Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-dh8gc Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-15T07:27:11.490Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Global international relations and the essentialism trap

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  09 November 2023

Michael Barnett
Affiliation:
The Elliot School of International Affairs, George Washington University, Washington, DC, USA
Ayşe Zarakol*
Affiliation:
Department of Politics and International Studies, University of Cambridge, Cambridge, UK
*
Corresponding author: Ayşe Zarakol; Email: [email protected]
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Global IR is an encompassing term for a range of work that has set out to globalize the discipline in terms of its core concepts, assumptions, and substantive areas of study. Our symposium supports Global IR's goals but also offers some friendly critiques of the project with the aim of increasing its impact and durability. In this Introduction to the symposium, we posit that Global IR is vulnerable to a dynamic that limits its capacity to upend the status quo, which we term the ‘essentialism trap’. Essentialism captures a range of commitments oriented around the notion that the world is constituted by pre-formed, fixed, internally coherent, and bounded social forms. The trap involves the overuse of essentialist categories by radical projects, a process that can result in the reinforcement of status quo categories and assumptions. With reference to previous openings in IR that have succumbed to this trap, we identify the dynamics that lead to this trap and suggest ways in which Global IR can avoid it by leaning more into relationalism and global history, and, thereby, fulfil the promise contained in the range of movements it speaks with and for.

Type
Symposium: A Symposium on Global IR
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution and reproduction, provided the original article is properly cited.
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press

The challenge of global international relations

The contemporary discipline of International Relations (IR) is home to impassioned debates, from questions over the enduring legacies of imperialism and racism to the ways in which positionality can be used to certify who is, and who is not, a legitimate voice in the discipline.Footnote 1 A number of studies have shown that the discipline is dominated by (mostly male) scholars based in Western institutions, who tend to work with Euro-Atlantic histories and theories.Footnote 2 Most of what is considered to be the discipline's agenda-setting scholarship is published in US-based journals that also carry the greatest international prestige.Footnote 3 Not only do students of IR around the world primarily read US-based scholarship,Footnote 4 they also learn about, and test their theories with, histories of the West.Footnote 5 This Western-centrism affects who and what gets taught, how explanations are tested, and how coding is carried out.Footnote 6

Global IR is an encompassing term for a range of work that has, over recent years, set out to globalize the discipline in terms of its core concepts, assumptions, and substantive areas of study.Footnote 7 This work focuses attention on several points of contention, including the Eurocentrism of much of the discipline's concepts and histories,Footnote 8 how best to conceive the relationship between theory and Area Studies, and how to match a more ‘worldly’ discipline with a more inclusive infrastructure. Not only does Global IR challenge the taken-for-granted assumptions that undergird mainstream approaches,Footnote 9 it also seeks to authorize new sites of knowledge production in order to construct a truly ‘global’ discipline. Global IR has generated considerable enthusiasm through its capacity to harness the contemporary zeitgeist and serve as a platform for organizing dissent to IR's parochial frames of reference.Footnote 10

We aim to advance this conversationFootnote 11 in two ways. First, we argue that Global IR is vulnerable to a dynamic that limits its capacity to upend the status quo, which we term the `essentialism trap’. Essentialism captures a range of commitments oriented around the notion that the world is constituted by pre-formed, fixed, internally coherent, and bounded social forms. The trap involves the overuse of essentialist categories by radical projects, a process that can result in the reinforcement of status quo categories and assumptions. For example, advocates of Global IR often orient their challenge around binaries such as ‘Western’ and ‘non-Western’, which are inevitably inscribed with essentialist ideas about cultures, regions, and civilizations, and their specific ‘brands’ of IR. This makes sense as a political move seeking the inclusion of previously marginalized sites of knowledge production. However, it can also enable existing approaches to co-opt large parts of critique without being fundamentally disrupted. Radical intent becomes conformist outcome.

Second, we suggest ways in which Global IR can avoid the essentialism trap and, thereby, fulfil the promise contained in the range of movements it speaks with and for. We support Global IR's aim to open up the discipline theoretically, empirically, geographically, and epistemologically. We see the ‘global’ as a useful frame for doing this work. We thus focus on the benefits to Global IR of taking up a relational ontology, taking seriously the assumption that relations come before entities. Although Global IR often invokes relationalism, it tends to use the term in a thin sense to denote connections between pre-formed entities (such as cultures, regions, and civilizations) rather than as the entanglements that forge these entities in the first place. A closer alignment with global history can help here.Footnote 12 Specifically, global history heightens the empirical warrant for Global IR, demonstrating how a range of processes central to the formation of contemporary international order has been generated by transboundary connections.

Each of the contributions to this symposium demonstrates the promise for the Global(izing) IR project of combining relationalism with global history. This introduction establishes the parameters for these contributions in four sections. First, we outline the core commitments of essentialism and explain why they are problematic. We also show how the essentialism trap has constrained radical challenges to orthodoxies in IR by using examples from the 1970s and 1990s to highlight the ways in which previous moments of opening have been tamed. The second section outlines the main features of Global IR. Third, we explore some of the reasons why Global IR (and previous movements) are susceptible to the essentialism trap: the ‘common sense’ appeal of essentialism; the cooptation of alternatives by the discipline; and the hold of a particular version of standpoint epistemology. The final, concluding, section outlines an alternative path for Global IR blending relationalism and global history, highlighting how these are deployed in the papers that make up the symposium.

Essentialism: can't live with it, can't live without it?

Essentialism is often used more as a ‘slur’ than as a clearly articulated term.Footnote 13 At root, essentialism is the claim that social forms have an immutable set of properties. It is the position that entities – personalities, genders, races, cultures, states, regions, and civilizations – have an innate, natural, fixed character.Footnote 14 At root, essentialism contains three linked assumptions: first, that there is something natural about differences between peoples, whether biological, cultural, or historical; second, that these differences are enduring, perhaps even eternal; and third, that all members of a particular category are homogeneous, sharing a quality or set of qualities.Footnote 15 It follows that these points of distinction distinguish some peoples from others: Western and non-Western, white and black, men and women, American and Chinese, Jews and Muslims, and so on. In essentialist tropes, these features are simultaneously points of differentiation and modes of explanation. For example, ideas about an innate ‘Western rationality’, often layered onto claims about racial, geographical, and historical exceptionalism, have long anchored claims about the positional advantages enjoyed by Western states in contemporary world politics.

Essentialism provides a ‘common sense’ for much of the practice of world politics.Footnote 16 Indeed, practitioners would find it difficult to work without presumptions of a fixed, readily digestible world, such as the supposedly fundamental differences between democracies and autocracies in which, at least in many parts of the West, the former are considered to be ‘enlightened’, ‘advanced’, and ‘pacific’, while the latter are seen as ‘deficient’, ‘backwards’, and ‘conflict-ridden’. For instance, in an October 2022 speech, Josep Borell, the European Union's High Representative for Foreign Affairs and Security Policy, called Europe a ‘garden’ of prosperity, to be contrasted to other parts of the world, which were, in contrast, a ‘jungle’ of lawlessness.Footnote 17 This ‘essentialism effect’, in which stereotypical attributes are used to underpin and, ultimate, enact policy agendas form an everyday backdrop to IR. Essentialist assumptions can also be found in a range of theoretical claims in IR: that democracies are inherently peaceful in their relations with each other; that capitalist markets are naturally wealth-generating (by advocates) or crisis-generating (by critics); that cultures in certain parts of the world are predisposed towards peace (e.g. historical East Asia) and others towards conflict (e.g. the contemporary Middle East); that the West alone is home to modern notions of reason, progress, sovereignty, and more. Essentialism is, in many ways, a common denominator within IR theory and practice.

Essentialism is sustained by a number of auxiliary claims: substantialism, internalism, and methodological nationalism. Substantialism is an ontological position that sees entities, such as states, cultures, regions, or civilizations, as prior to relations.Footnote 18 To take one obvious example, structural realism is substantialist in the ways it ascribes permanent logics to the international system and pre-existing interests to states. Internalism is the tendency to see historical development as the product of processes drawn from within a particular unit. In this way, labels such as ‘the West’ or ‘China’ are given meaning through dynamics that are taken to be internally produced: individual rationality and guanxi, balance of power and balance of relations, the separation of powers and Confucianism, respectively.Footnote 19 Methodological nationalism is the view that the boundaries of social relations map directly onto the boundaries of the nation-state and that nation-states are the natural units of scholarly analysis.Footnote 20 This view applies both to contemporary and historical analyses to the extent that polities before the emergence of nationalism in the nineteenth century are usually taken to be nation-states, proto nation-states, or equivalents to nation-states.Footnote 21 Together, substantialism, internalism, and methodological nationalism generate a taken-for-granted backdrop to IR knowledge production in which ‘natural’ national, regional, and civilizational units are differentiated by homogenous characteristics that are the result of endogenous characteristics that are, in turn, produced through shared histories, cultures, or both. Much of IR theory tends to adopt, at minimum, a ‘rump essentialism’, whether this concerns the properties of the structural environment in which world politics takes place, the character of its units, or the assumptions that motivate actors.

We are not the first to point to these disciplinary tendencies towards essentialism.Footnote 22 Nor are we the first to point to the propensity to divide up, and make explanations through, essentialist reasoning.Footnote 23 In many ways, this is to be expected. IR has to start from somewhere, has to adopt the perspective of a kind, has to hold things stable in order to make claims and test theories. This is why essentialist claims of many kinds, whether ‘as-if’ or ‘hard-wired’, ‘strategic’ or ‘unintentional’, ‘explicit’ or ‘implicit’, are so resilient. However, there is a danger in the way that essentialism fixes essences to units, seeing them as containing transhistorical, immutable characteristics, especially given the broader aims of Global IR. As the contributions to this symposium show, historical actors, from states to epistemic communities, are nested within broader scales: imperial orders, transnational knowledge complexes, global practices of accumulation, international social movements, and more.

If there are ways of constructing historical–theoretical arguments in IR that do not rest on essentialism, why are essentialist claims so resilient? We address this question in subsequent sections. For now, it is worth simply noting that we have been here before. Previous critiques of the disciplinary status quo, despite often including critiques of essentialism, often fell back onto essentialist logics. In the 1970s, for example, a range of radical movements challenged global order: ‘Third World’ revolutionary currents, from Ethiopia to Nicaragua; militancy within forums of international administration, from Organization of the Petroleum Exporting Countries (OPEC) to the United Nations (UN); activist rights-based movements – civil, feminist, ecological, and more. During this period, IR was pushed by approaches such as Dependency Theory and World-Systems Analysis to rethink its core categories and modes of analysis, not least the essentialist assumptions of modernization theory. This helped to generate interest in global, relational dynamics, such as the connections between north-south and core-periphery that sustained global order. Major approaches, including Realism and Liberalism, were recast during this period, partly as a response to these challenges. In the process, a moment of potential opening was trapped within essentialist categories. The multilayered insights of Classical Realism, for example, morphed into the substantialist framing provided by Structural Realism, which relied on the ascriptive dynamics of a self-help system, while it's like-units-under-anarchy assumption axiomatically generated a state-centric theory in which actor interests were pre-determined. Perhaps more surprisingly, some challengers to the disciplinary status quo also succumbed to these modes of reasoning. For example, World-Systems analysts ascribed innate properties to axial positions within the global economy (core, semi-periphery, and periphery), and located whole regions and sub-regions within these positions. In the process, what appeared to be a dynamic account of core-periphery relations could be taken to support a form of spatialized essentialism. This is the essentialism trap in operation – a form of closure in which theoretical openings become circumscribed and, ultimately, tamed.

A similar process took place in the 1990s. Once again, major events in world politics, notably the end of the Cold War, provided an opening for novel approaches. This time, the pre-eminent challenge to mainstream accounts came from constructivism, which critiqued the rationalist neo-neo consensus for its static, unchanging assumptions about global structure and international actors, arguing instead for their relational constitution and, by implication, the mutable nature of world politics. In this way, constructivism was a call for the discipline to pay more attention to intersubjectivities, historical change, and the ways in which identities were ‘achieved’ rather than ‘ascribed’. But constructivism too, or at least parts of it, fell prey to the essentialism trap. Over time, the constructivist challenge became divided, however crudely, into ‘thin’ and ‘thick’ variants, with ‘thin constructivism’ incorporated into the mainstream and ‘thick constructivism’ largely excluded from it.Footnote 24 In order to demonstrate that it was theoretically and empirically ‘progressive’, ‘thin constructivism’ attempted to best rationalism on its own terms, reinforcing existing terms of debate and frames of reference.Footnote 25 Gradually, a disciplinary compromise emerged: constructivists studied identity, culture, and norms (categories that often took on substantialist forms), while realists focused on power and interests, and liberals examined cooperation and institutions.

In this way, mainstream IR theory was reoriented, particularly in the US, around three main approaches (realism, liberalism, constructivism) and one central axis (rationalism vs. constructivism).Footnote 26 While ‘thin constructivists’ accepted in principle a relational ontology that followed from a social constructionist philosophy, in practice they often reproduced a world of fixed, unitary units. By contrast, ‘thick constructivism’, which maintained more of a relational ethos, found a home alongside more explicitly critical approaches, often outside mainstream spaces.Footnote 27 In part, this alternative ecology was made possible by the expansion of IR around the world since the 1990s. US-based research outputs in the global social sciences, including IR, have declined from around a half to around a third since the 1990s. The ISA now has 75 partner institutions, from Chile to the Philippines. Global IR speaks directly to this development. It joins a long list of challengers that have sought to open up mainstream IR to accounts of world politics that fall outside conventional histories, concepts, and theories.

In many ways, therefore, the contemporary challenge presented by Global IR is a familiar one.Footnote 28 So too is the danger presented by the essentialism trap that has limited the challenge of some previous movements. If Global IR is to fulfil its promise to make IR more global,Footnote 29 the project needs to avoid this trap.

The global IR project

Like previous challenges from the 1970s and 1990s, Global IR has emerged during a tumultuous moment in the international order, seeking to rethink the discipline in order to meet the challenges of the day. Global IR rests on three core commitments: first, that IR is a particular product of a particular distribution of power at a particular moment in history – a ‘West-side story’ as de Carvalho et al. put it;Footnote 30 second, that the underdevelopment of theories from outside the West can be rectified by attention to ‘indigenous histories and cultures, nationalist leaders, and distinctive local and regional interaction patterns’; and third, that these theories can usefully ‘supplement’ rather than ‘supplant’ existing IR theories.Footnote 31 To date, it is argued, Western IR has used its hegemonic influence over the field to build the stage, write the play, and define the audience.Footnote 32 It follows that, as global distributions of power are leveling-out, forms of Western-centrism will be challenged. Global IR aims to be an umbrella movement for these challenges, providing a space through which ‘local’ currents of thought can be excavated, animated, and incorporated. To that end, a central aim of Global IR is to connect IR theory to Area Studies, providing a ‘broad-brush overview of some of the key themes and where possible institutional centers of IR in regions outside of Europe and North America’.Footnote 33 These regions or countries are taken to have ‘radically different histories and political theories than that of the West’.Footnote 34 In the case of China, for example, the notion of tianxia and the tribute system are seen as stark contrasts to Western traditions of anarchy, sovereignty, and territoriality. By placing these traditions on an equal footing with Western concepts and theories, IR can be ‘reimagined’ as a site of ‘plural universalism’: many civilizations within one world.Footnote 35

For some critics, this vision of Global IR represents an ‘accommodationist’ approach that works within existing ecologies rather than seeking to replace them. As such, Global IR is said to promise a form of ‘affirmative action’ or a ‘workers’ visa’ for those previously excluded from disciplinary citadels.Footnote 36 In doing so, it leaves the citadels intact. What is needed, it is argued, is a more revolutionary expropriation of disciplinary strongholds. Post-colonial and decolonial scholarship for example, some of which also seeks to contribute to the formation of Global IR,Footnote 37 aim to shift the ‘geography of reason’ that sustains stratification between a Western disciplinary ‘core’ and a marginalized ‘periphery’.Footnote 38 For decolonial scholarship in particular, non-capture in the present is premised on undoing ‘colonial logics of thinking’ from the past, which rest on a ‘separate but unequal’ logic wherein Western experiences are taken to be exemplary and the non-West taken to be incapable of reason and agency.Footnote 39 If the structural sources of IR's biases are left in place, it is argued, the result will be the cooptation of Global IR into a plural-monoculturalism in which space for ‘others’ is opened up, but only as satellites around the orbit of a mainstream sun.

For all of their different points of emphasis and political orientations, however, both projects operate through a shared set of binaries. Most obviously, even when the differentiation between West and non-West is normatively disavowed, it has proved to be analytically persistent.Footnote 40 Many of the assumptions that underpin Global IR support the idea of internally distinct cultural units, whether these units are nations, regions, or civilizations. For example, Amitav Acharya writes that ‘indigenous’ IR traditions are based on ‘our’ questions and ‘our’ histories, something that will foster ‘mutual engagement’ between Western and non-Western approaches.Footnote 41 These categories only make sense if the ‘our’ in this story is meaningful, forged from a particular cultural milieu that is distinct from other, equally meaningful units. Acharya's vision of a ‘multiplex world’ is premised on the interactions between separate civilizational entities.Footnote 42 Many radical approaches are also premised on the assumption of separate entities. Decolonial work, for example, favours a strategy of de-centering in which ‘geocultural sites’ premised on ‘local cultures, languages, religions, and ways of life’ serve as the building blocks of distinct ‘worlds’.Footnote 43 This ‘geo-epistemological’ stance sees knowledge as bound by ‘where you find yourselves’ in the world.Footnote 44 From this starting point, it is possible to develop solidarities between geocultural communities, but any ‘worldist dialogue’ must be premised on the recognition of distinct starting points, which are themselves rooted in diverse historical and cultural inheritances.Footnote 45 Geocultural entities are treated as detached, sealed units. Any notion of a singular world, real or epistemic, represents a ‘colonial science’ in operation.Footnote 46

In this way, both reformist and radical positions associated with Global IR, whether directly or more indirectly, are, at root, premised on an ethos of separation. Reformist Global IR opens up a space within which distinct national, regional, and civilizational knowledge-communities can be fostered. Radical approaches aim to foster ‘pluriversality’ – the intercommunal recognition of cultural differences free from colonial capture.Footnote 47 The strategy favoured by reformist Global IR is to pluralize IR from distinct epistemological vantage points; the strategy favoured by more radical positions is to delink from the discipline in order to recover ‘local’ worlds. Either way, the order of analysis is: first, internally constructed units; second, connections. This is the ‘essentialism trap’ in action. By operating through essentialist foundations, both approaches are pushed towards an essentialist reading of categories and assumptions: Western and non-Western; global and local; coloniality and indigeneity.

The essentialism trap and global IR

Among the many reasons for the shared susceptibility of various forms of Global IR to the essentialism trap, three stand out: first, essentialism provides a ‘common sense’ for disciplinary knowledge production; second, alternative viewpoints are subject to logics of cooptation; and third, there is the appeal of standpoint epistemologies. We briefly outline each in turn.

First, as noted above, essentialism provides a ‘common sense’ for the practice and theorization of world politics. Essentialized categories are almost required for those who want to understand strategic and instrumental action.Footnote 48 Any time categories of analysis are invoked, there is also necessarily a moment of reification, of fixing meanings. Indeed, by naming ‘Global IR’ as a ‘thing’ that displays certain ‘tendencies’, we could be read as essentializing our object of enquiry, even as we critique advocates of Global IR for doing just this. The same can be said of many other terms we invoke: ‘mainstream’ IR, ‘the West’, and more. However, there is a major difference between recognizing that naming objects involves ‘as if’ assumptions about their intersubjective meaning and relative stability, and resting claims, whether descriptive, interpretative or explanatory, on the essential properties of these objects. The assumption that countries and regions have ‘radically different histories and political theories than that of the West’ relies on claims about homogenous units that are inscribed within unique historical points of origin that, in turn, generate singular, or at least distinctive, cultural packages – and, hence, different theoretical traditions.Footnote 49 Of course, lived experiences are hugely important to the creation of lifeworlds – place matters. And equally importantly, many of the units of analysis that are examined in world politics are stable and, oftentimes, highly resilient: religions, states, racism, and more. But this does not make them static: religions are reconfigured, the character of states ebbs and flows, racism takes diverse forms across time and place. And these shifts are not just the product of interactions between units. Rather, they are generated by the interplay between peoples, belief-systems, forms of governance, modes of exchange, and more. A relational understanding of ‘things’ does not deny the importance of enduring patterns or relatively stability within objects of analysis. It would be impossible, and nonsensical, to claim that states, regions, and similar entities were not meaningful categories of analysis. A mix of relational social theory and global history can help both to disrupt ‘common sense’ essentialism,Footnote 50 however, and serve as an alternative way of examining the space opened up by Global IR.

Second, essentialism is hard to dislodge because of disciplinary logics. Disciplines have material, institutional, and epistemic resources that reinforce the status quo.Footnote 51 IR is no exception. As noted above, IR also often adopts features of radical challenges that help to maintain its legitimacy. At present, Global IR is mixing a more radical normative agenda with a conventional ontology. This leaves it vulnerable to cooptation as a kind of disciplinary ‘diversity plan’. For example, a core aspiration of Global IR is to recover the agency of actors in the Global South. The point is well-made: Western IR scholarship has written history as if the only actors that mattered were Western. By placing non-Western traditions on an equal footing with Western concepts and theories,Footnote 52 it is argued, IR can be ‘reimagined’ as a site of ‘plural universalism’: many civilizations within one world.Footnote 53 However, this is a thin form of globalizing in which representation emerges from the sum of its parts rather than the deep-rooted, entangled histories that forge global order. The papers in this symposium outline an agenda premised on a more consistent link between ethical intent and ontology, with the potential to develop Global IR in novel directions. We hope to replace an ‘add and stir’ strategy with a ‘global all the way down’ approach that deepens the remit of the Global IR project.

The third dynamic driving Global IR towards the essentialism trap is the way in which its advocates contain a particular form of standpoint epistemology. Standpoint epistemology is rooted in the notion that worldviews emerge from positionalities: what we think derives from where we stand.Footnote 54 This view lies at the heart of attempts to think IR from different starting points – from a distinct positionality, it is argued, comes a distinctive set of interests.Footnote 55 This assumption also lies at the heart of decolonial scholarship, which rests on a geo-epistemological standpoint underlining cultural dissonance. In both cases, identities shape both how actors act in the world and how we, as observers, see it. If actors ‘know’ the world through their positionalities (geography, race, class, gender, political alignment, and so on), scholars also ‘know’ the world through these contexts. Positionalities are inescapable. The question then becomes: what forms of knowledge production are adequate once the centrality of positionality to worldviews is recognized? Standpoint theory valorizes ‘insider’ perspectives for very good reasons – it helps to empower peoples and communities who have been silenced by hegemonic practices and reveals that these practices are themselves perspectival. Yet when ‘insider’ positions become the only way in which valid scholarly knowledge production operates, then it follows that only Chinese scholars can teach and research about China, only Muslims about Islam, only white men about white men, and so on.

In this way, we return to the essentialism trap, one in which the authorization to take part in conversations about ‘insider’ concerns is restricted to ‘insiders’ who can be identified, through preordained positionalities. In such cases, it is often geography that denotes ‘authentic’ subjectivity. And this subjectivity, in turn, represents the limits of our communities. To reiterate: there are sound reasons why standpoint epistemologies are mobilized to certify lived experiences that have been violently suppressed through exploitation. But in scholarship, there is a need for caution, not least because this positionality can serve as a form of ‘primitivism’ that rests on the idealization of a supposed ‘prelapsarian innocence’.Footnote 56 It can also be vulnerable to cooptation by powerful elites, becoming deployed in tandem with claims to authority that rest on notions of cultural authenticity, something made more likely by trends towards authoritarianism of various kinds.Footnote 57 The unintended consequence of a movement seeking to open up the discipline to more diverse voices then could be to sustain political forces that promote narrow, even chauvinistic, agendas. In IR's current operating environment, claims around ‘pluralism’ can lead towards closure rather than openness.

Whatever important work standpoint theory does politically, therefore, we do not think it should serve as the only basis for the scholarly project of Global IR. To see positionality, whether around geography or culture, as the start – and end – of conversations about Global IR is, we think, a limited vision of the project's potential. The challenge is to represent diversity without essentializing difference. The articles in this symposium take up this challenge by identifying both distinct experiences and the deep connections between social sites ‘at home’ and ‘over there’, the ‘foreign’ and the ‘domestic’, the ‘East’ and the ‘West’, ‘metropole’ and ‘colony’. Standpoint epistemologies can occlude these connections and the wider dynamics they are embedded within. This symposium inverts this approach, seeing connections as the basis of units. The foundations of this approach lie in a relational ontology.

Escape velocity: relationalism and global history

Relationalism takes many forms, from the familiar (some varieties of constructivism) to the avant-garde (quantum-inspired hyperhumanism).Footnote 58 Although the differences between forms of relationalism are considerable, all relational approaches recognize that relations are prior to and produce entities. Tilly's processual sociology, for instance, is pitched against the presumption of ‘coherent durable monads’ to the neglect of ‘contingent, transitory connections among socially constructed identities.’Footnote 59 According to Tilly, bad habits have been passed down by his generation:

We learned and in turn taught a practice of this sort: (1) assume a coherent durable, self-propelling social unit; (2) attribute a general condition or process to that unit; (3) invoke or invent an invariant model of that condition or process; (4) explain the behavior of the unit on the basis of its conformity to that invariant model.Footnote 60

For Tilly and other relational thinkers, this procedure will not do. Emirbayer makes clear what is at stake: ‘whether to conceive of the social world as consisting primarily in substances or in processes, in static ‘things’ or in dynamic unfolding relations.’Footnote 61 Relational thinkers do not argue that interests, goals, and identities cannot be stable. Rather, their position is that, however stable, these entities are forged relationally and subject to ongoing logics of reproduction and contestation. The West, for example, is not a fixed entity that existed prior to its engagement with the non-Western world – transboundary relations between Western and non-Western societies led to a change in their organizing logics, positions, and sense of the world. Similarly, the idea of the West and the institutions that support it are regularly reassessed, contested, and reproduced. It is an entity-in-motion. Against claims of constancy, relational accounts stress the ways in which traditions are always living.

Relations may be fleeting or enduring, deep or superficial, direct or indirect, mono- or multi-directional, interpersonal or impersonal. To assess their significance, we need to know which relations matter and when, where, and how they do so. This directs attention to sites where relations cohere (e.g. borders), actors that direct relations (e.g. powerful polities), gaps where relations are sparse or reversible (e.g. extractive regimes), and historical moments when relations break or global integration is either stopped or reversed (e.g. aspects of contemporary world politics). This symposium, therefore, seeks to identify patterns of connections: the structural entanglements, premised on asymmetrical power relations, which generate processes of historical development. Relations, hypothetically speaking, can be egalitarian, but most social relations that concern IR are defined by inequality and hierarchy. Our concern is with the ways in which relations generate systems of stratification: racial, epistemic, geographic, and more.

Despite this shared concern with hierarchical patterns of global order, the symposium offers a major challenge to the use of essentialism and its auxiliary claims in Global IR. Against essentialism, it replaces the starting point of units as entities-with-fixed-attributes with the notion of units as entities-in-motion. Against substantialism, relational approaches argue that it is connections between social sites that produce the entities that are often treated as having an essence: cultures, geographies, nations, regions, civilizations, and more. In contrast to internalism, relationalism stresses the entanglements between ‘inside’ and ‘outside’ that are generative of historical development. Against methodological nationalism, this approach points to the ways in which actors and units are nested within broader scales. Taken together, these moves have two main components: first, the papers in this symposium identify the ways in which historical processes are boundary-crossing; second, they theorize these boundary-crossing connections as patterns of entanglements. The result is an interest in systems of stratification. A relational starting point leads, in turn, to a focus on transboundary connections, structural entanglements, and systems of stratification.

The aim of Global IR is to use the openness of the contemporary conjuncture to reform or recast core components of the discipline: its forms of epistemic certification, its geographical range, its conceptual grids, and more. We want this project to succeed. However, for this to happen, we think that Global IR must avoid the gravitational pull presented by the essentialism trap. This symposium sets out some ways in which this trap might be avoided and articulates another way of advancing Global IR.

The first article, by Barkawi, Murray, and Zarakol, analyses the underlying power dynamics that have pulled the Global IR project in potentially problematic directions. It argues that both American and Global IR share a Eurocentric spatial imaginary, one that was a product of Western expansion and empire. Insisting that geographical representation – geo-epistemology – is the solution to the problem of Eurocentrism (or American bias) reproduces the very problems Global IR seeks to address, and traps Global IR in essentialist representation. The second article extends this analysis by examining the ways in which proponents of Global IR read IR's disciplinary history. Focusing on India, Bayly shows how a relational sociology of disciplinary knowledge, rooted in imperial knowledge complexes, provides an account of disciplinary IR as ‘global at birth’, a globality that has subsequently been occluded in favour of a more essentialist reading of a singular birth story. Also deploying insights from global history, the third article, by Hui, questions if students of historical Asia who challenge Western IR for ‘getting Asia wrong’ do ‘get Asia right’. The paper de-essentializes ‘China's hegemony’ by disaggregating the concept of ‘China’ and examining the multivocal and contradictory reactions of China's neighbours in the full universe of China's relevant relations across Asia. The final article, by Barnett and Lawson, demonstrates one way of achieving the relational escape velocity discussed above by providing a reappraisal of one of the central theoretical concerns in contemporary IR: the notion of global order. The symposium closes with a series of critical reflections on its main themes by Pardesi, Çapan, and Yunis.

Recognizing that we have been here before is important in terms of analysing what is at stake in contemporary debates about Global IR. It is equally important for attempts, such as ours, to generate alternative ways of theorizing the global. Each of the papers in this symposium therefore rests on a shared sense of critique (essentialism and its auxiliary assumptions) but develops its own particular remedy (relational accounts premised on transboundary connections, structural entanglements, and systems of stratification). The takeaway from the symposium is not, therefore, a single ‘solution’ for where IR theory in general, or Global IR in particular, should go, but rather a series of openings through which IR theory can use the current crisis productively rather than as another means of closure. But the symposium promises more than this. It argues that engagement with global history, alongside a relational ontology, helps to provide theoretical resources – connections, entanglements, stratification – that can underpin Global IR's research agenda. It is an agenda, we think, that is rich in possibilities.

Acknowledgements

We would like to thank the contributors to this symposium and the anonymous referees for their generous feedback.

Footnotes

2 e.g. Colgan Reference Colgan2019; Maliniak et al. Reference Maliniak2013.

3 Maliniak et al. Reference Maliniak2019.

5 Kang and Lin Reference Kang and Lin2019, 394; Shilliam Reference Shilliam2021, 51.

7 The approach is most closely associated with Amitav Acharya (Reference Acharya2014, Reference Acharya2016a, Reference Acharya2016b, Reference Acharya2017, Reference Acharya2019) and his co-authored work with Barry Buzan (Acharya and Buzan Reference Acharya and Buzan2007, Reference Acharya and Buzan2017, Reference Acharya and Buzan2019, Reference Acharya and Buzan2021), and others (e.g. Acharya et al., Reference Acharya, Deciancio and Tussie2021). For reasons of space, this symposium largely engages these central statements. However, Global IR is a diverse rather than monolithic movement. A representative sample of texts within the wider genre includes Bilgin Reference Bilgin2016; Deciancio Reference Deciancio2016; Hurrell Reference Hurrell2016; Wemheuer-Vogelaar et al. Reference Wemheuer-Vogelaar, Bell, Morales and Tierney2016; Kavalski Reference Kavalski2017; Wiener Reference Wiener2018; Alejandro Reference Alejandro2019; Yong-Soo Reference Yong-Soo2019; Reference Yong-Soo2022; Gelardi Reference Gelardi2019; Baruah and Selleslaghs Reference Baruah, Selleslaghs, Hosli and Selleslaghs2019; Barbieri Reference Barbieri2019; Fierke and Jabri Reference Fierke and Jabri2019; Fonseca Reference Fonseca2019; Kristensen Reference Kristensen2015; Bentil Reference Bentil2020; Kuru Reference Kuru2020; Qin Reference Qin2020; Lohaus and Wemheuer-Vogelaar Reference Lohaus and Wemheuer-Vogelaar2021; Gonzalez-Vicente and Montoute Reference Gonzalez-Vicente and Montoute2020; Wilkens and Kessler Reference Wilkens, Kessler and Ish-Shalom2021; Williams Reference Williams2021; Dian Reference Dian2022; Raineri and Baldaro Reference Raineri and Baldaro2022; Dalacoura Reference Dalacoura2021; Sula Reference Sula2022; Do Reference Do2022; Thalang Reference Thalang2022; Düzgün Reference Düzgün2022; Chu Reference Chu2022; Costa Buranelli and Taeuber Reference Costa Buranelli and Taeueber2022.

8 On Eurocentrism, see Amin Reference Amin1989; Chakrabarty Reference Chakrabarty2000; Hobson Reference Hobson2012. On concepts, see Bell Reference Bell2020; Inayatullah and Blaney Reference Inayatullah and Blaney2004; Jahn Reference Jahn2017. On histories, see e.g. Hobson Reference Hobson2020; Zarakol Reference Zarakol2022.

9 So far the mainstream has paid little mind to Globlal IR, however. See also Risse et al. Reference Risse, Wemheuer-Vogelaar and Havemann2022.

10 Google Ngram searches show a sharp spike in both articles and books using the term ‘Global IR’ since 2015. As of 2022, there is a Global IR section of the ISA. A range of forums, perhaps most notably the World International Studies Conference (WISC), also serve as a means of pluralizing and globalizing the discipline, including through the development of Global IR.

12 Despite being one of six research agendas proposed for Global IR (Acharya Reference Acharya2014, 652), links between Global IR and global history are not well developed.

13 Hacking Reference Hacking1999, 17.

14 Sayer Reference Sayer1997, 454.

18 Emirbayer Reference Emirbayer1997, 283–6).

19 See Qin Reference Qin2018.

20 Wimmer and Schiller Reference Wimmer and Schiller2002.

21 Ferguson and Mansbach (Reference Ferguson and Richard1996).

22 Jackson and Nexon Reference Jackson and Nexon1999; McCourt Reference McCourt2016. Advocates of Global IR themselves often critique essentialist readings of history, culture, and development. See, for example Acharya and Buzan Reference Acharya and Buzan2019, 247, 306.

24 On the distinction between ‘thin’ and ‘thick’ constructivism, see Wendt Reference Wendt1999; Kratochwil Reference Kratochwil2006.

26 This debate is well critiqued in Fearon and Wendt Reference Fearon, Wendt, Carlsnaes, Risse and Simmons2002.

27 This was true of earlier challengers too, which often also found refuge outside mainstream US spaces.

28 Although we do not have the space to extend this point further, our hunch is that the essentialism trap predates the examples we have given here. See also Bayly in this symposium.

29 e.g. Colgan Reference Colgan2019; Kristensen Reference Kristensen2015; Lohaus and Wemheuer-Vogellar Reference Lohaus and Wemheuer-Vogelaar2020.

31 Acharya Reference Acharya2014, 649.

32 Acharya and Buzan Reference Acharya and Buzan2007, 436.

33 Acharya and Buzan Reference Acharya and Buzan2019, 1–2. Also, see Acharya et al. Reference Acharya, Deciancio and Tussie2021.

34 Acharya and Buzan Reference Acharya and Buzan2019, 3. Note that this is a starting assumption.

35 Acharya Reference Acharya2014, 649). Elsewhere Acharya does caution against ‘assuming a benign Asian hierarchy and seeking evidence to fit this cultural historicist straitjacket.’ Acharya 2003/4, 162.

36 Anderl and Witt Reference Anderl and Witt2020, 43–4.

37 See, for example, Blaney and Tickner Reference Blaney and Tickner2017; Tickner and Smith Reference Tickner and Karen2020.

38 Shilliam Reference Shilliam2021, 24. Although post-colonial and decolonial approaches share a common starting point in seeing Western colonialism as the generative grammar of modern world order, they emerged from different geographies and intellectual genres, and have different ways of diagnosing and overcoming the colonial condition.

39 Footnote Ibid., 52, 86.

40 Inayatullah and Blaney Reference Inayatullah and Blaney2004, 10–11. To some extent, the use of this binary language is unavoidable (we also use it). The issue arises when present-day politics of representation is conflated with analytical purchase.

41 Acharya Reference Acharya2019, 471.

42 Acharya Reference Acharya2017, 202.

43 Smith and Tickner 2020, 7.

46 Blaney and Tickner Reference Blaney and Tickner2017, 295.

47 Mignolo Reference Mignolo2011, 23. See also Bhambra Reference Bhambra2014; Rutazibwa Reference Rutazibwa2020; Sabaratnam Reference Sabaratnam2011.

48 Even sympathisers of relationalism, in fact, worry that substantialism has been thrown out with the bathwater of essentialism, with the implication that actors no longer exist. Pan Reference Pan2021.

49 Acharya and Buzan Reference Acharya and Buzan2019, 3.

51 This assertion lies at the heart of the view of scientific ‘paradigms’ developed in Kuhn Reference Kuhn1962.

52 Acharya Reference Acharya2017, 202.

53 Acharya Reference Acharya2014, 649.

54 The classic text is Harding Reference Harding1986; also see Haraway Reference Haraway1991.

56 Brigg et al. Reference Brigg, Graham and Weber2022, 11–2.

57 V-Dem 2021. See also Çapan and Zarakol Reference Çapan and Ayşe2017.

58 Katzenstein Reference Katzenstein and Katzenstein2022, Kurki Reference Kurki2020. For a useful overview, see Guzzini Reference Guzzini, Guillaume and Bilgin2017. We do not distinguish between processual and relational ontologies. On this, see Abbott Reference Abbott2016.

59 Tilly Reference Tilly1995, 1595. Also see Abbott Reference Abbott2016.

60 Tilly Reference Tilly1995, 1595.

61 Emirbayer Reference Emirbayer1997, 281.

References

Abbott, Andrew. 2016. Processual Sociology. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Acharya, Amitav. 2014. “Global International Relations (IR) and Regional Worlds.” International Studies Quarterly 58 (4): 647–59.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Acharya, Amitav. 2016a. “Advancing Global IR: Challenges, Contentions and Contributions.” International Studies Review 18 (1): 414.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Acharya, Amitav. 2016b. “Studying the Bandung Conference From a Global IR Perspective.” Australian Journal of International Affairs 70 (4): 342–57.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Acharya, Amitav. 2017. “After Liberal Hegemony.” Ethics & International Affairs 31 (3): 271–85.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Acharya, Amitav. 2019. “From Heaven to Earth.” Chinese Journal of International Politics 12 (4): 467–94.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Acharya, Amitav, and Buzan, Barry. 2007. “Why Is There No Non-Western International Relations Theory?International Relations of the Asia-Pacific 7 (3): 287312.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Acharya, Amitav, and Buzan, Barry. 2017. “Why Is There No Non-Western International Relations Theory? Ten Years on.” International Relations of the Asia-Pacific 17 (3): 341–70.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Acharya, Amitav, and Buzan, Barry. 2019. The Making of Global International Relations. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Acharya, Amitav, and Buzan, Barry. 2021. Re-Imagining International Relations. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Acharya, Amitav, Deciancio, Melisa and Tussie, Diana, eds. 2021. Latin America in Global International Relations. Abingdon: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Agnew, John. 2007. “Know-Where: Geographies of Knowledge of World Politics.” International Political Sociology 1 (2): 138–48.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Alejandro, Audrey. 2019. Western Dominance in International Relations? The Internationalisation of IR in Brazil and India. Abingdon: Routledge.Google Scholar
Amin, Samir. 1989. Eurocentrism. New York: NYU Press.Google Scholar
Anderl, Felix, and Witt, Antonia. 2020. “Problematising the Global in Global IR.” Millennium: Journal of International Studies 49 (1): 3257.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Aydınlı, Ersel, and Erpul, Onur. 2022. “The False Promise of Global IR: Exposing the Paradox of Dependent Development.” International Theory 14 (3): 419–59.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barbieri, Giovanni. 2019. “Regionalism, Globalism and Complexity: A Stimulus Towards Global IR?Third World Thematics 4 (6): 424–41.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baruah, Indraneel, and Selleslaghs, Joren. 2019. “Alternative Post-Positivist Theories of IR and the Quest for A Global IR Scholarship.” In The Changing Global Order, edited by Hosli, Madeleine O. and Selleslaghs, Joren, 2343. Cham: Springer.Google Scholar
Bell, Duncan. 2020. Dreamworlds of Race. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google ScholarPubMed
Bentil, Shadrack. 2020. “When You Think of a Global IR Theory, Think Uhuru Na Ujamaa?Asian Research Journal of Arts & Social Sciences 10(1): 820.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bhambra, Gurminder K. 2014. Connected Sociologies. London: Bloomsbury.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bhambra, Gurminder K., Yolande, Bouka, Randolph, B. Persaud, Olivia, U. Rutazibwa, Vineet, Thakur, Duncan, Bell, Karen, Smith, Toni, Haastrup and Seifudein, Adem. 2020. “Why Is Mainstream International Relations Blind to Racism.” Foreign Affairs, July 3rd. Available at: https://foreignpolicy.com/2020/07/03/why-is-mainstream-international-relations-ir-blind-to-racism-colonialism/.Google Scholar
Bilgin, Pınar. 2016. “‘Contrapuntal Reading’ as A Method, an Ethos, and A Metaphor for Global IR.” International Studies Review 18 (1): 134–46.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Blaney, David L., and Tickner, Arlene B.. 2017. “Worlding, Ontological Politics and the Possibility of A Decolonial IR.” Millennium: Journal of International Studies 45 (3): 293311.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brigg, Morgan, Graham, Mary, and Weber, Martin. 2022. “Relational Indigenous Systems: Aboriginal Australian Political Ordering and Reconfiguring IR.” Review of International Studies 48 (5): 891909.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Çapan, Zeynep G., and Ayşe, Zarakol. 2017. “Postcolonial colonialism? The case of Turkey.” In Against International Relations Norms, edited by Charlotte Epstein, 193211. London: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chakrabarty, Dipesh. 2000. Provincializing Europe. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Chu, Sinan. 2022. “Fantastic Theories and Where to Find Them: Rethinking Interlocutors in Global IR.” Millennium: Journal of International Studies 50 (3): 700–29.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Colgan, Jeff D. 2019. “American Perspectives and Blind Spots on World Politics.” Journal of Global Security Studies 4 (3): 300–09.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Costa Buranelli, Filippo, and Taeueber, Simon F.. 2022. “The English School and Global IR – A Research Agenda.” All Azimuth 11 (1): 87105.Google Scholar
Dalacoura, Katerina. 2021. “Global IR, Global Modernity and Civilization in Turkish Islamist Thought: A Critique of Culturalism in International Relations.” International Politics 58 (2): 131–47.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
de Carvalho, Benjamin, Leira, Halvard, and Hobson, John M.. 2011. “The Big Bangs of IR.” Millennium: Journal of International Studies 39 (3): 735–58.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Deciancio, Melisa. 2016. “International Relations From the South: A Regional Research Agenda for Global IR.” International Studies Review 18 (1): 106–19.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dian, Matteo. 2022. “The Rise of China Between Global IR and Area Studies: An Agenda for Cooperation.” Italian Political Science Review 52 (2): 252–67.Google Scholar
Do, Thuy T. 2022. “Between Integration and Differentiation: International Relations Studies and the Promise of Global IR in Vietnam.” Contemporary Southeast Asia 44 (2): 289314.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Düzgün, Eren. 2022. “Radicalising Global IR: Modernity, Capitalism, and the Question of Eurocentrism.” The Chinese Journal of International Politics 15 (3): 313–33.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Emirbayer, Mustafa. 1997. “Manifesto for A Relational Sociology.” The American Journal of Sociology 103 (2): 281317.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ferguson, Yale, and Richard, W. Mansbach. 1996. Polities: Authority, Identities, and Change. Columbia, SC: University of South Carolina Press.Google Scholar
Fearon, James D. Alexander Wendt, . 2002. “Rationalism V. Constructivism: A Skeptical View.” In Handbook of International Relations, edited by Carlsnaes, Walter, Risse, Thomas and Simmons, Beth A., 5272. London et al.: Sage Publ.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fierke, Karin M., and Jabri, Vivienne. 2019. “Global Conversations: Relationality, Embodiment and Power in the Move Towards A Global IR.” Global Constitutionalism 8 (3): 506–35.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fonseca, Melody. 2019. “Global IR and Western Dominance: Moving Forward or Eurocentric Entrapment?Millennium: Journal of International Studies 48 (1): 4559.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gelardi, Maiken. 2019. “Moving Global IR Forward – A Road Map.” International Studies Review 22 (4): 830–52.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gonzalez-Vicente, Ruben, and Montoute, Annita. 2020. “A Caribbean Perspective on China-Caribbean Relations: Global IR, Dependency and the Postcolonial Condition.” Third World Quarterly 42 (2): 219–38.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Guzzini, Stefano. 2017. “International Political Sociology, or: The Social Ontology and Power Politics of Process.” In The Routledge Handbook of International Political Sociology, edited by Guillaume, Xavier and Bilgin, Pınar, 366–75. Abingdon: Routledge.Google Scholar
Hacking, Ian. 1999. The Social Construction of What? Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Haraway, Donna J. 1991. Simians, Cyborgs and Women. New York: Free Association.Google Scholar
Harding, Sandra. 1986. “The Instability of the Analytical Categories of Feminist Theory.” Signs: Journal of Women in Culture and Society 11 (4): 645–64.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hobson, John M. 2012. The Eurocentric Conception of World Politics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hobson, John M. 2020. Multicultural Origins of the Global Economy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hurrell, Andrew. 2016. “Beyond Critique: How to Study Global IR?International Studies Review 18 (1): 149–51.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Inayatullah, Naeem, and Blaney, David L.. 2004. International Relations and the Problem of Difference. London: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jackson, Patrick Thaddeus, and Nexon, Daniel H.. 1999. “Relations Before States.” European Journal of International Relations 5 (3): 291332.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jahn, Beate. 2017. “Theorizing the Political Relevance of International Relations Theory.” International Studies Quarterly 61 (1): 6477.Google Scholar
Kang, David, and Lin, A. Y. T.. 2019. “US Bias in the Study of Asian Security.” Journal of Global Security Studies 4 (3): 393401.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Katzenstein, Peter J. 2022. “Worldviews in World Politics.” In Uncertainty and Its Discontents: Worldviews in World Politics, edited by Katzenstein, Peter J., 170. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kavalski, Emilian. 2017. The Guanxi of Relational International Theory. Abingdon: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kratochwil, Friedrich. 2006. “History, Action and Identity.” European Journal of International Relations 12 (1): 529.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kristensen, Peter Marcus. 2015. “The South in ‘Global IR’: Worlding Beyond the ‘Non-West’ in the Case of Brazil.” International Studies Perspectives 22 (2): 218–39.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kuhn, Thomas. 1962. The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Kurki, Milja. 2020. International Relations and Relational Cosmology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kuru, Deniz. 2020. “Dialogue of the ‘Globals’: Connecting Global IR to Global Intellectual History.” All Azimuth 9 (2): 229–48.Google Scholar
Ling, L. H. M., and Pinheiro, Carolina M.. 2020. “South–South Talk.” In International Relations From the Global South, edited by Tickner, Arlene B. & Smith, Karen, 317–40. London: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lohaus, Mathis, and Wemheuer-Vogelaar, Wiebke. 2021. “Who Publishes Where?International Studies Review 23 (3): 645–69.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Maliniak, Daniel et al. 2013. “The Gender Citation Gap in International Relations.” International Organization 67 (4): 889922.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Maliniak, Daniel et al. 2019. “Policy-Relevant Publications and Tenure Decisions in International Relations.” PS: Political Science & Politics 52 (2): 318–24.Google Scholar
McCourt, David. 2016. “Practice Theory and Relationalism as the New Constructivism.” International Studies Quarterly 60 (3): 475–85.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mignolo, Walter D. 2011. “Geopolitics of Sensing and Knowing.” Postcolonial Studies 14 (3): 273–83.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pan, Chengxin. 2021. “Reclaiming Substances in Relationalism: Quantum Holography and Substance-Based Relational Analysis in World Politics.” Millennium: Journal of International Studies 49 (3): 577603.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Phillips, Anne. 2010. ‘What's Wrong with Essentialism?Distinktion: Scandinavian Journal of Social Theory. 11 (1): 4760.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Qin, Yaqing. 2018. A Relational Theory of World Politics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Qin, Yaqing, ed. 2020. Globalizing IR Theory. London: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Raineri, Luca, and Baldaro, Edoardo. 2022. “The Place of Africa in International Relations: The Centrality of the Margins in Global IR.” Italian Political Science Review 52 (2): 236–51.Google Scholar
Risse, Thomas, Wemheuer-Vogelaar, Wiebke, and Havemann, Frank. 2022. “IR Theory and the Core–Periphery Structure of Global IR: Lessons From Citation Analysis.” International Studies Review 24 (3): viac029. https://doi.org/10.1093/isr/viac029CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rutazibwa, Olivia U. 2020. “Hidden in Plain Sight.” Millennium: Journal of International Studies 48 (2): 221–41.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sabaratnam, Meera. 2011. “IR in Dialogue … but Can We Change the Subjects?Millennium: Journal of International Studies 39 (3): 781803.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shilliam, Robbie. 2021. Decolonizing Politics. Cambridge: Polity.Google Scholar
Sayer, Andrew. 1997. “Essentialism, Social Constructionism, and Beyond.” The Sociological Review 45 (3): 453487.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tickner, Arlene B., and Karen, Smith, eds. 2020. International Relations from the Global South. London: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sula, Ismail Erkam. 2022. “’Global’ IR and Self-Reflections in Turkey: Methodology, Data Collection, and Data Repository.” All Azimuth 11 (1): 123–42.Google Scholar
Thalang, Chanintira Na. 2022. “Advancing Global IR From A Thai Perspective: Opportunities for Pre-Theorization and Conceptualization.” Contemporary Southeast Asia 44 (2): 250–73.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tilly, Charles. 1995. “To Explain Political Processes.” The American Journal of Sociology 100 (6): 1594–610.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
V-Dem. 2021. Autocratization Turns Viral. Gothenburg: V-Dem Institute.Google Scholar
Wacquant, Loïc. 2022. “Resolving the Trouble with Race.” New Left Review 133/134: 6788.Google Scholar
Wemheuer-Vogelaar, Wiebke, Bell, Nicholas J., Morales, Mariana Navarrete, and Tierney, Michael J.. 2016. “The IR of the Beholder: Examining Global IR Using the 2014 TRIP Survey.” International Studies Review 18 (1): 1632.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wendt, Alexander. 1999. Social Theory of International Politics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wiener, Antje. 2018. Contestation and Constitution of Norms in Global International Relations. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wilkens, Jan, and Kessler, Oliver. 2021. “Concepts at Work in Global IR.” In Concepts at Work: On the Linguistic Infrastructure of World Politics, edited by Ish-Shalom, Piki, 203–22. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.Google Scholar
Williams, John. 2021. “English School-’Chinese IR’ Engagements: Order, Harmony and the Limits of Elitism in Global IR.” The Chinese Journal of International Politics 14 (1): 127–57.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wimmer, Andreas, and Schiller, Nina Glick. 2002. “Methodological Nationalism and Beyond.” Global Networks 2 (4): 301–34.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Yong-Soo, Eun. 2019. “Global IR through Dialogue.” The Pacific Review 32 (2): 131–49.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Yong-Soo, Eun. 2022. “Reflexive Solidarity: Toward A Broadening of What It Means to be ‘Scientific’ in Global IR Knowledge.” All Azimuth 11 (1): 107–22.Google Scholar
Zarakol, Ayşe. 2022. Before the West: The Rise and Fall of Eastern World Orders. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar