generalisable — idea (‘mortality’, for example).Footnote 99 Familiarity with visual and literary mythological traditions enabled artists to vary stories, viewers to recognise them, and both to construct new ideas from the reconfigurations.Footnote 100 Multiplicity is deliberate, sophisticated and generative of stable and cohesive meaning.

However, the proliferation of specifics on sarcophagi also draws attention to the more destructive implications of death for identity and individuality.Footnote 101 What is lost when a dying man looks like himself and also like Adonis and Meleager and others? For Simone Weil, war transformed men into things, ‘inert matter’ or ‘blind force’, and this was reflected in the similes of the Iliad, which liken men to forces of nature and wild animals (like boars).Footnote 102 When the Rinuccini sarcophagus sets Adonis opposite a boar, face-to-face in the approximation of a mirror image, it stages a similar transformation in a similar way. Dying like Adonis is likened to dying like a boar, and this visual analogy, by presenting the possibility of transformation in either direction, echoes the transformation of both identities into something else (a corpse) on death. Thus, the survival of multiple identities from literary and visual traditions (as recalled, deliberately or not, by specific details) and their combination (but not their blending) in a sarcophagus frieze also draws attention to the possibility of a loss, the transformation or dissolution of discrete identity on death.Footnote 103 When Adonis looks like Meleager, or Hippolytus, or a boar (or a Roman, living or dead, looks like Adonis and so on), Adonis ceases to be, well, Adonis — what viewers encounter in these unstable and fragmenting images is a vision of death.

Analogies on sarcophagi might have been consoling for some: even Adonis died; even Venus grieved.Footnote 104 And they might have reinforced the confidence with which viewers extrapolated a generalised concept of what dying is like from observation of other people's experiences, whether mythological or real. But, to the extent that being more than one person means being no one in particular, the fact that we cannot say with conviction that a nude dying figure ‘is’ Adonis, or is ‘just’ Adonis, also points towards a crisis of identity. This has two ramifications, both of which are in tension with the suggestions just offered. The possibility that the end of life involves the end of the self may inspire and express grief, even fear, as opposed to relief. And the survival of multiple similar but not same identities undermines the premise that the living might know from another's example what it is like to die. Analogy on sarcophagi is generative, but any generalised concept of death that emerges is mystifying and not enlightening.

III CONCLUSION: A ROMAN ART OF ANALOGY

Over the course of this article, I have argued two things: that analogies on sarcophagi invited the living to reflect upon death and on the possibilities and limitations of analogy for thanatological reflection, and that sarcophagi should be viewed more expansively, allowing for figures and scenes to have more than one identity, rather than collapsing them into one: this multiplicity reinforced meditation on death.

I conclude by returning to the Vatican sarcophagus (Fig. 10). Consider the Adonis on the left, who stands in a frontal pose with his head in profile. His left leg is slightly bent, the right straight; his right arm is extended by his side, the left raised to clasp a spear. This figure needs no pedestal: though sculpted in relief, he is another Roman copy of Polykleitos's Doryphoros.Footnote 105 The cultural echo calls to mind not just the thanatological implications of making an object or image a substitute for a flesh and blood body,Footnote 106 but the very idea of art and the artistic tradition as a medium for thought.Footnote 107 On objects that draw extensively on that tradition to create a multiplicity of analogies and identities, this presentation of the exemplary figure of Adonis, the analogue himself, in the guise of one of the most famous sculptures of the Graeco-Roman world turns attention upon the entwined forces of art and exemplarity that enable and limit meditation on dying.Footnote 108 Like Ovid's Adonis, who looked like not a Love, but a painted Love,Footnote 109 the analogies presented by the Vatican sarcophagus are themselves works of art, individually and as a whole.

Thinking with Adonis involves an artistic mode of thought (analogy) and extrapolation from or comparison with an example that is known, primarily, through the artistic tradition.Footnote 110 One way of imagining what it is like to die requires movement from another's specific example to a general idea. Art, sculptural or poetic, facilitates that movement, partly by indicating and staging resemblance, partly by presenting and perpetuating an experience or action as exemplary.Footnote 111 When images on sarcophagi spotlight this process, they reveal the possibilities offered by art for vicarious experience, imagining what it is like to die from the position of an outsider. But they also call attention to art's limitations: it offers what is, ultimately, an artistic way of dying.

The self-consciousness here, and the interest that it reveals and stirs in conceptual possibilities, is markedly Roman. Think back to the jarring impact of the portraits on the Vatican and Rinuccini sarcophagi, which serve to align apparently comparable identities (real and mythological) and to demarcate them, thus turning attention upon the process and possibilities of analogy (see above, Section II). Such disjuncture (head/body and specific/general) is a provocative hallmark of Roman portraiture more generally: as Michael Squire argues, Roman artists were interested not just in extracting heads to produce busts or portraits (or combining more individualised heads with generic bodies), but in the conceptual implications of that extraction for an ontology of portraiture — namely, portraiture as a marker of present and absent identity.Footnote 112 This conceptual point sharpens against the backdrop of death, as can be observed not just on sarcophagi, but in the Roman tradition of imagines, funerary portraits that played upon the simultaneous presence and absence of dead ancestors (carried in the memories and arms of their descendants; departed in body).Footnote 113 In funerary contexts, theorisation of art and its representational possibilities becomes thanatologically inflected — it mediates meditations on identity and its loss.

This presents an additional lens through which we might think about the increased prominence of portraits on sarcophagi in the early third century c.e.:Footnote 114 it seems plausible that a desire amongst the living for greater proximity to their dead (as proposed by Mont Allen to explain the ‘death of myth’ on Roman sarcophagi)Footnote 115 went hand-in-hand with more intense theoretical meditation upon the possibility of achieving that proximity through an image and, more generally, on the nature of death; as death drew closer, its conceptual implications grew more provoking.

That said, the image-mediated thanatology explored here was already a feature of sarcophagi in the previous century. Analogous thinking was always a conceivable response, though invitations may have been more implicit, tapping into viewers’ readiness to make links and draw distinctions, underpinned for some by their rhetorical training.Footnote 116 When combinations and comparisons were more overt (for example, in noticeably composite scenes or composite figures), reliefs became a particularly fertile site — with a fitting thanatological slant — for what was a long-standing Roman discourse on representation and identity, but a rhetoric of analogy had long permeated the Roman and imperial Greek world and is likely to have conditioned exactly the sort of responses explored in this paper.

Indeed, such analogical thinking was encouraged not only as part of formal education, but by the cultural and, especially, the visual environment in which viewers were immersed (and viewing of the latter would have been reinforced by the former).Footnote 117 Key here is Arne Reinhardt's study of image reproduction in Roman reliefs, in which he argues that formal and substantive visual analogies within a series (both diachronic and context-specific) assume and generate a ‘comparative seeing’ (vergleichenden Sehens) that is similar to the comparative analysis exhibited in and stimulated by contemporary literature and rhetoric.Footnote 118 In the funerary sphere, we might point to Roman funerary speeches, which, according to Polybius, involved not just praise of the deceased, but praise of his or her ancestors,Footnote 119 all also juxtaposed in a visual congregation of imagines, with the deceased nearby on a bier.Footnote 120 Mythological comparisons, by contrast, were a feature of verse consolations and epitaphs, as well as funerary monuments.Footnote 121 As observed above, the encomiastic and consolatory rhetoric of examples in the funerary sphere has been well established.Footnote 122 But when we look closely at the images discussed in this paper, visual analogies also articulate a more provocative, deliberative rhetoric:Footnote 123 they retain their plurality, fragmenting as much as they blend, and the disjuncture invigorates exploratory thought.Footnote 124 What is more, the idea of image-mediated conceptualisation (including about death) might not have been unfamiliar to thinkers in this period.Footnote 125

The phenomenon that I explore here through one set of objects can thus be emically situated within a specific cultural regime characterised by emphasis on examples, analogies and the visual. Though death — and the conceptual challenge that it poses — might be considered a transcultural phenomenon (as intimated in my opening paragraph), the way in which it was conceptualised by Romans was culturally mediated; what I hope to have sketched out here, then, is both a philosophy-of-sorts of image-mediated thanatology and a specifically Roman way of figuring death by analogy.

Footnotes

I thank Mont Allen and Jaś Elsner for their generosity in reading this paper and sharing their ideas and photographs; I am also grateful to Peter Thonemann and the reviewers of this article for their comments, to audiences at the Manchester Research Seminar in Classics, Ancient History, Archaeology and Egyptology, at which I presented a draft of this paper, and to Barry Ferst, Lisa Schadow (Forschungsarchiv für Antike Plastik) and Daria Lanzuolo (Deutsches Archäologisches Institut Rom) for assistance in obtaining images and permissions.

1 On death and outsideness, see Clark Reference Clark2012.

2 Compare the challenge underlying pain communication and, generally, subjective experience: see Nagel Reference Nagel1974; Scarry Reference Scarry1985.

3 On comparing Roman and Chinese sarcophagi, see Clark Reference Clark2012.

4 For an ancient spin on ‘art’, see Tanner Reference Tanner2006 and responses in Platt and Squire Reference Platt and Squire2010.

5 See especially Grassinger Reference Grassinger1975: 70–90, nos. 43–67; Koch and Sichtermann Reference Koch and Sichtermann1982: 131–3; Zanker and Ewald Reference Ewald2012: 298–306. About twenty-five Adonis sarcophagi have been identified. The earliest dates to c. 150/160 c.e.; most fall in the second half of that century. On Roman sarcophagi generally, see Elsner Reference Elsner2011b.

6 On how Alfred Nock's dismissal of Franz Cumont's religious and symbolic readings of sarcophagi in Cumont Reference Cumont1942 swerved the discipline of non-Christian sarcophagi away from belief-oriented interpretations, see Elsner Reference Elsner2011b: 9–11; Elsner and Wu Reference Elsner and Wu2012a: 8–12; Zanker and Ewald Reference Ewald2012: 20; Koortbojian Reference Koortbojian2015: 288. See further Nock Reference Nock1946 and, defending Cumont's approach, J.-C. Balty Reference Balty2013.

7 See esp. Müller Reference Müller and Müller1994; Koortbojian Reference Koortbojian1995: 122–6; Zanker and Ewald Reference Ewald2012: 57–109, 199–243; Birk Reference Birk2013, esp. 21, 181–4; Newby Reference Newby2016, esp. 228–9, 273–319. On biography on sarcophagi, see Koortbojian Reference Koortbojian2015: 291–2. For emphasis on grief, see Newby Reference Newby2014. See further Elsner Reference Elsner2014.

8 For some recent work on exemplarity in Roman culture, see Langlands Reference Langlands2015; Roller Reference Roller2015; Newby Reference Newby2016, esp. 3–4, 320–47; Langlands Reference Langlands2018; Roller Reference Roller2018, esp. 4–23; Rood et al. Reference Rood, Atack and Phillips2020: 145–68; Elsner Reference Elsner, Sacchi and Formisano2022. On mythological exemplarity and rhetoric, see Koortbojian Reference Koortbojian1995: 278–83. On myth as a space for free thinking, see De Angelis Reference De Angelis2015: 581.

10 See for example Jones Reference Jones2015; Turner Reference Turner2015; Walter-Karydi Reference Walter-Karydi2015, part 4, esp. 331–4; Estrin Reference Estrin2016; Arrington Reference Arrington2018; Estrin Reference Estrin, Telò and Mueller2018; Gaifman and Platt Reference Gaifman and Platt2018, esp. 415–16; Squire Reference Squire2018a. For earlier work in this vein, see Vernant Reference Vernant1983: 305–20; Frontisi-Ducroux Reference Frontisi-Ducroux1986; Reference Frontisi-Ducroux1988: 34–5; Osborne Reference Osborne1988; Frontisi-Ducroux Reference Frontisi-Ducroux, Bérard and Lyons1989: 160–1. For the object-oriented turn, see especially Harman Reference Harman2005; Reference Harman2012.

11 In this I concur with Bielfeldt Reference Bielfeldt2019, who has drawn attention to the existentialist framework within which we might set sarcophagi that were commissioned by the living for themselves in anticipation of death.

12 On private visibility in a tomb setting, see Birk Reference Birk2012: 108–9; Borg Reference Borg2013: 214–29; Koortbojian Reference Koortbojian2015: 286–7; Newby Reference Newby2016: 228–72, 274. Some were publicly displayed, on which see Thomas Reference Thomas2012; Borg Reference Borg2013: 213–14. See further Elsner Reference Elsner2011b: 4–7; Birk Reference Birk2013: 34–9.

13 On the burial or concealment of sarcophagi, see Dresken-Weiland Reference Dresken-Weiland2003: 185–98; Meinecke Reference Meinecke2012; Zanker and Ewald Reference Ewald2012: 25–6; Borg Reference Borg2013: 229–35; Meinecke Reference Meinecke2013: 40–1. Vatican 10409 (Fig. 10, discussed below), a rare Adonis sarcophagus for which we have contextual detail, was piled in a tomb chamber with five other sarcophagi (Meinecke Reference Meinecke2014: 224–7, nos. 8–13); it is unlikely that it was seen after interment.

14 Even if ultimately hidden, some sarcophagi may have been displayed during the funeral: see Borg Reference Borg2013: 236–40; Meinecke Reference Meinecke2014: 144; Borg Reference Borg2019: 152–4.

15 On the choice involved in sarcophagus selection, see Birk Reference Birk2012; Russell Reference Russell2013: 293–310. Brilliant Reference Brilliant1992: 1031 argues that the Rinunccini sarcophagus was specially commissioned.

16 Note especially Robert et al. Reference Robert, Matz, Rodenwaldt and Andreae1890. Sarcophagi also appear in catalogues of collections and thematic publications. On the history of scholarship on sarcophagi, see Elsner and Wu Reference Elsner and Wu2012a, esp. 7–9; Zanker and Ewald Reference Ewald2012: 18–21; Koortbojian Reference Koortbojian2015: 287–8.

17 Indeed, on a more object-oriented model, efforts to pin down ‘the essence’ of a stone box and its images are doomed to failure. See Clark Reference Clark2012; Vout Reference Vout2014, with n. 10 above. See further Elsner Reference Elsner1995: 33–9; Reference Elsner2007: 128–31; Neer Reference Neer2010.

18 The mode of viewing invited is more expansive than the approach to the ‘openness’ of sarcophagi in Zanker and Ewald Reference Ewald2012: 49, which privileges artistic intention, and 51, on ‘narrative “excess”’.

20 On sarcophagi as narrative and allegory, see especially Giuliani Reference Giuliani1989: 37–9. See further Huskinson Reference Huskinson2012: 89.

21 On our evidence, see especially Elsner Reference Elsner2010; Elsner and Wu Reference Elsner and Wu2012a: 12; Elsner Reference Elsner, Holmes and Marta2017. On classicism and exemplarity, see Goldhill Reference Goldhill, de Jong and Sullivan1994; Reference Goldhill2017; Güthenke Reference Güthenke2020. One story that risks being lost in an example-based study is change over time; for this, see Borg Reference Borg2014: 248–51.

22 For the myth: Apollod., Bibl. 3.14.3–4; Bion, Lament for Adonis; Hyg., Poet. astr. 2.7.4; Ov., Met. 10.298–739; Sappho, fr. 140a Lobel–Page; Theoc., Id. 3.46–8 and 15.100–44. See further Atallah Reference Atallah1966, esp. 53–91; Gantz Reference Gantz1993: 729–31; Cyrino Reference Cyrino2010: 95–6.

23 For the cult: Ar., Lys. 387–98; Lucian, Syr. D. 6; Men., Sam. 38–46. See further Atallah Reference Atallah1966: 259–73; Frazer [1914] Reference Frazer2013: 223–35; Cyrino Reference Cyrino2010: 97–8. On Rome's inheritance of oriental religions: Cumont Reference Cumont1911; Reference Cumont1922: 8–43.

24 See Cumont Reference Cumont1922: 116–17, 203–4; see further n. 23 above.

25 For images, discussion and bibliography, see Grassinger Reference Grassinger1975: no. 59. See further Gori Reference Gori1743: 104–5, pl. 24; Dütschke Reference Dütschke1875: 129–32, no. 316; Heilmeyer Reference Heilmeyer1987; Blome Reference Blome1990; Zanker and Ewald Reference Ewald2012: 44–6, 303–6; Reinsberg Reference Reinsberg2006: 26–9, 192, no. 6; Newby Reference Newby2016: 287–91.

26 I am grateful to Mont Allen for drawing my attention to this architectural detail.

27 On the association of mythical and real on sarcophagi, see Zanker and Ewald Reference Ewald2012: 305; Koortbojian Reference Koortbojian2013; Stilp Reference Stilp2013, esp. 60–2; Allen Reference Allen2022: ch. 6, esp. 167–80 (the Rinuccini sarcophagus is discussed on 171–2). On the complexities of the interface, see Giuliani Reference Giuliani1989: 38–9; Bielfeldt Reference Bielfeldt2005: 19–22, 329–32; Lorenz Reference Lorenz2011, esp. 309–11 and nn. 3–6. There is also a juxtaposition of Greek and Roman and of sculptural styles: see Newby Reference Newby2016: 10–14 on the difficulty of dividing Greek and Roman myth; Heilmeyer Reference Heilmeyer1987: 224 on the styles.

28 On the expansion and amplification offered by myth, see De Angelis Reference De Angelis2015: 574–5.

29 See for example Heilmeyer Reference Heilmeyer1987: 224. Indeed, viewers might also move between these spaces, since they are implicitly situated in the imaginary vaulted space beneath the arch, which appears to project outwards from the relief and into the real world: see the opening paragraph of this Section.

30 On the handshake (dextrarum iunctio) on sarcophagi and suppression of individuality in the motif, see Huskinson Reference Huskinson2012: 84–91.

31 See especially Newby Reference Newby2016: 281–2. On nude Adonis as an example of courage, see Brilliant Reference Brilliant1992, esp. 1032, 1038; Koortbojian Reference Koortbojian1995, esp. 34–9. For focus on senatorial virtues, see Wrede Reference Wrede2001: 21–35, 103. The spear is lost: see Grassinger Reference Grassinger1975: no. 59. Grassinger emphasises the Adonis scene as a picture of wounding and death rather than courage (virtus).

32 See for example Newby Reference Newby2016: 291.

33 See n. 27.

34 For a confident assertion that a male corpse occupied the sarcophagus, see Heilmeyer Reference Heilmeyer1987: 220; Newby Reference Newby2016: 287. For a cautionary tale, see Neer Reference Neer2012a: 102–4.

35 The portraits of the two Roman male figures also differ. For some explanations, see Newby Reference Newby2016: 287–8.

36 See Zanker and Ewald Reference Ewald2012: 44–6, and also 47–9 on abstract viewing. See further Koortbojian Reference Koortbojian1995, esp. 29–32; Borg Reference Borg2014, esp. 249–51. For emphasis on the deceased's areas of life (family, gods and community), see Muth Reference Muth2004.

37 Blome Reference Blome1990: 66 notes that the right hand of the crouching figure grasped a slaughter knife, of which only traces have survived. On the practicalities of Roman bull sacrifice and its standard iconography, see Aldrete Reference Aldrete2014, esp. 33; the axe-wielding figure is the popa.

38 See for example Atallah Reference Atallah1966: 57–62; Cyrino Reference Cyrino2010: 95; Frazer [1914] Reference Frazer2013: 11.

39 See Koortbojian Reference Koortbojian1995: 25, nn. 10 and 11. Though note Schultz Reference Schultz2016 on the alignment (or not) between emic and etic perspectives on Roman sacrifice, esp. 62–3 on the relative scarcity in Roman art of scenes showing the moment or aftermath of killing. See further Elsner Reference Elsner2012b on images of sacrifice in late Roman art as rhetorical statements; here, the rhetoric surrounds not just religion and virtue (at least), but also death.

40 On another libation in a funerary context (on a south Italian pot), see Gaifman Reference Gaifman, Dill and Walde2009.

41 Compare Gaifman Reference Gaifman and Wood2013. On sacrifices to the dead, see Birk Reference Birk2013: 63.

42 Compare how Artemis sends a boar against Meleager in Hom., Il. 9.527–99.

43 Ares slays men in, for example, Hom., Il. 5.704 and 6.203. See further 16.543, 17.210, 22.72, 24.260, 498. Hector fights like Ares in 15.605 and like a boar in 12.41–50. Other men attack like boars in 11.413–20, 12.146–52, 13.471–7, 17.281–5. On the hunt as a metaphor for battle, see Koortbojian Reference Koortbojian1995: 34, n. 41.

44 See n. 37: Gregory Aldrete argues that both the popa (who strikes from above with the axe) and the cultrarius (who kneels with a knife) deal fatal blows.

45 See Blome Reference Blome1990: 66 on reconstruction of the lost spear from surviving traces: he proposes that Adonis's spear, broken in two places, was held in his right hand (lost), crossed his thighs (breaks and traces survive) and ended with its tip in the boar's throat (traces survive beneath the boar's jaw and a break in its throat).

46 On mise en abyme on funerary sculpture, see for example Elsner Reference Elsner2018a; Trimble Reference Trimble2018.

47 This man also enacts harmony generally: see Zanker and Ewald Reference Ewald2012: 303.

48 See Hersch Reference Hersch2010: 144–8. See further Brown Reference Brown1995 on themes of harmony in Rome's foundational story of marriage by abduction.

49 It would not be unusual to think of Proserpina in the context of Adonis. In some versions of his story, she competed with Venus for his affections and she appears, facing Venus, on one side panel of an Adonis sarcophagus in Rostock. See Grassinger Reference Grassinger1975: no. 47; Koch and Sichtermann Reference Koch and Sichtermann1982: 133.

50 Huskinson Reference Huskinson2012: 85 suggests a conflation of identities (Concordia and Juno Pronuba).

51 In fact, Blome Reference Blome1990: 39 observed that the raised arm of the butcher is positioned so close to her head as to give the impression that she is almost, in a figurative sense, artistically killed by the axe.

52 On Proserpina sarcophagi, see Zanker and Ewald Reference Ewald2012: 84–8, 384–9; Borg Reference Borg2014: 240–4. Compare the violent and erotic associations between killing and marriage in the sacrifice of Polyxena, discussed in Neer Reference Neer2012a: 109–10. Stine Birk finds more consolatory resonances in images of Pluto and Proserpina: Birk Reference Birk2013: 100–3. Hans Dütschke suggested the Rinuccini left-hand panel featured a wedding sacrifice, which would further link marriage with death: Dütschke Reference Dütschke1875: 129–32, no. 316; see further Blome Reference Blome1990: 38–42.

53 Image permalink: arachne.dainst.org/entity/6486982. Proserpina was a popular funerary motif: see Newby Reference Newby2011: 219–24; Reference Newby2016: 232–6.

54 Image permalink: arachne.dainst.org/entity/6208553. See further Zanker and Ewald Reference Ewald2012: 88–90, 314–18.

55 On an object-oriented model: see n. 10.

56 For a symbolic reading of the Dioscuri here (representing the cosmic cycle), see Blome Reference Blome1990: 55–9.

57 See for example Grassinger Reference Grassinger1975: nos. 53, 55, 61, 62, 65, 67. She does not, however, appear in the hunt scene in earlier sarcophagi: Koortbojian Reference Koortbojian1995: 33, n. 37.

58 Image permalink: arachne.dainst.org/entity/6222820. See Grassinger Reference Grassinger1975: no. 62; Zanker and Ewald Reference Ewald2012: 209–10, 300–1.

59 Image permalink: arachne.dainst.org/entity/5406902. See Grassinger Reference Grassinger1975: no. 65; Koortbojian Reference Koortbojian1995: 50–3; Zanker and Ewald Reference Ewald2012: 301–3.

60 See Brilliant Reference Brilliant1992: 1038.

61 On cross-gender application of role models, see Newby Reference Newby2014: 269–70.

62 See n. 23.

63 See Newby Reference Newby2014: 260, 262, 271–80.

64 For example, profectio scenes appear on the right end of Grassinger Reference Grassinger1975: no. 46 and on the left of nos. 53, 61, 62, 65, 67; wound-tending scenes appear on, for example, the left end of nos. 43, 45, 46, 47, 48, 52, 55.

65 Compare Zanker Reference Zanker, Angelis, Muth and Hölscher1999 and Linant de Bellefonds Reference Linant de Bellefonds2013 on the idealised love and despair of a mourning woman. See further Koortbojian Reference Koortbojian1995: 40–1. It is striking, in fact, that the bride on the Rinuccini sarcophagus looks not only like the soldier beside her, but like her counterpart in departure scenes on other (later) sarcophagi — Adonis. See Grassinger Reference Grassinger1975: nos. 65 and 67.

66 See for example Newby Reference Newby2016: 318–19.

67 Compare the claim in Koortbojian Reference Koortbojian2015: 290 that Roman life scenes (by contrast with mythological scenes) ‘might have highly specific resonance’. In fact, an image of marriage or military sacrifice can also be figurative; see especially Koortbojian Reference Koortbojian2013: 149, 153–5; Allen Reference Allen2022, esp. 167–72, 174–6.

68 We might describe the relationship between image and identity as one of frame and framed (or, in Kantian terms, parergon and ergon). On frames and ornaments in classical art, see Platt and Squire Reference Platt and Squire2017b and Dietrich and Squire Reference Dietrich and Squire2018, especially the introductions to those volumes (Platt and Squire Reference Platt and Squire2017a; Squire Reference Squire2018b). On the relationship between head, body, hair and dress and the ‘visual power of formula, repetition and analogy’ see Trimble Reference Trimble2017.

69 Koortbojian Reference Koortbojian1995: 47–8. The allegorical approach in Brilliant Reference Brilliant1984: 159–65 is comparable: behind the combinations (in his words, a ‘conflation’, 161) of motifs stands the ‘heroic hunter’ who ‘serves the needs of the deceased beyond the limits of narrative integrity’.

70 Text: OCT. My translation. Comparable interest in the ambiguity generated by the absence or presence of visual attributes is discernable in Hellenistic and Second Sophistic literature: see Gutzwiller Reference Gutzwiller, Harder, Regtuit and Wakker2002: 93–4 on pointed ambivalence in Hellenistic epigrams; see further Lucian, Heracles 1 and Syr. D. 36, where a mismatch between body and attribute is notable and understood to be significant.

71 Variously called erotes, cupids, amorini, amoretti, putti and so on (with symbolic or mythological associations accordingly, on which see Nock Reference Nock1946: 144, 148–9).

72 On the body schema of the nude male hunter (in Roman wall painting), see Elsner and Squire Reference Elsner and Squire2015: 192. On visual allusion, see Elsner Reference Elsner2014: 332–3. On typology and assimilation of one myth by another, see Koortbojian Reference Koortbojian1995, esp. 134–5. For the origins of the Adonis hunt scene in Calydonian boar hunt imagery (involving Meleager), see Grassinger Reference Grassinger1975: 80–1. On the participation of the Dioscuri in the Calydonian boar hunt, see Blome Reference Blome1990: 55.

73 Koch Reference Koch1975: nos. 6, 8.

74 Nearly all boar-spearing Meleager figures in Koch Reference Koch1975 are shown in this pose (including Loves posing as Meleager, as in no. 12). Grassinger Reference Grassinger1975: 81 observes similarities between Adonis's stone-throwing hunting companions on the Rinuccini sarcophagus and spear-throwing hunters on Meleager sarcophagi. Compare the dead Meleager in the superior frieze (discussed below).

75 Zanker and Ewald Reference Ewald2012: 300.

76 Vatican: see n. 59. Mantua: image permalink: arachne.dainst.org/entity/1935791. See Grassinger Reference Grassinger1975: no. 55.

77 On ‘iconographic promiscuity’ and the rhetoric of translating scenes between Christian and non-Christian sarcophagi, see Elsner Reference Elsner2011a, and n. 72. In fact, Antonio Gori initially identified the Rinuccini scene as featuring Meleager: see Gori Reference Gori1743: 105.

78 This is the suggestion in Grassinger Reference Grassinger1975: 85–8. Non-mythological hunters might appear on horseback: see Birk Reference Birk2013: 107–13. On the challenge of distinguishing mythological and generic scenes, see Newby Reference Newby2016: 268. See further Borg Reference Borg2013: 178–82. On the popularity of portraits on non-mythological hunt sarcophagi, see Newby Reference Newby2011: 215–16. On a shift over time from mythological stories to more philosophical narrative-free lion-hunt scenes, see Ewald Reference Ewald2012.

79 Image permalink: arachne.dainst.org/entity/6282311. See Grassinger Reference Grassinger1975: nos. 61, 53.

80 Image permalink: arachne.dainst.org/entity/5406909. See Sichtermann Reference Sichtermann1992: nos. 2, 99, who emphasises contrast. Compare no. 145 in that volume, which frames a central portrait with Ganymede and Leda (each attended by Zeus in bird form, as eagle and swan). For the combination of two scenes featuring Patroclus's death in a lower frieze with two featuring Hector's in a narrow upper frieze, see Grassinger Reference Grassinger1975: no. 27. See further Koortbojian Reference Koortbojian1995: 102–6; Reference Koortbojian2015: 293–4; Newby Reference Newby2016: 343–7.

81 This is true of other scenes on supposed Adonis friezes. Scenes of departure may not just borrow from Hippolytus and Phaedra iconography but actually represent them. Compare Koch and Sichtermann Reference Koch and Sichtermann1982: 131–3. Koortbojian Reference Koortbojian1995: 30–1 notes the connection, called ‘a form of contamination’ in Koortbojian Reference Koortbojian2015: 294. See further Brilliant Reference Brilliant1992: 1035, ‘a blurring of identities’; Zanker and Ewald Reference Ewald2012: 302. This sort of ‘montage’ (a term used in Giuliani Reference Giuliani1989: 35) does not fit within the four-fold categorisation in Snodgrass Reference Snodgrass1982: 5 and Shapiro Reference Shapiro1994: 8–9. For a similar approach to mine, see Allen Reference Allen2022: 154–60 on how ‘typological assimilation’ invites viewers to think, to explore affinities and discrepancies. On replication, repetition and death, see especially Elsner Reference Elsner2018a: 353–4.

82 See Elsner Reference Elsner2012a: 188–93. See further Koortbojian Reference Koortbojian1995: 41–6.

83 Robert Reference Robert1897: 7–24. The double departure in, for example, the left-hand scene of the Mantua sarcophagus (on which see Koortbojian Reference Koortbojian1995: 41–6) acts as beginning and end.

84 Moreover, Vatican 10409 sits outside either category because the ‘care scene’ is in the centre. See Grassinger Reference Grassinger1975: 76, 90; Koortbojian Reference Koortbojian1995: 50–3.

85 Birk Reference Birk2013: 65–6.

86 Image permalink: arachne.dainst.org/entity/1075027. For outstretched nude figures with different identities, see for example Sichtermann Reference Sichtermann1992: nos. 27–137 (Endymion); Grassinger Reference Grassinger1975: nos. 40 (Hector), 75 (Alcestis); Koch Reference Koch1975: nos. 8, 64, 78, 79, 80, 83, 88, 91, 92, 93, 98, 101 (Meleager), as well as 73, 74, 75, 77 (Loves as Meleager). Koortbojian Reference Koortbojian1995: 59–62 finds intimations of Aeneas in the central Adonis figure on the Rospigliosi sarcophagus (Fig. 9). Grassinger Reference Grassinger1975 notes echoes of falling figures inherited from Greek art such as the Dying Gaul or the fallen soldier on the grave marker of Dexileos. See further Giuliani Reference Giuliani1989 on similarities between Achilles and Meleager compositions. There are also echoes here of the fallen Sarpedon in Greek art; on that dead-body motif and its afterlife, see Spivey Reference Spivey2018: chs 7 and 8.

87 See n. 77.

88 Zanker and Ewald Reference Ewald2012: 44–6. On mingling biography with mythology or allegory on sarcophagi, see Koortbojian Reference Koortbojian2015: 292.

89 See especially Koortbojian Reference Koortbojian2013: 150–1 on the simultaneous ‘intensification of individuation’ and ‘de-personalization’ when mythological figures are given portraits. In fact, we might treat any figure on a sarcophagus as a portrait, as in Elsner Reference Elsner2018b, esp. 548. On how portraits control (and ‘tie down’), as well as enhance, the messages of mythological representations, see especially Newby Reference Newby2011; Reference Newby2014: 280. See also Zanker and Ewald Reference Ewald2012: 39–44. For further discussion of portraits on sarcophagi and what they do for death, see Huskinson Reference Huskinson1998: 131; Platt Reference Platt2011: 377–84; Elsner Reference Elsner2012a: 179–80; Platt Reference Platt2017: 379–80.

90 On the unusual portraits on the Rinuccini sarcophagus and implications for its use over time, see Reinsberg Reference Reinsberg2006: 28–9. See further n. 35 above.

91 Early drawings of the sarcophagus, such as the one by Antonio Gori, suggest that Adonis may once have had a portrait (argued in Brilliant Reference Brilliant1992: n. 3 on Gori Reference Gori1743: pl. 24), but we cannot be sure that these features were not supplemented by the artist.

92 See Huskinson Reference Huskinson1998: 149–55; Reference Huskinson2012: 84; Birk Reference Birk2013: 55–8; Elsner Reference Elsner2018b: 561–2.

93 This might have been especially noticeable in ‘cross-gendered figures’, though see Birk Reference Birk2011 and Reference Meinecke2013: 115–56. See further Allen Reference Allen2019 on techniques for distinguishing portraits of the deceased and De Angelis Reference De Angelis2015: 573–4 on how though, for Romans, individuality was restricted to the head with the body communicating general qualities or status, some examples (such as a lack of portraits on figures of Bacchus) indicate that bodies did not completely lose their identities.

94 Zanker and Ewald 2016: 254–60; Borg Reference Borg2013: 161–211; Koortbojian Reference Koortbojian2015: 296. Though see Allen Reference Allen2022: 197–214 for the suggestion that Romans did not so much reject mythology as embrace the present and proximate.

95 Ewald Reference Ewald2012: 62–4; Zanker and Ewald Reference Ewald2012: 301–3.

96 On the alienating effect of their self-presentation as an expression of death, see Bielfeldt Reference Bielfeldt2005: 326–7.

97 See especially Vout Reference Vout2014: 294, ‘unconvincing is the point’. Compare De Angelis Reference De Angelis2019 on the distancing effect of second-century mythological sarcophagi, which, he argues, helped regulate excessive emotions. The impact here is consistent with the disjointed combination of individualised heads and generic bodies: see below, Section III, esp. nn. 113 and 124.

99 Koortbojian Reference Koortbojian1995: 135–41. The reasoning is similar in Brilliant Reference Brilliant1984, esp. 159–65 (see n. 69 above): for Brilliant, combinations of mythological motifs dissolve into allegory; his emphasis on the ‘inner truth’ (164) behind such allegory misses the meaningful impact of the combination's plurality. See further Borg Reference Borg2013: 177.

100 On familiarity with and formalisation of myths and their images, see Koortbojian Reference Koortbojian1995: 10–13. See further Huskinson Reference Huskinson2012 on how strigilated sarcophagi enabled and encouraged viewers to explore associations between the figured images that were set amidst the fluting.

101 See Koortbojian Reference Koortbojian2015: 287 on loss of individuality in death in Roman tradition; Elsner Reference Elsner2018b: 557 on a sarcophagus's ‘meditation on both the particularity and the general implications of life and death’.

103 On the potential for ‘mythological emplotment’ to erase individuality, see Ewald Reference Ewald2011: 264. Compare the play in one Greek inscription from the Roman imperial period (IG XIV 2131) on the impossibility of knowing whether a ‘fleshless corpse’ is Hylas or Thersites (discussed in Vout Reference Vout2014: 292–3, with n. 22). See further n. 70 above.

104 Zanker and Ewald Reference Ewald2012: 305.

105 See Grassinger Reference Grassinger1975: 78.

106 See Elsner Reference Elsner2012a; Trimble Reference Trimble2018: 341–2; Elsner Reference Elsner2018b: 551–2. Notable here is the late third- or early fourth-century c.e. child's sarcophagus in the Capitoline Museum (Koch and Sichtermann Reference Koch and Sichtermann1982: no. 215, 183–4), which combines a three-dimensional sculpture of a sleeping or dead boy on the lid with themes of artistic creation (including the myth of Prometheus) on the base in relief: see Elsner Reference Elsner2018b: 556–8 for discussion.

107 See especially Neer Reference Neer2012b: 118: the act of seeing a person (or the idea of a person) as a work of art is, in itself, a sort of violence. Seeing Adonis as a statue might enact the experience of seeing a person as a cold, stiff corpse. See further n. 106.

108 On imitation, allegory and reflexivity in art, in a different context, see Neer Reference Neer2002. For further examples and discussion of the influence of sculpture in the round on sarcophagi, see Allen Reference Allen2022: 160–3.

109 See above, Section II.

110 On art's mediation of myth, see Gaifman Reference Gaifman, Dill and Walde2009: 580–1.

111 On the ‘presence’ of mythological art, see De Angelis Reference De Angelis2015: 569–70.

112 Squire Reference Squire, Boehm, Budelacci, Di Monte and Renner2015a, building on especially the ‘appendage aesthetic’ of Brilliant Reference Brilliant1963: 26–31 (discussed on 89). For approaches to the head/body disjuncture, see further Brilliant Reference Brilliant1974: 166–87; Nodelmann Reference Nodelmann and D'Ambra1993, esp. 20–5 (on the allegorical nature of Roman portrait heads); Stewart Reference Stewart2004: 47–59; Hallett Reference Hallett2005: ch. 7, esp. on portrait heads as somewhat idealised (277–81) and a dramatisation of character (281–9) (note that Hallett sees no head/body contradiction); Fejfer Reference Fejfer2008: 181–3, 203–5; Trimble Reference Trimble2011: ch. 4 (on how visual head/body assemblages could ‘shape and extend social identity’).

113 On the mediation by imagines of ideas about portraiture and memory, see Squire Reference Squire, Boehm, Budelacci, Di Monte and Renner2015a: 81–2, 88. See further Trimble Reference Trimble2011: 152–3 and especially Vout Reference Vout2014: 294–8.

114 For a review of the changes in style and subject on Roman mythological sarcophagi, and interrogation of the explanations offered in scholarship, see now Allen Reference Allen2022: 24–40, chs 1–5. Note his section on how a new portrait style (chiselled rather than drilled) in the reign of Caracalla enabled sculptors of sarcophagi to distinguish portrait heads (190–5). See further nn. 93 and 94 above.

115 See n. 94 above.

116 The preparatory educational exercises in Greek (progymnasmata) undertaken by elites as a foundation for rhetorical training might include practice in comparison (synkrisis): see Webb Reference Webb2001: 294; Goldhill Reference Goldhill and Gunderson2009: 230–1. Such comparative exercises appear in surviving Greek handbooks: see for example Theon, Prog. 10.112–15 Pat. (first century c.e.); ps.-Hermog., Prog. 8.42–4 Rabe (possibly third century c.e.). For synkrisis on Roman sarcophagi, see Elsner Reference Elsner2014: 330–3. Moreover, the use that progymnasmata exercises make of examples from classical literature as models drilled pupils in analogical thinking: see Webb Reference Webb2001: 307–8.

117 See n. 116 above with Rousselle Reference Rousselle2001 and especially Elsner and Squire Reference Elsner and Squire2015. Indeed, invitations to think in analogical terms were not limited to funerary media: consider the networks of images orchestrated by Roman domestic wall paintings. The classic work here is Bergmann Reference Bergmann1994. See further, for example, Lorenz Reference Lorenz2014; Elsner and Squire Reference Elsner and Squire2015: 190–203, esp. 192–3. Allen Reference Allen2022: 155–60 also observes the common theme.

118 Reinhardt Reference Reinhardt2019, esp. 122–8 (citation at 123).

119 Polyb. 6.53–4. On comparison with historical exempla as a feature of funerary speeches, especially under the influence of Greek rhetoric, see Newby Reference Newby2016: 279–82 (noting on 282–3 that prose consolations also made use of historical exempla).

120 See Beck Reference Beck2018: 269–70; Pepe Reference Pepe2018: 288.

121 Newby Reference Newby2014; Reference Newby2016: 282–3. See further Elsner and Squire Reference Elsner and Squire2015: 183–5 on the interaction of image, text and memory on an early Hadrianic funerary altar.

122 See n. 7 above.

123 See n. 97 above: the notion of failure or aporia in Vout Reference Vout2014 offers a powerful corrective to the idea that Roman rhetoric was full of answers (as argued by Meyer Reference Meyer2014). See further Elsner Reference Elsner2014, emphasising the panegyrical qualities of Roman rhetoric: the deliberative (which he identifies in Christian art) can also be found in Graeco-Roman visual culture.

124 Compare Squire Reference Squire, Boehm, Budelacci, Di Monte and Renner2015a: 95 on Roman portrait statues as simultaneously ‘an assemblage of eclectic parts and a single coherent whole’. In a similar vein, Rebecca Langlands's work on Roman exemplarity has emphasised its role in promoting controversial thinking: see Langlands Reference Langlands2018, esp. ch. 12. See further n. 8 above.

125 See Webb Reference Webb2015 on ideas in the Roman imperial period that sight influenced imagination and speech.

References

BIBLIOGRAPHY

Aldrete, G. S. 2014: ‘Axes, bulls, and blood: Some practical aspects of Roman animal sacrifice’, Journal of Roman Studies 104, 2850.10.1017/S0075435814000033CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Allen, M. 2019: ‘Isolating the deceased in the picture: Tools and technique on mythological sarcophagi’, in Hallett 2019, 97–123.Google Scholar
Allen, M. 2022: The Death of Myth on Roman Sarcophagi: Allegory and Visual Narrative in the Late Empire, Cambridge.10.1017/9781009039031CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Arrington, N. 2018: ‘Touch and remembrance in Greek funerary art’, Art Bulletin 100(3), 7–27.10.1080/00043079.2018.1429743CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Atallah, W. 1966: Adonis dans la littérature et l'art grecs, Paris.Google Scholar
Balty, J. 2013: ‘Achille à Skyros: polysémie de l'image mythologique’, in Galinier and Baratte 2013, 117–30.Google Scholar
Balty, J.-C. 2013: ‘Franz Cumont et l'interprétation symbolique des sarcophages romains, à près de soixante ans des Recherches’, in Galinier and Baratte 2013, 7–27.Google Scholar
Beck, H. 2018: ‘Of fragments and feelings: Roman funeral oratory revisited’, in Gray, Balbo, Marshall and Steel 2018, 263–80.Google Scholar
Bergmann, B. 1994: ‘The Roman house as memory theater: The House of the Tragic Poet in Pompeii’, Art Bulletin 76: 225–56.10.1080/00043079.1994.10786585CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bielfeldt, R. 2005: Orestes auf römischen Sarkophagen, Berlin.Google Scholar
Bielfeldt, R. 2019: ‘Vivi fecerunt. Roman sarcophagi for and by the living’, in Hallett 2019, 65–96.Google Scholar
Birk, S. 2011: ‘Cross-gendering and individuality on third century Roman sarcophagi’, in Elsner and Huskinson 2011, 229–60.Google Scholar
Birk, S. 2012: ‘Sarcophagi, self-representation, and patronage in Rome and Tyre’, in Birk and Poulsen 2012, 107–33.Google Scholar
Birk, S. 2013: Depicting the Dead: Self-Representation and Commemoration on Roman Sarcophagi with Portraits, Aarhus.10.2307/jj.608129CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Birk, S. and Poulsen, B. (eds) 2012: Patrons and Viewers in Late Antiquity, Aarhus.10.2307/jj.608309CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Blome, P. 1990: ‘Der Sarkophag Rinuccini. Eine unverhoffte Wiederentdeckung’, Jahrbuch der Berliner Museen 32, 3568.10.2307/4125821CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Borg, B. 2013: Crisis and Ambition: Tombs and Burial Customs in Third-Century CE Rome, Oxford.Google Scholar
Borg, B. 2014: ‘Rhetoric and art in third-century AD Rome’, in Elsner and Meyer 2014, 235–55.Google Scholar
Borg, B. (ed.) 2015: A Companion to Roman Art, Chichester.10.1002/9781118886205CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Borg, B. 2019: ‘Hidden splendour: the display context of metropolitan sarcophagi’, in Hallett 2019, 145–59.Google Scholar
Brilliant, R. 1963: Gesture and Rank in Roman Art. The Use of Gestures to Denote Status in Roman Sculpture and Coinage, New Haven.Google Scholar
Brilliant, R. 1974: Roman Art from the Republic to Constantine, London.Google Scholar
Brilliant, R. 1984: Visual Narratives: Storytelling in Etruscan and Roman Art, Ithaca and London.Google Scholar
Brilliant, R. 1992: ‘Roman myth/Greek myth: Reciprocity and appropriation on a Roman sarcophagus in Berlin’, Studi Italiani di Filologia Classica, 3rd series, 10(2), 1030–45.Google Scholar
Brown, R. 1995: ‘Livy's Sabine women and the idea of Concordia’, Transactions of the American Philological Association 125, 291319.Google Scholar
Clark, T. J. 2012: ‘Death panels’, in Elsner and Wu 2012b, 237–41.Google Scholar
Cumont, F. 1911: The Oriental Religions in Roman Paganism, Chicago.Google Scholar
Cumont, F. 1922: After Life in Roman Paganism, New Haven.Google Scholar
Cumont, F. 1942: Recherches sur le symbolisme funéraire des Romains, Paris.Google Scholar
Cyrino, M. S. 2010: Aphrodite, London and New York.Google Scholar
De Angelis, F. 2015: ‘Roman art and myth’, in Borg 2015, 569–84.Google Scholar
De Angelis, F. 2019: ‘The violence of emotions: Death, myths, and empathy in Rome (and Etruria)’, in Hallett 2019, 43–56.Google Scholar
Dietrich, N. and Squire, M. (eds) 2018: Ornament and Figure in Graeco-Roman Art: Rethinking Visual Ontologies in Classical Antiquity, Berlin.10.1515/9783110469578CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dresken-Weiland, J. 2003: Sarkophagbestattungen des 4.–6. Jahrhunderts im Westen des römischen Reiches, Rome.Google Scholar
Dütschke, H. 1875: Antike Bildwerke in Oberitalien, vol. 2, Leipzig.Google Scholar
Elsner, J. 1995: Art and the Roman Viewer: The Transformation of Art from the Pagan World to Christianity, Cambridge.Google Scholar
Elsner, J. 2007: Roman Eyes: Visuality and Subjectivity in Art and Text, Princeton.10.1515/9780691240244CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Elsner, J. 2010: ‘Myth and chronicle: A response’, in Platt and Squire 2010, 289–307.Google Scholar
Elsner, J. 2011a: ‘Image and rhetoric in Early Christian sarcophagi: Reflections on Jesus’ trial’, in Elsner and Huskinson 2011, 359–86.Google Scholar
Elsner, J. 2011b: ‘Introduction’, in Elsner and Huskinson 2011, 1–20.Google Scholar
Elsner, J. 2012a: ‘Decorative imperatives between concealment and display: The form of sarcophagi’, in Elsner and Wu 2012b, 178–95.Google Scholar
Elsner, J. 2012b: ‘Sacrifice in Late Roman art’, in Faraone and Naiden 2012, 120–63.Google Scholar
Elsner, J. 2014: ‘Rational, passionate and appetitive: The psychology of rhetoric and the transformation of visual culture from non-Christian to Christian sarcophagi in the Roman world’, in Elsner and Meyer 2014, 316–49.Google Scholar
Elsner, J. 2017: ‘Transmission’, in Holmes, B. and Marta, K. (eds), Liquid Antiquity, Geneva, 182–5.Google Scholar
Elsner, J. 2018a: ‘Ornament, figure and mise en abyme on Roman sarcophagi’, in Dietrich and Squire 2018, 352–91.Google Scholar
Elsner, J. 2018b: ‘The embodied object: Recensions of the dead on Roman sarcophagi’, in Gaifman, Platt and Squire 2018, 546–65.Google Scholar
Elsner, J. 2022: ‘Visual epitome in Late Antique art’, in Sacchi, P. F. and Formisano, M. (eds), Epitomic Writing in Late Antiquity and Beyond: Forms of Unabridged Writing, London, 202–29.Google Scholar
Elsner, J. and Huskinson, J. (eds): 2011: Life, Death and Representation: Some New Work on Roman Sarcophagi, Berlin and New York.Google Scholar
Elsner, J. and Meyer, M. J. (eds) 2014: Art and Rhetoric in Roman Culture, New York.10.1017/CBO9780511732317CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Elsner, J. and Squire, M. 2015: ‘Sight and memory’, in Squire 2015b, 180–204.Google Scholar
Elsner, J. and Wu, H. 2012a: ‘Editorial’, in Elsner and Wu 2012b, 5–21.Google Scholar
Elsner, J. and Wu, H. (eds) 2012b: ‘Sarcophagi’, special issue, Res: Anthropology and Aesthetics 61/62.Google Scholar
Estrin, S. 2016: ‘Cold comfort: Empathy and memory in an Archaic funerary monument from Akraiphia’, Classical Antiquity 35(2), 190214.10.1525/ca.2016.35.2.189CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Estrin, S. 2018: ‘Memory incarnate: Material objects and private visions in Classical Athens, from Euripides’ Ion to the gravesite’, in Telò, M. and Mueller, M. (eds), The Materialities of Greek Tragedy. Objects and Affect in Aeschylus, Sophocles, and Euripides, London, 111–32.Google Scholar
Ewald, B. 2011: ‘Myth and visual narrative in the second sophistica comparative approach: Notes on an Attic Hippolytus sarcophagus in Agrigento’, in Elsner and Huskinson 2011, 261–307.Google Scholar
Ewald, B. 2012: ‘Paradigms of personhood and regimes of representation: Some notes on the transformation of Roman sarcophagi’, in Elsner and Wu 2012b, 41–64.Google Scholar
Faraone, C. A. and Naiden, F. S. (eds) 2012: Greek and Roman Animal Sacrifice, Cambridge.10.1017/CBO9780511894602CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fejfer, J. 2008: Roman Portraits in Context, Berlin.10.1515/9783110209990CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frazer, J. [1914] 2013: The Golden Bough. Volume 5, Adonis, Attis, Osiris, 3rd edn, Cambridge.Google Scholar
Frontisi-Ducroux, F. 1986: ‘La mort en face’, Mètis 1(2), 197217.Google Scholar
Frontisi-Ducroux, F. 1988: ‘Figures de l'invisible: stratégies textuelles et stratégies iconiques’, Annali. Dipartimento di studi del mondo classico e del Mediterraneo antico, Sezione di archeologia e storia antica 10, thematic session on ‘La parola, l'immagine, la tomba’, 27–40.Google Scholar
Frontisi-Ducroux, F. 1989: ‘In the mirror of the mask’, in Bérard, C. et al. (eds) and Lyons, D. (trans.), A City of Images: Iconography and Society in Ancient Greece, 151–65, Princeton.Google Scholar
Gaifman, M. 2009: ‘The libation of Oinomaos’, in Dill, U. and Walde, C. (eds), Antike Mythen, Medien, Transformationen, Konstruktionen, Berlin, 576–98.10.1515/9783110217247.7.576CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gaifman, M. 2013: ‘Timelessness, fluidity, and Apollo's libation’, in Wood, C. (ed.), ‘Wet/Dry’, special issue, Res 63/64 (spring/autumn 2013), 3952.Google Scholar
Gaifman, M. and Platt, V. 2018: ‘Introduction: From Grecian urn to embodied object’, in Gaifman, Platt and Squire 2018, 402–19.Google Scholar
Gaifman, M., Platt, V. and Squire, M. (eds) 2018: ‘The embodied object in Classical Antiquity’, special issue, Art History 41(3).Google Scholar
Galinier, M. and Baratte, F. (eds) 2013: Iconographie funéraire romaine et société: Corpus antique, approches nouvelles?, Perpignan.10.4000/books.pupvd.7039CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gantz, T. 1993: Early Greek Myth: A Guide to Literary and Artistic Sources, Baltimore.Google Scholar
Giuliani, L. 1989: ‘Achill-Sarkophage in Ost und West: Genese einer Ikonographie’, Jahrbuch der Berliner Museen 31, 2539.10.2307/4125849CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldhill, S. 1994: ‘The failure of exemplarity’, in de Jong, I. J. and Sullivan, J. J. (eds), Modern Critical Theory and Classical Literature, Leiden, 5173.10.1163/9789004329263_004CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldhill, S. 2009: ‘Rhetoric and the second sophistic’, in Gunderson, E. (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Ancient Rhetoric, Cambridge, 228–41.10.1017/CCOL9780521860543.015CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldhill, S. 2017: ‘The limits of the case study: exemplarity and the reception of Classical literature’, New Literary History 48(3), 415–35.10.1353/nlh.2017.0023CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gori, A. F. 1743: Inscriptionum antiquarum Graecarum et Romanarum quae in Etruriae urbibus extant, vol. 3, Florence.Google Scholar
Grassinger, D. 1975: Die mythologischen SarkophageAchill bis Amazonen, Die antiken Sarkophagreliefs, vol. 12, no. 1, Berlin.Google Scholar
Gray, C., Balbo, A., Marshall, R. M. A. and Steel, C. E. W. (eds) 2018: Reading Republican Oratory: Reconstructions, Contexts, Receptions, Oxford.10.1093/oso/9780198788201.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Güthenke, C. 2020: ‘“For Time is / nothing if not amenable”–exemplarity, time, reception’, Classical Receptions Journal 12(1), 4661.10.1093/crj/clz025CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gutzwiller, K. 2002: ‘Art's echo: The tradition of Hellenistic ecphrastic epigram’, in Harder, M. A., Regtuit, R. F. and Wakker, G. C. (eds), Hellenistic Epigrams, 85112, Leuven, Paris and Sterling, VA.Google Scholar
Hallett, C. H. 2005: The Roman Nude: Heroic Portrait Statuary 200 BC–AD 300, Oxford.10.1093/oso/9780199240494.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hallett, C. H. (ed.) 2019: Flesheaters: An International Symposium on Roman Sarcophagi, Wiesbaden.Google Scholar
Harman, G. 2005: Guerrilla Metaphysics: Phenomenology and the Carpentry of Things, Chicago.Google Scholar
Harman, G. 2012: ‘The well-wrought broken hammer: Object-oriented literary criticism’, New Literary History 43(2), 183203.10.1353/nlh.2012.0016CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Heilmeyer, W.-D. 1987: ‘Der Sarkophag Rinuccini’, Jahrbuch Preussischer Kulturbesitz 24, 215–28.Google Scholar
Hersch, K. K. 2010: The Roman Wedding: Ritual and Meaning in Antiquity, Cambridge.10.1017/CBO9780511762086CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Huskinson, J. 1998: ‘“Unfinished portrait heads” on later Roman sarcophagi: Some new perspectives’, Papers of the British School at Rome 66, 129–58.10.1017/S0068246200004256CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Huskinson, J. 2012: ‘Reading identity on Roman strigilated sarcophagi’, in Elsner and Wu 2012b, 80–97.Google Scholar
Jones, N. 2015: ‘Phantasms and metonyms: The limits of representation in fifth-century Athens’, Art History 38(5): 814–37.10.1111/1467-8365.12183CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Koch, G. 1975: Die mythologischen SarkophageMeleager, Die antiken Sarkophagreliefs, vol. 12, Berlin.Google Scholar
Koch, G. and Sichtermann, H. 1982: Römische Sarkophage, Munich.Google Scholar
Koortbojian, M. 1995: Myth, Meaning, and Memory on Roman Sarcophagi, Berkeley and London.Google Scholar
Koortbojian, M. 2013: ‘The mythology of everyday life’, in Galinier and Baratte 2013, 148–69.Google Scholar
Koortbojian, M. 2015: ‘Roman sarcophagi’, in Borg 2015, 286–300.Google Scholar
Langlands, R. 2015: ‘Roman exemplarity: Mediating between general and particular’, in Lowrie and Lüdemann 2015, 68–80.Google Scholar
Langlands, R. 2018: Exemplary Ethics in Ancient Rome, Cambridge.10.1017/9781139629164CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Linant de Bellefonds, P. 2013: ‘Le «motif de Phèdre» sur les sarcophages romains: comment l'image crée la vertu’, in Galinier and Baratte 2013, 65–79.Google Scholar
Lorenz, K. 2011: ‘Image in distress? The death of Meleager on Roman sarcophagi’, in Elsner and Huskinson 2011, 309–36.Google Scholar
Lorenz, K. 2014: ‘The Casa del Menandro in Pompeii: Rhetoric and the topology of Roman wall painting’, in Elsner and Meyer 2014, 183–210.Google Scholar
Lowrie, M. and Lüdemann, S. (eds) 2015: Exemplarity and Singularity: Thinking through Particulars in Philosophy, Literature, and Law, London and New York.10.4324/9781315778419CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Meinecke, K. 2012: ‘Invisible sarcophagi: Coffin and viewer in the Late Imperial Age’, in Birk and Poulsen 2012, 83–105.Google Scholar
Meinecke, K. 2013: ‘Funerary cult at sarcophagi, Rome and vicinity’, in Galinier and Baratte 2013, 31–49.Google Scholar
Meinecke, K. 2014: Sarcophagum posuit: Römische Steinsarkophage im Kontext, Wiesbaden.Google Scholar
Meyer, M. 2014: ‘Preface’, in Elsner and Meyer 2014, xviii–xxii.10.1016/j.fuel.2013.07.041CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Müller, F. G. J. M. 1994: ‘The emergence of the mythological sarcophagus’, in Müller, F. G. J. M. (ed.), The So-Called Peleus and Thetis Sarcophagus in the Villa Albani, Amsterdam, 100–6.10.1163/9789004672963CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Muth, S. 2004: ‘Drei statt vier. Zur Deutung der Feldherrnsarkophage’, Archäologischer Anzeiger 2004(1), 263–73.Google Scholar
Nagel, T. 1974: ‘What is it like to be a bat?’, Philosophical Review 83(4), 435–50.10.2307/2183914CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Neer, R. 2002: ‘Poussin, Titian and tradition: The Birth of Bacchus and the genealogy of images’, Word & Image 18(2), 267–81.10.1080/02666286.2002.10404994CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Neer, R. 2010: ‘Jean-Pierre Vernant and the history of the image’, in Platt and Squire 2010, 181–95.Google Scholar
Neer, R. 2012a: ‘“A tomb both great and blameless”: Marriage and murder on a sarcophagus from the Hellespont’, in Elsner and Wu 2012b, 98–115.Google Scholar
Neer, R. 2012b: ‘Sacrificing stones: on some sculpture, mostly Athenian’, in Faraone and Naiden 2012, 99–119.Google Scholar
Newby, Z. 2011: ‘In the guise of gods and heroes: portrait heads on Roman mythological sarcophagi’, in Elsner and Huskinson 2011, 189–228.Google Scholar
Newby, Z. 2014: ‘Poems in stone: Reading mythological sarcophagi through Statius’ Consolations', in Elsner and Meyer 2014, 256–87.Google Scholar
Newby, Z. 2016: Greek Myths in Roman Art and Culture: Values and Identity in Italy, 50 BCAD 250, Cambridge.10.1017/CBO9781139680387CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nock, A. D. 1946: ‘Sarcophagi and symbolism’, American Journal of Archaeology 50, 140–70.10.2307/499754CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nodelmann, S. 1993: ‘How to read a Roman portrait’, in D'Ambra, E. (ed.), Roman Art in Context: An Anthology, Hoboken, NJ, 1025.Google Scholar
Osborne, R. 1988: ‘Death revisited, death revised: The death of the artist in Archaic and Classical Greek art’, Art History 11, 116.10.1111/j.1467-8365.1988.tb00279.xCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pepe, C. 2018: ‘Fragments of epideictic oratory: The exemplary case of the laudatio funebris for women’, in Gray, Balbo, Marshall and Steel 2018, 281–96.Google Scholar
Platt, V. 2011: Facing the Gods: Epiphany and Representation in Graeco-Roman Art, Literature and Religion, Cambridge.Google Scholar
Platt, V. 2017: ‘Framing the dead on Roman sarcophagi’, in Platt and Squire 2017b, 353–81.Google Scholar
Platt, V. and Squire, M. (eds) 2010: ‘The art of art history in Greco-Roman antiquity’, special issue, Arethusa 43(2).Google Scholar
Platt, V. and Squire, M. 2017a: ‘Framing the visual in Greek and Roman antiquity’, in Platt and Squire 2017b, 3–100.Google Scholar
Platt, V. and Squire, M. (eds) 2017b: The Frame in Classical Art: A Cultural History, Cambridge.10.1017/9781316677155CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Reinhardt, A. 2019: Reproduktion und Bild: Zur Wiederholung und Vervielfältigung von Reliefs in römischer Zeit, Wiesbaden.10.29091/9783954906888CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Reinsberg, C. 2006: Die Sarkophage mit Darstellungen aus dem Menschenleben. Vita Romana, Die antiken Sarkophagreliefs, vol. 1, no. 3, Berlin.Google Scholar
Robert, C. 1897: EinzelmythenActaeon bis Hercules, Die antiken Sarkophagreliefs, vol. 3, no. 1, Berlin.Google Scholar
Robert, C., Matz, F., Rodenwaldt, G. and Andreae, B. (eds) 1890: Die Antiken Sarkophagreliefs, Berlin.Google Scholar
Roller, M. 2015: ‘Between unique and typical: Senecan exempla in a list’, in Lowrie and Lüdemann 2015, 81–95.Google Scholar
Roller, M. 2018: Models from the Past in Roman Culture: A World of Exempla, Cambridge.10.1017/9781316677353CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rood, T., Atack, C. and Phillips, T. 2020: Anachronism and Antiquity, London.10.5040/9781350115231CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rousselle, A. 2001: ‘Images as education in the Roman Empire (second-third centuries AD)’, translated by R. Webb, in Too 2001, 373–403.Google Scholar
Russell, B. 2013: The Economics of the Roman Stone Trade, Oxford.10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199656394.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Scarry, E. 1985: The Body in Pain, New York.Google Scholar
Schultz, C. E. 2016: ‘Roman sacrifice, inside and out’, Journal of Roman Studies 106, 5876.10.1017/S0075435816000319CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shapiro, H. A. 1994: Myth into Art: Poet and Painter in Classical Greece, London.Google Scholar
Sichtermann, H. 1992: Die Mythologischen SarkophageApollon bis Grazien, Die antiken Sarkophagreliefs, vol. 12, Berlin.Google Scholar
Snodgrass, A. M. 1982: Narration and Allusion in Archaic Greek Art, London.Google Scholar
Spivey, N. 2018: The Sarpedon Krater: The Life and Afterlife of a Greek Vase. London.Google Scholar
Squire, M. 2015a: ‘Roman portraiture and the semantics of extraction’, in Boehm, G., Budelacci, O., Di Monte, M. G. and Renner, M. (eds), Gesicht und Identität/Face and Identity, Munich, 79106.Google Scholar
Squire, M. (ed.) 2015b: Sight and the Ancient Senses, London.10.4324/9781315719238CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Squire, M. 2018a: ‘Embodying the dead on Classical Attic grave-stelai’, in Gaifman, Platt and Squire 2018, 518–45.Google Scholar
Squire, M. 2018b: ‘“To haunt, to startle, and way-lay”: Approaching ornament and figure in Graeco-Roman art’, in Dietrich and Squire 2018, 1–35.Google Scholar
Stewart, P. 2004: Statues in Roman Society: Representation and Response, Oxford.10.1093/oso/9780199240944.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stilp, F. 2013: ‘Autoreprésentation funéraire, entre mythe, art officiel et «Berufsdarstellung»’, in Galinier and Baratte 2013, 51–64.Google Scholar
Tanner, J. 2006: The Invention of Art History in Ancient Greece: Religion, Society and Artistic Rationalisation, Cambridge.Google Scholar
Thomas, E. 2012: ‘“Nero's Tomb” and the crisis of the third century: Roman sarcophagi as public and private monuments’, in Elsner and Wu 2012b, 132–51.Google Scholar
Too, Y. L. (ed.) 2001: Education in Greek and Roman Antiquity, Leiden.Google Scholar
Trimble, J. 2011: Women and Visual Replication in Roman Imperial Art and Culture, Cambridge.Google Scholar
Trimble, J. 2017: ‘Framing and social identity in Roman portrait statues’, in Platt and Squire 2017b, 317–52.Google Scholar
Trimble, J. 2018: ‘Figure and ornament, death and transformation in the Tomb of the Haterii’, in Dietrich and Squire 2018, 327–52.Google Scholar
Turner, S. 2015: ‘Sight and death: Seeing the dead through ancient eyes’, in Squire 2015b, 143–60.Google Scholar
Vernant, J.-P. 1983: Myth and Thought among the Greeks, London.Google Scholar
Vout, C. 2014: ‘The funerary altar of Pedana and the rhetoric of unreachability’, in Elsner and Meyer 2014, 288–315.Google Scholar
Walter-Karydi, E. 2015: Die Athener und ihre Gräber (1000–300 v.Chr.), Berlin.10.1515/9783110348675CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Webb, R. 2001: ‘The progymnasmata as practice’, in Too 2001, 289–316.Google Scholar
Webb, R. 2015: ‘Sight and insight: Theorizing vision, emotion and imagination in ancient rhetoric’, in Squire 2015b, 205–19.Google Scholar
Weil, S. 2005: ‘The Iliad, or the poem of force’, in Weil, S. and Bespaloff, R., War and the Iliad, with an essay by Broch, H. and an introduction by Benfrey, C. and translated by McCarthy, M., New York, 137. [First published in French in 1940/1941.]Google Scholar
Wrede, H. 2001: Senatorische Sarkophage Roms, Mainz.Google Scholar
Zanker, P. 1999: ‘Phädras Trauer und Hippolytos’ Bildung: Zu einem Sarkophag im Thermenmuseum’, in Angelis, F. De, Muth, S. and Hölscher, T. (eds), Im Spiegel des Mythos: Bilderwelt und Lebenswelt, Wiesbaden, 131–42.Google Scholar
Zanker, P. 2012: ‘Reading images without texts on Roman sarcophagi’, in Elsner and Wu 2012b, 167–77.Google Scholar
Zanker, P. and Ewald, B. 2012: Living with Myths: The Imagery of Roman Sarcophagi, Oxford.Google Scholar
Figure 0

FIG. 1. Rinuccini sarcophagus front panel, c. 200 c.e., marble, length 212–15 cm, height 101 cm. Berlin State Museums, Berlin, 1987.2. (Artwork in the public domain; photograph by the author)

Figure 1

FIG. 2. Rinuccini sarcophagus front panel (Fig. 1), detail of the left-hand side. (Artwork in the public domain; photograph by the author)

Figure 2

FIG. 3. Rinuccini sarcophagus front panel (Fig. 1), detail of the right-hand side. (Artwork in the public domain; photograph by the author)

Figure 3

FIG. 4. Rinuccini sarcophagus front panel (Fig. 1), detail of the centre. (Artwork in the public domain; photograph by the author)

Figure 4

FIG. 5. Rinuccini sarcophagus left-end panel, marble, depth 94 cm. Berlin State Museums, Berlin, 1987.2. (Artwork in the public domain; photograph by the author)

Figure 5

FIG. 6. Rinuccini sarcophagus right-end panel, marble, depth 99 cm. Berlin State Museums, Berlin, 1987.2. (Artwork in the public domain; photograph by the author)

Figure 6

FIG. 7. Sarcophagus with the abduction of Proserpina, c. 160–180 c.e., marble, length 210 cm, height 75 cm, depth 63 cm. Uffizi Gallery, Florence, 1914, 86 (Photograph by Gerhard Singer, provided by the Deutsches Archäologisches Institut Rom, D-DAI-ROM-72.120, cropped by the author)

Figure 7

FIG. 8. Sarcophagus with the abduction of the daughters of Leucippus by the Dioscuri, c. 160–180 c.e., marble, length 220 cm, height 56 cm, depth 75 cm. Uffizi Gallery, Florence, 1914, 104. (Artwork in the public domain; photograph by Gerhard Singer, provided by the Deutsches Archäologisches Institut Rom, D-DAI-ROM-72.131, cropped by the author)

Figure 8

FIG. 9. Sarcophagus with Adonis, c. 200 c.e., marble, length 237 cm, height 58 cm. Casino Rospigliosi, Rome. (Artwork in the public domain; photograph by Franz Schlechter, provided by the Deutsches Archäologisches Institut Rom, D-DAI-ROM-86.48, cropped by the author)

Figure 9

FIG. 10. Sarcophagus with Adonis, c. 220 c.e., marble, length 215 cm, height 72 cm, depth 71 cm. Museo Gregoriano Profano, Vatican, 10409. (Artwork in the public domain; photograph by Gisela Geng, provided by the Forschungsarchiv für Antike Plastik, FA-S-GEN-5710-01a_21252, cropped by the author)

Figure 10

FIG. 11. Sarcophagus with Meleager, c. 180–200 c.e., marble, length 247 cm, height 94 cm, depth 110 cm. Palazzo Doria Pamphilj, Rome. (Artwork in the public domain; photograph by Peter Barritt, provided by Alamy, G3DJN3)

Figure 11

FIG. 12. Sarcophagus with Adonis, c. 190 c.e., marble, length 218 cm, height 73 cm. Palazzo Ducale, Mantua (Artwork in the public domain; photograph by Gisela Fittschen-Badura, provided by the Forschungsarchiv für Antike Plastik, Fitt77-03-01_12159, cropped by the author)

Figure 12

FIG. 13. Sarcophagus with Adonis, c. 200 c.e., marble, length 198 cm, height 52 cm, depth 55 cm. Chiesa Santa Maria Assunta, Blera. (Artwork in the public domain; photograph by Barry Ferst)

Figure 13

FIG. 14. Sarcophagus with Adonis, c. 180 c.e., marble, length 210 cm, height 49 cm. Villa Giustiniani Massimo, Rome. (Artwork in the public domain; photograph by Gerhard Singer, provided by Deutsches Archäologisches Institut Rom, D-DAI-ROM-68.5200, cropped by the author)

Figure 14

FIG. 15. Sarcophagus with Mars and Rhea Silvia, Selene and Endymion, c. 200–215 c.e., marble, length 225 cm, height 82 cm. Museo Gregoriano Profano, Vatican, 9558. (Artwork in the public domain; photograph by Gisela Geng, provided by the Forschungsarchiv für Antike Plastik, FA-S-GEN-5713-01_21259)

Figure 15

FIG. 16. Sarcophagus with Hector brought back from Troy, c. 200 c.e., marble, length 175 cm, height 50 cm. Louvre, Paris, Ma 353. (Artwork in the public domain; photograph by Gisela Fittschen-Badura, provided by the Forschungsarchiv für Antike Plastik, file Fitt71-24-08, cropped by the author)