Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-l7hp2 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-23T19:14:24.992Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

‘If one knows what is to come’: ethics, audience and eschatology in Pindar’s Olympian 2

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 November 2024

Henry Spelman*
Affiliation:
Christ’s College, Cambridge
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

This essay uses one difficult sentence from Pindar’s Olympian 2 as a jumping-off point to address larger issues about the relationship between literature and belief. Section II tackles Pindar’s judgement of the dead (56–60) and argues that this passage is better understood as an instance of unusual particle usage rather than as an elliptical expression of recondite doctrine. Here the posthumous fate of humanity is decided on the grounds of ethical conduct. Section III discusses the unfinished conditional beginning in line 56 and probes the connection between eschatological knowledge and pragmatic action. Scholars have focused on the unusual details of Pindar’s eschatology, but its overarching practical thrust is to reinforce a conventional ethic. Section IV examines the knowledge of the future mentioned in line 56 and other gestures towards privileged knowledge. Scholars have considered Olympian 2 an ‘intimate’ text intended for a select audience, but there is reason to think that this epinician aimed at a panhellenic reception. Combining motifs from various sources, Pindar creates a unique vision of the afterlife that is capable of transcending doctrinal labels and appealing to many. Section V briefly concludes by considering how this poem works as both a victory ode and a religious text. Pindar’s ode is not a ‘corrupt paraphrase’ of anything else; the text creates a world of its own and inscribes core epinician values into the very architecture of the cosmos.

Type
Research Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution and reproduction, provided the original article is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2024. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of the Society for the Promotion of Hellenic Studies

I. Introduction

At a key moment in Plato’s Meno, Socrates introduces Pindar as a privileged representative for a class of ‘divine’ poets (Πίνδαρος καὶ ἄλλοι πολλοὶ τῶν ποιητῶν ὅσοι θϵῖοί ϵἰσιν, 81a–b). Alongside certain priests and priestesses who have taken the care to be able to give a rational account of their affairs (τῶν ἱϵρέων τϵ καὶ τῶν ἱϵρϵιῶν ὅσοις μϵμέληκϵ πϵρὶ ὧν μϵταχϵιρίζονται λόγον οἵοις τ’ ϵἶναι διδόναι, Meno 81a), Pindar and these other poets say, according to Socrates, that the soul is immortal and born again after death and that one must live as purely as possible. Socrates then goes on to quote from a poem in which Persephone receives ‘requital for ancient grief’ (ποινὰν παλαιοῦ πένθϵος, Pind. fr. 133.1) in the underworld and sends souls back to the world above. This famous fragment has aroused a debate of its own,Footnote 1 but I cite the context of the quotation because it brings into sharp focus central questions about the interpretation of another poem, Olympian 2: does Pindar echo the doctrine of special religious groups? How much does his authority, as a ‘divine poet’, resemble that of a priest? Is he, like Plato’s priests and priestesses, concerned to give a rational account?

Olympian 2 is a strange epinician. In place of the standard central myth there is an eschatological section that blends together various motifs attested in a range of other texts. Discussion has focused on identifying Pindar’s sources and working out the disputed details of his underworld. Scholarship has often been guided by a dichotomy between poetry and religion, with critics either emphasizing epic intertexts and epinician tropes or tracing potential links with special beliefs, chiefly Orphism, Pythagoreanism and Sicilian mystery cult. There is no reason to see here a set of two exclusive alternatives. The challenge, as I understand it, is to read Olympian 2 simultaneously as both an epinician and a religious text, but not necessarily as a personal confession or a sectarian gospel.

This essay uses one difficult sentence as a jumping-off point to address much larger issues about the relationship between literature and belief. Section II tackles Pindar’s judgement of the dead in lines 56–60 and argues that this controversial passage is better understood as an instance of unusual particle usage rather than as an elliptical expression of recondite doctrine. There is no need to invoke external evidence from any special school of thought in order to understand these verses; for the first time in extant Greek literature, the posthumous fate of all humanity is decided on the grounds of their ethical conduct on earth. Pindar’s depiction of the underworld, like his praise of his patron Theron, emphasizes the causative link between intellectual insight and virtuous action. Section III discusses the unfinished conditional that begins in line 56 and probes the connection between eschatological knowledge and pragmatic action in Olympian 2. Scholars have given much attention to the unusual details of Pindar’s eschatology, but its overarching practical thrust is to reinforce a generically conventional ethic. The afterlife depicted in this ode offers new rewards for familiar forms of merit praised throughout the epinician corpus. Section IV in turn examines the knowledge of the future mentioned in line 56 and other gestures towards privileged knowledge in Pindar’s account of the underworld. It argues that Olympian 2 evokes the esoteric without itself being esoteric in any substantial sense. Scholars have long considered this poem an ‘intimate’ and ‘personal’ text intended for a select audience, but there is reason to think that Olympian 2, like the rest of the epinicians, aimed at a panhellenic reception. Recent research into Orphism, Pythagoreanism and Greek eschatology reframes the age-old question of Pindar’s sources. I argue that he does not passively reflect any orthodoxy but rather draws on fluid and overlapping bundles of ideas in order to create something new that is capable of standing apart from doctrinal labels and appealing to a wide audience. Section V concludes by briefly considering how this poem works as both a victory ode and a religious text. Like the myths of other victory odes, the distinctly epinician eschatology of Olympian 2 offers a framework for thinking about how excellence fits into the world. Combining motifs from many sources, this poem offers a singular vision of the afterlife ultimately underwritten by a religious authority no greater and no lesser than ‘the divine bird of Zeus’ (88), Pindar himself. The text is not a ‘corrupt paraphrase’ of anything else; it creates a world of its own and inscribes core epinician values into the very architecture of the cosmos.

If the arguments of this essay point in the right direction, then Olympian 2 emerges as at once a more normal victory ode than it has often been taken to be and also a unique testimonium to the rich variety of ideas about the afterlife that circulated and coexisted in dialogue with each other during the Classical period.

II. Pindar’s judgement of the dead

The eschatological section of Olympian 2 begins with what Malcolm Willcock deems ‘the most outrageously difficult sentence in all the epinician odes’ (56–60):Footnote 2

ϵἰ δέ νιν ἔχων τις οἶδϵν τὸ μέλλον,

ὅτι θανόντων μὲν ἐν-

θάδ’ αὐτίκ’ ἀπάλαμνοι φρένϵς

ποινὰς ἔτϵισαν, τὰ δ’ ἐν τᾷδϵ Διὸς ἀρχᾷ

ἀλιτρὰ κατὰ γᾶς δικάζϵι τις ἐχθρᾷ

λόγον φράσαις ἀνάγκᾳ·

And if someone has it [sc. wealth] and knows what is to come, that the foolish wits of those who have died here immediately pay a penalty, and someone beneath the earth passes judgement on misdeeds committed in this realm of Zeus, having pronounced sentence with hateful necessity.

More than a century ago Ludwig Deubner could describe this passage as ‘a playground of philological acumen’ (‘ein Tummelplatz philologischen Scharfsinns’).Footnote 3 These lines have attracted much attention, and for good reason. Here fine-grained philological questions have cosmological consequences: precisely what, according to Pindar, is the posthumous fate of humanity?

Hugh Lloyd-Jones, reacting to the publication of important new ‘Orphic’ gold leaves, offered an original and influential interpretation:

the sense must be that when men die here, their feeble minds at once pay the penalty; the penalty consists in their minds becoming feeble, that is to say, in death. If the penalty which those who die pay consists in death, it is not the same as the penalty paid by the souls whose crimes are judged according to the following sentence.Footnote 4

This argument provokes several objections. ἔτϵισαν (58) and δικάζϵι (59) are such a natural pair that it is counter-intuitive to suppose that the verbs refer to two separate quasi-legal proceedings rather than the complementary sides of the same process. Lloyd-Jones’ reading would be easier if Pindar had written the present participle γιγνόμϵναι, which Lloyd-Jones himself supplied when asked by Douglas Gerber for a more detailed explanation of the syntax in the discussion of his paper at a Fondation Hardt conference that formed the basis for the volume in which Lloyd-Jones’ chapter appears.Footnote 5 The aorist participle θανόντων (57) strongly suggests a penalty paid after death rather than through the act of dying.Footnote 6 On Lloyd-Jones’ interpretation, Pindar leaves unspecified the crime for which some penalty is paid on earth. If earthly misdeeds are punished in the underworld, what then is left to be answered for in this sublunary world? Lloyd-Jones points to the sins of humanity’s Titanic ancestors and connects our passage with the ‘requital’ (ποινάν) that Persephone receives in Pindar fr. 133, itself the topic of extensive and ongoing controversy. Since it is uncertain which doctrine, if any, Pindar is following in Olympian 2, it is hazardous to invoke external sources for crucial data which the poet does not provide.

Modifying Lloyd-Jones’ approach, Bruno Gentili et al. understand lines 56–60 in close connection with what follows (61–67):Footnote 7

ἴσαις δὲ νύκτϵσσιν αἰϵί,

ἴσαις δ’ ἁμέραις ἅλιον ἔχοντϵς, ἀπονέστϵρον

ἐσλοὶ δέκονται βίοτον, οὐ χθόνα τα-

ράσσοντϵς ἐν χϵρὸς ἀκμᾷ

οὐδὲ πόντιον ὕδωρ

κϵινὰν παρὰ δίαιταν, ἀλλὰ παρὰ μὲν τιμίοις

θϵῶν οἵτινϵς ἔχαιρον ϵὐορκίαις

ἄδακρυν νέμονται

αἰῶνα, τοὶ δ’ ἀπροσόρατον ὀκχέοντι πόνον.

But always having sunlight in equal nights and in equal days, the good receive a life with less toil, not disturbing the earth or the water of the sea with the strength of their hand for the sake of an empty way of living; rather, in the company of the honoured gods those who rejoiced in oath-keeping spend a tearless existence, whereas the others endure toil which one cannot bear to look upon.

Gentili et al. take lines 56–67, as a whole, to articulate a threefold contrast between the moderately bad, the very bad and the good.Footnote 8 Yet the binary contrast between ‘those in company of the honoured gods’ (παρὰ μὲν τιμίοις | θϵῶν οἵτινϵς, 65–66) and ‘the others’ (τοὶ δ’, 67) suggests that in lines 56–60 we are also dealing with a simple dichotomy, not with a more complex ‘scale of faults and related punishments’ (‘gradazione delle colpe e delle relative punizioni’).Footnote 9 There is little in the μέν-clause beginning in line 57 to suggest that some penalty is paid for only middling misdeeds, and the nature of that penalty would again be left unspecified. Gentili et al. posit a punishment of immediate reincarnation, but this has still less of a textual basis than a punishment of death.Footnote 10

Both of these interpretations, while problematic in other respects, posit a contrast which accords well with the μέν/δέ construction of lines 56–60, as proponents of these readings rightly stress. Others construe the particles in more unusual ways, but none of these solutions carries conviction. Many take μέν (57) to contrast with δέ (61) and interpret δ’ (58) as introducing a long parenthetical thought.Footnote 11 Lowell Edmunds instead sees a μέν solitarium in line 57 while Johannes van Leeuwen takes the particle as emphatic.Footnote 12 Yet lines 57–60 treat concepts which are so fundamentally related (the rendering of a judgement and the payment of a penalty) that it is natural to interpret μέν (57) and δ’ (58) as closely linking together two clauses.

The problem is seeing how these lines may be lucidly understood as a μέν/δέ construction. As fledgling Hellenists are taught, such constructions are contrastive and the words immediately before the particles are contrasted. Pindar’s usage, however, often does not conform to this rough-and-ready formula. As recent scholars have stressed, in dealing with Greek particles we should be sensitive to diachronic change and generic peculiarities, and we should not rigidly impose stereotyped usages on the flow of discourse in a given passage.Footnote 13

John Denniston states that the combination μέν/δέ marks ‘a grammatically co-ordinated antithesis’ but concedes that ‘the strength of the antithesis varies within wide limits’.Footnote 14 In fact, Tom Phillips argues, ‘μέν … δέ need not have oppositional force in Pindar’.Footnote 15 Consider, for example, Ol. 8.67 τύχᾳ μὲν δαίμονος, ἀνορέας δ’ οὐκ ἀμπλακών (‘through the favour of a god and by not falling short of his own manliness …’): Pindar does not contrast divine favour against mortal virtue but rather combines them as complementary reasons for victory in a classic case of double determination. In Olympian 2, he similarly uses a μέν/δέ construction to pair athletic victories (48–49).

Denniston writes that ‘the words standing immediately before μέν and δέ are usually corresponding elements in the contrasted thoughts’ but notes that this rule is ‘constantly subject to exception’, especially in verse.Footnote 16 Chris Carey catalogues many Pindaric cases which do not conform to this tendency.Footnote 17 Consider, for example, Pyth. 2.48 τὰ ματρόθϵν μὲν κάτω, τὰ δ’ ὕπϵρθϵ πατρός (‘the mother’s features below, the features of the father above’). Ol. 2.73 is comparable: τὰ μὲν χϵρσόθϵν ἀπ’ ἀγλαῶν δϵνδρέων, ὕδωρ δ’ ἄλλα φέρβϵι (‘some from the land off brilliant trees, the water feeds others’).

In Ol. 2.57–60, Glenn W. Most asserts, ‘the word order must be abandoned, and with it two separate legal actions’.Footnote 18 The μέν/δέ construction links thoughts which are complementary, not contrastive: first the payment of a penalty and then the judgement which imposes that penalty. While the μέν-clause does not specify why a penalty is paid, this information is supplied by the δέ-clause, which helps to explain the μέν-clause.Footnote 19 Pyth. 4.283–84 presents a comparable discursive structure: ὀρφανίζϵι μὲν κακὰν γλῶσσαν φαϵννᾶς ὀπός, | ἔμαθϵ δ’ ὑβρίζοντα μισϵῖν (‘he deprives a base tongue of its radiant voice, and he has learned to hate a man who commits hubris’). As Bruce Braswell observes, the δέ clause is logically subordinate to the μέν clause and roughly equivalent to γάρ.Footnote 20 Isthm. 8.11–14 is also comparable to our passage: ἀλλ’ ἐμοὶ δϵῖμα μὲν παροιχόμϵνον | καρτϵρὰν ἔπαυσϵ μέριμναν· τὸ δὲ πρὸ ποδὸς | ἄρϵιον ἀϵὶ βλέπϵιν | χρῆμα πάν, ‘but for me, bygone fear put an end to mighty anxiety, and it is ever better to attend to what is at hand’. As Carey notes, ‘the μέν-clause gives the specific … the δέ-clause the general’. As in our passage, the second limb of the construction explicates the first.Footnote 21

If Ol. 2.57–60 exhibits unusual but acceptable Pindaric word order and has a complementary μέν/δέ construction in which the second limb helps to explain the first, then various subsidiary philological challenges become easier and the nature of Pindar’s judgement of the dead becomes clearer. The adverb αὐτίκ’ (57) goes with the verb ἔτϵισαν (58), as is normal. Together these two words make an important point. In early Greek poetry, a wrongdoer often pays the price ‘in time’ later in his life, or retribution is visited upon his descendants; divine justice is commonly delayed.Footnote 22 In Olympian 2, wrongdoers may reap short-term advantage on earth, but they inexorably (ἀνάγκᾳ, 60) and immediately pay the price later below; this impending judgement is ‘what is to come’ (τὸ μέλλον, 56). Prompt punishment connotes the justice of this subterranean regime (cf. Soph. El. 1505–07; Ar. Vesp. 453–55) and implicitly contrasts with oft-delayed divine justice in the world above. If αὐτίκ’ (57) goes with ἔτϵισαν (58), then ἐνθάδ’ (57) must go with θανόντων (57), as word order suggests. Some query where mortals could die besides earth, but it makes sense to talk of ‘those who die here’ when directly contrasting upper and lower worlds.Footnote 23

ἀπάλαμνοι φρένϵς (57) refers to a particular class of the dead (cf. 61–66), not to all of humanity. This phrase means, at least primarily, ‘foolish wits’. Lloyd-Jones instead translates the adjective as ‘helpless’ and persuasively argues against the sense ‘wicked’ espoused by some earlier scholars.Footnote 24 Yet the attested sense of ‘foolish’ may readily assume moral connotations in context (‘reckless’).Footnote 25 In our passage there may be genuine ambiguity as helplessness is at issue (ἀνάγκᾳ, 60; cf. Ol. 1.59), but the intellectual sense of the adjective is surely relevant since it pointedly modifies an intellectual organ (φρένϵς, 57); one might have instead expected ψυχαί (‘souls’), which would be more normal in this context.Footnote 26

The ‘foolish wits’ of those who commit misdeeds contrast with the wise man ‘who knows what is to come’ (οἶδϵν τὸ μέλλον, 56), namely that misdeeds do not pay in the end. Hearing moral overtones in ἀπάλαμνοι (57) also further sharpens a subsequent contrast with ‘the good’ (ἐσλοί, 63). The reckless pay a penalty (ἔτϵισαν, 58); the good receive their reward (δέκονται, 63). Pindar’s vision of the underworld, like his praise of Theron, as we shall see in the next section, emphasizes the causative connection between wisdom and ethical action.

There is no need to invoke external evidence from any special doctrine in order to understand lines 56–60. Like Aeschylus slightly later in the fifth century,Footnote 27 Pindar depicts humans paying the penalty for earthly misdeeds in the underworld. For the first time in extant Greek literature the posthumous fate of all humanity is decided on the grounds of their ethical conduct.Footnote 28

III. Ethics and eschatology

‘And if someone has it [sc. wealth] and knows what is to come’ (56), Pindar says, but the expected apodosis never comes as the narrator instead gets carried away with explaining precisely ‘what is to come’.Footnote 29 Earlier scholars, vexed by ‘the most marked instance of anacolouthon in Pindar’,Footnote 30 proposed unconvincing emendations, none of which found general favour. As Basil Gildersleeve writes, ‘it would be better to leave the … sentence frankly without an apodosis’.Footnote 31 This ‘bad syntax’ (Lewis Farnell) is a reflex of Pindar’s ‘oral subterfuge’ (Carey), a pervasive rhetorical fiction already embodied in the ostensibly extemporaneous question opening Olympian 2 (1–2).Footnote 32

The poetic relevance of Pindar’s eschatology is much affected by the interpretation of this incomplete thought, which provokes reflection on what the narrator was about to say.Footnote 33 If someone knows the nature of the afterlife, what then follows from that? C.A.M. Fennell supplies ‘then he is Theron’ as the missing apodosis,Footnote 34 but our passage looks different from the idiom exemplified by Ol. 1.54–55 and Pyth. 3.85–86. Many prefer versions of ‘then all will be well for him’,Footnote 35 but wealth and foreknowledge are not sufficient to ensure a good afterlife in this poem (cf. Ol. 2.58–60, 68–70). Citing Elroy Bundy for encomiastic conditionals, Andrew Miller instead suggests supplying ‘χρὴ τὸν αἰνϵῖν [“one must praise him”] or the like’ (43) and argues that the final section more than 40 lines later (89–100) ‘enacts the conventional apodotic injunction to praise’.Footnote 36 Yet throughout the epinician corpus and in this particular ode (ll. 5–6, 46–49) what demands praise is not knowledge but accomplishments. Pindar’s many general conditionals with transparent relevance to the victor often cite deeds; none cites knowledge.Footnote 37 In the sentence immediately preceding our unfinished conditional, βαθϵῖαν … μέριμναν (‘profound ambition’, 54) calls to mind the practical pursuit of accomplishments guided by intellectual insight.Footnote 38

Another possibility presents itself. The omitted apodosis may be understood to concern the proper use of wealth in accordance with the knowledge which Pindar goes on to describe: if one has wealth and knows that misdeeds are punished in the afterlife, then one should employ wealth for just ends.Footnote 39 Pyth. 3.103–04 provides a parallel for the thought: ‘if some mortal has in his mind the road of truth, then he should take pleasure in what he receives from the immortal gods’ (ϵἰ δὲ νόῳ τις ἔχϵι θνατῶν ἀλαθϵίας ὁδόν, χρὴ πρὸς μακάρων | τυγχάνοντ’ ϵὖ πασχέμϵν). The following lines explicate the ‘road of truth’ by grounding this injunction in a view of the human condition. Elsewhere in Pindar foreknowledge is closely connected with the proper use of wealth. Consider Nem. 7.17–18: ‘the wise have learned the wind coming on the third day, and they are not harmed by profit’ (σοφοὶ δὲ μέλλοντα τριταῖον ἄνϵμον | ἔμαθον, οὐδ’ ὑπὸ κέρδϵι βλάβϵν). Knowledge of the future, which includes the death awaiting rich and poor alike (Nem. 7.19–20), prompts intelligent men to eschew transient profits and instead pursue enduring glory through expensive accomplishments and professional poets like Pindar.Footnote 40 Isthm. 1.67–68 articulates the reverse side of this core epinician theme: ‘if someone keeps his wealth hidden and laughs as he attacks others, he does not realize that without glory he is paying his soul to Hades’ (ϵἰ δέ τις ἔνδον νέμϵι πλοῦτον κρυφαῖον, | ἄλλοισι δ’ ἐμπίπτων γϵλᾷ, ψυχὰν Ἀίδᾳ τϵλέων οὐ φράζϵται δόξας ἄνϵυθϵν).Footnote 41

In the passages just cited, the future in question pertains to death; in our passage, ‘what is to come’ also includes the post-mortem afterlife. If one knows the shape of that future, then one does not commit misdeeds (ἀλιτρά, 59), one abides by oaths (ϵὐορκίαις, 66),Footnote 42 one abstains from injustice (ἀπὸ πάμπαν ἀδίκων ἔχϵιν | ψυχάν, 69–70); in short, one acts like Theron, who knows what is to come and uses his wealth in accordance with that knowledge. He is introduced as a benefactor to both his fellow citizens and xenoi (ὄπι δίκαιον ξένων, ἔρϵισμ’ Ἀκράγαντος, 6), and the final section returns in ring composition to the innumerable ‘delights that he has rendered for others’ (χάρματ’ ἄλλοις ἔθηκϵν, 99). When he is described as ‘beneficent in his prapides’ (ϵὐϵργέταν πραπίσιν, 94), the reference to his intellectual organ is pointed. His just prapides contrast with the ‘foolish minds’ (ἀπάλαμνοι φρένϵς, 57) of those who pay a penalty below for earthly misdeeds.Footnote 43 Theron realizes that the good enjoy a better afterlife, and he acts accordingly (ἐσλοί, 63→ἐσλῶν, 97; δίκαιον, 6→ἀδίκων, 69). His deeds are indeed guided by an ambition that shows his profound intellectual understanding (βαθϵῖαν … μέριμναν, 54).

As we would expect from any epinician, the conspicuous display of wealth, including competing in the most expensive event at the panhellenic games and commissioning a major professional poet, is being presented as a characteristic manifestation of an admirable ethic which benefits others.Footnote 44 As we find in no other epinician, this ethic is grounded in a complex vision of the afterlife. Elsewhere foreknowledge of death inspires liberality that aims for deathless fame; here foreknowledge of what comes after death inspires liberality which aims for fame and more besides. Theron acts in accordance with his knowledge of an eschatology without epinician parallel, but he does not act differently from other epinician laudandi.

The eschatology of Olympian 2 reframes a conventional ethic for the poet as well as for his patron. Pindar vows that his praise is true and just (ἐνόρκιον λόγον, 92; οὐ δίκᾳ συναντόμϵνος, 96). These are generic commonplaces, but they sound different when combined with the idea that abiding by oaths secures a better afterlife and that abstaining from injustice can win the best (ϵὐορκίαις, 66→ἐνόρκιον, 92; ἀδίκων, 69→δίκᾳ, 96). The poet’s words, like Theron’s actions, express an ethical identity which is in congruence with the cosmos mapped out in this poem.

Pindar’s eschatology has an exhortative as well as an encomiastic function. Its ultimate prize is reserved for those who pass a strict test: ‘as many as have brought themselves to keep their soul completely apart from injustice, having remained three times on both sides’ (ὅσοι δ’ ἐτόλμασαν ἐστρίς | ἑκατέρωθι μϵίναντϵς ἀπὸ πάμπαν ἀδίκων ἔχϵιν | ψυχάν, 68–70).Footnote 45 ἐτόλμασαν (68) emphasizes the fortitude required, μϵίναντϵς (69) the long duration to be passed; πάμπαν (69) stresses the absoluteness of the requirement. The misdeeds and alternations across the preceding generations of Theron’s family history (35–45) further heighten a sense of how hard it is for one to avoid committing any wrong action across multiple lifetimes. He has done innumerable good deeds (90–95), but the ultimate fate of his soul depends on abstaining from injustice (69–70) and benefactions do not entail the absence of malefaction. All that is done, just or unjust (ἐν δίκᾳ τϵ καὶ παρὰ δίκαν, 16), cannot be undone; this generalization covers not just what Theron has done but also all that he will do. Olympian 2 implicitly exhorts him to win a special place in the afterlife by acting justly in this lifetime. Pythian 1 concludes with a more explicit but comparable exhortation: Hieron should be generous so that he, like Croesus, may earn eternal praise; if he acts unjustly, he will be reviled among later generations as Phalaris is (89–98).Footnote 46 Hieron will be judged in the court of posterity and Theron will (also) be judged beneath the earth, but the paraenetic force and practical implications of both afterlives are similar.

The eschatology of Olympian 2, however unusual it may be, serves familiar generic values. The judgement of the dead in lines 56–60 is purely ethical (section II above), but Pindar’s afterlife is expansive and plastic enough also to reward other forms of merit which are constantly celebrated across the epinician corpus. His selective census of the Island of the Blessed (ἐν τοῖσιν ἀλέγονται, 78) does not neatly align with the criteria for admission just expounded. Peleus was just (cf. ϵὐσϵβέστατον, Isthm. 8.40), but pairing him with Cadmus suggests that these two were issued their passport to bliss because they, rather like Menelaus in the Odyssey (4.569), enjoyed the exceptional divine favour of marrying goddesses (cf. Pyth. 3.86–95). In this ode divine favour, in addition to justice, can win the best afterlife.

The last, longest and hence climactic entry in Pindar’s open-ended catalogue buttresses that inference while further expanding the criteria valid for admission to paradise. Achilles, who also enjoyed divine favour, was spirited away to the Island of the Blessed by his mother ‘after she persuaded Zeus’ heart with entreaties’ (ἐπϵὶ Ζηνὸς ἦτορ | λιταῖς ἔπϵισϵ, μάτηρ, 79–80).Footnote 47 The immediately ensuing roll-call of her son’s great opponents (81–83) evokes in summary fashion the totality of Trojan epic while assigning to Achilles an afterlife that diverges markedly from that tradition, which instead places him in the less idealized locations of Hades (Od. 11) or the White Island (Aethiopis arg. 4 West).Footnote 48 In this discursive context, the précis of the hero’s epic accomplishments suggests that they constitute the grounds for Thetis’ request to Zeus, which was just mentioned: Achilles punches his ticket to the Island of the Blessed on the basis of his achievements.Footnote 49 While Thetis’ son could hardly exemplify abstinence from injustice, elsewhere in Pindar, for obvious reasons, he often serves as a paradigm for how great deeds can win immortal glory (Ol. 10.16–21; Nem. 3.64, 6.48–54; Isthm. 8.47–48). In Olympian 2, he attains a different sort of privileged afterlife on the basis of those same deeds.

The inhabitants of Pindar’s Island of the Blessed together show that the cosmos may award its highest prize to the divinely favoured and the exceptionally accomplished, as well as to the just. The relevance of all this to the just, divinely favoured (cf. 35–37) and accomplished Theron is too obvious to need spelling out. Epinicians routinely immortalize great deeds, divine favour and ethical conduct; Olympian 2 inflates the wages for conventional forms of excellence by adding a special place in the afterlife to deathless glory in song.

Discussing early Orphism, Robert Parker writes that ‘an eschatology is not a contract in law, but an imaginative picture, designed … to shape attitudes in the here and now’.Footnote 50 This holds all the more for an epinician eschatology written by an international poet. Much attention has been paid to the difficult details of Pindar’s underworld, but its practical thrust is clear: it further valorizes traditional values. This eschatology, like Wittgenstein’s ideal philosophy, leaves everything as it is, at least for pragmatic purposes on earth. So, far from entailing anything as outré as vegetarianism, Pindar’s underworld raises the stakes of normal life and provides new reasons for conventionally praiseworthy actions.

IV. Audiences and eschatologies

Pindar can express uncertainty about the workings of the gods and about the afterlife (ποι, ‘in some way’, Ol. 3.4 and Pyth. 5.101). He can report human stories (λέγοντι, ‘they say’, Ol. 2.28) and invoke the Muses for truth about the distant past (Pae. 6.50–58). The eschatological section of Olympian 2 is introduced in a more marked way: this is the truth of one who ‘knows what is to come’ (οἶδϵν τὸ μέλλον, 56). The best Pindaric parallel for such a phrase concerns the Eleusinian mysteries: ‘blessed is he who goes beneath the earth after he has seen those things; he knows the end of life, he knows its Zeus-given beginning’ (ὄλβιος ὅστις ἰδὼν κϵῖν’ ϵἶσ’ ὑπὸ χθόν’· | οἶδϵ μὲν βίου τϵλϵυτάν, | οἶδϵν δὲ διόσδοτον ἀρχάν, fr. 137). Maria Cannatà Fera observes that the emphatically repeated verb is ‘“quasi-technical” in the language of the mysteries’ (‘“quasi tecniche” nella lingua dei misteri’), and the second best Pindaric parallel for our passage (fr. 70b.5–8) plays on similar ‘telestic’ resonances.Footnote 51 In Olympian 2, eschatological knowledge is framed in striking temporal terms: it is not about ‘the things in Hades’ but ‘what is to come’. In early Greek thought, knowledge of the future is paradigmatically beyond the human ken and often attributed to gods in contradistinction to mortals.Footnote 52 Our passage concerns a very special sort of knowledge.

This is only the first signal of privileged understanding in Pindar’s underworld. The indefinite pronoun τις (59), coming soon after emphasis on precise knowledge, hints at a definite correlate known to those in the know.Footnote 53 ‘The honoured among the gods’ (τιμίοις | θϵῶν, 65–66) may likewise be identified by those who can see through the euphemism.Footnote 54 Enacting the attitude that he describes, Pindar says that the wicked ‘endure a labour that one cannot bear to look upon’ (ἀπροσόρατον ὀκχέοντι πόνον, 67); he conveys a threat all the more potent for its vagueness and suggests that he knows more than he cares to say.Footnote 55

Prompted in part by these hints at privileged knowledge withheld, scholars have long supposed that Olympian 2 was composed for a small circle who shared certain special beliefs. Erwin Rohde thinks that Pindar ‘reveals for a moment to like-minded friends’ what ‘he believes himself’, and Cecil Bowra asserts that the poet ‘speaks as man to man on intimate, personal matters’.Footnote 56 Ulrich Wilamowitz infers that, in contrast to Olympian 3, this poem was directed towards an intimate circle (‘im Gegensatze zu Ol. 3 ist es auf einen intimen Kreis berechnet’).Footnote 57 Günther Zuntz finds this ‘an outstandingly personal and intimate poem’, and Gentili et al. similarly judge Olympian 2 ‘more personal and intimate’ (‘più personale … più intimo’) than Olympian 3.Footnote 58

There is reason to reject this traditional line of interpretation. One might wonder why the poet would hint at privileged knowledge withheld if he were addressing only those who already share that knowledge. On a more fundamental level, Pindar of Thebes was hardly the person to hire when you wanted to keep a secret. Olympian 2, like the rest of his poetry, was meant to circulate as widely as possible. The ultimate goal of this poem (σκοπῷ, 89) is to shower its honorand with ‘glorifying arrows’ (ϵὐκλέας ὀιστούς, 90).Footnote 59 As often elsewhere, so here Pindar wishes to immortalize his subject through space and time. The elliptical references in his description of the underworld may be ‘swift arrows speaking to those who understand’ (ὠκέα βέλη … φωνάϵντα συνϵτοῖσιν, 83–85), but this poem was supposed to reach many people.Footnote 60 There cannot be anything truly ‘personal’ or ‘intimate’ going on here.

One might instead understand Pindar’s gestures towards privileged knowledge in relation to what Ruth Scodel terms ‘pseudo-intimacy’. Scodel writes of Greek lyric generally that ‘one of the particular effects of this poetry for outsiders is precisely the sense of eavesdropping, of admission to a small, enclosed world’ behind its first performance and argues that poets consciously exploit this effect.Footnote 61 Olympian 2 grants admission into a special group distinguished by knowledge not about the ephemeral circumstances behind its performance but rather about the afterlife that awaits all mortals. Widespread audiences can join the coterie of the wise who know the shape of the cosmos as it is disclosed in this ode.

Pindar’s eschatology evokes the esoteric without being esoteric in any substantial sense; it is pseudo-esoteric, to adapt Scodel’s terminology. The poet’s reference to ‘someone who knows what is to come’ (56) recalls the privileged knowledge of esoteric discourse, but he then goes on to divulge explicitly and at length ‘what is to come’. Nor is there any hint that such knowledge is insufficient to obtain a better and indeed the best afterlife. Olympian 2 mentions no special rite. Since the fate of souls is normally decided on ethical grounds (57–60), there is no decisive role left for any such ritual to play (contrast frr. 131a, 133). The final section asserts that ‘wise is he who knows many things by nature’ (σοφὸς ὁ πολλὰ ϵἰδὼς φυᾷ, 86), not he who learns some doctrine. Pindar’s reference to ‘someone’ (59) who judges the dead probably plays a game of indefiniteness designed to be won by more than a select few.Footnote 62

The purported ‘intimacy’ of Olympian 2 is bound up with the disputed question of its sources, a topic of scholarly interest since the time of Aristarchus (Σ 106a), who apparently asserted that Pindar followed Pythagoras. More recently, Willcock reasserts a Pythagorean connection, and Alberto Bernabé includes Olympian 2 within his collection of Orphic testimonia (Ol. 2.56–72 = 445 V).Footnote 63 Aimé Puech hesitates between Orphic and Pythagorean doctrine (‘doctrine orphique ou pythagoricienne’), and Gentili et al. speak of Orphico-Pythagorean influence (‘orfico-pitagoriche’), as does Albertine Cerrutti.Footnote 64 Nancy Demand, by contrast, posits that ‘Theron’s faith was peculiarly Akragantine, a mystery cult of Cretan origin’, and George Gazis suggests that the poet is addressing initiates of a local cult and offering a ‘corrupt paraphrase’ of their beliefs: ‘Pindar was not aware of the exact nature of these ideas’.Footnote 65

Many have sought to trace the ‘doctrinal affiliations’ of Olympian 2 but, as Fritz Graf observes, ‘modern scholars have debated … without a clear result’.Footnote 66 Why has consensus proved elusive? Perhaps scholars have not yet converged on the best arguments or the decisive evidence has been lost. Alternatively, the problem might run deeper: in the fifth century the divisions between various schools of thought may not have been sufficiently clear-cut for any single doxographical label to be uniquely appropriate to our poem. Several classical texts imply a connection between Orphism and Pythagoreanism, and modern scholars have long debated their doctrinal and historical relationship, without a clear result.Footnote 67 Recent research suggests that Orphism and Pythagoreanism were not fixed and uniform orthodoxies but rather flexible bundles of beliefs and practices, rather like the more mainstream Greek religion with which they are often contrasted in older scholarship.Footnote 68

Perhaps Olympian 2 adapts ideas which could feature in multiple overlapping and fluid belief systems. Those who trace special religious influence invariably cite the passing reference to reincarnation (68–70), which is agreed to be the single most exotic element in the ode even by those who stress the solidly Homeric and Hesiodic pedigree of much else. Among the myriad beliefs attributed to Pythagoras in antiquity and modernity, metempsychosis claims the clearest basis in the early evidence (Xenophanes 21 B 7 DK). The Pindaric fragment (133) cited by Plato at the start of this essay has in turn been hypothesized to provide the earliest witness to an Orphic belief in reincarnation. Yet the evidence for reincarnation among Orphics is limited and mostly late, and it is not clear that all early Pythagoreans espoused metempsychosis.Footnote 69 A belief in the return of the soul to some new terrestrial life was perhaps neither a unique nor even a necessary feature of either Orphism or Pythagoreanism.

It is almost as difficult to deny any influence of special religious beliefs in Olympian 2 as it is to identify the poem with any one body of beliefs. Indeed, Pindar may avoid clear hallmarks of ‘doctrinal affiliation’ because this poem is designed to travel beyond narrow doctrinal boundaries to reach a wider audience. It is worth mentioning what the poet does not mention. Orpheus, named in other contexts arguably eschatological (fr. 128c.12) and patently not (Pyth. 4.177), is nowhere to be found. Dionysus is the familiar ‘ivy-bearing child of Semele’ (28), not the son of Zeus and Persephone. Pindar’s eschatology, moreover, is fundamentally incompatible with other beliefs and practices linked to early Orphics and Pythagoreans. The majesty, and the basic intelligibility, of this epinician is much diminished if we imagine that Theron, like Pythagoras’ friend (Xenophanes 21 B 7 DK), could be reincarnated as a puppy. Since in the underworld mortals are judged on ethical grounds (see section II above), there is no need for rites peddled by Orphic priests (Pl. Resp. 364b–365a) or gold leaves disclosing ‘Instructions for the Beyond’.Footnote 70 Pindar’s ode is not a ‘corrupt paraphrase’ of anything else; rather, this text creates a world of its own.

If Olympian 2 is indeed composed in order to circulate and not a private communication to Theron and his co-religionists, then this remarkable text offers evidence for the wider interest and palatability of diverse eschatological ideas in the early fifth century rather than documentation for the reception of one particular strain of thought which has yet to be conclusively identified. Different conceptions of the afterlife coexisted from early on; in this area, as throughout the rest of Greek religion, plurality and adaptability were the norm.Footnote 71 While Homer and Hesiod never mention souls returning from the underworld to be reborn on earth, such an idea would not necessarily have been unfamiliar in the Classical period. Writing from the opposite ends of the Greek world before or during Pindar’s career, Xenophanes (21 B 7 DK) in Magna Graecia and Heraclitus (22 B 40, 81, 129 DK) in Asia Minor both presume knowledge of, but do not share, Pythagoras’ beliefs (cf. Hdt. 2.123).

Many among Pindar’s panhellenic audience were probably likewise familiar with reincarnation and related concepts but did not belong to any special religious group. Heraclitus and Xenophanes, for their part, both attack Pythagoras, and classical texts sometimes depict Orphics as cranks.Footnote 72 Writing for a panhellenic audience, Pindar had reason to avoid being labelled an Orphic or Pythagorean. If Olympian 2 incorporates ideas which could feature in such special belief systems, it inserts them into a larger systematic vision of the afterlife which seems designed to defy easy doctrinal classification. If Pindar adapts beliefs espoused by minority religious groups, he presses them into the service of further valorizing core epinician themes and familiar elite ideology (see section III above). Xenophanes and Heraclitus, who had their own unusual ideas, would have also had their reasons to dislike Olympian 2, but there is much here to appeal to the widespread audience envisioned in other epinicians. Perhaps for such an ancient audience, as for modern scholars, the interest of this ode in no small part resided in how it blends together the relatively exotic and the more mainstream to fashion something fascinating and altogether original.

V. Conclusion

Olympian 2 begins by articulating a threefold ontology of gods, heroes and men (1–2); the eschatological section culminates with exceptional men who come to live together with heroes and gods (70, 78–79). Pindar describes their happy lot (70–74):

ἔνθα μακάρων

νᾶσον ὠκϵανίδϵς

αὖραι πϵριπνέοισιν· ἄνθϵμα δὲ χρυσοῦ φλέγϵι,

τὰ μὲν χϵρσόθϵν ἀπ’ ἀγλαῶν δϵνδρέων,

ὕδωρ δ’ ἄλλα φέρβϵι,

ὅρμοισι τῶν χέρας ἀναπλέκοντι καὶ στϵφάνους …

There breezes from Oceanus breathe about the Island of the Blessed. Golden flowers blaze, some from the land sprung from brilliant trees, others the water feeds; with chains of those they entwine their hands and weave crowns …

Gold is a conventional symbol of durability, flowers a conventional symbol of transience; these golden flowers thus paradoxically evoke time-dependent flourishing arrested in time (cf. fr. 129.5). While Homer (Od. 4.565) and Hesiod (Op. 172–73) have beneficent nature yield up an easy livelihood in Elysium and on the Island of the Blessed, Pindar transfers this motif to the good region of his underworld (62–65) and reserves something better for his best, who use nature for adornment rather than mere sustenance. Their existence is not only free from sorrow and the banal labour of winning their daily bread but positively joyous. They have transcended biological necessity to achieve something greater, like immortalized victors elsewhere in Pindar, only more so.Footnote 73 Whereas Aristotle in his Protrepticus apparently imagined that the inhabitants of the Island of the Blessed, released from practical constraints, practise philosophy (fr. 58 Rose = 43 Düring), Pindar gives them over to eternal celebration (cf. Pyth. 10.37–40, fr. 129). ‘Such images of life in a hereafter’, as Hannah Arendt writes, ‘if we strip them of their religious connotations, present nothing more nor less than various ideals of human happiness’. Olympian 2 presents a distinctly epinician ideal of human happiness.Footnote 74

The victors of the cosmos crown themselves, and Theron now crowns himself with an Olympic victory (ἄνθϵμα, 72→ἄνθϵα, 50). The Island of the Blessed is severed from Akragas by oceanic waters, yet the two locations are brought into significant contact. Olympian 2 makes Theron’s victory synecdochic for the virtues that can win him a special place in the afterlife, and this particular passage transforms his epinician celebration into a foretaste of greater celebration to come. Like the backward-looking myths of other epinicians, Pindar’s forward-looking vision of ‘what is to come’ provides a polyvalent framework for thinking about how excellence fits into the world.

This essay began by quoting a Platonic passage which elides Pindar’s voice with that of certain priests and priestesses. In Olympian 2, the poet, for his part, presents himself as ‘the divine bird of Zeus’ (Διὸς πρὸς ὄρνιχα θϵῖον, 88) using the same adjective that Plato later applies to him (θϵῖοι, Meno 81b). In this exceptional cosmological poem, his inspiration is, unusually, linked not to the Muses but directly to the supreme deity who rules the cosmos.Footnote 75 Pindar really was a religious figure with a special relationship to the divine, as he consistently presents himself to be,Footnote 76 but the nature of his authority was profoundly different from that of ‘priests and priestesses who give a rational account of their affairs’ (Pl. Meno 81a). Olympian 2 draws eschatological ideas from various sources and mines Homer and Hesiod to anchor its underworld in poetic tradition. Pindar is recombining, repurposing and modifying special eschatological ideas in a manner analogous to the process of bricolage whereby these ideas had themselves been formed.Footnote 77 The final authority underwriting this novel blend is no more and no less than ‘the divine bird of Zeus’ (88), but that does not mean that it is just a flight of fancy. Willcock writes that the eschatology of this ode has ‘more to do with Theron than Pindar’,Footnote 78 but the poet’s rhetorical and historical personality cannot, and should not, be erased from the text and replaced with anything else. This ode says something that Theron wanted to hear, but it mattered to him, and to others in the Greek world, that ‘the divine bird of Zeus’ (88) was the one to say it.

As Olympian 2 demonstrates, ‘the afterlife is endlessly “good to think with”’,Footnote 79 both for ancient writers and for modern readers. In this ode, the afterlife offers Pindar an opportunity to inscribe core epinician values into the very architecture of the cosmos. For us today his unique vision of the afterlife provides fascinating insight into the varied, fluid and adaptable nature of all early Greek thinking about ‘what is to come’ after we die.

Acknowledgements

This essay was originally written for a conference on Pindar and early Greek philosophy which sadly fell victim to the pandemic. I am deeply grateful to Tom Mackenzie for the invitation to consider this theme. Several other scholars also generously provided commentary and discussion: Gábor Betegh, James Diggle, Miguel Herrero de Jáuregui, Robert Fowler, William H. Race, Sol Tor and Matt Ward.

Footnotes

1 Bernabé (Reference Bernabé1999) and Edmonds (Reference Edmonds2013) 305–26 offer discussion and bibliography. References to Pindar and the Pindaric scholia follow Snell-Maehler and Drachmann, respectively. Translations are my own.

2 Willcock (Reference Willcock1995) 150. Departing from Snell-Maehler, I punctuate with a comma rather than a dash after ἔτϵισαν (58), as do many editors, including Bowra, Turyn and Willcock. There is no reason to posit (further) anacoluthon here, as will be argued below.

3 Deubner (Reference Deubner1908) 638.

4 Lloyd-Jones (Reference Lloyd-Jones1985) 254.

5 Lloyd-Jones (Reference Lloyd-Jones1985) 280.

6 It would be odd to have a coincidental aorist participle with a present-tense verb: see Braswell (Reference Braswell1988) 115–16 with references. Carey (Reference Carey1991) 219 objects that, for Lloyd-Jones’ reading, ‘one expects θανοῦσαι … not θανόντων’.

8 Gentili et al. (Reference Gentili, Catenacci, Giannini and Lomiento2013) 401. Cf. Catennaci (Reference Catennaci2014) 133–35; somewhat similarly, Ferrari (Reference Ferrari1998) 94–95 n.29.

11 So Farnell (Reference Farnell1930–1932) 2.17, Willcock (Reference Willcock1995) 155, Holzhausen (Reference Holzhausen2004) 23 n.17; cf. Ol. 2.25–30, Pyth. 5.15–20.

12 Edmunds (Reference Edmunds2009) 669; J. van Leeuwen (Reference Leeuwen1964) 1.171.

13 See Bakker (Reference Bakker1997) 80–85 on Homeric μέν/δέ in particular and Bonifazi et al. (Reference Bonifazi, Drummen and de Kreij2016) in general. Pindar’s usage of μέν/δέ is influenced by a pervasive distaste for predictable symmetry (Dornseiff (Reference Dornseiff1921) 103: ‘Symmetrie wird gemieden’).

14 Denniston (Reference Denniston1954) 369–70.

15 Phillips (Reference Phillips2013) 47. Slater (Reference Slater1969) s.v. μέν 2 lists cases ‘where sentences are opposed’ and cases ‘where sentences are joined’.

16 Denniston (Reference Denniston1954) 371–72.

17 Carey (Reference Carey1981) 46.

18 Most (Reference Most1985) 100 n.27.

19 Apparently Aristarchus (Σ 106a) already took δ’ (58) as equivalent to γάρ; cf. Carrière (Reference Carrière1973) 440. Hummel (Reference Hummel1993) 388 gives the particle ‘une simple valeur articulaire’ while allowing that explanatory force may be inferred (somewhat similarly, Bollack (Reference Bollack1963) 238). The discursive function of explanatory δέ always has to be inferred from context. As Wilamowitz-Moellendorff (Reference Wilamowitz-Moellendorff1908) 134 n.9 remarks, ‘mit δέ reiht Pindar nur zu oft Gedanken aneinander, deren logisches Verhältnis durch diese Partikel gar nicht bezeichnet wird’. This is a stylistic choice (Dornseiff (Reference Dornseiff1921) 94: ‘Der Chorlyriker meidet die logischen Partikeln bewußt’). For the combination of gnomic aorist (ἔτϵισαν, 58) and iterative present (δικάζϵι, 59) see Hummel (Reference Hummel1993) 246.

20 Braswell (Reference Braswell1988) 383.

21 Carey (Reference Carey1981) 191. Generalizations explaining a particular case: Pyth. 3.85–86, 10.59–60; Isthm. 2.33–34 (all with γάρ). Carey (Reference Carey1981) 190–91 persuasively defends Benedictus’ emendation of the transmitted παροιχομένων (Isthm. 8.11).

22 Il. 4.260–62; Solon 13.29–32 IEG 2; Thgn. 201–02; Pind. Pyth. 4.139–40, 8.15, 11.36; Harder (Reference Harder1985) 257; Garvie (Reference Garvie1986) 61; Noussia-Fantuzzi (Reference Noussia-Fantuzzi2010) 164–65.

23 So, for instance, Dissen (Reference Dissen1830) 34; Wilamowitz (1922) 248–49; Lehnus (Reference Lehnus1989) 54. On the commonplace religious idiom of ‘here and there’ see van Leeuwen (Reference Leeuwen1896) 20 and Burnet (Reference Burnet1924) 247.

24 Lloyd-Jones (Reference Lloyd-Jones1985) 253–54. Gentili et al. (Reference Gentili, Catenacci, Giannini and Lomiento2013) 400: ‘ἀπάλαμνος non significa e non può significare “malvagio”, “empio”, “criminale”’.

25 Alc. 360 Voigt; Solon 27.11–12 IEG 2; [Thgn.] 279–82, 481; Page (Reference Page1955) 315; van Groningen (Reference Groningen1966) 113. The entry for ἀπάλαμνος in LSJ9 is unsatisfactory; see now The Cambridge Greek Lexicon s.v.

26 At Il. 23.104 the dead do not have phrenes; at Od. 10.493 Teiresias is the exception that proves the rule. In Homer (Od. 11.37, 51, 65 and often), as elsewhere in Pindar (Pyth. 11.21, Nem. 8.44, Isthm. 1.68; but note Pyth. 5.101), the psuchē is more often linked to the underworld than the phrenes. Compare and contrast Lloyd-Jones (Reference Lloyd-Jones1985) 254; Currie (Reference Currie2005) 36.

27 Aesch. Supp. 230–31, from after 470 BC: κἀκϵῖ δικάζϵι τἀμπλακήμαθ’, ὡς λόγος, | Ζϵὺς ἄλλος (‘there too, as the story goes, another Zeus judges misdeeds’); cf. Eum. 273–74, from 458 BC: μέγας γὰρ Ἅιδης ἐστὶν ϵὔθυνος βροτῶν | ἔνϵρθϵ χθονός (‘for great Hades is a corrector of mortals beneath the earth’). Note also Hom. Hymn Dem. 367 with Richardson (Reference Richardson1979) 271.

28 Cf. Nisetich (Reference Nisetich1989) 27; Edmonds (Reference Edmonds2013) 259; Svavarsson (Reference Svavarsson2020) 602.

29 Race (Reference Race1979) 257–58; Miller (Reference Miller1993) 40–44; Morrison (Reference Morrison2007) 47. For broadly comparable instances of anacoluthon, cf. Pind. Ol. 10.86–93, Pyth. 12.29–32, Nem. 4.79–88; Schwyzer (Reference Schwyzer1934–1971) 2.687.

30 Nisetich (Reference Nisetich1988) 8.

31 Gildersleeve (Reference Gildersleeve1885) 149.

32 Farnell (Reference Farnell1930–1932) 2.16; Carey (Reference Carey1981) 5.

33 It will not do to more or less ignore δέ (56) and take the conditional as backward-looking; contrast Σ 102a; Kirkwood (Reference Kirkwood1982) 71; Gentili et al. (Reference Gentili, Catenacci, Giannini and Lomiento2013) 400.

34 Fennell (Reference Fennell1893) 33.

35 Willcock (Reference Willcock1995) 154. Similarly, for example, Bowra (Reference Bowra1964) 121; compare and contrast Edmunds (Reference Edmunds2009) 665–66. Van Leeuwen (Reference Leeuwen1964) 1.162–65 and Hurst (Reference Hurst1981) 121–22 provide doxography.

36 Bundy (Reference Bundy1962) 54–62; Miller (Reference Miller1993) 40–44.

37 Nem. 9.46–47 (ἄρηται | κῦδος), 11.14 (ἀριστϵύων), Isthm. 3.1 (ϵὐτυχήσαις); cf. Bundy (Reference Bundy1962) 58, citing further examples.

38 For the adjective evoking ‘deep’ insight cf. Nem. 3.53, 4.8, 7.1. In Pindar μέριμνα often means ‘concern, sc. for ἀρϵταί, i.e. ambition’ (Slater (Reference Slater1969) s.v. b); cf. Gerber (Reference Gerber1982) 163; Maehler (Reference Maehler1997) 252 (‘das planende, auf ein Ziel gerichtete Denken’). The point made above is stronger if we retain, as I would prefer, ἀγροτέραν (Ol. 2.54), ‘hunting’, ‘questing’; see now Lane (Reference Lane2020), who instead proposes ἁγνοτέραν, ‘purer’.

39 Somewhat similarly Σ 102d; Heyne (Reference Heyne1824) 1.25–26; Hermann apud Boeckh (1821) 129; Deubner (Reference Deubner1908) 641; Ciampa (Reference Ciampa2021) 133.

40 Cf. Pyth. 1.92–94, 8.92; Bacchyl. 1.178–84, 3.13–14 (where note οἶδϵ). Nem. 7.18–19 pertains especially to patrons rather than poets: Carey (Reference Carey1981) 141–42; Most (Reference Most1985) 144–47; Cannatà Fera (Reference Cannatà Fera2020) 441. Nem. 1.31–33 is closely related, but there ἐλπίδϵς may refer to a hope for glory rather than an expectation of death.

41 Bundy (Reference Bundy1962) 87–91. I take the much-debated sentence in Isthm. 1.40 to describe the reverse of the situation in Isthm. 1.67–68: one who has struggled attains foresight (προμάθϵιαν) and devotes himself to the glorious pursuits mentioned in the following lines.

42 Oath-keeping can be a synecdoche for virtue (cf. Soph. Ant. 369–70; Ar. Plut. 61), but its prominence is also explained by two Iliadic passages describing underworld gods punishing oath-breakers (3.278–79, 19.259–60). I suspect that Pindar took the dual τίνυσθον (3.279) to refer to Persephone and subterranean Zeus/Hades; cf. Bowie (Reference Bowie2019) 143 and n. 55 below.

43 πραπίσιν … χέρα (94) denotes in a significant sequence a disposition and the deeds that flow thence (cf. Aesch. Cho. 140–41). In Pindar, prapides and phrenes encompass the intellectual, emotional and ethical spheres: Slater (Reference Slater1969) s.v.; Jackson (Reference Jackson1989).

44 Hampe (Reference Hampe1952) 47–53 discusses Olympian 2 within the context of epinician euergetism; cf. Gianotti (Reference Gianotti1971) 38–39. See, in general, Kurke (Reference Kurke1991) chapter 7.

45 With the majority, I take ἐστρίς | ἑκατέρωθι (68–69) to mean six lives, three on earth and three in the underworld. Scholars sometimes infer that Theron is now on the verge of completing this cycle and travelling to the Island of the Blessed: so, for example, Kirkwood (Reference Kirkwood1982) 73.

46 Phillips (Reference Phillips2016) 153–54. Pyth. 1.92–98 is closely modelled on Od. 19.328–34. An afterlife in fame or poetry is conventionally linked to the underworld and often framed as a consolation: Tyrtaeus 12.31–32 IEG 2; Sappho fr. 65 Voigt; Thgn. 243–50; Pind. Ol. 10.91–96.

47 Since Zeus oversees admission to the Island of the Blessed (79–80; cf. Hes. Op. 167–73), Διὸς ὁδόν (‘the road of Zeus’, 70) will describe a road controlled by him, not one that leads into his presence (contrast Lavecchia (Reference Lavecchia2001)). The older Kronos (70, 76–77) now holds a privileged but subordinate place within Zeus’ new cosmos; cf. [Hes.] Op. 173a–c; Pind. Pyth. 4.291; [Aesch.] fr. 190 TrGF with Griffith (Reference Griffith1983) 289.

48 Cf. Pind. Nem. 4.49–50. See Nisetich (Reference Nisetich1988) 14–16 and (1989) 59–72 on our passage and Spelman (Reference Spelman2018a) on Pindar’s relationship to the epic cycle. Burgess (Reference Burgess2009) 41 et passim discusses Achilles’ varied and not necessarily incompatible afterlives.

49 Cf. Nisetich (Reference Nisetich1988) 14, (Reference Nisetich1989) 70–71 and, more generally, Edmonds (Reference Edmonds2015) 552–54.

50 Parker (Reference Parker1995) 500–01.

51 Cannatà Fera (Reference Cannatà Fera1990) 206; Lavecchia (Reference Lavecchia2000) 134–35; cf. Eur. Bacch. 74, 472–74; [Eur.] Rhes. 973; Burkert (Reference Burkert1969) 5–6.

52 Il. 3.308, Od. 14.119–20, 15.523–24; Spelman (Reference Spelman2014). Nisetich (Reference Nisetich1989) 54 writes that ‘the source of this knowledge remains undisclosed, but its divine character is easily inferred: gods, not mortals, know the future’.

53 Some among Pindar’s audience may well have thought of the subterranean Zeus/Hades who features already in Homer (Il. 9.457) and Hesiod (Op. 465); cf. Aesch. Supp. 156–58, 230–31, Ag. 1386–87, Eum. 273–74; West (Reference West1978) 276; Garvie (Reference Garvie1986) 144. ‘This realm of Zeus’ (ἐν τᾷδϵ Διὸς ἀρχᾷ, 58) implies another (cf. Ζϵὺς ἄλλος, ‘another Zeus’, Aesch. Supp. 231). Contrast Kirkwood (Reference Kirkwood1982) 74, who writes that ‘the indefiniteness may be necessary, in view of the untraditional nature of the whole passage’.

54 Already Σ 117b plausibly identifies these gods as Hades and Persephone, as do many modern scholars. The anonymity itself speaks to the correctness of this identification: see West (Reference West1966) 369–70. παρὰ μὲν τιμίοις | θϵῶν (65–66) means ‘among the honoured gods’, not ‘among those humans honoured by the gods’. The phrase demarcates one part of the underworld from another overseen by other gods (cf. 70, 76–77). A subjective genitive with τίμιος would be hard to parallel (Aesch. Eum. 967 is not a counter-example); the partitive genitive is normal (Pind. Ol. 14.14, Nem. 10.18, Isthm. 7.5).

55 Cf. Richardson (Reference Richardson1979) 315 on Hom. Hymn Dem. 481–82: ‘the vague threat suggests more than it expresses’.

56 Rohde (Reference Rohde1966) 416–17; Bowra (Reference Bowra1964) 120.

57 Wilamowitz (1922) 240.

58 Zuntz (Reference Zuntz1971) 88; Gentili et al. (Reference Gentili, Catenacci, Giannini and Lomiento2013) 45–46. By a somewhat curious logic such judgements sometimes accompany a hypothesis of (exceptional) solo performance; so, for instance, Farnell (Reference Farnell1930–1932) 2.12: ‘the ode seems unsuitable for choral performance, and there is no reference to a chorus. We can better imagine Pindar reciting it himself to the dynast and a select circle as the message delivered is so intimate and cryptic’.

59 The adjective has active force: Gerber (Reference Gerber1999) 63.

60 Cf. Morrison (Reference Morrison2007) 52 and Lewis (Reference Lewis2019) 212–13 on Olympian 2 in particular and Spelman (Reference Spelman2018b) on Pindar in general.

61 Scodel (Reference Scodel1996) 60–61.

62 See nn.53 and 54 above. Similar games of indefiniteness built to be won: Pyth. 9.89–89a (τι), 103–05 (τις), Nem. 1.64 (τινα), 10.30–33.

63 Willcock (Reference Willcock1995) 138–39; Bernabé (Reference Bernabé2004).

65 Demand (Reference Demand1975) 354; Gazis (Reference Gazis2021) 82, 80.

66 Edmunds (Reference Edmunds2009) 675); Graf (Reference Graf2018) 23 n.50.

67 Heraclitus 22 B 129 DK; Hdt. 2.81, 123; Ion of Chios 36 B 2 DK; Betegh (Reference Betegh2014) 150–51: ‘already the earliest stratum of evidence about Pythagoras … assumes a tight connection with Orphism … modern assessments of the extent, nature and direction of the connection between Orphism and Pythagoreanism remain widely divergent’.

68 Zhmud (Reference Zhmud2012) 110–11 and Edmonds (Reference Edmonds2013) 72–73, discussing Pythagoreanism and Orphism, respectively, both invoke Wittgenstein’s idea of family resemblance. Betegh (Reference Betegh2014) 152 writes that ‘it is highly doubtful whether one can justifiably speak about “systems” to describe either Orphism of Pythagoreanism’ and advocates a ‘non-essentialist conception’ (p. 153).

69 Edmonds (Reference Edmonds2014) 36–41, Betegh (Reference Betegh2014) 154–59.

70 Graf and Johnston (Reference Graf and Johnston2013) 55.

71 Gazis and Hooper (Reference Gazis and Hooper2021) 1: ‘there was no monolithic view’. Currie (Reference Currie2005) 39 writes that ‘we should be prepared to admit a plurality of belief, not just across a whole community, but also within individuals’. Edmonds (Reference Edmonds2015) and (Reference Edmonds2021) cautions against assuming that the Homeric model was either primordial or dominant.

72 See, for example, Eur. Hipp. 952–54; Pl. Resp. 364b–365a; Edmonds (Reference Edmonds2013) 5–6.

73 Cf. especially Isthm. 1.47–51. Race (Reference Race1981) illuminates the frequent Pindaric opposition between biological necessity and immortal fame.

74 Arendt (Reference Arendt1963) 131.

75 Cf. Bacchyl. 5.19–20; Most (Reference Most1986) 315.

76 D’Alessio (Reference D’Alessio1994) 139: his contemporaries ‘really believed in [Pindar’s] closeness to the gods … His poetic excellence is depicted by the poet himself as strictly connected with his religious inspiration and was probably felt as such by the audience too’; cf. Gagné (Reference Gagné2021) 1–25 and Fowler (Reference Fowler2022) 137–44.

77 Cf. Graf and Johnston (Reference Graf and Johnston2013) 94 and Edmonds (Reference Edmonds2013) 6 on Orphism.

78 Willcock (Reference Willcock1995) 139. Cf. Wilamowitz-Moellendorff (Reference Wilamowitz-Moellendorff1922) 251–52; Bowra (Reference Bowra1964) 121 (Pindar ‘turns to high poetry Theron’s own views’); Demand (Reference Demand1975) 347–48 (‘we are dealing with the beliefs of Theron and not those of Pindar’); Lehnus (Reference Lehnus1989) 46; Gentili et al. (Reference Gentili, Catenacci, Giannini and Lomiento2013) 55–56; Gazis (Reference Gazis2021).

79 Edmonds (Reference Edmonds2015) 555.

References

Arendt, H. (1963) On Revolution (New York)Google Scholar
Bakker, E. (1997) Poetry in Speech: Orality and Homeric Discourse (Ithaca)Google Scholar
Bernabé, A. (1999) ‘Una cita de Píndaro en Platón Men. 81 b (Fr. 133 Sn.-M.)’, in J.A. López Férez (ed.), Desde los poemas homéricos hasta la prosa griega del siglo IV d.C.: veintiséis estudios filológicos (Madrid) 239–59Google Scholar
Bernabé, A. (2004) Poetae epici Graeci: testimonia et fragmenta: pars II fasc. 1: Orphicorum et Orphicis similium testimonia (Berlin)Google Scholar
Betegh, G. (2014) ‘Pythagoreans, orphism, and Greek religion’, in C. Huffman (ed.), A History of Pythagoreanism (Cambridge) 149–66CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boeckh, A. (1821) Pindari opera quae supersunt: tomi secundi pars altera (Leipzig)Google Scholar
Bollack, J. (1963) ‘L’or des rois: le mythe de la deuxième Olympique de Pindare’, RPh 37, 234–54Google Scholar
Bonifazi, A., Drummen, A. and de Kreij, M. (2016) Particles in Ancient Greek Discourse: Exploring Particle Use Across Genres (Cambridge MA)Google Scholar
Bowie, A. (2019) Homer: Iliad III (Cambridge)Google Scholar
Bowra, C.M. (1964) Pindar (Oxford)Google Scholar
Braswell, B.K. (1988) A Commentary on the Fourth Pythian Ode of Pindar (Berlin)Google Scholar
Bundy, E.L. (1962) Studia Pindarica (2 vols) (Berkeley)Google Scholar
Burgess, J.S. (2009) The Death and Afterlife of Achilles (Baltimore)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Burkert, W. (1969) ‘Das Proömium des Parmenides und die Katabasis des Pythagoras’, Phronesis 14, 130 Google Scholar
Burnet, J. (1924) Plato’s Euthyphro, Apology of Socrates, and Crito (Oxford)Google Scholar
Cannatà Fera, M. (1990) Pindarus: threnorum fragmenta (Rome)Google Scholar
Cannatà Fera, M. (2020) Pindaro: le Nemee (Milan)Google Scholar
Carey, C. (1981) A Commentary on Five Odes of Pindar (New York)Google Scholar
Carey, C. (1991) Review of Nisetich (1989), CR 41, 219CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carrière, J. (1973) ‘Sur l’Olympique II de Pindare, à propos d’un récent examen’, REG 86, 436–43CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Catennaci, C. (2014) ‘Tre note all’Olimpica 2 di Pindaro’, in A. Gostoli and R. Velardi (eds), Mythologeîn: mito e forme di discorso nel mondo antico (Pisa) 132–37Google Scholar
Cerrutti, A. (1995) ‘Poesia eternatrice ed esistenza ultraterrena: l’immortalità nella II Olimpica di Pindaro’, Acme 48, 5–15Google Scholar
Ciampa, C.R. (2021) ‘Eschatological visions in Pindar and Empedocles’, in H. Marlow, K. Pollman and H. Van Noorden (eds), Eschatology in Antiquity (London) 131–43CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Currie, B. (2005) Pindar and the Cult of Heroes (Oxford)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
D’Alessio, G.B. (1994) ‘First-person problems in Pindar’, BICS 39, 117–39Google Scholar
Demand, N. (1975) ‘Pindar’s Olympian 2, Theron’s faith, and Empedocles’ Katharmoi’, GRBS 16, 347–57Google Scholar
Denniston, J.D. (1954) The Greek Particles (rev. K.J. Dover) (2nd edition) (Oxford)Google Scholar
Deubner, L. (1908) ‘Totengericht (Pind. Ol. II 57–60)’, Hermes 43, 638–42Google Scholar
Dissen, L. (1830) Pindari carmina quae supersunt cum deperditorum fragmentis selectis ex recensione Boeckhii (2 vols) (Gotha)Google Scholar
Dornseiff, F. (1921) Pindars Stil (Berlin)Google Scholar
Edmonds, R.G. (2013) Redefining Ancient Orphism: A Study in Greek Religion (Cambridge)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Edmonds, R.G. (2014) ‘A lively afterlife and beyond: the soul in Plato, Homer, and the Orphica’, EPlaton 11 https://doi.org/10.4000/etudesplatoniciennes.517 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Edmonds, R.G. (2015) ‘Imagining the afterlife’, in E. Eidinow and J. Kindt (eds), The Oxford Handbook of Ancient Greek Religion (Oxford) 551–64Google Scholar
Edmonds, R.G. (2021) ‘A path neither simple nor single: the afterlife as good to think with’, in G.A. Gazis and A. Hooper (eds), Aspects of Death and the Afterlife in Greek Literature (Liverpool) 1–32Google Scholar
Edmunds, L. (2009) ‘A hermeneutic commentary on the eschatological passage in Pindar Olympian 2 (57–83)’, in U. Dill and C. Walde (eds), Antike Mythen: Medien, Transformationen und Konstruktionen (Berlin) 662–77CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Farnell, L.R. (19301932) The Works of Pindar (3 vols) (London)Google Scholar
Fennell, C.A.M. (1893) Pindar: The Olympian and Pythian Odes (2nd edition) (Cambridge)Google Scholar
Ferrari, F. (1998) Pindaro: Olimpiche (Milan)Google Scholar
Fowler, B. (2022) Pindar and the Sublime (London)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gagné, R. (2021) Cosmography and the Idea of Hyperborea in Ancient Greece (Cambridge)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Garvie, A.F. (1986) Aeschylus: Choephori (Oxford)Google Scholar
Gazis, G.A. (2021) ‘What is your lot? Lyric pessimism and Pindar’s afterlife’, in G.A. Gazis and A. Hooper (eds), Aspects of Death and the Afterlife in Greek Literature (Liverpool) 69–87Google Scholar
Gazis, G.A. and Hooper, A. (2021) ‘Introduction’, in G.A. Gazis and A. Hooper (eds), Aspects of Death and the Afterlife in Greek Literature (Liverpool) 1–7Google Scholar
Gentili, B., Catenacci, C., Giannini, P. and Lomiento, L. (2013) Pindaro: le Olimpiche (Milan)Google Scholar
Gerber, D.E. (1982) Pindar’s Olympian One: A Commentary (Toronto)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gerber, D.E. (1999) ‘Pindar, Nemean six: a commentary’, HSPh 99, 3391 Google Scholar
Gianotti, G.F. (1971) ‘Sull’Olimpico seconda di Pindaro’, RFIC 99, 26–52Google Scholar
Gildersleeve, B.L. (1885) Pindar: The Olympian and Pythian Odes (London)Google Scholar
Graf, F. (2018) ‘Travels to the beyond’, in G. Ekroth and I. Nilsson (eds), Round Trip to Hades in the Eastern Mediterranean Tradition: Visits to the Underworld from Antiquity to Byzantium (Leiden) 11–36Google Scholar
Graf, F. and Johnston, S.I. (2013) Ritual Texts for the Afterlife: Orpheus and the Bacchic Gold Tablets (2nd edition) (London)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Griffith, M. (1983) Aeschylus: Prometheus Bound (Cambridge)Google Scholar
Groningen, B.A. van (1966) Theognis: le premier libre (Amsterdam)Google Scholar
Hampe, R. (1952) ‘Zur Eschatologie in Pindars zweiter olympischer Ode’, in Hermeneia: Festschrift Otto Regenbogen (Heidelberg), 46–65Google Scholar
Harder, A. (1985) Euripides’ Kresphontes and Archelaos (Leiden)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Heyne, C.G. (1824) Pindari carmina cum lectionis varietate et adnotationibus (3rd edition) (3 vols) (London)Google Scholar
Holzhausen, J. (2004) ‘Pindar und die Orphik: zu Frg. 133 Snell/Maehler’, Hermes 132, 2036 Google Scholar
Hummel, P. (1993) La syntaxe de Pindare (Louvain)Google Scholar
Hurst, A. (1981) ‘Observations sur la deuxième Olympique de Pindare’, ZAnt 31, 121–33Google Scholar
Jackson, S.D. (1989) ‘A study of φρένϵς in Pindar and Bacchylides’, Glotta 67, 148–89Google Scholar
Kirkwood, G. (1982) Selections from Pindar (Chico CA)Google Scholar
Kurke, L. (1991) The Traffic in Praise: Pindar and the Poetics of Social Economy (Ithaca)Google Scholar
Lane, N. (2020) ‘Pindar Olympian 2.54’, Mnemosyne 73, 1025–31CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lavecchia, S. (2000) Pindari dithyramborum fragmenta (Rome)Google Scholar
Lavecchia, S. (2001) ‘La via di Zeus nella seconda Olimpica di Pindaro’, in M. Cannatà Fera and G.B. D’Alessio (eds), I lirici greci: forme della comunicazione e storia del testo (Messina) 187–92Google Scholar
Leeuwen, J. van (1964) Pindarus’ tweede Olympische ode (2 vols) (Assen)Google Scholar
Leeuwen, J.F. van (1896) Aristophanis Ranae (Leiden)Google Scholar
Lehnus, L. (1989) Pindaro: Olimpiche (2nd edition) (Milan)Google Scholar
Lewis, V.M. (2019) Myth, Locality, and Identity in Pindar’s Sicilian Odes (Oxford)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lloyd-Jones, H. (1985) ‘Pindar and the afterlife’, in A. Hurst (ed.), Pindare (Geneva) 245–83 (= (1990) Greek Epic, Lyric, and Tragedy: The Academic Papers of Sir Hugh Lloyd-Jones (Oxford) 80–103)Google Scholar
Maehler, H. (1997) Die Lieder des Bakchylides: Zweiter Teil (Leiden)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Miller, A. (1993) ‘Pindaric mimesis: the associative mode’, CJ 89, 2153 Google Scholar
Morrison, A.D. (2007) Performances and Audiences in Pindar’s Sicilian Odes (London)Google Scholar
Most, G.W. (1985) The Measures of Praise: Structure and Function in Pindar’s Second Pythian and Seventh Nemean Odes (Göttingen)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Most, G.W. (1986) ‘Pindar, O. 2.83–90’, CQ 36, 304–16CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nisetich, F.J. (1988) ‘Immortality in Acragas: poetry and religion in Pindar’s second Olympian ode’, CPh 83, 1–19CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nisetich, F.J. (1989) Pindar and Homer (Baltimore)Google Scholar
Noussia-Fantuzzi, M. (2010) Solon the Athenian: The Poetic Fragments (Leiden)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Page, D.L. (1955) Sappho and Alcaeus: An Introduction to the Study of Ancient Lesbian Poetry (Oxford)Google Scholar
Parker, R. (1995) ‘Early orphism’, in A. Powell (ed.), The Greek World (London) 483–510Google Scholar
Phillips, T. (2013) ‘Epinician variations: music and text in Pindar, Pythians 2 and 12’, CQ 63, 3756 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Phillips, T. (2016) Pindar’s Library: Performance Poetry and Material Texts (Oxford)Google Scholar
Puech, A. (1931) Pindare: Olympiques (Paris)Google Scholar
Race, W.H. (1979) ‘The end of Olympian 2: Pindar and the vulgus ’, CSCA 12, 251–67Google Scholar
Race, W.H. (1981) ‘Pindar’s “best is water”: best of what?’, GRBS 22, 119–24Google Scholar
Richardson, N. (1979) The Homeric Hymn to Demeter (2nd edition) (Oxford)Google Scholar
Rohde, E. (1966) Psyche: The Cult of Souls and Belief in Immortality among the Greeks (trans. W.B. Hillis) (New York)Google Scholar
Schwyzer, E. (19341971) Griechische Grammatik (rev. A. Debrunner) (4 vols) (Munich)Google Scholar
Scodel, R. (1996) ‘Self-correction, pseudo-spontaneity, and orality in archaic poetry’, in I. Worthington (ed.), Voice into Text: Orality and Literacy in Ancient Greece (Leiden) 59–79CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Slater, W.J. (1969) A Lexicon to Pindar (Berlin)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Spelman, H.L. (2014) ‘Zeus and the maidens: Pindar fr. 94b.31–7’, ZPE 192, 3133 Google Scholar
Spelman, H.L. (2018a) ‘Pindar and the epic cycle’, JHS 138, 182201 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Spelman, H.L. (2018b) Pindar and the Poetics of Permanence (Oxford)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Svavarsson, S. (2020) ‘Justice and the afterlife’, in D. Wolfsdorf (ed.), Early Greek Ethics (Oxford) 593–611CrossRefGoogle Scholar
West, M.L. (1966) Hesiod: Theogony (Oxford)Google Scholar
West, M.L. (1978) Hesiod: Works and Days (Oxford)Google Scholar
Wilamowitz-Moellendorff, U. von (1908) ‘Pindars siebentes nemeisches Gedicht’, SitzBer. Königl. Preuß. Akad. 15, 328–52 (repr. in Calder, W.M. III and Stern, J. (eds) (1970) Pindaros und Bakchylides (Darmstadt) 127–58)Google Scholar
Wilamowitz-Moellendorff, U. von (1922) Pindaros (Berlin)Google Scholar
Willcock, M.M. (1995) Pindar: Victory Odes (Cambridge)Google Scholar
Zhmud, L. (2012) Pythagoras and the Early Pythagoreans (Oxford)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zuntz, G. (1971) Persephone: Three Essays on Religion and Thought in Magna Graecia (Oxford) Google Scholar